Rethinking_Death_in_and_after_Heidegger
Rethinking_Death_in_and_after_Heidegger
1
“Die Sterblichen sterben den Tod im Leben.” Martin Heidegger, “Hölderlin’s Earth and
Heaven [1959]” (EHP 190/GA4 165).
2
I say “begin” because I think some of the best evidence for the reading advanced here is the
revealing light it casts on the interconnected issues taken up in subsequent chapters, which
develop and extend aspects of this analysis while also focusing on details and implications
of the view not addressed here (as well as addressing some critical responses to it).
3
See John Haugeland, “Truth and Finitude: Heidegger’s Transcendental Existentialism,” in
Heidegger, Authenticity, and Modernity: Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus, Volume 1,
ed. by Mark Wrathall and Jeff Malpas (Cambridge, MA: MIT, 2000), 44.
4
Temporality is the most fundamental structure of intelligibility accessible to phenomen-
ology, in the early Heidegger’s view. (See also William Blattner, Heidegger’s Temporal
Idealism [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999].) As we will see later, in “genuine
anxiety,” our being is, or becomes, sheer becoming; we exist as a pure or empty existing,
deprived of the practical world. (“As we will see later” – as a phrase by which something
still to come enters into and makes itself felt in our present – is not itself a bad indication
of what “futurity” means.)
5
Such “understanding” is not meant by Heidegger to be merely cognitive or intellectual but,
rather, primarily something we personally instantiate or stand-under (such that our
intelligible worlds are implicitly organized in its terms). Indeed (at the risk of being too
provocative at the outset), Being and Time repeatedly contends that each of us must pass
through existential death in order to reach authenticity. (But because this is a death of the
lived possibilities that organize our worldly selves rather than a mortal demise, Heidegger
does not thereby presuppose any kind of metaphysical afterlife.) What is more, I show
below (and would try to demonstrate thoroughly, were I offering a broader interpretation
of Being and Time here) that the multifaceted phenomenon disclosed by death turns out to
be absolutely central to almost all of the subsequent phenomenological analyses in
Division II of Being and Time, many of which disclose interconnected aspects of the same
phenomenon (see n. 6) or trace its roots and subsequent implications.
critical readers of the text cannot indeûnitely postpone the difûcult task of
coming to terms with Heidegger’s understanding of the phenomenon.
That brings us directly to the third reason for the controversy surrounding
the meaning of death in Being and Time, which is that the phenomenological
method we are supposed to use to adjudicate the matter is particularly difûcult
to employ in this crucial case. The problem, put simply, is that many readers
seem to have trouble experiencing the phenomenon that Heidegger describes as
“death” for themselves. Without such ûrst-personal experience, however,
readers can neither contest nor conûrm Being and Time’s existential
phenomenology of death. It is worth emphasizing that this is a general problem
for critical readers of phenomenological works: Absent our own experience of
the phenomenon at issue, we can neither attest to that phenomenon and its
purported signiûcance (and so conûrm or develop it for ourselves) nor testify
against it (and so seek to contest, reûne, or redescribe it). This general phenom-
enological problem is greatly exacerbated in the case of death, however, because
unlike phenomenological descriptions of more mundane phenomena (such as
using a hammer, staring at a Gestalt ûgure or optical illusion, or even such
unsettling experiences as being stared at by a stranger or feeling the pangs of a
guilty conscience), the phenomenon by means of which we ûrst encounter what
Heidegger means by “death” – namely, the affective attunement of “‘real’ or
‘authentic’ anxiety” (“eigentliche” Angst), in which, as we will see, we experience
ourselves as radically “not-at-home” in the world of our everyday projects – is
both quite “rare” (BT 234/SZ 190) and extremely difûcult to endure.6
The requirement that we must personally undergo an anguished experience
of the utter desolation of the self in order to be able to testify for or against the
adequacy of Heidegger’s phenomenological analysis of death thus seems
6
As Heidegger puts it, “this primordial anxiety . . . clears away everything covering over the
fact that Dasein has been abandoned to itself. The ‘nothing’ with which anxiety brings us
face to face unveils the nullity [or “emptiness,” Nichtigkeit] by which Dasein, in its very
basis, is deûned; and this basis itself is as thrownness into death” (BT 356/SZ 308). Hence:
“Being-toward-death is essentially anxiety” (BT 310/SZ 266; see also BT 295/SZ 251).
Blattner nicely articulates this connection in terms of Heidegger’s three inextricably
interconnected existentials (that is, structures that condition all existence): “Death is the
self-understanding that belongs to this experience, anxiety is the mood, and conscience its
discourse” (see William Blattner, Heidegger’s Being and Time: A Reader’s Guide [London:
Continuum, 2006], 140). By “primordial” (ursprüngliche) or “real or authentic anxiety,”
Heidegger means anxiety that stems not from individual physiological peculiarities or
unrelated neurochemical imbalances but, instead, from the ontological structure of the
self, speciûcally, from what I shall explain as the “uncanny” lack of ût between the empty
self at our volitional and intentional, existential core, on the one hand, and the practical
world of particular ontic and existentiell choices by which we give this self concrete,
worldly meaning, on the other (see also n. 74). This lack of any perfect ût between self and
world is common to everyone whether we realize it or not, Heidegger suggests (we will
see), and so the source of an ineliminable undercurrent of existential anxiety in all our
everyday lives.
7
Heidegger’s use of this term has faint Kierkegaardian echoes, since a Zumutung is the
kind of completely “unreasonable demand” that the Judeo-Christian God legendarily
requires of Abraham by commanding him to sacriûce his only son (who is still a child)
after having promised the now elderly Abraham that his descendants would one day be as
plentiful as grains of sand on the beach or stars in the sky ( that is, a demand that goes
against the rationality of our preexisting worldly cares and concerns).
8
For the Heidegger of Being and Time, philosophy must be phenomenological: “Ontology
and phenomenology are not two distinct philosophical disciplines among others. These
terms characterize philosophy itself with regard to its object and its way of treating that
object. Philosophy is universal phenomenological ontology” (BT 62/SZ 38). (We return to
this point in the Concluding Recapitulations.) As we will see in Chapter 2, Heidegger will
later abandon this project of fundamental ontology (the attempt to understand “the
meaning of being in general”) and, with it, “philosophy” itself (which he will then identify
with the pursuit of the very “metaphysics” he later tries to help us think beyond).
9
(See Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness: A Phenomenological Essay on Ontology,
trans. by H. E. Barnes [New York: Philosophical Library, 1956 [original 1943]], 271, 288;
and Emmanuel Levinas, Time and the Other, trans. by R. A. Cohen [Pittsburgh:
Duquesne University Press, 1987].) When a stranger stares at me, Sartre will argue (using
his famous phenomenological example of being caught looking through a keyhole), my
subjectivity temporarily becomes objectiûed by this stranger’s gaze; that is, I implicitly
experience myself not as stretching out into a world of practical projects that implicitly
deûne me but, instead, as caught and frozen by this stranger’s stare like a bug on a pin,
transformed by a subjectivity outside myself into one (for me inaccessible and so
over the last century, has also rendered us much more reluctant to inject
ourselves into the discussion by testing Heidegger’s descriptions for ourselves
(where that also means testing them on ourselves, that is, comparing them to
our own ûrst-personal encounters with the phenomenon at issue). Or perhaps
Heidegger’s own appalling misadventure with Nazism has led interpreters to
distance themselves from the fact that, as he acknowledged in Being and Time,
“a deûnite ontic interpretation of authentic existence, a factical ideal of Dasein,
underlies our ontological interpretation” (BT 358/SZ 310).10
then conceptualizes its conditioning structures in ways that should deepen, enrich, and
transform life). Thus, part of the test of any phenomenological analysis will be how well it
deepens, enriches, or transforms our everyday experience of the phenomenon whose
underlying structures it seeks to conceptualize (as we shall see in the case of death here,
and as I showed in the case of art in Iain Thomson, Heidegger, Art, and Postmodernity
[Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011], chs. 3–4).
11
On the relation of Heidegger’s Nazism to his philosophy, see esp. Iain Thomson,
Heidegger on Ontotheology: Technology and the Politics of Education (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2005), chs. 3–4, and “Heidegger’s Nazism in the Light of
His Early Black Notebooks: A View from America,” in Zur Hermeneutik der ‘Schwarzen
Hefte’: Heidegger Jahrbuch 10, ed. by Alfred Denker and Holger Zaborowski (Freiburg:
Karl Alber, 2017). (Some of these issues will come back in Chapters 6–8.)
12
See Paul Edwards, Heidegger’s Confusions (New York: Prometheus, 2004) (which reprints
Edward’s incredibly confused articles from 1975 and 1976); Piotr Hoffman, “Death,
Time, History: Division II of Being and Time,” in The Cambridge Companion to
13
(Hubert L. Dreyfus, Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time,
Division I [Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1990], 3, 10.) As Dreyfus suggests, the
English “human being” (which can designate both a way of being and an individual)
comes closest to Heidegger’s use of “Dasein” and “a Dasein” in Being and Time (ibid., 14).
As is well known, however, Heidegger vociferously rejected “anthropological” misunder-
standings of Being and Time (which would reduce his work to an attempt to understand
“the being of the human,” an effort that Heidegger – insofar as he did indeed engage in
it – always meant to serve the larger ambition of “fundamental ontology,” viz., the
attempt to understand “the meaning of being in general,” as we will see in Chapter 2).
But for this and other reasons, it has now become common to misunderstand Heidegger
in almost the opposite terms, as an “anti-humanist.” In truth, however, from beginning to
end, “Heidegger is an afûrmative thinker of the ontological essence of the human being,
that is, an ontological humanist dedicated to disclosively thinking the being deûnitive of
the human being” (as I show in Chapter 4 and in Iain Thomson, “Hearing the Pro-
Vocation within the Provocation: Heidegger on the Way to Post-Metaphysical
Humanism,” Gatherings: The Heidegger Circle Annual, XII [2022], 187).
14
“To characterize with a single term both the involvement of being in human nature and
the essential relation of humanity to the openness (‘here’ [Da]) of being as such, the name
‘being-here’ [Dasein] was chosen” (WBGM 270).
15
(“Division I” makes up roughly the ûrst half of Being and Time as it was published, albeit
not as it was planned – an important proviso I will explain in Chapter 2.) Heidegger
clearly employs the tools of conceptual analysis in Being and Time. He does so, however,
not to try to deûne some new philosophical position into existence out of the logical space
of possible options but, instead, to help analyze and develop the larger signiûcance of a
momentous phenomenon he has experienced in his own life, since Heidegger’s version of
existential phenomenology is empty and pointless without such ûrst-personal experience,
as we will see repeatedly (see also n. 10).
16
In fact, Heidegger’s account of the relation of mutual conditioning between Dasein and
being will turn out to be considerably more complex than he initially recognized in Being
and Time (though we can bracket most of these complications until Chapters 2 and 4).
Put simply, the (more idealistic) early Heidegger of Being and Time thinks of our
understanding of being as something we unknowingly constitute by subconsciously
employing temporal structures as necessary and sufûcient transcendental conditions that
most deeply shape our intelligible worlds (thus Heidegger describes Being and Time’s goal
to “expose primordial time . . . as the condition which makes the everyday experience of
time both possible and necessary” [BT 381, my emphasis/SZ 333], although this ambitious
goal fails, as we shall see in Chapter 2), whereas the (more realistic) later Heidegger thinks
of our understanding of being as shaped by historically changing ontotheological struc-
tures that are largely inherited from our historical tradition. But Being and Time already
begins to recognize that we Dasein are entities whose existence as embodied ways of being
implicitly answer the question of what it means for us to be, and also that these particular
existential answers always borrow (in multiple ways) from our preexisting answer to the
larger ontological question of what it means to be anything at all. Most importantly, for
example, Being and Time argues (in Division One) that our taken-for-granted modern
answer to the ontological question (in which we understand ourselves as “subjects”
ontologically separated from and so standing-over against “objects” [Gegenstand]) “dis-
astrously” misunderstands (BT 46/SZ 25) and so obscures our deeper nature as Dasein
(that is, entities whose “usual and ordinary” practical ways of disclosing being in time
“always-already” bridge and so undermine the supposed ontological gulf that post-
Cartesian modernity posits between subjects and objects). In Being and Time, however,
this “disaster” seems to be primarily for our philosophical self-understanding, whereas for
the later Heidegger, the broader (and ever more pervasively embodied) ramiûcations of
this philosophical disaster of modern “subjectivism” take on increasingly world-historical
proportions, especially as such modern “subjectivism” continues to evolve historically
into the late-modern epoch of technological “enframing” in which we now ûnd ourselves
every Dasein already embodies an answer to the question of the meaning of its
own being. This largely implicit existential answer to the question of the
meaning of my own being may or may not be recognized as such, but it is
nevertheless embodied concretely in the ways I go about being a teacher,
father, husband, friend, brother, citizen, nature-lover, bike-rider, and so on.
This embodied stand each of us takes on what it means to be can of course be
more or less coherent, honest, thoughtful, unique, and so on, but for the early
Heidegger the crucial issue here is just whether or not we own up to being this
trapped (see Iain Thomson, “Post/Modernity? How to Separate the Stereo from the
Styrofoam,” Gatherings: The Heidegger Circle Annual, XI [2021], 183–97). As a result,
for the later Heidegger (beginning in the late-1930s), Dasein increasingly becomes a
prescriptive existential achievement (and eventually even a literally “postmodern” way
of being-in-the-world) rather than just an unbiased phenomenological description of our
distinctive way of being. In other words, as we will begin to see in Chapter 4 (and I argue
in Thomson, Heidegger, Art, and Postmodernity), Dasein becomes something we need to
understand ourselves in terms of – and so progressively transform ourselves into – in
order to ûnd our way beyond the historical “epochs” of modern “subjectivism” and late-
modern “enframing,” in whose reductive and nihilistic ontologies we all tend initially to
understand ourselves, owing to our current place in the “history of being”
(Seinsgeschichte), the historical succession of different ways of understanding “the being
of entities” that the later Heidegger discovers at the metaphysical core of the West.
(Heidegger’s later history of being designates the succession of historical epochs that take
shape around the different answers metaphysics gives us to the question of what it means
to be anything at all. These typically taken-for-granted, metaphysical answers to the
question of what it means to be profoundly shape the history of the West, in which, put
simply, to be an entity means, successively, to be a presocratic “whooshing-up” [phusis], a
medieval “creature” of God, a modern “object” for a subject to master and control, a late-
modern “resource” [“Bestand”] on standby for efûcient ordering and enhancement, or
even a postmodern, polysemic world-discloser, in tune with being’s inexhaustibility and
so seeking poetically to compose its polysemic disclosures meaningfully.) In Being and
Time, Heidegger has not yet situated his existential analysis “ontohistorically” (that is, in
terms of that later “history of being”), so his most famous early work suggests that all
typical adult humans are basically already Dasein (and just need to recognize that to
correct the philosophical errors that follow from modern subject/object dualism). The
early Heidegger thus lacks most of his later story about the transformative power of
metaphysics to reshape entire epochs of intelligibility (as I show in ch. 1 of Thomson,
Heidegger on Ontotheology). But for Heidegger, both early and late, there is still a sense in
which we need to doubly realize that we are Dasein (that is, both recognize what that
means and also embody that truth in our lives, so that we transformatively “become what
we are”), though the difûculties for and consequences of that double realization continue
to ramify dramatically as his thinking develops. In the end, however, these two views of
what it means to be “Dasein” (that is, his earlier, more descriptive view and his later, more
prescriptive one) are largely compatible, since the later view dramatically builds on and
complicates the earlier one. (If that were all the orthodox Heideggerians meant when they
asserted that the early and later Heidegger were just saying identical things in different
ways, then I would partly agree with them. They go much further, however, and assert
that Heidegger never changed his mind about what “being” [Sein] means, which is not
only false but deeply misleading, as we will see in Chapters 2 and 5.)