Eudaimonia Perspectives for Music Learning Gareth Dylan Smith 2024 scribd download
Eudaimonia Perspectives for Music Learning Gareth Dylan Smith 2024 scribd download
https://ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/eudaimonia-
perspectives-for-music-learning-gareth-dylan-
smith/
https://ebookgate.com/product/musimathics-the-mathematical-
foundations-of-music-volume-1-1st-edition-gareth-loy/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/musimathics-the-mathematical-
foundations-of-music-volume-1-1st-edition-gareth-loy-2/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/consciousness-new-philosophical-
perspectives-1st-edition-quentin-smith/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/french-music-since-berlioz-1st-edition-
richard-langham-smith-editor/
ebookgate.com
Essential Biology for Cambridge IGCSE 2nd Edition Gareth
Williams
https://ebookgate.com/product/essential-biology-for-cambridge-
igcse-2nd-edition-gareth-williams/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/perspectives-on-ontology-learning-1st-
edition-j-lehmann/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/music-neurology-and-neuroscience-
historical-connections-and-perspectives-first-edition-altenmuller/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/lennie-tristano-his-life-in-music-jazz-
perspectives-1st-edition-eunmi-shim/
ebookgate.com
Eudaimonia
Eudaimonia
Perspectives for Music Learning
Edited by Gareth Dylan Smith and Marissa Silverman
Eudaimonia
Perspectives for Music Learning
Reference
Randles, C. (2019). Routledge new directions in music education series. Retrieved
from: http://clintrandles.com/?page_id=89. [Accessed 7.12.2019].
1 Eudaimonia
Flourishing through Music Learning
Gareth Dylan Smith and Marissa Silverman
What is “Eudaimonia”?
In After virtue, philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre (2007) draws our attention to a
potential, fictional world in which our planet experiences “catastrophic”
environmental disasters, the cause of which are blamed on all scientists. The
result of such catastrophe is not only “riots,” but also the “laboratories are burnt
down, physicists are lynched, books and instruments are destroyed” (p. 1). Fur
thermore, in MacIntyre’s “imaginary” world, “a Know-Nothing political move
ment takes power” and removes science from the curriculum in schools and
universities, and imprisons and executes any scientists left in the world (p. 1).
MacIntyre continues to imagine further results of this, including but not limited
to an eventual reimagining of science based on half-truths which, in turn, would
promote pseudoscience and a language that is as imprecise as it is harmful. This
is not a wholly original premise. Dystopian writers have created similar-
sounding spaces (e.g., Brave new world, 1984, The handmaid’s tale).
Still, MacIntyre’s thought experiment reveals how easy it is to lose “our
comprehension, both theoretical and practical,” and, most importantly
perhaps, our morality (p. 2). And what might the more pernicious result of
this be? According to MacIntyre, in the end, unless we rightly understand the
world in which we live, and make value judgements that are ethically and
truthfully sound, we cannot have any hope of living humanistically or pur
posefully, or, in others words, virtuously. Where do we learn how to live
virtuously? According to MacIntyre—who interprets and expands upon Aris
totle and Thomas Aquinas—“it is always through the engagement” in “a
variety of practices, including those of making and sustaining families and
households, schools, clinics, and local forms of political community” that we
can reflect critically on what matters and determine how best to live (p. xv).
Furthermore, without living “virtuously”—living in a way that engenders
generosity of spirit and person—we run the risk of dismantling the import
ance of asking truly essential questions: “Why?” Why live? Why make
music? Why teach and learn anything?
2 G. D. Smith and M. Silverman
In offering some potential answers to these questions, this volume rests on
the premise that the purpose of engagement in/with/through music making—
and music teaching and learning—widely seen across a variety of community
music sites, programs, and formal school environments—is to engage and
pursue lifelong fulfillment and flourishing and, in doing so, to live a “good
life,” a life of meaningfulness and significance (Silverman, 2013). But what
does it mean to live a “good life”?
As some of the chapters in this volume propose, the answer to this ques
tion involves the concept of eudaimonia. This Greek term derives from “eu,”
meaning “good” or “well,” and “daimon” meaning “a spirit,” or “one’s per
sonal fortune.” Literally, then, it means something like “having a good
guardian spirit,” or “a good divine power,” or “good fortune.” Time and
again, eudaimonia is translated as “happiness.” But, as Gordon Graham
(2011) notes, this translation is not very helpful (p. 47). Moreover, interpret
ing Aristotle, Graham explains that well-being is often “misconceived as
mere contentment.” Rather, he states, a sense of well-being in this context is
exercising “healthy appetites, imaginative and productive use of one’s mental
faculties, and the establishment of good personal, professional, and public
relationships” (pp. 47–48). “Eudaimonia,” then, is most often translated as
“human flourishing,” which requires deeper consideration (Elliott & Silver
man, 2014, 2015).
According to Aristotelian ethics, human flourishing and self-reflective
happiness are the rewards of a life of virtue. Aristotle states, “The human
good turns out to be the soul’s activity that expresses virtue, and if there is
more than one virtue … it will be in a complete life” (Nicomachean Ethics,
pp. 1098a2, 12–21). As Graham continues, eudaimonia helps to explain the
nature of a person’s life filled with “active engagement, rather than passive
experience” (p. 47). For Aristotle, eudaimonia describes people possessing
“excellence,” meaning those who live for the betterment of themselves and
their community, thus maintaining a feeling of contentment, well-being, and
comfort. Human flourishing and, thereby, well-being can be achieved when
one lives for the betterment of oneself and one’s community. This notion of
the “good life” and, therefore, “well-being” is at the heart of “artistry” and
what it means to rightly live in the world with others (e.g., Wiles, 2016).
Still, commonplace interpretations of eudaimonia—e.g., first-person
“happiness” and self-centered flourishing—denote “arguably an ideologically
liberal and, indeed, neoliberal stance inherent in [a] eudaimonic lifestyle and
philosophy” (Smith, 2016, p. 162). Understanding eudaimonism as concerned
only or primarily with seeking purpose and meaning in one’s own life (Dier
endonck & Mohan, 2006; Norton, 1976; Waterman, 1992), while consistent
with an ideology pervading certainly the USA and increasingly in other con
temporary Western nation states, “contradicts Aristotle’s definition of eudai
monia as the fulfillment of one’s deepest nature in harmony with the
Eudaimonia: Flourishing through Learning 3
collective welfare” (Della Fave, Brdar, Friere, Vella-Brodrick, & Wissing,
2011, p. 204). Therefore, it is eudaimonism in its fuller, most generous form,
for which the authors in this volume advocate. Why? Increased emphasis on
individualism and isolation, instead of community and collaboration, can lead
to the death of democracy and the rise of narcissists and ignorant populists
whose hunger for power threatens to harm millions of people, almost indis
criminately (Levitsky & Ziblatt, 2018). The current fashion for selfishness,
myopia, and willful ignorance threatens to undermine the chances of human
civilization—in anything like its current forms—surviving at all (Orr, this
volume). These pernicious ideologies perpetuated by a powerful few (Giroux,
this volume; Sachs, 2019; Wilson & Pickett, 2019) are incredibly challeng
ing, but hopefully not insurmountable obstacles to realizing a more utopian
vision for a world guided more by compassion and eudaimonic thriving.
1. Understanding that the world is horribly unjust and that recognizing our
place in the global system of brutal capitalist plutocracy may help us to
envision and act for a more equitable and just world;
2. Taking part in music-making activity that curates mutually flourishing
communities where individuals and the collective flourish and thrive and
feel the meaningfulness created by and for one another; and
3. Curating spaces for music making, where flourishing through learning is
the primary objective.
An ethic of care for others is a vital part of embracing and living eudaimonia.
Karin Hendricks’ (2018) approach to music learning thus resonates with
eudaimonia, as an ethos characterized by “compassion … a relationship of
experience-sharing in which one might offer support to another based on a
shared understanding of feelings, hopes, and/or desires” (p. 5). Higgins
(2007), drawing on Lenk (2006), describes communities of music making in
which “members are responsible for each other without their personal or indi
vidual responsibilities being reduced” (p. 87). David Elliott, Marissa Silver
man, and Wayne Bowman (2016) describe something similar, invoking
Eudaimonia: Flourishing through Learning 7
music-making and learning as a form of “ethically guided citizenship” (p. 6,
emphasis in original), based on the premise that “artistry involves civic-
social-humanistic-emancipatory responsibilities, obligations to engage in art
making that advances social ‘goods’ ” (Elliott, Silverman, & Bowman, 2016,
p. 7). One of the fundamental premises of a eudaimonic orientation is that
music and music learning can serve and epitomize human flourishing. The
power of music to engender feelings of competence, agency, and community
is extraordinary. Music is certainly not uniquely capable in this regard, but
we believe, and hope readers may find too, that thinking and acting with
eudaimonia is invigorating and exciting.
The notion that each of us should be able to flourish, and not be subject to
conditions preventing us from doing so, is a key tenet of anarchism (Bakunin,
1972; Chomsky, 2013; Rocker, 1938). Noam Chomsky (2013) invokes
Rudolf Rocker (1938) to explain how contemporary anarchism embraces the
eudaimonic dyad of flourishing of the self and others, describing it as the con
fluence of liberalism and socialism. As a politically motivated, socially con
scious alternative construal of educational purpose and praxis, Allan Antliff
(2012) describes “anarchist pedagogy” as concerned with “subverting and
transcending oppressive social formations” (p. 328). He further explains that:
In the context of the stifling global neoliberal consensus, “anarchy is the polit
ical blank slate of the early twenty-first century. It is shorthand for an eternal
now, for a chance to reset the clock” (Schneider, 2013, p. ix). Ruth Wright
(2019) considers the implications of anarchism for music learning, rooting
her concerns in the need to act to challenge the devastation being wrought on
education systems by rampant neoliberalism. Citing Geoffrey Baker (2014),
Wright (2019) looks at diverse music-making practices that occur outside of
schooling institutions and suggests, “we music-makers might perhaps always
have been anarchists at heart and perhaps our mistake has been to try to sys
tematise and codify these practices within education” (p. 221).
All music-making and music-learning practices are to an extent codified
and systematized (Cremata, Pignato, Powell, & Smith, 2018; Hebert, Abramo,
& Smith, 2017), in order to be recognized as practices. Notwithstanding these
semantics, it is an alluring conviction – that empowering, agentive, demo
cratic music learning may only be possible in small anarchist communities
(inside or outside of schools) that are able to resist the imperatives and pres
sures of oppressive hegemonic power. Or at least it may be more possible to
8 G. D. Smith and M. Silverman
achieve flourishing—eudaimonia—for individuals and groups in anarchist
settings. The idea of anarchist music learning communities recalls the polis—
the ancient Greek context in which Aristotle defined and for which he envi
sioned eudaimonia. Perhaps it is not possible for all members of society to
thrive in so big and unlikely and diverse a conglomerate as a modern nation
state such as the US. Under one flag, people are supposed to share values and
ideals but there is such great richness and diversity of wealth, experience, and
culture that to suggest we can all thrive under the banner of a nation state is
absurd.
* * *
Dylan van der Schyff describes a recent move from Enlightenment aesthetics
and a “technological enframing” of music education toward an increased
focus on collaboration and musical activity construed as positive social inter
action. van der Schyff explains various ancient Greek understandings of
knowledge and ways of being, travelling through phusis, poiesis, and ekstasis
before lighting on phronesis, which describes a caring disposition. This con
nects with orexis—how humans reach out to the world and to nature to make
meaning. The author argues that music learning, conceived as socially ori
ented musical praxes, is essential to humanity.
The aims and achievements of Jane Addams’s Hull House and Hull House
Music School provide the springboard for Marissa Silverman’s examination
of the actual and potential relationships that can be created among music,
social ethics, politics, and citizenship. After probing several dimensions of
Addams’s achievements, her work is considered next to the writings of John
Dewey (who was largely influenced by Addams) and several of today’s
leading feminist theorists. The work of these feminist scholars is especially
important in building a more nuanced and balanced understanding of the
“ethics of care” that underpinned Addams’s musical-communal-ethical work
and, today, points us toward a robust concept of democratic school and com
munity music education.
Kathleen Dean Moore’s chapter recounts her experiment keeping brief
notes over a 12-month period, documenting experiences that made her feel
happy. This essay reads as a brief clutch of beautiful, deeply personal recol
lections, detailing the meaningful, surprising, and mundane. Moore lists
things that made her feel truly happy, indicates necessary conditions for
enabling these, and lists recurring themes. Overlapping with other chapters in
the book, happiness themes including contact with the natural world, stimu
lating ideas, meaningful work, celebratory arts, and time to pause, reflect, and
enjoy. The editors gratefully acknowledge permission granted by Shambhala
to reproduce this essay that first appeared in Wild comfort: The solace of
nature (2010).
Environmentalist David W. Orr discusses the possibility of eudaimonia by
reminding readers that the human race is rushing headlong toward cata
strophic climate change. Prioritizing consumerism, greed, and isolation, our
species is increasingly disconnected from understandings of “biophilia” and
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
“No! why not? Do you think yourself better than other children?”
No answer.
“Is it because people tell you you are rich, you won’t play?”
The young lady was gone. He stretched his hand to arrest her, but
she wheeled beyond his reach, and ran quickly out of sight.
“An only child,” pleaded Miss Wilcox; “possibly spoiled by her
papa, you know; we must excuse a little pettishness.”
“Humph! I am afraid there is not a little to excuse.”
CHAPTER II.