40666
40666
com
https://ebookultra.com/download/arguments-about-
arguments-first-edition-maurice-a-finocchiaro/
https://ebookultra.com/download/the-routledge-guidebook-to-galileo-s-
dialogue-1st-edition-maurice-a-finocchiaro/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/the-logic-of-real-arguments-2nd-
edition-alec-fisher/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/external-arguments-in-transitivity-
alternations-a-layering-approach-2nd-impression-edition-alexiadou/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/theories-of-development-contentions-
arguments-alternatives-3rd-edition-richard-peet/
ebookultra.com
Arguments for a Better World Essays in Honor of Amartya
Sen Kaushik Basu
https://ebookultra.com/download/arguments-for-a-better-world-essays-
in-honor-of-amartya-sen-kaushik-basu/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/companions-in-guilt-arguments-in-
metaethics-1st-edition-christopher-cowie-editor/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/logic-and-theism-arguments-for-and-
against-beliefs-in-god-sobel/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/attacking-faulty-reasoning-a-
practical-guide-to-fallacy-free-arguments-6th-edition-t-edward-damer/
ebookultra.com
MAURICE A. FINOCCHIARO
University of Nevada, Las Vegas
C Maurice A. Finocchiaro 2005
A catalog record for this publication is available from the British Library.
Contents
vi Contents
vii
1 The first definition given by the Oxford English Dictionary for the word “informal” is: “Not
done or made according to a recognized or prescribed form; not observing forms; not
according to order; irregular; unofficial, disorderly” (1933 edition, vol. 5, p. 273).
2 Here I am thinking of the interpretation given in Woods 1980. Woods is certainly right
to distinguish between two senses of “formal”: (1) the use of formal, mathematical, or
symbolic techniques, and (2) formalization or the construction of logistic or axiomatic
systems (p. 58). He is also correct in noting that, from the point of view of (2), even
mathematics is typically informal; and so he is merely advocating (1). Nevertheless, it is
questionable whether this can escape the present difficulty.
3 What I mean here is that if we take the label “informal logic” too seriously, and then we
try to examine its meaning and uses, we could not ignore the sense given to the term in
21
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
22 Theorizing about Reasoning and Argument
2. Clarifications
Let me begin by clarifying my definition of the theory of reasoning. First,
notice that I speak of reasoning, rather than, for example, argumentation;
this is deliberately meant to allow a broader domain, by including, be-
sides the study of arguments, such activities as problem-solving, decision-
making, persuasion, and explaining, which cannot be equated with ar-
gumentation, but which may involve reasoning in an essential way. The
emphasis on reasoning is also meant as a reminder that what is being
studied here is a mental activity that actually occurs in the world and
which leaves empirical traces (normally in the form of written or oral dis-
course). This in turn means that the theory of reasoning has an empirical
orientation and is not a purely formal or abstract discipline.
Second, you should notice my explicit reference to the interpretation of
reasoning. This is needed partly for the intrinsic reason that such interpre-
tation aims at the understanding of reasoning, and the understanding of
Ryle 1954. For Ryle informal logic is essentially identical to ordinary-language philosophy,
or to be more exact, to the analysis of the “logic” of concepts like pleasure, memory,
responsibility, chance; whereas formal logic is the study of concepts such as “all,” “some,”
“not,” etc.
4 In speaking of the theoretical concerns of “informal logicians,” I mean to distinguish them
from practical concerns. In fact, as Michael Scriven stressed at the Second International
Symposium on Informal Logic, informal logic cannot be equated with the theory of
reasoning simpliciter, any more than medicine can be equated with the theory of healing;
just as medicine includes the activity of actually curing diseases, so informal logic refers to
the activity of formulating actual arguments. What this means is that informal logic must
be taken to refer both to the theory and practice of reasoning. This, in turn, introduces
further complications, some of which will be discussed below, toward the end. For other
developments, see Finocchiaro 1980b, especially pp. 299–302, where a different twist is
given to Scriven’s point, by introducing the notion of reasoning about reasoning, as a helpful
way of combining the theory and the practice of reasoning.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
Informal Logic and the Theory of Reasoning 23
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
24 Theorizing about Reasoning and Argument
8 Johnstone 1978.
9 Hintikka 1974.
10 L. J. Cohen 1977; 1981b.
11 Johnson 1981a.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
Informal Logic and the Theory of Reasoning 25
12 McPeck 1981, especially pp. 84–85. McPeck is directly concerned with teaching, and so
he might not endorse my adaptation of his criticism to the context of theorizing. The
same qualification applies to some of the other objections discussed below which stem
from his book.
13 McPeck 1981, 84–85.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
26 Theorizing about Reasoning and Argument
other words, these critics ignore the fact (which they themselves admit14 )
that “reasoning” is both a task and an achievement term; to engage in
reasoning does not necessarily imply to be successful at it. This means
that, at worst, what’s impossible is a general theory of correct reasoning,
and not necessarily a general interpretative theory of the structure of
reasoning. However, even the limited pessimistic conclusion seems ex-
cessively apriorist, since, given that it would allow for limited theories of
correct reasoning in particular fields, there is no a priori reason to pre-
dict that the further generalization and systematization of these limited
theories will necessarily fail. Moreover, the notion of a field of reasoning
is problematic,15 and the same criticism made against the possibility of
generalizations among fields could be leveled against the possibility of
generalizing within a given field, which after all consists of various sub-
fields. Finally, it is possible that a general theory of evaluation might be
based in part on a general theory of interpretation, whose possibility, as
we have seen, is untouched by the present criticism. But this brings us
to the question of what all types and instances of reasoning have in com-
mon, and it is here that my constructive suggestion becomes relevant. I
think that the essential feature of all reasoning is the interrelating of in-
dividual thoughts in such a way that some follow from others,16 and that
the normal linguistic expression of such interrelated thinking involves
the use of particles like ‘because,’ ‘therefore,’ etc. However minimal this
conception is, it allows the theory of reasoning to get started by suggest-
ing that we try to understand and to evaluate those discourses having a
high incidence of these logical particles.
If this first objection to the legitimacy of the theory of reasoning threat-
ens to deprive it of a genuine subject matter, a second criticism threatens
to let a discipline other than philosophy lay claim upon that domain. The
objection would now be that there already exists a branch of cognitive
psychology, namely the psychology of reasoning, that theorizes about the
phenomenon in an a posteriori fashion. What then is the difference, if
any, between the psychology of reasoning and the philosophical theory of
reasoning?
Let me begin answering this objection by noting that at a phenomeno-
logical level there are certainly some differences. To be specific, psychol-
ogists tend to be experimental, to refrain from explicit evaluation, and to
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
Informal Logic and the Theory of Reasoning 27
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
28 Theorizing about Reasoning and Argument
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
Informal Logic and the Theory of Reasoning 29
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
30 Theorizing about Reasoning and Argument
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
Informal Logic and the Theory of Reasoning 31
are such people as Galileo, Newton, Lavoisier, and Einstein, whereas the
most outstanding theorists of science are such people as Bacon, Peirce,
Duhem, Popper, etc.; in politics we find, on the one hand, Pericles, Caesar
Augustus, Jefferson, Disraeli, etc., and on the other hand, Aristotle,
Machiavelli, Tocqueville, etc.; in morality, one group would include
Socrates, St. Francis, Gandhi, etc., the other Aristotle, Kant, Bentham,
etc. Why should we expect the situation to be any different in the do-
main of our present interest?
This difficulty can also be elaborated in another way. From the point of
view of reasoning, the theory of reasoning is at best an instance of a spe-
cial kind of reasoning, namely reasoning about reasoning. What reason is
there to think that if one becomes proficient in reasoning about reason-
ing, one will be also proficient in reasoning about atoms and molecules,
torts and contracts, personal and emotional problems, affirmative action
and nuclear deterrence, etc.? When expressed in these terms, this objec-
tion may be reminiscent of the earlier one about whether there is any such
thing as reasoning in general. However, what we have here is a new diffi-
culty, since we are now asking whether there is any significant similarity
between, for example, reasoning about reasoning and reasoning about
atoms and molecules, whereas earlier we were asking whether there is any
significant similarity between such things as reasoning about atoms and
molecules and reasoning about torts and contracts. Someone could ad-
mit that there are significant similarities among fields at the object level,
but not between the object level and the metalevel, or one might think
that each field is significantly different from each other, but argue that,
for example, object-level reasoning about atoms and metalevel reasoning
about reasoning about atoms do not constitute two different fields. But
the transference between these two levels is what the present objection
questions, or to be more exact, the transference from the higher into the
lower level.
In order to begin answering this objection, I would want to say that
the divergence between theory and practice mentioned above does not
show that the theoretical reflections of the practitioners, or the actual
behavior of the theorists, are inadequate, but only that normally they do
not excel. Second, even from the point of view of excellence, there are ex-
ceptions to this generalization. For example, Socrates is not only a model
of moral life, but a brilliant ethical theorist; Galileo is not only “the father
of modern science,” but also an acute methodological theorist; and both
Socrates and Galileo were nonnegligible theorists of reasoning, as well as
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
32 Theorizing about Reasoning and Argument
4. Summary
To sum up, I have addressed myself to the problem of giving a positive,
constructive, and self-sufficient interpretation of informal logic, by view-
ing it as a philosophical approach to the theory of reasoning. I began
by defining the theory of reasoning in such a way as to avoid apriorism,
excessive evaluationism, dogmatic universalism, and premature systemati-
zation. And then I defended the viability, the philosophical character, and
the methodological legitimacy of the theory of reasoning so conceived by
defending it from a number of objections. These were the criticisms that
its defining subject matter – reasoning – is perhaps a fictitious one; that
even if reasoning is not a fictitious subject matter, it can be studied only
by a branch of cognitive psychology; that even if there is a distinct, philo-
sophical way of studying reasoning, this is not a discipline that can be
taken seriously, as the difficulties afflicting argument analysis show; and
finally, that at any rate, the practical import of the theory of reasoning is
26 The case of Socrates is, of course, well known, while for the case of Galileo the thesis is
demonstrated in Finocchiaro 1980b.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
Informal Logic and the Theory of Reasoning 33
27 Notice that I speak of overlap, and not of identity, partly because, as clarified earlier,
informal logic has a practical component which cannot be completely reduced to the
theoretical one, even when the latter is required to include the elaboration of principles
for the sound practice of reasoning.
28 Cf. Finocchiaro 1981, where it is argued that the theories of fallacies prevalent among
informal logicians are contributions (of various worth) to the theory of the evaluation
of reasoning.
29 A possible example might be to elaborate the “informal logic” aspect of a work like
Finocchiaro 1980b; cf. Johnson and Blair 1985.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:34:52, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.003
2
1 This may be regarded as being in the tradition of Toulmin, who was explicit that “not
only will logic have to become more empirical; it will inevitably tend to become more
historical. . . . In the natural sciences, for instance, men such as Kepler, Newton, Lavoisier,
Darwin and Freud have transformed not only our beliefs, but also our way of arguing and
our standards of relevance and proof” (1958, 257). There are differences, however. For
example Toulmin’s thesis here is primarily a metalogical claim, whereas mine bypasses
issues in the philosophy of logic as such. And his conception of ‘historical’ here seems
to refer primarily to notions of evolutionary development, emergence of novelty, and
absence of eternal absolutes, whereas mine emphasizes merely the past, the naturally
occurring, and the observational.
2 Here I am thinking of a work like Kalish et al. 1980, whereas Tarski 1965 may be regarded
as a semi-empirical approach to mathematical reasoning, and Jeffrey 1967 a relatively
autonomous and self-contained investigation.
34
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:36:08, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.004
Historical Approach to the Study of Argumentation 35
3 See, for example, Wason and Johnson-Laird 1972, Johnson-Laird and Wason 1977, and
Evans (1982; 1983c).
4 In Finocchiaro (1979b; 1980b, 256–72) I argued for the superiority of the historical
approach by exploring some difficulties in the otherwise important work in the psy-
chology of reasoning by Wason and Johnson-Laird (1972). In a recent paper, Wason
(1983) has replied to some of my criticism and has thrown some new light on the spe-
cific experimental phenomenon that had occasioned my criticism, that is the so-called
“Watson’s four-card problem.” Nevertheless, I am not sure that the methodological issue
is significantly affected. If we take the issue to be that of experimental versus historical-
observational approach, I would now want to strengthen my argument in two ways, which,
ironically, would utilize ideas and arguments advanced by other cognitive psychologists.
One would be what I take to be a central point in Byrne 1983, namely that if we
reject the use of subjects’ “protocols” as explanations of their performance, and regard
them merely as data, then they can function to provide more stringent tests for theoretical
claims. Another would be to exploit some of the conclusions found in Evans (1982; 1983b;
1983c). His work is too important and controversial for any one-sentence summary, and it
certainly deserves extended critical scrutiny. Nevertheless, at the risk of oversimplification
I will say that he criticizes the “rationalist” approach in the experimental psychology of
reasoning, and he engages in an impressive constructive attempt to interpret such exper-
imental data along the lines of general cognitive psychology, using notions and activities
like perception, memory, and at times even purely statistical scholastic considerations.
From this it is a short step to conclude that psychologists’ reasoning experiments have
not really been testing reasoning and argumentation, but other cognitive activities, so
that if it is the study of reasoning and argumentation that we are dealing with, then the
experimental approach has been shown to have severe limitations indeed. Needless to
say, this methodological issue deserves further discussion, and I will tackle it more fully
on some other occasion.
5 This is not to say, of course, that even among philosophers the empirical emphasis is
totally absent. In fact, the recent emergence of what is sometimes called “informal logic”
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:36:08, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.004
36 Theorizing about Reasoning and Argument
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:36:08, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.004
Historical Approach to the Study of Argumentation 37
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The Librarian-Seeley Historical Library, on 30 Nov 2019 at 13:36:08, subject to the
Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511527517.004
Other documents randomly have
different content
with active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or
expense to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or
a means of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original
“Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must
include the full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in
paragraph 1.E.1.
• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive
from the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”
• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.
1.F.
1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.
Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.
Our website is not just a platform for buying books, but a bridge
connecting readers to the timeless values of culture and wisdom. With
an elegant, user-friendly interface and an intelligent search system,
we are committed to providing a quick and convenient shopping
experience. Additionally, our special promotions and home delivery
services ensure that you save time and fully enjoy the joy of reading.
ebookultra.com