Microeconomics Ch 1_ Preferences
Microeconomics Ch 1_ Preferences
Saba Yifredew
Department of Economics
Addis Ababa University
Email: [email protected]
Consumer theory
Introduction
• Central assumption in the theory of the consumer: optimization
• “Given the feasible set of consumption bundles, the bundle chosen is
the one the consumer prefers”
• A three-steps analysis:
1. How to model the consumer’s preferences?
2. What are the feasible consumption bundles?
3. What is (are) the best consumption bundle(s) among all feasible
consumption bundles?
Why is the choice essential in the study of
economics?
• How do people make choices?
• Is there a pattern in choice making?
• How do we impact choices? Do we need to ?
How do incentives affect choices?
Most notable incentives prices, tax
Moral incentives: Society, culture, norms, moral appeals
Coercive incentives: Punishment
Remunerative incentives: Material rewards
The traditional approach to consumer behavior is to
assume that
Rules out thickness of indifference curve : We preclude the possibility that the
consumer can even imagine having all his wants and whims for commodities completely
satisfied.)
It rules out the possibility of having ‘zones of indifference’, such as that surrounding 𝑥 1
(See previous fig)
Axioms of consumer choice: Local non-satiation
• If the indifference curves were thick, as in above figure, then there
would be points such as x, where in its neighborhood (the dotted circle)
all points are indifferent to x
• Local non-satiation does not rule out the possibility that the preferred
alternative may involve less of some or even all commodities.
Note: The indifference set is the intersection of the upper and lower contour
sets.
Question on preference relation
Q. Prove that if ≿ is rational, then ∼ is transitive, that is, x ∼ y and y ∼ z
implies x ∼ z.
Solution
For x ∼ z, we must show x ≿ z and z ≿ x
We need to prove that x ∼ y and y ∼ z implies x ∼ z if ≿ is rational.
• We know that x ∼ y is equivalent to x ≿ y and y ≿ x.
• Similarly, y ∼ z is equivalent to y ≿ z and z ≿ y.
• Hence, know x ≿ y and y ≿ z. Using the transitivity of ≿ , it implies that x
≿ z. But we have z ≿ y and y ≿ x.
• The transitivity of ≿ therefore implies that, z ≿ x.
• But x ≿ z and z ≿ x is exactly x ∼ z, hence proved
The Utility Function