texto 01 TNOS-Ch-1
texto 01 TNOS-Ch-1
Douglas Allchin
ISBN 978-0-9892524-0-9
| Contents
Preface ix
Part I: Perspectives
1. The Nature of Science: From Test Tubes to YouTube 3
2. History as a Tool 28
3. Myth-Conceptions 46
4. How Not to Teach History in Science 77
5. Pseudohistory and Pseudoscience 93
6. Sociology, Too 107
7. Kettlewell’s Missing Evidence: A Study in Black and White 121
8. Teaching Lawless Science 133
9. Nature of Science in an Age of Accountability 152
Notes 259
References 273
Acknowledgements 301
Index 303
| Preface
ix
x | preface
My aim here is not to survey the vast knowledge of the history, philosophy,
and sociology of science (HPSS), although such knowledge is, in a sense,
foundational. Nor is my aim to profile basic scientific methodology, or the
principles of “good science,” particularly in contrast to pseudoscience or
fraud. These approaches to learning NOS focus on content, too, but of a
different kind. They are relatively unhelpful as an introduction.
Rather, my aim is how one can foster the development of thinking
skills: ways to analyze and reflect fruitfully about NOS. The goal is for the
teacher to develop a knack for delving into NOS and asking important NOS
questions. Given a particular case, is one able to notice and highlight the
relevant dimensions of science that affect the reliability of the claims? Can
one interpret and articulate their significance? Can one identify further
information that will deepen that understanding? The target is thus a
repertoire of tools in NOS inquiry, not declarative knowledge. Ideally,
a prepared teacher will be equipped to (1) serve as an explicit model for
students, (2) guide others in their own emerging efforts, and (3) reflect
further and continue to learn about the nature of science.
This strategy involves, in part, engaging the reader in new and different
perspectives. To expand one’s analytical repertoire, one needs to open
new ways of seeing. Some things may have always been there to see. By
recognizing how to notice them, one can appreciate their significance more
fully. One needs to learn, in a sense, how to probe the nature of science and
to pose the appropriate questions.
Accordingly, the style of presentation here is chiefly by illustration, or
demonstration through cases. Perspectives are exhibited and articulated.
There are no formal abstract principles to elucidate, no arguments to master
or dissect, no lists to memorize. This book does not resemble a conventional
textbook in that sense, even while it endeavors to guide deep and meaningful
learning. In style, it follows basic findings in cognitive science. Learning, here,
is fostered through anomalies and paradigmatic exemplars and generalizing
from them.
Of course, NOS conceptions abound among teachers and students,
even without any explicit instruction. So cases that illustrate commonplace
notions or conceptions already entrenched in our culture are not, in general,
addressed here. At the same time, many widespread NOS conceptions—
including those entrenched in the culture of teaching—are ill informed. There
is much to unlearn about NOS. One must separate the wheat from the chaff.
The focus here is thus selective, especially in targeting caricatures and naive
conceptions. Further, in adopting a pedagogical constructivist perspective,
most examples mindfully challenge the NOS preconceptions that are ill
informed. Other examples consider teaching methods that seem intuitive
to some but that, ironically, prove ineffective or even counterproductive. The
overall posture may seem critical. Still, the intent is to motivate reflection
and conceptual growth. Individually and collectively, the essays may seem to
preface | xi
challenge many assumptions or practices. Yet this is precisely where one may
expect genuine learning to occur.
The book is also incomplete in many ways. Learning involves
engagement. Thus, ideally, the reader will couple reading of the text with
an extended exploration of at least one case in the history of science. The
perspectives introduced here become vivid when applied to and measured
against real science. Appreciation of the many dimensions of NOS will be
greatly enhanced by familiarity with the concrete details of one case. This,
too, follows an educational approach that highlights the value of depth.
Some educators believe that the primary or best way to learn about
scientific practice is to become a scientist oneself. Yet this may overstate the
goal. Yes, every individual should develop some basic investigative skills that
enable them to troubleshoot a lamp that does not light, say. They should be
able to read simple graphs and evaluate simple data charts. But dealing with
evidence at an elementary level is not sufficient for interpreting most science
today: for example, the complexities of climate change models, or vast meta-
analyses of the significance of mammograms at different ages. Students, like
scientists themselves, must rely on the expertise of others. One must learn
to be a prudent consumer of science: interpreting the difference between
science that is well done and that which should be regarded skeptically or
jettisoned outright. The relevant dimensions of scientific practice extend well
beyond what one might expect individual students to perform themselves.
One may develop an understanding of the practice of science in many
ways. The primary ways are through (1) a student’s own labs or inquiry
activities, (2) contemporary case studies, and (3) historical case studies.
I will not have much to say about student investigations: this is familiar
territory for most teachers (including from their experience as students).
My primary focus is the role of historical cases (see Chapter 2). Indeed, I
contend that deeper appreciation of historical case studies—when styled in
an inquiry mode or problem-based format (Chapter 14)—provide deeper,
more complete lessons. Indeed, they may well inform how a practicing
teacher guides student reflection in the other two formats.
Another major emphasis in contemporary discussions of NOS education
is profiling the nature of models and the process of model building. The
theme has an important deflationary function, qualifying widely held
popular views of the monumentality of scientific theories. Models have been
and continue to be important tools in science. But not all science is model
driven or explanatory in nature (see Chapter 1). The current enthusiasm
for models carries the traces of a short-lived educational fad. One would
do well to disregard the hype and focus just on the enduring features of
models that have been acknowledged by philosophers of science for decades
(see Chapter 8). Thus, while a model-based perspective complements and
provides an important context for the themes discussed in this volume, I
leave the articulation of that theme to others.
xii | preface
Nearly all the material in this book has been published elsewhere. It
seemed appropriate, however, to bring it together in a single volume and
present it as a coherent constellation. In addition, I have rewritten and
updated every chapter to convey a more unified vision of teaching the
nature of science. I have added cross-references and additional comments
to underscore their integrated themes and enhance their integrity as an
ensemble. In particular, I address topics that are overlooked elsewhere and
stress themes that probe common yet misleading cultural conceptions.
It is not a comprehensive, “textbook” introduction to the field. Still, one
should find the basic tools for NOS reflection here, along with methods
for empowering students with those tools, to promote self-guided NOS
learning.
In assembling this volume, I have drawn on a unique cross section of
experience in science teaching, scientific research, and advanced study in the
history and philosophy of science. I taught high school biology for several
years, both introductory and AP levels, and later introductory college biology
at several institutions. One interdisciplinary science course was structured as
an episodic history of science, supplemented with historically inspired labs.
I have also participated in research at three biological field stations: looking
at treegaps and forest succession in a mid-Atlantic forest; mapping long-
term succession in a tropical rainforest; and measuring sexual selection in
flowers through the differential transfer of pollen in meadows of the Rocky
Mountains. I certainly recommend to any science teacher the exhilarating
and enriching experience of living and working in a research community for
a season. My own work for a master’s degree in evolutionary biology focused
on a mathematical model for information-center foraging, such as one
finds in honeybee hives, ant societies, and many bird colonies. I couple this
firsthand experience with a Ph.D. in the history and philosophy of science
from the University of Chicago—and I continue to publish scholarly articles
in these fields (from the Dictionary of Scientific Biography and an examination
of eighteenth-century geologist James Hutton’s views on coal, to analyses
of disagreement in science, error types, and the conceptual dilemmas of
Mendelian dominance). Many of my students in undergraduate history
and philosophy-of-science classes have been en route to careers in science
teaching, and it is rewarding to shepherd them to deeper understanding
of, and reflection on, scientific practice. Through these diverse experiences,
I have gained immense respect for science teachers, scientific researchers,
historians, philosophers and sociologists of science, and, above all, students. I
hope the present volume offers a fruitful synthesis, integrating and honoring
these multiple contexts.
The contents of this book are presented in two sections. In the first, I
provide perspectives for deepening an awareness and appreciation of NOS.
The second section profiles some sample classroom case studies in several
disciplines, each with supplemental pedagogical commentary.
preface | xiii
us rethink these widely accepted but misleading truisms about science. They
help illustrate the importance of reflecting on the nature of science, even
about commonplaces we may at first consider beyond question. Thus we
may begin to clear the field and open fruitful exploration. Readers anxious
for a more positively expressed view—where this preliminary skepticism
leads us—may prefer to jump ahead to the subsequent three sections on
characterizing the scope of NOS in science education, especially in the
context of functional scientific literacy as profiled in this opening. Namely,
what do we need to teach? The final section introduces the guiding notion
of Whole Science and helps map out the issues addressed in the remaining
chapters: how does one deepen an understanding of scientific practice and
help students develop similar skills in analysis and reflection?
The Demarcation Project
The first impulse—common among students, at least—may be to rush to a
dictionary for a clear definition of science. Of course, dictionaries define the
use of words only. They do not articulate concepts. Still, the common urge
is telling. It reflects a number of tendencies and unschooled beliefs. First,
many assume that the world is organized so as to yield quick, easy, and clear
answers. Second, problems are to be solved by external authorities. Third,
science is an abstract concept that can be stipulated, rather than a human
activity that is to be interpreted or understood. There is great faith that a
simple factor distinguishes science as a special form of knowledge.
Philosophers of science have duly considered this challenge, known as
the demarcation problem. But without clear success. Early efforts were largely
motivated by ideological distaste for Marxism and psychoanalysis. Each
claimed to be empirical and thus “scientific.” Many prominent philosophers
did not want to share the privileged status of science with such allegedly
wrong-headed pursuits. They sought criteria by which to exclude them.
One effort focused on logic, which could be imbued with mathematical
certainty. Yet while one might hope to express a theory and its derivative
concepts in a rigorous logical framework, observations themselves have no
logical structure. Linking them securely and unambiguously to linguistic or
mathematical expressions proved difficult. The effort failed.
Another effort to demarcate science focused on verifiability. Only
claims that could be verified by observation would count as science. Yet that
seemed to exclude all kinds of unobservables and theoretical entities, such as
atoms, magnetic fields, and genes. Reasoning about unrepeatable historical
events, whether in geology, cosmology, or evolutionary biology, also seemed
problematic. So that criterion fell by the wayside as well.
Yet another proposal focused on science as uniquely progressive. The
cumulative growth of knowledge in science seemed intuitive. Even today,
students tend to regard science as synonymous with progress. However, in
many scientific revolutions, scientists seemed to jettison former knowledge
6 | from test tubes to youtube
in favor of new approaches that did not fully replace them. We no longer
talk of phlogiston, caloric, electrical fluid, or worldwide floods. We no longer
discuss chemical affinities, pangenes, bodily humors, or fixed continents. All
of these were once widely accepted concepts. Even the apparently secure
universality of Newton’s laws was abandoned in favor of relativity; they did
not apply to very light or very fast bodies. One more demarcation criterion
for the creative wastebin.
Other ways of defining progress proved equally elusive. A later
perspective focused on growth in the ability to solve problems. But
clearly defining a problem or solution proved no easier. In addition, some
acknowledged sciences, such as mineralogy, taxonomy, and astronomy,
focused on documenting or collecting information about the natural world,
not solving problems.
And so on.
The successive failures to demarcate science are now deeply informative.
First, they help demonstrate that the reliability of knowledge so commonly
associated with science is not simple. One needs to clarify the often arbitrary
connections between phenomena and the terms one uses to discuss them.
One needs to be mindful of theoretical context in interpreting observations.
One needs to ascertain the limited scope of concepts. One needs to consider
the value of theories in guiding further research as well as explaining existing
results. Reflection on scientific reasoning has sharpened how scientists think
and communicate.
With the privilege of retrospect, one may also wonder: what motivated
the repeatedly unsuccessful efforts to define science? Ultimately, the project
aimed not only to characterize science but also to distinguish it. Indeed,
special distinction was central. Each proposed nature of science was imbued
with value. A positive value. The role of demarcation was not neutral. It was
normative.
Philosophers did not endeavor to describe science as it is. Rather, they
rendered an idealized version of science. We want science to be logical. We
want science to be progressive. We want observation to be independent
of theoretical perspective. It makes the task of justifying and interpreting
scientific knowledge much easier. It is a tribute to science, perhaps, that
it has achieved so much without being reducible to any single identifiable
principle or attribute. Science seems to work, even without adhering
rigorously to some ideal. Normative and descriptive views of science differ.
And this distinction becomes an important recurring theme in teaching the
nature of science.
The demarcation project also tended to treat science as a paradigm (if
not the exclusive domain) of rationality or objectivity. Scientific knowledge
earned special authority. Authority, hence power. As reflected in the early
aim to disenfranchise Marxism and psychoanalysis, the repeated efforts
were inherently political. Such political overtones remain. Scientists—and
the demarcation project | 7
the new findings, rather than abandon it. Or they wait until the exception
itself is found to be mistaken. All towards developing reliable knowledge.
For example, William Thomson contended on the basis of simple
thermodynamic evidence that Darwinian evolution was wrong. By
measuring thermal gradients at the Earth’s surface and using known rates
of heat dispersion, he calculated the age of the cooling Earth. His initial
determinations of 40 to 200 million years did not seem to allow enough
time for the gradual changes that Darwin proposed. The physical evidence,
it seems, falsified Darwin’s theory. Yet Darwin did not thereby abandon his
conclusions. Nor did geologists. They maintained their own, quite different
estimates of the age of the Earth, based primarily on interpreting sedimentary
rocks. Decades later, the status of the evidence changed dramatically. The
discovery of radioactivity introduced a new source of heat for the Earth’s
interior. Also, new ideas about convection currents in the mantle indicated
that internal heat could be redistributed. The original cooling calculations
had erred by at least an order of magnitude. The Earth was indeed very old.
In the long run, disregarding Thomson’s “falsification” seemed justified.
Another renowned episode of apparent falsification appears frequently
in physics texts. In the late nineteenth century, Michelson and Morley
tried to document the ether in space, by measuring the Earth’s movement
through it. They detected no ether wind: hence (apparently), no ether.
With no medium for propagating light waves, Newtonian physics was (the
oft-told story goes) falsified, generating a crisis that led to the theory of
relativity. Yet physicists at the time experienced no such crisis. They found
many ways to interpret the experimental results. Michelson acknowledged
that an ether wind sweeping the surface of the globe seemed unlikely. But
the Earth might very well be dragging the ether with it (as suggested earlier
by Stokes). In addition, the apparatus, while expertly assembled, had limited
sensitivity. The measurements only set an upper boundary to the density of
the ether. Some physicists readily accepted that the ether might be very thin.
Lorentz and others, by contrast, did rethink the basic physical laws. They
postulated that bodies might contract while moving through the ether. If so,
then the Michelson-Morley experiments would not have measured anything
about the ether. All these alternatives reconciled the experimental results
with theory, without abandoning Newtonian physics.11 While falsification
may contribute to a more dramatic story, it does not seem to describe how
scientists actually work (also see Chapters 3 and 4).
The fate of Prout’s hypothesis is another informative case.12 William
Prout proposed in 1815 that all atomic weights were whole-number
multiples of hydrogen, viewed as a basic unit. However, there were many
atomic weights—most notably, for chlorine—that did not follow this
rule. Was Prout’s hypothesis falsified and thus abandoned? Over the
next century, chemists’ views were mixed. Many were impressed with the
theoretical match for many elements. Others focused on the exceptions. In
falsifiability | 11
the early twentieth century the role of isotopes became clear. Individual
isolated isotopes tended to fit the hypothesis. Mixtures, typically found in
nature, yielded non-whole-number measurements. In addition, hydrogen
proved to be an approximate but inappropriate unit. One could think more
precisely in terms of whole-number multiples of protons, neutrons, and
electrons. (There are some exceptions even here, attributed to combinatorial
interactions.) Ultimately, Prout’s hypothesis was not strictly falsified; it was
successively revised to accommodate the evidence.
Consider, finally, the case of a proposed fourth physical force—the
weak interaction—to accompany gravity, electromagnetism, and the strong
interaction in atomic nuclei. Murray Gell-Mann explained:
You know, frequently a theorist will even throw out a lot of data on
the grounds that if they don’t fit an elegant scheme, they’re wrong.
That happened to me many times. The theory of the weak interac-
tion: there were nine experiments that contradicted it—all wrong.
Every one. When you have something simple that agrees with all
the rest of physics and really seems to explain what’s going on, a
few experimental data against it are no objection whatever. Almost
certain to be wrong.13
For Gell-Mann, as for other scientists, what mattered is the overall balance
of the evidence, not individual results exclusive of others. The role of
falsification is widely overstated.
As these historical examples illustrate, falsification is a romanticized ideal
that mischaracterizes real, productive science. Researchers are eminently
pragmatic. They typically finesse the evidence rather than regard theories as
falsified. They redefine terms. They modify the theory or restrict its scope.
They may even tolerate unresolved anomalies. Effective reasoning seems to
integrate evidence and counterevidence both. Eventually, weaker theories do
wane—but rarely because they are disproved. Philosopher of science Imre
Lakatos, having profiled these flaws in what he called naive falsificationism,
quite justly declared an “end of instant rationality.” Science is not so simple
or one-dimensional as it may at first seem. To teach the nature of science,
therefore, one must endeavor to convey some of its subtlety.
The demarcation project and appeals to falsifiability each reflect
widespread intuitions about science. However, simple consideration of actual
episodes in science shows that these intuitions are mistaken. Historical cases
can prove relevant in interpreting NOS. Here, then, is a primary strategy
for teachers: to render science through concrete examples, or case studies. Aiming
to understand scientific practice, one should delve into such historical or
contemporary cases, rather than rely on platitudes or claims easily distorted
by ill-informed preconceptions. One should observe authentic science in
action. In this way, students address their preconceptions about the nature
of science, just as they might address scientific misconceptions themselves
12 | from test tubes to youtube
Consider also the case of global warming. Despite the scientific consensus
expressed by the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, skepticism
dominated American politics for many years. Critics cited patchy data,
questionable models based on numerous assumptions, the unpredictability
of the daily weather, isolated results that contradicted general conclusions,
the newness of climate science, the limitations of peer review, and so on.
Note the telltale catchphrase of the former website, ClimateChangeFraud.
com: “Because the debate is NOT over.” The website seems to delight in
quoting Mark Twain: “There is something fascinating about science. One
gets such wholesale returns of conjecture from such a trifling investment
of fact.”20 In the skeptics’ rhetoric, climate science suffers from incautious
overstatement and premature conclusions.
Of course, these are not the voices of reliable science. A study of scientists
unconvinced about climate change confirmed that they are typically in
peripheral fields and that their work is far less widely cited.21 Indeed, as
documented by historians Naomi Oreskes and Erik Conway, the public
doubt has been deliberately orchestrated by just a handful of politically
connected scientists.22 Their strategy has been to generate an image of
uncertain, still actively debated science. That has been enough to stall
political action. That is, they did not need to present evidence for their own
counterclaims. They were able to leverage the alleged status of tentativeness.
The tactic is not new. Earlier, the same cadre of scientists planted seeds of
doubt to mislead the public on secondhand smoke, acid rain, the ozone hole,
and DDT. If all one learns is that “science is tentative,” without learning
how or why, mischief remains possible.
Finally, consider the case of a parent in Minnesota aligned with an
anti-vaccine movement inspired by the fraudulent paper (noted above) that
purportedly linked the measles vaccine to autism. In a letter to the local
newspaper, he contended that
Health professionals demonstrate great hubris when they claim to
know all there is to know about the safety of a vaccine. Medical
studies cannot prove that a vaccine is safe, only that it has not yet
proven to be unsafe. Studies need to be continually performed, re-
peated, and expanded to get us ever closer to the “truth” about a
drug or vaccine’s safety.23
Here, someone seems to have learned the consensus-list principle but
does not appreciate the fabric of reliability in science. When combined
with misconceptions about falsifiability, the superficial fragment of NOS
knowledge can open the way to scientific nihilism. In this case, knowing
about tentativeness, but only incompletely, proved counterproductive.
As illustrated in these three cases—creationists, climate-change
naysayers, and vaccine critics—merely acknowledging science as tentative is
insufficient. The concept can backfire if not understood fully. Understanding
16 | from test tubes to youtube
and the person in the middle is asked to settle the matter. Here is a prime
example of a role for scientific literacy.
What NOS concepts does one need to interpret this case effectively?
The consensus list is relatively unhelpful. For example, the central issue here
is credibility, not tentativeness. But credibility does not even appear on the
list. Does it help to know the difference between a law and a theory? No.
The nature of an experiment? Not really. “Science can be shaped by its social
milieu”? Perhaps, but political bias could well influence both views. Has it?
As noted above, one needs analytical tools, not general tenets.
To interpret Climategate, one needs to know instead about
••the spectrum of personalities in science
••the nature of graphs
••the norms of handling data
••how scientists communicate
••credibility and expertise
••robustness of evidential networks
••fraud or other forms of misconduct
That is, one needs to acknowledge that scientists are humans and that
their activities are not immune to emotion and personal rivalries. Scientific
discourse can get testy, especially behind the scenes and along informal
networks (such as e-mail). At the same time, the system of formal publication
helps filter arguments to relevant evidence. Graphs function to express data
in meaningful formats. That may entail creative arrangement of results.
(Here, data from two different studies and time scales were combined on the
same graph.) Using “tricks” (in the researchers’ jargon) is normal and does
not indicate fraud. Original data are not always released publicly—although,
in this case, public laws dictated the sharing of information. That was about
legal misconduct, however, and hardly affected the scientific status of the
data. Researchers may jockey politically for status and prominent publication
venues. Yet past performance and expertise matter. Credible voices earn
more profile. And here, especially, James Delingpole is a journalist with a
strong ideological edge: he is not a reliable source on interpreting science or
the nature of science. Ultimately, nothing in the e-mails provided grounds
for challenging the evidence itself, which came from many sources and
many converging lines of research. As subsequent investigations into this
incident bore out, the violation of open access to data was a serious offense,
but nothing weakened the scientific consensus, as alleged by so many online
commentators.
NOS includes the whole spectrum of features that affect the reliability, or
trustworthiness, of scientific claims. One cannot responsibly escape teaching
any relevant factor. For example, credibility (even among scientists) has a
central role, yet is missing from the NOS consensus list. Virtually all social
interaction of scientists, especially the system of checks and balances through
mutual criticism, are generally absent from various available NOS lists (see
18 | from test tubes to youtube
Chapter 6). One also needs to consider the role of funding, motivations,
peer review, inherent cognitive processes, fraud, and the validation of new
methods—all features of scientific practice that become relevant at different
times in public discussions. When one considers the diversity of cases that
emerge in contemporary society, such as Climategate, one finds that the
current NOS lists are severely truncated—and that, in a few items, emphasis
is misplaced. Using science in daily life as the relevant context, what is an
appropriate scope and focus of NOS in education?
Several approaches and studies may be worth noting. For example,
Dankert Kolstø offered a prospective framework based on addressing
socioscientific issues, especially controversies where one needs to resolve or
address conflicting scientific claims. Such debates are often local and reported
in the media: occasions where students as adults will likely participate in
the community. The objective is “to empower the students as citizens” by
describing “science as an institution and the processes by which scientific
knowledge is produced.” One aims to “increase students’ competence in
interpreting science-related statements.”25 One need not expect students
to be scientists themselves. Rather, the student who is familiar with the
methods of science, its social processes, and institutional norms is better
equipped to interpret and assess claims made by experts in various fields.
Kolstø outlined eight essential topics in four categories (Figure 1.2).26
First, science is a process. Science is not always complete. In public
issues, especially, the science is often still at the frontier. Results are
uncertain, meaning especially that different scientists may hold contrary
views. Without instruction, students tend to attribute such disagreements
to personal interests, opinions, or incompetence: that is, as pathology, rather
than as normal in emerging science. One thus needs to understand science
as a social process. Consensus is achieved through criticism, argumentation,
and peer review. Students need to appreciate the difference between what
in a coma for twenty-three years following a car crash was apparently able
to communicate using a special touchscreen and the assistance of an aide.
Laureys linked this to his research, noting that people in noncommunicative
states are misdiagnosed up to 40 percent of the time. Major news media,
including National Public Radio, CNN, Fox News, and MSNBC, aired the
remarkable story. Several months later, Laureys himself acknowledged that
the method of “facilitated communication” proved to be bogus and that he
had not exercised appropriate critical judgment of the method when it was
first “demonstrated” to him. Even an expert can be an unwitting victim of
fraud.
In addition, experts sometimes disagree. Credible claims may conflict.
One needs additional resources to assess the nature of the disagreement
and the relative status of alternative claims. Even credible claims may come
with qualifications and caveats, whose meaning becomes clear only when
one understands the various methods for ensuring reliability, as well as their
limits. Trust should not be blind. Credibility merely signals responsible
communication; it does not wholly substitute for it.
One needs to understand the nature of uncertainty and possible sources
of error. As science on a particular topic matures, problems of debate and
uncertainty tend to be resolved. In most contemporary decision-making
cases, however, the science is young—still science-in-the-making, as Kolstø
observed.36 In such circumstances, uncertainty is high. Neither credible voices
nor evidence can fully resolve the uncertain possibilities. At such times—
those most typical of the challenge of scientific literacy—assessments of the
nature and limits of reliable knowledge are especially important for guiding
decisions and helping to plan for contingencies. Teaching an understanding
of the uneasy status of scientific uncertainty, between ignorance and well-
founded claims, seems just as important as understanding (the more
familiar) tentativeness.
The informed citizen, then—the mature, well-educated student—will
be able (at least) to interact with experts on topics they may know next
to nothing about; recognize relevant evidence as well as presentations of
bogus evidence; appreciate the limits as well as the foundations of emerging
scientific claims; and negotiate through scientific uncertainty. One will be
a competent interpreter, or critic, of science, even if not a practitioner of
science (in the same way that film or music critics can effectively assess art
without necessarily producing art themselves).37 Interpreting the reliability
of scientific claims requires a broad understanding of scientific practice,
or how science works, from a simple laboratory or field setting to science
journalism.
A simple yet synoptic approach tracks the genesis and movement of
scientific claims. Namely, how are scientific claims generated and then
transmitted? What ensures reliability at each step, as each may prove
important in different cases?
mapping nos | 23
Experiments
• Controlled experiment (one variable)
• Blind and double-blind studies
• Statistical analysis of error
• Replication and sample size
Instruments
• New instruments and their validation
• Models and model organisms
• Ethics of experimentation on human subjects
Patterns of reasoning
• Evidential relevance (empiricism)
• Verifiable information versus values
• Role of probability in inference
• Alternative explanations
• Correlation versus causation
Historical dimensions
Conceptual
Any one element can be a source of error if not addressed properly. Ironically,
then, a complete profile of NOS also parallels potential sources of error, or
error types, in scientific practice. Accordingly, in a science classroom, one may
need to inform students about all the ways in which science can fail, so that
they might understand how scientists prevent, mitigate, or accommodate
potential errors. Paradoxically, perhaps, error can be a potent vehicle for
teaching the process of science (see Chapter 5).39 At least this would initiate
the lesson, widely regarded as central, that scientists can—and sometimes
do—err.
Whole Science
One might call this framing of NOS, sensitive to all the dimensions
of reliability in scientific practice, Whole Science. Whole Science, like
whole food, does not exclude essential ingredients. It supports healthier
understanding. Metaphorically, educators must discourage a diet of highly
processed, refined “School Science.” Short or truncated lists of NOS features
are simply unhealthy for understanding science.
The notion of Whole Science echoes and extends ongoing efforts
to characterize NOS inclusively. In recent years, treatment of NOS in
some places has yielded to discussions of “science as a way of knowing”
(or “how scientific knowledge is constructed,” “scientific inquiry,” or “the
scientific worldview”), “scientific practices” or the “scientific enterprise,” and
“how science works.”40 These labels tend to partition and treat as distinct
experimental, conceptual, and social processes. They splinter material,
cognitive, and cultural contexts. The label of Whole Science is a reminder
that these components function together.
Many characterizations of the nature of science are incomplete. Targeting
Whole Science helps restore the fullness to science. For example, some
science educators profile science as fundamentally explanatory and focus
almost exclusively on building theories and models. Yet science includes a
variety of investigations, such as documenting, describing, and organizing
natural phenomena; mapping causes (not always explaining them); and
producing certain effects. Other educators advocate scientific arguments as
the primary means for understanding what justifies scientific knowledge.
Yet scientists exchange material demonstrations and samples as well as
textual arguments. They assemble grant proposals and secure resources as
well as presenting claims and evidence. In addition, knowledge-generating
practices include not only cognitive and evidential methods, but social
interactions. They find flaws in each other’s work, adapt existing models to
new domains, collaborate to bring together complementary skills, and so
on.41 Nor is science just a conceptual exercise: it includes lab skills and quasi-
autonomous work on experimental systems.42 Most important, perhaps, a
Whole Science approach underscores the integrity of scientific practice, or
how all the various NOS strands interact towards epistemic ends.
26 | from test tubes to youtube