Semantics of Languages - Neel
Semantics of Languages - Neel
Neel Krishnaswami*
University of Cambridge
Department of Computer Science and Technology
Michaelmas 2021
1
Contents
Syllabus 3
Learning Guide 4
Summary of Notation 5
1 Introduction 8
2 A First Imperative Language 14
2.1 Operational Semantics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15
2.2 Typing . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23
2.3 L1: Collected definition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30
2.4 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32
3 Induction 33
3.1 Abstract Syntax and Structural Induction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35
3.2 Inductive Definitions and Rule Induction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41
3.3 Example proofs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 44
3.4 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
4 Functions 50
4.1 Abstract syntax up to alpha conversion, and substitution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52
4.2 Function Behaviour . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 56
4.3 Function Typing . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 60
4.4 Local Definitions and Recursive Functions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62
4.5 Implementation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65
4.6 L2: Collected Definition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 68
4.7 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 71
5 Data 72
5.1 Products and sums . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 72
5.2 Datatypes and Records . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 75
5.3 Mutable Store . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 77
5.4 Evaluation Contexts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 80
5.5 L3: Collected definition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 81
5.6 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 85
6 Subtyping and Objects 86
6.1 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 92
7 Concurrency 93
7.1 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 103
8 Semantic Equivalence 104
8.1 Contextual equivalence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 109
8.2 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 109
9 Epilogue 109
2
Syllabus
This course is a prerequisite for Types (Part II), Denotational Semantics (Part II), and
Topics in Concurrency (Part II).
Aims
The aim of this course is to introduce the structural, operational approach to program-
ming language semantics. It will show how to specify the meaning of typical programming
language constructs, in the context of language design, and how to reason formally about
semantic properties of programs.
Lectures
• Introduction. Transition systems. The idea of structural operational semantics.
Transition semantics of a simple imperative language. Language design options.
• Types. Introduction to formal type systems. Typing for the simple imperative lan-
guage. Statements of desirable properties.
• Induction. Review of mathematical induction. Abstract syntax trees and struc-
tural induction. Rule-based inductive definitions and proofs. Proofs of type safety
properties.
• Functions. Call-by-name and call-by-value function application, semantics and typ-
ing. Local recursive definitions.
• Data. Semantics and typing for products, sums, records, references.
• Subtyping. Record subtyping and simple object encoding.
• Semantic equivalence. Semantic equivalence of phrases in a simple imperative lan-
guage, including the congruence property. Examples of equivalence and non-equivalence.
• Concurrency. Shared variable interleaving. Semantics for simple mutexes; a serial-
izability property.
Objectives
At the end of the course students should
• be familiar with rule-based presentations of the operational semantics and type systems
for some simple imperative, functional and interactive program constructs
• be able to prove properties of an operational semantics using various forms of induction
(mathematical, structural, and rule-based)
• be familiar with some operationally-based notions of semantic equivalence of program
phrases and their basic properties
Recommended reading
Hennessy, M. (1990). The semantics of programming languages. Wiley.
Out of print, but available on the web at
https://www.scss.tcd.ie/Matthew.Hennessy/splexternal2015/resources/sembookWiley.
pdf.
* Pierce, B.C. (2002). Types and programming languages. MIT Press.
Winskel, G. (1993). The formal semantics of programming languages. MIT Press.
3
Learning Guide
The books are all available in the Computer Laboratory Library. Books:
• Hennessy, M. (1990). The Semantics of Programming Languages. Wiley. Out of print.
Introduces many of the key topics of the course. There’s a copy on the web at
https://www.scss.tcd.ie/Matthew.Hennessy/splexternal2015/resources/sembookWiley.
pdf
• Pierce, B. C. (2002) Types and Programming Languages. MIT Press.
This is a graduate-level text, covering a great deal of material on programming language
semantics. The first half (through to Chapter 15) is relevant to this course, and some of the
later material relevant to the Part II Types course. ebook available at
http://search.lib.cam.ac.uk/?itemid=|eresources|1472
4
2. §4.7 (Page 71): 18, 19, 20, 21, 22, 23; §5.6 (Page 85): 28; 2003.5.11.
3. §7.1 (Page 103): 37, (39), 40; §6.1 (Page 92): 31, 32, 35; 2003.6.12, further tripos
questions
Tripos questions: This version of the course was first given in 2002–2003. The questions
since then are directly relevant, and there is an additional mock question on the course web
page. The previous version of the course (by Andrew Pitts) used a slightly different form
of operational semantics, ‘big-step’ instead of ‘small-step’ (see Page 67 of these notes), and
different example languages, so the notation in most earlier questions may seem unfamiliar
at first sight.
These questions use only small-step and should be accessible: 1998 Paper 6 Question 12,
1997 Paper 5 Question 12, and 1996 Paper 5 Question 12.
These questions use big-step, but apart from that should be ok: 2002 Paper 5 Question 9,
2002 Paper 6 Question 9, 2001 Paper 5 Question 9, 2000 Paper 5 Question 9, 1999 Paper 6
Question 9 (first two parts only), 1999 Paper 5 Question 9, 1998 Paper 5 Question 12, 1995
Paper 6 Question 12, 1994 Paper 7 Question 13, 1993 Paper 7 Question 10.
These questions depend on material which is no longer in this course (complete partial
orders, continuations, or bisimulation – see the Part II Denotational Semantics and Topics
in Concurrency courses): 2001 Paper 6 Question 9, 2000 Paper 6 Question 9, 1997 Paper 6
Question 12, 1996 Paper 6 Question 12, 1995 Paper 5 Question 12, 1994 Paper 8 Question
12, 1994 Paper 9 Question 12, 1993 Paper 8 Question 10, 1993 Paper 9 Question 10.
Feedback: Please do complete the on-line feedback form at the end of the course, and let
me know during it if you discover errors in the notes or if the pace is too fast or slow. A list
of corrections will be on the course web page.
Acknowledgements (N. Krishnaswami): These notes are a modification of the notes
that Peter Sewell used for the course, 2014–2018. Thanks also to Jean Pichon for comments.
Acknowledgements (P. Sewell): These notes are a modification of the notes that Sam
Staton used for the course, 2010–2013. Thanks also to Jean Pichon for comments.
Acknowledgements (S. Staton): These notes are a modification of the notes that Peter
Sewell used for the course, 2003–2009.
Acknowledgements (P. Sewell): These notes draw, with thanks, on earlier courses by
Andrew Pitts, on Benjamin Pierce’s book, and many other sources. Any errors are, of
course, newly introduced by me.
Summary of Notation
Each section is roughly in the order that notation is introduced. The grammars of the
languages are not included here, but are in the Collected Definitions of L1, L2 and L3 later
in this document.
5
Logic and Set Theory
Φ ∧ Φ′ and
Φ ∨ Φ′ or
Φ ⇒ Φ′ implies
¬Φ not
∀ x .Φ(x ) for all
∃ x .Φ(x ) exists
a ∈ A element of
{a1 , ..., an } the set with elements a1 , ..., an
A1 ∪ A 2 union
A1 ∩ A 2 intersection
A1 ⊆ A 2 subset or equal
A 1 ∗ A2 cartesian product (set of pairs)
6
Particular sets
B = {true, false} the set of booleans
L = {l , l1 , l2 , ...} the set of locations
Z = {.., −1, 0, 1, ...} the set of integers
N = {0, 1, ...} the set of natural numbers
X = {x, y, ...} the set of L2 and L3 variables
LAB = {p, q, ...} the set of record labels
M = {m, m0 , m1 , ...} the set of mutex names
T the set of all types (in whichever language)
Tloc the set of all location types (in whichever language)
L1 the set of all L1 expressions
TypeEnv the set of all L1 type environments, finite partial functions
from L to Tloc
TypeEnv2 the set of all L2 type environments, the pairs of a finite partial function
from L to Tloc and a finite partial function from X to T
Metavariables
b ∈ B boolean
n ∈ Z integer
ℓ ∈ L location
op binary operation
e, f expression (of whichever language)
v value (of whichever language)
s store (of whichever language)
T ∈ T type (of whichever language)
Tloc ∈ Tloc location type (of whichever language)
Γ type environment (also, set of propositional assumptions)
i, k, y natural numbers
c configuration (or state), typically he, si with expression e and store s
Φ formula
c tree constructor
R set of rules
(H , c) a rule with hypotheses H ⊆ A and conclusion c ∈ A for some set A
SR a subset inductively defined by the set of rules R
x ∈ X variable
σ substitution
lab ∈ LAB record label
E evaluation context
C arbitrary context
π permutation of natural numbers
m ∈ M mutex name
M state of all mutexes (a function M :M −→ B)
a thread action
Other
hole in a context
C [e] context C with e replacing the hole
7
1 Introduction
2019–20
• Science
• Engineering
Slide 2 • Craft
• Art
• Bodgery
Slide 3
8
Slide 4
Slide 5
Slide 6
In this course we will take a close look at programming languages. We will focus on how to
define precisely what a programming language is – i.e., how the programs of the language
behave, or, more generally, what their meaning, or semantics, is.
9
Semantics — What is it?
Many programming languages that you meet are described only in natural language, e.g.
the English standards documents for C, Java, XML, etc. These are reasonably accessible
(though often written in ‘standardsese’), but there are some major problems. It is very
hard, if not impossible, to write really precise definitions in informal prose. The standards
often end up being ambiguous or incomplete, or just too large and hard to understand.
That leads to differing implementations and flaky systems, as the language implementors
and users do not have a common understanding of what it is. More fundamentally, natural
language standards obscure the real structure of languages – it’s all too easy to add a feature
and a quick paragraph of text without thinking about how it interacts with the rest of the
language.
Instead, as we shall see in this course, one can develop mathematical definitions of how
programs behave, using logic and set theory (e.g. the definition of Standard ML, the .NET
CLR, recent work on XQuery, etc.). These require a little more background to understand
and use, but for many purposes they are a much better tool than informal standards.
10
Design choices, from Micro to Macro
• basic values
• evaluation order
• what can be stored
• what can be abstracted over
Slide 11 • what is guaranteed at compile-time and run-time
• how effects are controlled
• how concurrency is supported
• how information hiding is enforceable
• how large-scale development and re-use are supported
• ...
Warmup
Slide 12 In C, if initially x has value 3, what’s the value of the following?
C♯
class M {
public static void Main() {
IntThunk[] funcs = new IntThunk[11];
for (int i = 0; i <= 10; i++)
Slide 13 {
funcs[i] = delegate() { return i; };
}
foreach (IntThunk f in funcs)
{
System.Console.WriteLine(f());
}
}
}
11
JavaScript
• Operational semantics
Slide 15
• Denotational semantics
• Axiomatic, or Logical, semantics
Operational: define the meaning of a program in terms of the computation steps it takes in
an idealized execution. Some definitions use structural operational semantics, in which the
intermediate states are described using the language itself; others use abstract machines,
which use more ad-hoc mathematical constructions.
Denotational: define the meaning of a program as elements of some abstract mathematical
structure, e.g. regarding programming-language functions as certain mathematical functions.
cf. the Denotational Semantics course.
Axiomatic or Logical: define the meaning of a program indirectly, by giving the axioms of
a logic of program properties. cf. Specification and Verification.
‘Toy’ languages
Real programming languages are large, with many features and, often,
with redundant constructs – things that can be expressed in the rest of the
Slide 16 language.
Core
12
Operational semantics
(assignment and while ) L1✵❁1,2,3,4 Type systems
✵✵❁❁
✵✵❁❁ Implementations
✵ ❁❁❁
5,6 ✵✵ ❁❁ Language design choices
(functions and recursive definitions) L2 ✵✵ ❁
✵✵ ❁❁❁ Inductive definitions
✵✵ ❁❁
✵ ❁❁ Inductive proof – structural; rule
8 ✵✵ ❁❁
(products, sums, records, references) L3 ❁❁
✉✉ ✵
✉✉
✉ ✵✵ ❁❁ Abstract syntax up to alpha
Slide 18 ✉✉ ✵✵ ❁❁
✉✉ ❁
Subtyping Semantic ❁❁❁
9 10 ❁❁
and Objects Equivalence ❁❁
❁❁
❁❁
❁
Concurrency12
In the core we will develop enough techniques to deal with the semantics of a non-trivial
small language, showing some language-design pitfalls and alternatives along the way. It
will end up with the semantics of a decent fragment of ML. The second part will cover a
selection of more advanced topics.
Admin
13
2 A First Imperative Language
Slide 21
L1
L1 – Example
l2 := 0;
Slide 22
while !l1 ≥ 1 do (
l2 :=!l2 +!l1 ;
l1 :=!l1 + −1)
L1 – Syntax
Operations op ::= + |≥
Slide 23 Expressions
Points to note:
• we’ll return later to exactly what the set L1 is when we talk about abstract syntax
• unbounded integers
• abstract locations – can’t do pointer arithmetic on them
• untyped, so have nonsensical expressions like 3 + true
• what kind of grammar is that (c.f. RLFA)?
• don’t have expression/command distinction
• doesn’t much matter what basic operators we have
• carefully distinguish metavariables b, n, ℓ, op , e etc. from program locations l etc..
14
2.1 Operational Semantics
In order to describe the behaviour of L1 programs we will use structural operational seman-
tics to define various forms of automata:
Transition systems
To compare with the automata you saw in Regular Languages and Finite Automata: a
transition system is like an NFAε with an empty alphabet (so only ε transitions) except (a)
it can have infinitely many states, and (b) we don’t specify a start state or accepting states.
Sometimes one adds labels (e.g. to represent IO) but mostly we’ll just look at the values of
terminated states, those that cannot do any transitions.
Notation.
• −→∗ is the reflexive transitive closure of −→, so c −→∗ c ′ iff there exist k ≥ 0 and
c0 , .., ck such that c = c0 −→ c1 ... −→ ck = c ′ .
• 6−→ is a unary predicate (a subset of Config) defined by c 6−→ iff ¬ ∃ c ′ .c −→ c ′ .
The particular transition systems we use for L1 are as follows.
L1 Semantics (1 of 4) – Configurations
{l1 7→ 7, l3 7→ 23}
Slide 25
Take configurations to be pairs he, si of an expression e and a store s , so
our transition relation will have the form
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
Definition. A finite partial function f from a set A to a set B is a set containing a finite
number n ≥ 0 of pairs {(a1 , b1 ), ..., (an , bn )}, often written {a1 7→ b1 , ..., an 7→ bn }, for which
• ∀ i ∈ {1, .., n}.ai ∈ A (the domain is a subset ofA)
• ∀ i ∈ {1, .., n}.bi ∈ B (the range is a subset of B )
• ∀ i ∈ {1, .., n}, j ∈ {1, .., n}.i 6= j ⇒ ai 6= aj (f is functional, i.e. each element of A is
mapped to at most one element of B )
For a partial function f , we write dom(f ) for the set of elements in the domain of f (things
that f maps to something) and ran(f ) for the set of elements in the range of f (things that
something is mapped to by f ). For example, for the store s above we have dom(s) = {l1 , l3 }
and ran(s) = {7, 23}. Note that a finite partial function can be empty, just {}.
We write store for the set of all stores.
15
Transitions are single computation steps. For example we will have:
hl := 2+!l , {l 7→ 3}i
−→ hl := 2 + 3, {l 7→ 3}i
−→ hl := 5, {l 7→ 3}i
−→ hskip, {l 7→ 5}i
Slide 26 6−→
want to keep on until we get to a value v , an expression in
V = B ∪ Z ∪ {skip}.
Say he, si is stuck if e is not a value and he, si 6−→. For example
2 + true will be stuck.
We could define the values in a different, but equivalent, style: Say values v are expressions
from the grammar v ::= b | n | skip.
Now define the behaviour for each construct of L1 by giving some rules that (together)
define a transition relation −→.
L1 Semantics (2 of 4) – Rules (basic operations)
he2 , si −→ he2′ , s ′ i
(op2)
hv op e2 , si −→ hv op e2′ , s ′ i
How to read these? The rule (op +) says that for any instantiation of the metavariables
n, n1 and n2 (i.e. any choice of three integers), that satisfies the sidecondition, there is a
transition from the instantiated configuration on the left to the one on the right.
We use a strict naming convention for metavariables: n can only be instantiated by integers,
not by arbitrary expressions.
The rule (op1) says that for any instantiation of e1 , e1′ , e2 , s, s ′ (i.e. any three expressions
and two stores), if a transition of the form above the line can be deduced then we can
deduce the transition below the line.
Observe that – as you would expect – none of these first rules introduce changes in the store
part of configurations.
16
Example
(op +)
h2 + 3, ∅i −→ h5, ∅i
Slide 28 (op1)
h(2 + 3) + (6 + 7), ∅i −→ h5 + (6 + 7), ∅i
(op +)
h6 + 7, ∅i −→ h13, ∅i
(op2)
h5 + (6 + 7), ∅i −→ h5 + 13, ∅i
(op +)
h5 + 13, ∅i −→ h18, ∅i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
Slide 29 (assign2)
hℓ := e, si −→ hℓ := e ′ , s ′ i
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(seq2)
he1 ; e2 , si −→ he1′ ; e2 , s ′ i
17
Example
hl := 3; l :=!l , {l 7→ 0}i −→ ?
h15+!l , ∅i −→ ?
Slide 31
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(if3)
hif e1 then e2 else e3 , si −→ hif e1′ then e2 else e3 , s ′ i
(while)
Example
If
he, si −→∗ ?
That concludes our definition of L1. The full definition is collected on page 30.
Determinacy
Note that top-level universal quantifiers are usually left out – the theorem really says “For
all e, s, e1 , s1 , e2 , s2 , if he, si −→ he1 , s1 i and he, si −→ he2 , s2 i then he1 , s1 i = he2 , s2 i”.
18
L1 implementation
L1 implementation
Will implement an interpreter for L1, following the definition. Use mosml
(Moscow ML) as the implementation language, as datatypes and pattern
datatype expr =
Integer of int
| Boolean of bool
| Op of expr * oper * expr
Slide 36
| If of expr * expr * expr
| Assign of loc * expr
| Deref of loc
| Skip
| Seq of expr * expr
| While of expr * expr
The expression and operation datatypes have essentially the same form as the abstract
grammar. Note, though, that it does not exactly match the semantics, as that allowed
arbitrary integers whereas here we use the bounded Moscow ML integers – so not every
term of the abstract syntax is representable as an element of type expr, and the interpreter
will fail with an overflow exception if + overflows.
19
Store operations
(you might think it would be better ML style to use exceptions instead of these options;
that would be fine).
(op1), (op2)
...
if (is value e1) then
case reduce (e2,s) of
SOME (e2’,s’) =>
SOME (Op(e1,opr,e2’),s’)
Slide 40
| NONE => NONE
else
case reduce (e1,s) of
SOME (e1’,s’) =>
SOME(Op(e1’,opr,e2),s’)
| NONE => NONE )
Note that the code depends on global properties of the semantics, including the fact that it
20
defines a deterministic transition system, so the comments indicating that particular lines
of code implement particular semantic rules are not the whole story.
(assign1), (assign2)
The full interpreter code is in Appendix A, and you can also download it from the course
website, in the file l1.ml, together with a pretty-printer and the type-checker we will come
to soon. For comparison, there is also a Java implementation in l1.java.
Slide 43 • the ML groups together all the parts of each algorithm, into the
reduce, infertype, and prettyprint functions;
• the Java groups together everything to do with each clause of the
abstract syntax, in the IfThenElse, Assign, etc. classes.
21
L1 is a simple language, but it nonetheless involves several language design choices.
he2 , si −→ he2′ , s ′ i
Slide 44 (op1b)
he1 op e2 , si −→ he1 op e2′ , s ′ i
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(op2b)
he1 op v , si −→ he1′ op v , s ′ i
Recall
Matter of taste? Another possiblity: return the old value, e.g. in ANSI C signal handler
installation.
Language design 3. Store initialization
Recall that
2. allow assignment to an ℓ ∈
/ dom(s) to initialize that ℓ.
In the next section we will introduce a type system to rule out any program that could reach
22
a stuck expression of these forms. (Would the two alternatives be a good idea?)
Also, store is global. We will consider programs that can create new
locations later.
Expressiveness
Slide 49
• no: there’s no support for gadgets like functions, objects, lists, trees,
modules,.....
2.2 Typing
Slide 50 L1 Typing
23
Type systems
used for
Type systems are also used to provide information to compiler optimizers; to enforce security
properties, from simple absence of buffer overflows to sophisticated information-flow policies;
and (in research languages) for many subtle properties, e.g. type systems that allow only
polynomial-time computation. There are rich connections with logic, which we’ll return to
later.
Formal type systems
Slide 52
{} ⊢ if true then 2 else 3 + 4 : int
l1 :intref ⊢ if !l1 ≥ 3 then !l1 else 3 : int
{} 6⊢ 3 + false : T for any T
{} 6⊢ if true then 3 else false : int
Note that the last is excluded despite the fact that when you execute the program you will
always get an int – type systems define approximations to the behaviour of programs, often
quite crude – and this has to be so, as we generally would like them to be decidable, so that
compilation is guaranteed to terminate.
Types for L1
Types of expressions:
Write T and Tloc for the sets of all terms of these grammars.
Let Γ range over TypeEnv, the finite partial functions from locations L
to Tloc . Notation: write a Γ as l1 :intref, ..., lk :intref instead of
{l1 7→ intref, ..., lk 7→ intref}.
24
Defining the type judgement Γ ⊢ e:T (1 of 3)
(if) Γ ⊢ e1 :bool Γ ⊢ e2 :T Γ ⊢ e3 :T
Γ ⊢ if e1 then e2 else e3 :T
Note that in (if) the T is arbitrary, so long as both premises have the same T .
In some rules we arrange the premises vertically to save space, e.g.
Γ ⊢ e1 :int
Γ ⊢ e2 :int
(op +)
Γ ⊢ e1 + e2 :int
but this is merely visual layout. Derivations using such a rule should be written as if it was
in the horizontal form.
(op +) Γ ⊢ e1 :int Γ ⊢ e2 :int
Γ ⊢ e1 + e2 :int
Example
where ∇ is
(int) (int)
{} ⊢ 3:int {} ⊢ 4:int
(op +)
{} ⊢ 3 + 4:int
(assign)
Γ(ℓ) = intref Γ ⊢ e:int
Slide 56 Γ ⊢ ℓ := e:unit
(deref)
Γ(ℓ) = intref
Γ ⊢!ℓ:int
25
Defining the type judgement Γ ⊢ e:T (3 of 3)
(skip) Γ ⊢ skip:unit
Note that the typing rules are syntax-directed – for each clause of the abstract syntax for
expressions there is exactly one rule with a conclusion of that form.
Properties
From these two we have that well-typed programs don’t get stuck:
Second problem is usually harder than the first. Solving it usually results
in a type inference algorithm: computing a type T for a phrase e , given
type environment Γ (or failing, if there is none).
More Properties
26
a look.
Type inference – Implementation
In the semantics, type environments Γ are partial functions from locations to the singleton
set {intref}. Here, just as we did for stores, we represent them as a list of loc*type loc
pairs containing, for each ℓ in the domain of the type environment, exactly one element of
the form (l,intref).
27
The Type Inference Algorithm – If
...
| infertype gamma (If (e1,e2,e3))
= (case (infertype gamma e1,
infertype gamma e2,
infertype gamma e3) of
Γ ⊢ e1 :bool
Γ ⊢ e2 :T
Γ ⊢ e3 :T
(if)
Γ ⊢ if e1 then e2 else e3 :T
...
| infertype gamma (Deref l)
= (case lookup (gamma,l) of
(deref)
Γ(ℓ) = intref
Γ ⊢!ℓ:int
Again, the code depends on a uniqueness property (Theorem 7), without which we would
have to have infertype return a type L1 list of all the possible types.
Executing L1 in Moscow ML
where s is the store {l1 7→ n1 , ..., lk 7→ nk } and all locations that occur
in e are contained in {l1 , ..., lk }.
28
Why Not Types?
Some languages build the type system into the syntax. Original FORTRAN, BASIC etc.
had typing built into variable names, with e.g. those beginning with I or J storing inte-
gers). Sometimes typing is built into the grammar, with e.g. separate grammatical classes
of expressions and commands. As the type systems become more expressive, however, they
quickly go beyond what can be captured in context-free grammars. They must then be
separated from lexing and parsing, both conceptually and in implementations.
29
2.3 L1: Collected definition
Syntax
Operational semantics
Note that for each construct there are some computation rules, doing ‘real work’, and some
context (or congruence) rules, allowing subcomputations and specifying their order.
Say stores s are finite partial functions from L to Z. Say values v are expressions from the
grammar v ::= b | n | skip.
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(op1)
he1 op e2 , si −→ he1′ op e2 , s ′ i
he2 , si −→ he2′ , s ′ i
(op2)
hv op e2 , si −→ hv op e2′ , s ′ i
(deref) h!ℓ, si −→ hn, si if ℓ ∈ dom(s) and s(ℓ) = n
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(if3)
hif e1 then e2 else e3 , si −→ hif e1′ then e2 else e3 , s ′ i
(while)
hwhile e1 do e2 , si −→ hif e1 then (e2 ; while e1 do e2 ) else skip, si
30
Typing
Types of expressions:
T ::= int | bool | unit
Types of locations:
Tloc ::= intref
Write T and Tloc for the sets of all terms of these grammars.
Let Γ range over TypeEnv, the finite partial functions from locations L to Tloc .
Γ ⊢ e1 :int Γ ⊢ e1 :int
Γ ⊢ e2 :int Γ ⊢ e2 :int
(op +) (op ≥)
Γ ⊢ e1 + e2 :int Γ ⊢ e1 ≥ e2 :bool
(if) Γ ⊢ e1 :bool Γ ⊢ e2 :T Γ ⊢ e3 :T
Γ ⊢ if e1 then e2 else e3 :T
Γ(ℓ) = intref
(deref)
Γ ⊢!ℓ:int
(skip) Γ ⊢ skip:unit
(seq) Γ ⊢ e1 :unit Γ ⊢ e2 :T
Γ ⊢ e1 ; e2 :T
31
2.4 Exercises
Exercise 1 ⋆Write a program to compute the factorial of the integer initially in location
l1 . Take care to ensure that your program really is an expression in L1.
Exercise 2 ⋆Give full derivations of all the reduction steps of
h(l0 := 7); (l1 := (!l0 + 2)), {l0 7→ 0, l1 7→ 0}i
Exercise 3 ⋆Give full derivations of the first four reduction steps of the he, si of the first
L1 example on Slide 22.
Exercise 4 ⋆Adapt the implementation code to correspond to the two rules (op1b) and
(op2b) on Slide 44. Give some test cases that distinguish between the original and the new
semantics.
Exercise 5 ⋆Adapt the implementation code to correspond to the two rules (assign1’) and
(seq1’) on Slide 45. Give some test cases that distinguish between the original and the new
semantics.
Exercise 6 ⋆⋆Fix the L1 semantics to match the implementation, taking care with the
representation of integers.
Exercise 7 ⋆Give a type derivation for (l0 := 7); (l1 := (!l0 +2)) with Γ = l0 :intref, l1 :intref.
Exercise 8 ⋆Give a type derivation for e on Slide 32 with Γ = l1 :intref, l2 :intref, l3 :intref .
Exercise 9 ⋆Does Type Preservation hold for the variant language with rules (assign1’)
and (seq1’)? on Slide 45? If not, give an example, and show how the type rules could be
adjusted to make it true.
Exercise 10 ⋆Adapt the type inference implementation to match your revised type system
from Exercise 9.
Exercise 11 ⋆Check whether mosml, the L1 implementation and the L1 semantics agree
on the order of evaluation for operators and sequencing.
32
3 Induction
Key concepts in this chapter:
• Structural induction
• Rule induction
Slide 67
Induction
We’ve stated several ‘theorems’, but how do we know they are true?
Use proof process also for strengthening our intuition about subtle
Slide 68 language features, and for debugging definitions – it helps you examine all
the various cases.
Most of our definitions are inductive. To prove things about them, we need
the corresponding induction principles.
We shall see that all three boil down to induction over certain trees.
∀ x ∈ N.Φ(x )
Slide 70
it’s enough to prove
33
� �
Φ(0) ∧ (∀ x ∈ N.Φ(x ) ⇒ Φ(x + 1)) ⇒ ∀ x ∈ N.Φ(x )
For example, to prove
(instantiate Φ)
Φ(0) is (1 + ... + 0 = 1/2 ∗ 0 ∗ (0 + 1)), which holds as both sides are equal to 0.
34
3.1 Abstract Syntax and Structural Induction
How to prove facts about all expressions, e.g. Determinacy for L1?
Abstract Syntax
Recall we said:
Slide 73
e ::= n | b | e op e | if e then e else e |
ℓ := e |!ℓ |
skip | e; e |
while e do e
defining a set of expressions.
+ 4
✌ ✶✶
✌✌ ✶
2 2
1 + 2 + 3 – ambiguous
Slide 75 (1 + 2) + 3 6= 1 + (2 + 3)
+ +
☛ ✶✶✶ ✌ ✸✸
☛☛ ✌✌ ✸
+ 3 1 +
✌ ✸✸ ☛ ✶✶
✌✌ ✸ ☛☛ ✶
1 2 2 3
Parentheses are only used for disambiguation – they are not part of the
grammar. 1 + 2 = (1 + 2) = ((1 + 2)) = (((((1)))) + ((2)))
35
For semantics we don’t want to be distracted by concrete syntax – it’s easiest to work
with abstract syntax trees, which for this grammar are finite trees, with ordered branches,
labelled as follows:
• leaves (nullary nodes) labelled by B ∪ Z ∪ ({!} ∗ L) ∪ {skip} = {true, false, skip} ∪
{..., −1, 0, 1, ...} ∪ {!l , !l1 , !l2 , ...}.
• unary nodes labelled by {l :=, l1 :=, l2 :=, ...}
• binary nodes labelled by {+, ≥, ; , while do }
• ternary nodes labelled by {if then else }
Abstract grammar suggests a concrete syntax – we write expressions as strings just for
convenience, using parentheses to disambiguate where required and infix notation, but really
mean trees.
Principle of Structural Induction (for abstract syntax)
∀ e ∈ L1 .Φ(e)
it’s enough to prove for each tree constructor c (taking k ≥ 0 arguments)
Slide 76 that if Φ holds for the subtrees e1 , .., ek then Φ holds for the tree
c(e1 , .., ek ). i.e.
� �
∀ c.∀ e1 , .., ek .(Φ(e1 ) ∧ ... ∧ Φ(ek )) ⇒ Φ(c(e1 , .., ek )) ⇒ ∀ e.Φ(e)
where the tree constructors (or node labels) c are n , true, false, !l , skip,
l :=, while do , if then else , etc.
nullary: Φ(skip)
∀ b ∈ {true, false}.Φ(b)
∀ n ∈ Z.Φ(n)
∀ ℓ ∈ L.Φ(!ℓ)
Slide 77 unary: ∀ ℓ ∈ L.∀ e.Φ(e) ⇒ Φ(ℓ := e)
binary: ∀ op .∀ e1 , e2 .(Φ(e1 ) ∧ Φ(e2 )) ⇒ Φ(e1 op e2 )
∀ e1 , e2 .(Φ(e1 ) ∧ Φ(e2 )) ⇒ Φ(e1 ; e2 )
∀ e1 , e2 .(Φ(e1 ) ∧ Φ(e2 )) ⇒ Φ(while e1 do e2 )
ternary: ∀ e1 , e2 , e3 .(Φ(e1 ) ∧ Φ(e2 ) ∧ Φ(e3 )) ⇒ Φ(if e1 then e2 else e3 )
(See how this comes directly from the grammar)
36
def
Φ(e) = ∀ s, e ′ , s ′ , e ′′ , s ′′ .
(he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i ∧ he, si −→ he ′′ , s ′′ i)
⇒ he ′ , s ′ i = he ′′ , s ′′ i
nullary: Φ(skip)
∀ b ∈ {true, false}.Φ(b)
Slide 79 ∀ n ∈ Z.Φ(n)
∀ ℓ ∈ L.Φ(!ℓ)
unary: ∀ ℓ ∈ L.∀ e.Φ(e) ⇒ Φ(ℓ := e)
binary: ∀ op .∀ e1 , e2 .(Φ(e1 ) ∧ Φ(e2 )) ⇒ Φ(e1 op e2 )
∀ e1 , e2 .(Φ(e1 ) ∧ Φ(e2 )) ⇒ Φ(e1 ; e2 )
∀ e1 , e2 .(Φ(e1 ) ∧ Φ(e2 )) ⇒ Φ(while e1 do e2 )
ternary: ∀ e1 , e2 , e3 .(Φ(e1 ) ∧ Φ(e2 ) ∧ Φ(e3 )) ⇒ Φ(if e1 then e2 else e3 )
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(op1)
he1 op e2 , si −→ he1′ op e2 , s ′ i (if1) hif true then e2 else e3 , si −→ he2 , si
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(seq2)
he1 ; e2 , si −→ he1′ ; e2 , s ′ i
def
Φ(e) = ∀ s, e ′ , s ′ , e ′′ , s ′′ .
(he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i ∧ he, si −→ he ′′ , s ′′ i)
⇒ he ′ , s ′ i = he ′′ , s ′′ i
Slide 81
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(assign2)
hℓ := e, si −→ hℓ := e ′ , s ′ i
37
Inversion
Slide 85 +
☛ ✶✶✶
☛☛
+ 3
☞ ✸✸
☞☞ ✸
!l 2
38
Theorem 1 (Determinacy) If he, si −→ he1 , s1 i and he, si −→ he2 , s2 i then he1 , s1 i =
he2 , s2 i .
Proof Take
def
Φ(e) = ∀ s, e ′ , s ′ , e ′′ , s ′′ .(he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i ∧ he, si −→ he ′′ , s ′′ i) ⇒ he ′ , s ′ i = he ′′ , s ′′ i
so e ′ = e ′′ and s ′ = s ′′ .
Case ℓ := e. Suppose Φ(e) (then we have to show Φ(ℓ := e)).
Take arbitrary s, e ′ , s ′ , e ′′ , s ′′ such that hℓ := e, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i ∧ hℓ := e, si −→
he ′′ , s ′′ i.
It’s handy to have this lemma:
Lemma 12 For all e ∈ L1 , if e is a value then ∀ s.¬ ∃e ′ , s ′ .he, si −→
he ′ , s ′ i.
Proof By defn e is a value if it is of one of the forms n, b, skip. By
examination of the rules on slides ..., there is no rule with conclusion
of the form he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i for e one of n, b, skip.
The only rules which could be applicable, for each of the two transitions, are
(assign1) and (assign2).
case hℓ := e, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i is an instance of (assign1). Then for some n we have
e = n and ℓ ∈ dom(s) and e ′ = skip and s ′ = s + {ℓ 7→ n}.
case hℓ := n, si −→ he ′′ , s ′′ i is an instance of (assign1) (note we are using
the fact that e = n here). Then e ′′ = skip and s ′′ = s + {ℓ 7→ n} so
he ′ , s ′ i = he ′′ , s ′′ i as required.
case hℓ := e, si −→ he ′′ , s ′′ i is an instance of (assign2). Then hn, si −→
he ′′ , s ′′ i, which contradicts the lemma, so this case cannot arise.
case hℓ := e, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i is an instance of (assign2). Then for some e1′ we have
he, si −→ he1′ , s ′ i (*) and e ′ = (ℓ := e1′ ).
case hℓ := e, si −→ he ′′ , s ′′ i is an instance of (assign1). Then for some n we
have e = n, which contradicts the lemma, so this case cannot arise.
case hℓ := e, si −→ he ′′ , s ′′ i is an instance of (assign2). Then for some
e1′′ we have he, si −→ he1′′ , s ′′ i(**) and e ′′ = (ℓ := e1′′ ). Now, by the
induction hypothesis Φ(e), (*) and (**) we have he1′ , s ′ i = he1′′ , s ′′ i, so
he ′ , s ′ i = hℓ := e1′ , s ′ i = hℓ := e1′′ , s ′′ i = he ′′ , s ′′ i as required.
Case e1 op e2 . Suppose Φ(e1 ) and Φ(e2 ).
Take arbitrary s, e ′ , s ′ , e ′′ , s ′′ such that he1 op e2 , si −→ he ′ , s ′ i∧he1 op e2 , si −→
he ′′ , s ′′ i.
39
By examining the expressions in the left-hand-sides of the conclusions of the rules,
and using the lemma above, the only possibilities are those below (you should
check why this is so for yourself).
case op = + and he1 + e2 , si −→ he ′ , s ′ i is an instance of (op+) and he1 +
e2 , si −→ he ′′ , s ′′ i is an instance of (op+ ).
Then for some n1 , n2 we have e1 = n1 , e2 = n2 , e ′ = n3 = e ′′ for n3 = n1 +n2 ,
and s ′ = s = s ′′ .
case op =≥ and he1 ≥ e2 , si −→ he ′ , s ′ i is an instance of (op≥) and he1 ≥
e2 , si −→ he ′′ , s ′′ i is an instance of (op≥).
Then for some n1 , n2 we have e1 = n1 , e2 = n2 , e ′ = b = e ′′ for b = (n1 ≥ n2 ),
and s ′ = s = s ′′ .
case he1 op e2 , si −→ he ′ , s ′ i is an instance of (op1) and he1 op e2 , si −→
he ′′ , s ′′ i is an instance of (op1).
Then for some e1′ and e1′′ we have he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i (*), he1 , si −→ he1′′ , s ′′ i
(**), e ′ = e1′ op e2 , and e ′′ = e1′′ op e2 . Now, by the induction hypothesis
Φ(e1 ), (*) and (**) we have he1′ , s ′ i = he1′′ , s ′′ i, so he ′ , s ′ i = he1′ op e2 , s ′ i =
he1′′ op e2 , s ′′ i = he ′′ , s ′′ i as required.
case he1 op e2 , si −→ he ′ , s ′ i is an instance of (op2) and he1 op e2 , si −→
he ′′ , s ′′ i is an instance of (op2).
Similar, save that we use the induction hypothesis Φ(e2 ).
Case e1 ; e2 . Suppose Φ(e1 ) and Φ(e2 ).
Take arbitrary s, e ′ , s ′ , e ′′ , s ′′ such that he1 ; e2 , si −→ he ′ , s ′ i ∧ he1 ; e2 , si −→
he ′′ , s ′′ i.
By examining the expressions in the left-hand-sides of the conclusions of the rules,
and using the lemma above, the only possibilities are those below.
case e1 = skip and both transitions are instances of (seq1).
Then he ′ , s ′ i = he2 , si = he ′′ , s ′′ i.
case e1 is not a value and both transitions are instances of (seq2). Then for some
e1′ and e1′′ we have he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i (*), he1 , si −→ he1′′ , s ′′ i (**), e ′ = e1′ ; e2 ,
and e ′′ = e1′′ ; e2
Then by the induction hypothesis Φ(e1 ) we have he1′ , s ′ i = he1′′ , s ′′ i, so
he ′ , s ′ i = he1′ ; e2 , s ′ i = he1′′ ; e2 , s ′′ i = he ′′ , s ′′ i as required.
Case while e1 do e2 . Suppose Φ(e1 ) and Φ(e2 ).
Take arbitrary s, e ′ , s ′ , e ′′ , s ′′ such that hwhile e1 do e2 , si −→ he ′ , s ′ i ∧
hwhile e1 do e2 , si −→ he ′′ , s ′′ i.
By examining the expressions in the left-hand-sides of the conclusions of the rules
both must be instances of (while), so he ′ , s ′ i = hif e1 then (e2 ; while e1 do e2 ) else skip, si =
he ′′ , s ′′ i.
Case if e1 then e2 else e3 . Suppose Φ(e1 ), Φ(e2 ) and Φ(e3 ).
Take arbitrary s, e ′ , s ′ , e ′′ , s ′′ such that hif e1 then e2 else e3 , si −→ he ′ , s ′ i ∧
hif e1 then e2 else e3 , si −→ he ′′ , s ′′ i.
By examining the expressions in the left-hand-sides of the conclusions of the rules,
and using the lemma above, the only possibilities are those below.
case e1 = true and both transitions are instances of (if1).
case e1 = false and both transitions are instances of (if2).
40
case e1 is not a value and both transitions are instances of (if3).
The first two cases are immediate; the last uses Φ(e1 ).
(check we’ve done all the cases!)
(note that the level of written detail can vary, as here – if you and the reader agree – but you
must do all the steps in your head. If in any doubt, write it down, as an aid to thought...!)
How to prove facts about all elements of the L1 typing relation or the L1
reduction relation, e.g. Progress or Type Preservation?
Slide 86
Theorem 2 (Progress) If Γ ⊢ e:T and dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s) then either e
is a value or there exist e ′ , s ′ such that he, si
−→ he ′ , s ′ i.
Theorem 3 (Type Preservation) If Γ ⊢ e:T and dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s)
and he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i then Γ ⊢ e ′ :T and dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s ′ ).
Inductive Definitions
41
For each rule we can construct the set of all concrete rule instances,
taking all values of the metavariables that satisfy the side condition. For
example, for (op + ) and (op1) we take all values of n1 , n2 , s, n
(satisfying n = n1 + n2 ) and of e1 , e2 , s, e1′ , s ′ .
Slide 89
(op+ ) (op + )
h2 + 2, {}i −→ h4, {}i , h2 + 3, {}i −→ h5, {}i , ...
Note the last has a premise that is not itself derivable, but nonetheless this is a legitimate
instance of (op1).
(op+)
h2 + 2, {}i −→ h4, {}i
(op1)
h(2 + 2) + 3, {}i −→ h4 + 3, {}i
(op1)
h(2 + 2) + 3 ≥ 5, {}i −→ h4 + 3 ≥ 5, {}i
Slide 90
(deref) (int)
Γ ⊢!l :int Γ ⊢ 2:int (op +) (int)
Γ ⊢ (!l + 2):int Γ ⊢ 3:int
(op +)
Γ ⊢ (!l + 2) + 3:int
and he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i is an element of the reduction relation
(resp. Γ ⊢ e:T is an element of the transition relation) iff there is a
derivation with that as the root node.
For any property Φ(a) of elements a of A, and any set of rules which
define a subset SR of A, to prove
∀ a ∈ SR .Φ(a)
Slide 91
it’s enough to prove that {a | Φ(a)} is closed under the rules, ie for each
concrete rule instance
h1 .. hk
c
if Φ(h1 ) ∧ ... ∧ Φ(hk ) then Φ(c).
For some proofs a slightly different principle is useful – this variant allows you to assume
each of the hi are themselves members of SR .
42
Principle of rule induction (a slight variant)
For any property Φ(a) of elements a of A, and any set of rules which
inductively define the set SR , to prove
∀ a ∈ SR .Φ(a)
Slide 92
(This is just the original principle for the property (Φ(a) ∧ a ∈ SR ).)
Principle of Rule Induction (variant form): to prove Φ(a) for all a in the
set SR , it’s enough to prove that for each concrete rule instance
h1 .. hk
c
43
Which Induction Principle to Use?
Example Proofs
In the notes there are detailed example proofs for Determinacy (structural
Slide 97 induction), Progress (rule induction on type derivations), and Type
Preservation (rule induction on reduction derivations).
What’s a proof?
Remember – the point is to use the mathematics to help you think about things that are too
complex to keep in your head all at once: to keep track of all the cases etc. To do that, and
to communicate with other people, it’s important to write down the reasoning and proof
structure as clearly as possible. After you’ve done a proof you should give it to someone
(your supervision partner first, perhaps) to see if they (a) can understand what you’ve said,
and (b) if they believe it.
1. proof lets you see (and explain) why they are obvious
44
Theorem 2 (Progress) If Γ ⊢ e:T and dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s) then either e is a value or there
exist e ′ , s ′ such that he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i.
Proof Take
def
Φ(Γ, e, T ) = ∀ s.dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s) ⇒ value(e) ∨ (∃ e ′ , s ′ .he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i)
We show that for all Γ, e, T , if Γ ⊢ e:T then Φ(Γ, e, T ), by rule induction on the
definition of ⊢.
Case (int). Recall the rule scheme
It has no premises, so we have to show that for all instances Γ, e, T of the con-
clusion we have Φ(Γ, e, T ).
For any such instance, there must be an n ∈ Z for which e = n.
Now Φ is of the form ∀ s.dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s) ⇒ ..., so consider an arbitrary s and
assume dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s).
We have to show value(e) ∨ (∃ e ′ , s ′ .he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i). But the first disjunct is
true as integers are values (according to the definition).
Case (bool) similar.
Case (op+ ). Recall the rule
Γ ⊢ e1 :int
Γ ⊢ e2 :int
(op +)
Γ ⊢ e1 + e2 :int
We have to show that for all Γ, e1 , e2 , if Φ(Γ, e1 , int) and Φ(Γ, e2 , int) then Φ(Γ, e1 +
e2 , int).
Suppose Φ(Γ, e1 , int) (*), Φ(Γ, e2 , int) (**), Γ ⊢ e1 :int (***), and Γ ⊢ e2 :int (****)
(note that we’re using the variant form of rule induction here).
Consider an arbitrary s. Assume dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s).
We have to show value(e1 + e2 ) ∨ (∃ e ′ , s ′ .he1 + e2 , si −→ he ′ , s ′ i).
Now the first disjunct is false (e1 + e2 is not a value), so we have to show the
second, i.e.∃he ′ , s ′ i.he1 + e2 , si −→ he ′ , s ′ i.
By (*) one of the following holds.
case ∃ e1′ , s ′ .he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i.
Then by (op1) we have he1 + e2 , si −→ he1′ + e2 , s ′ i, so we are done.
case e1 is a value. By (**) one of the following holds.
case ∃ e2′ , s ′ .he2 , si −→ he2′ , s ′ i.
Then by (op2) he1 + e2 , si −→ he1 + e2′ , s ′ i, so we are done.
case e2 is a value.
(Now want to use (op+ ), but need to know that e1 and e2 are really
integers. )
Lemma 13 for all Γ, e, T , if Γ ⊢ e:T , e is a value and T = int then for
some n ∈ Z we have e = n.
Proof By rule induction. Take Φ′ (Γ, e, T ) = ((value(e) ∧ T = int) ⇒
∃ n ∈ Z.e = n).
Case (int). ok
45
Case (bool),(skip). In instances of these rules the conclusion is a
value but the type is not int, so ok.
Case otherwise. In instances of all other rules the conclusion is
not a value, so ok.
(a rather trivial use of rule induction – we never needed to use the
induction hypothesis, just to do case analysis of the last rule that
might have been used in a derivation of Γ ⊢ e:T ).
Using the Lemma, (***) and (****) there exist n1 ∈ Z and n2 ∈ Z
such that e1 = n1 and e2 = n2 . Then by (op+) he1 + e2 , si −→ hn, si
where n = n1 + n2 , so we are done.
Case (op ≥ ). Similar to (op + ).
Case (if). Recall the rule
Γ ⊢ e1 :bool
Γ ⊢ e2 :T
Γ ⊢ e3 :T
(if)
Γ ⊢ if e1 then e2 else e3 :T
Suppose Φ(Γ, e1 , bool) (*1), Φ(Γ, e2 , T ) (*2), Φ(Γ, e3 , T ) (*3), Γ ⊢ e1 :bool (*4),
Γ ⊢ e2 :T (*5) and Γ ⊢ e3 :T (*6).
Consider an arbitrary s. Assume dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s). Write e for if e1 then e2 else e3 .
This e is not a value, so we have to show he, si has a transition.
case ∃ e1′ , s ′ .he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i.
Then by (if3) he, si −→ hif e1′ then e2 else e3 , si, so we are done.
case e1 is a value.
(Now want to use (if1) or (if2), but need to know that e1 ∈ {true, false}.
Realize should have proved a stronger Lemma above).
Lemma 14 For all Γ, e, T . if Γ ⊢ e:T and e is a value, then T = int ⇒
∃ n ∈ Z.e = n, T = bool ⇒ ∃ b ∈ {true, false}.e = b, and T = unit ⇒
e = skip.
Proof By rule induction – details omitted.
Using the Lemma and (*4) we have ∃ b ∈ {true, false}.e1 = b.
case b = true. Use (if1).
case b = false. Use (if2).
Case (deref). Recall the rule
Γ(ℓ) = intref
(deref)
Γ ⊢!ℓ:int
46
Theorem 3 (Type Preservation) If Γ ⊢ e:T and dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s) and he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
then Γ ⊢ e ′ :T and dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s ′ ).
Proof First show the second part, using the following lemma.
Lemma 16 If he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i then dom(s ′ ) = dom(s).
Proof Rule induction on derivations of he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i. Take Φ(e, s, e ′ , s ′ ) =
(dom(s) = dom(s ′ )).
All rules are immediate uses of the induction hypothesis except (assign1),
for which we note that if ℓ ∈ dom(s) then dom(s + (ℓ 7→ n)) = dom(s).
Now prove the first part, ie If Γ ⊢ e:T and dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s) and he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
then Γ ⊢ e ′ :T .
Prove by rule induction on derivations of he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i.
Take Φ(e, s, e ′ , s ′ ) = ∀ Γ, T .(Γ ⊢ e:T ∧ dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s)) ⇒ Γ ⊢ e ′ :T .
Case (op+). Recall
(op +) hn1 + n2 , si −→ hn, si if n = n1 + n2
Suppose Φ(e1 , s, e1′ , s ′ ) (*) and he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i. Have to show Φ(e1 op e2 , s, e1′ op e2 , s ′ ).
Take arbitrary Γ, T . Suppose Γ ⊢ e1 op e2 :T and dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s) (**).
case op = +. The last rule in the derivation of Γ ⊢ e1 + e2 :T must have been
(op+), so must have T = int, Γ ⊢ e1 :int (***) and Γ ⊢ e2 :int (****). By the
induction hypothesis (*), (**), and (***) we have Γ ⊢ e1′ :int. By the (op+)
rule Γ ⊢ e1′ + e2 :T .
case op =≥. Similar.
Case s (op2) (deref), (assign1), (assign2), (seq1), (seq2), (if1), (if2), (if3), (while).
Left as exercises.
Theorem 4 (Safety) If Γ ⊢ e:T , dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s), and he, si −→ he , s i then either e ′
∗ ′ ′
47
Proving Progress
Principle of Rule Induction (variant form): to prove Φ(a) for all a in the set
SR defined by the rules, it’s enough to prove that for each rule instance
h1 .. hk
c
def
Φ(Γ, e, T ) = ∀ s. dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s) ⇒
value(e) ∨ (∃ e ′ , s ′ .he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i)
Γ ⊢ e1 :int
Slide 103
Γ ⊢ e2 :int
(op +)
Γ ⊢ e1 + e2 :int
48
Using Φ(Γ, e1 , int) and Φ(Γ, e2 , int) we have:
3.4 Exercises
You should be able to prove all the theorems about L1 independently. These exercises are
to get you started.
Exercise 12 ⋆Without looking at the proof in the notes, do the cases of the proof of The-
orem 1 (Determinacy) for e1 op e2 , e1 ; e2 , while e1 do e2 , and if e1 then e2 else e3 .
Exercise 13 ⋆Try proving Determinacy for the language with nondeterministic order of
evaluation for e1 op e2 (ie with both (op1) and (op1b) rules), which is not determinate.
Explain where exactly the proof can’t be carried through.
Exercise 13.5 ⋆ Flesh out the statements of Inversion for the operational semantics and
type system. Prove them by rule induction (this needs a trivial use of rule induction, without
relying on the induction hypothesis).
Exercise 14 ⋆Complete the proof of Theorem 2 (Progress).
Exercise 15 ⋆⋆Complete the proof of Theorem 3 (Type Preservation).
Exercise 16 ⋆⋆Give an alternate proof of Theorem 3 (Type Preservation) by rule induc-
tion over type derivations.
Exercise 17 ⋆⋆Prove Theorem 7 (Uniqueness of Typing).
49
4 Functions
Slide 107
Functions – L2
<script type="text/vbscript">
function addone(x)
addone = x+1
end function
</script>
C♯
class M {
public static void Main() {
IntThunk[] funcs = new IntThunk[11];
for (int i = 0; i <= 10; i++)
Slide 109 {
funcs[i] = delegate() { return i; };
}
foreach (IntThunk f in funcs)
{
System.Console.WriteLine(f());
}
}
}
Most languages have some kind of function, method, or procedure – some way of abstracting
a piece of code on a formal parameter so that you can use the code multiple times with
different arguments, without having to duplicate the code in the source. The next two
lectures explore the design space for functions, adding them to L1.
50
Functions – Examples
(fn x:int ⇒ x + 1)
(fn x:int ⇒ x + 1) 7
Slide 110 (fn y:int ⇒ (fn x:int ⇒ x + y))
(fn y:int ⇒ (fn x:int ⇒ x + y)) 1
(fn x:int → int ⇒ (fn y:int ⇒ x (x y)))
(fn x:int → int ⇒ (fn y:int ⇒ x (x y))) (fn x:int ⇒ x + 1)
� �
(fn x:int → int ⇒ (fn y:int ⇒ x (x y))) (fn x:int ⇒ x + 1) 7
For simplicity, we’ll deal with anonymous functions only. Functions will always take a single
argument and return a single result — though either might itself be a function or a tuple.
Functions – Syntax
51
Some languages go further, forbidding partial application. We’ll come back to this.
In order to express the semantics for functions, we need some auxiliary definitions.
Variable shadowing
Variable shadowing is not allowed in Java. For large systems that would be a problem, eg
in a language with nested function definitions, where you may wish to write a local function
parameter without being aware of what is in the surrounding namespace.
Alpha conversion
Slide 114
17
x+y
fn x:int ⇒ x + 2
fn x:int ⇒ x + z
if y then 2 + x else ((fn x:int ⇒ x + 2)z)
All the other occurrences of x are bound by the closest enclosing
fn x :T ⇒ ....
Note that in fn x:int ⇒ 2 the x is not an occurrence. Likewise, in fn x:int ⇒ x + 2 the left
x is not an occurrence; here the right x is an occurrence that is bound by the left x.
52
Sometimes it is handy to draw in the binding:
�
fn x:int ⇒x+z
Slide 115 �
fn y:int ⇒y+z
�
fn z:int ⇒z+z
�
fn x:int ⇒ (fn x:int ⇒x+2)
+ ■■ + ■■ + ■■
tt ■■ ✉✉ ■■ ✉✉ ■■
ttt ■■ ✉✉ ■■ ✉✉✉ ■■
Slide 117 x
t
z ✉✉ z
✉
z
y z
add pointers (from each x node to the closest enclosing fn x :T ⇒ node);
remove names of binders and the occurrences they bind
+ ❏❏ + ❏❏ + ❏❏
tt ❏❏ tt ❏❏ tt ❏❏
ttt ❏❏ ttt ❏❏ ttt ❏❏
t t t
• z • z • •
53
fn x:int ⇒ (fn x:int ⇒ x + 2)
= fn y:int ⇒ (fn z:int ⇒ z + 2) 6= fn z:int ⇒ (fn y:int ⇒ z + 2)
fn ·� :int ⇒ fn · :int ⇒
+ ■■ + ■■
✉✉ ■■ ✉✉ ■■
✉✉✉ ■■ ✉✉✉ ■■
✉ ✉
• 2 • 2
@ fn · :int →
� int → int ⇒
tt ✷✷✷
ttt
Slide 119 fn ·� :int ⇒ 7 fn · :int
� ⇒�
• ❥❥ @ ❙❙❙❙❙
❥ ❥❥❥❥❥❥ ❙❙❙
❙❙❙
❥❥❥ ❙
@ ❚❚❚❚
❚❚❚❚
•
☛☛☛ ❚❚❚
☛ ❚❚
• •
De Bruijn indices
fn ·� :int ⇒ fn · :int ⇒
✉ + ■■■ ✉ + ■■■
✉✉✉ ■■ ✉✉✉ ■■
✉✉ ■ ✉✉ ■
• 2 • 2
Free Variables
Say the free variables of an expression e are the set of variables x for
which there is an occurence of x free in e .
fv(x ) = {x }
Slide 121 fv(e1 op e2 ) = fv(e1 ) ∪ fv(e2 )
fv(fn x :T ⇒ e) = fv(e) − {x }
54
For example
fv(x + y) = {x, y}
fv(fn x:int ⇒ x + y) = {y}
fv(x + (fn x:int ⇒ x + y)7) = {x, y}
fv(x ) = {x }
fv(fn x :T ⇒ e) = fv(e) − {x }
fv(e1 e2 ) = fv(e1 ) ∪ fv(e2 )
fv(n) = {}
fv(e1 op e2 ) = fv(e1 ) ∪ fv(e2 )
fv(if e1 then e2 else e3 ) = fv(e1 ) ∪ fv(e2 ) ∪ fv(e3 )
fv(b) = {}
fv(skip) = {}
fv(ℓ := e) = fv(e)
fv(!ℓ) = {}
fv(e1 ; e2 ) = fv(e1 ) ∪ fv(e2 )
fv(while e1 do e2 ) = fv(e1 ) ∪ fv(e2 )
The semantics for functions will involve substituting actual parameters for formal parame-
ters.
Substitution – Examples
The semantics for functions will involve substituting actual parameters for
formal parameters.
Write {e/x }e ′ for the result of substituting e for all free occurrences of x
in e ′ . For example
Slide 122
{3/x}(x ≥ x) = (3 ≥ 3)
{3/x}((fn x:int ⇒ x + y)x) = (fn x:int ⇒ x + y)3
{y + 2/x}(fn y:int ⇒ x + y) = fn z:int ⇒ (y + 2) + z
Note that substitution is a meta-operation – it’s not part of the L2 expression grammar.
The notation used for substitution varies – people write {3/x }e, or [3/x ]e, or e[3/x ], or
{x ← 3}e, or...
Substitution – Definition
Defining that:
{e/z }x = e if x =z
= x otherwise
55
Substitution – Example Again
{y + 2/x}(fn y:int ⇒ x + y)
= {y + 2/x}(fn y′ :int ⇒ x + y′ ) renaming
= fn y′ :int ⇒ {y + 2/x}(x + y′ ) as y′ 6= x and y′ ∈
/ fv(y + 2)
Slide 124
= fn y′ :int ⇒ {y + 2/x}x + {y + 2/x}y′
= fn y′ :int ⇒ (y + 2) + y′
Simultaneous substitution
σx = σ(x ) if x ∈ dom(σ)
= x otherwise
σ(fn x :T ⇒ e) = fn x :T ⇒ (σ e) if x ∈
/ dom(σ) and x ∈
/ fv(ran(σ)) (*)
σ(e1 e2 ) = (σ e1 )(σ e2 )
σn = n
σ(e1 op e2 ) = σ(e1 ) op σ(e2 )
σ(if e1 then e2 else e3 ) = if σ(e1 ) then σ(e2 ) else σ(e3 )
σ(b) = b
σ(skip) = skip
σ(ℓ := e) = ℓ := σ(e)
σ(!ℓ) = !ℓ
σ(e1 ; e2 ) = σ(e1 ); σ(e2 )
σ(while e1 do e2 ) = while σ(e1 ) do σ(e2 )
Function Behaviour
56
Function Behaviour. Choice 1: Call-by-value
This is a common design choice — ML, Java. It is a strict semantics – fully evaluating the
argument to function before doing the application.
L2 Call-by-value
• The rules for these constructs don’t touch the store. In a pure functional language,
configurations would just be expressions.
• A naive implementation of these rules would have to traverse e and copy v as many
times as there are free occurrences of x in e. Real implementations don’t do that,
using environments instead of doing substitution. Environments are more efficient;
substitutions are simpler to write down – so better for implementation and semantics
respectively.
57
Function Behaviour. Choice 2: Call-by-name
L2 Call-by-name
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(CBN-app)
he1 e2 , si −→ he1′ e2 , s ′ i
Without strict, call-by-value semantics, it becomes hard to understand what order your code
is going to be run in. Non-strict languages typically don’t allow unrestricted side effects (our
combination of store and CBN is pretty odd ). Haskell encourages pure programming, without
effects (store operations, IO, etc.) except where really necessary. Where they are necessary,
it uses a fancy type system to give you some control of evaluation order.
For a pure language, Call-By-Name gives the same results as Call-By-Need, which is more
efficient. The first time the argument evaluated we ‘overwrite’ all other copies by that value.
58
Slide 133 Purity
Allow both left and right-hand sides of application to reduce. At any point
where the left-hand-side has reduced to a fn-term, replace all
Slide 134
occurrences of the formal parameter in the fn-term by the argument.
Allow reduction inside lambdas.
L2 Beta
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(beta-app1)
he1 e2 , si −→ he1′ e2 , s ′ i
he2 , si −→ he2′ , s ′ i
(beta-app2)
Slide 135 he1 e2 , si −→ he1 e2′ , s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(beta-fn2)
hfn x :T ⇒ e, si −→ hfn x :T ⇒ e ′ , s ′ i
This reduction relation includes the CBV and CBN relations, and also reduction inside
lambdas.
L2 Beta: Example
(fn x:int ⇒ x + x)
❲❲❲(2
❲❲ + 2)❲❲❲❲❲
③③ ❲❲❲❲❲
�③③ �
(fn x:int ⇒ x■ + x) 4 (2 + 2) + (2 + 2)
❙❙❙
■■ ❦
Slide 136 ■■ ❦❦❦ ❙❙❙
■■ �❦❦❦ ❙�
■■ 4 + (2 + 2) (2 + 2) + 4
■■ ❡❡❡
■■ ❡
■■ ❡❡❡❡❡❡
� � ❡❡❡❡❡❡
�❡❡❡❡❡❡
4+4
�
8
• What will (fn x:unit ⇒ skip) (while true do skip) do in the different semantics?
• What about (fn x:unit ⇒ skip) (ℓ :=!ℓ + 1)?
Slide 138 Back to CBV (from now on).
59
4.3 Function Typing
(var) Γ ⊢ x :T if Γ(x ) =T
(app) Γ ⊢ e1 :T → T ′ Γ ⊢ e2 :T
Γ ⊢ e1 e2 :T ′
• Note that sometimes you need the alpha convention, e.g. to type
fn x:int ⇒ x + (fn x:bool ⇒ if x then 3 else 4)true
It’s a good idea to start out with all binders different from each other and from all
free variables. It would be a bad idea to prohibit variable shadowing like this in source
programs.
• In ML you have parametrically polymorphic functions, e.g. (fn x:α ⇒ x):α → α, but
we won’t talk about them here – that’s in Part II Types.
60
Another example:
(int)
l :intref, x:unit ⊢ 1:int
(asn) (var)
l :intref, x:unit ⊢ (l := 1):unit l :intref, x:unit ⊢ x:unit
(seq) (int)
l :intref, x:unit ⊢ (l := 1); x:unit l :intref ⊢ 2:int
(fn) (asn)
l :intref ⊢ (fn x:unit ⇒ (l := 1); x):unit → unit l :intref ⊢ (l := 2):unit
(app)
l :intref ⊢ (fn x:unit ⇒ (l := 1); x) (l := 2):unit
Properties of Typing
Taking
Φ(e, s, e ′ , s ′ ) =
Slide 144
∀ Γ, T .
Γ ⊢ e:T ∧ closed(e) ∧ dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s)
⇒
Γ ⊢ e ′ :T ∧ closed(e ′ ) ∧ dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s ′ )
Normalization
61
4.4 Local Definitions and Recursive Functions
Local definitions
(let)
Γ ⊢ e1 :T Γ, x :T ⊢ e2 :T ′
Γ ⊢ let val x :T = e1 in e2 end:T ′
Slide 148
(let1)
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
hlet val x :T = e1 in e2 end, si −→ hlet val x :T = e1′ in e2 end, s ′ i
(let2)
Our alpha convention means this really is a local definition – there is no way to refer to the
locally-defined variable outside the let val .
How about
62
But...
What about
Recursive Functions
Slide 151 e ::= ... | let val rec x :T1 → T2 = (fn y:T1 ⇒ e1 ) in e2 end
(here the y binds in e1 ; the x binds in (fn y:T ⇒ e1 ) and in e2 )
63
For example:
Below, in the context of the let val rec , x f n finds the smallest n ′ ≥ n for which f n ′
′
evaluates to some m ≤ 0.
xf0
end
end
As a test case, we apply it to the function (fn z :int ⇒ if z ≥ 3 then (if 3 ≥ z then 0 else 1) else 1),
which is 0 for argument 3 and 1 elsewhere.
64
More Syntactic Sugar
Do we need e1 ; e2 ?
Do we need while e1 do e2 ?
No: could encode by while e1 do e2
Slide 154
let val rec w:unit → unit =
fn y:unit ⇒ if e1 then (e2 ; (w skip)) else skip
in
w skip
end
In each case typing is the same. Reduction is ‘essentially’ the same — we will be able to
make this precise when we study contextual equivalence.
4.5 Implementation
Implementation
The implementation lets you type in L2 expressions and initial stores and watch them
resolve, type-check, and reduce.
65
Implementation – Substitution
If e’ represents a closed term fn x :T ⇒ e1′ then e’ = Fn(t,e1’) for t and e1’ representing
T and e1′ . If also e represents a closed term e then subst e 0 e1’ represents {e/x }e1′ .
type typeEnv
= (loc*type loc) list * type expr list
66
Implementation – Closures
(if you get that wrong, you end up with dynamic scoping, as in original
LISP)
67
4.6 L2: Collected Definition
Syntax
Operational Semantics
Say stores s are finite partial functions from L to Z. Values v ::= b | n | skip | fn x :T ⇒ e
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(op1)
he1 op e2 , si −→ he1′ op e2 , s ′ i
he2 , si −→ he2′ , s ′ i
(op2)
hv op e2 , si −→ hv op e2′ , s ′ i
(deref) h!ℓ, si −→ hn, si if ℓ ∈ dom(s) and s(ℓ) = n
68
(if1) hif true then e2 else e3 , si −→ he2 , si
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(if3)
hif e1 then e2 else e3 , si −→ hif e1′ then e2 else e3 , s ′ i
(while)
hwhile e1 do e2 , si −→ hif e1 then (e2 ; while e1 do e2 ) else skip, si
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(app1)
he1 e2 , si −→ he1′ e2 , s ′ i
he2 , si −→ he2′ , s ′ i
(app2)
hv e2 , si −→ hv e2′ , s ′ i
(let1)
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
hlet val x :T = e1 in e2 end, si −→ hlet val x :T = e1′ in e2 end, s ′ i
(let2)
hlet val x :T = v in e2 end, si −→ h{v /x }e2 , si
Typing
Type environments Γ are now pairs of a Γloc (a partial function from L to Tloc as before)
and a Γvar , a partial function from X to T.
Γ ⊢ e1 :int Γ ⊢ e1 :int
Γ ⊢ e2 :int Γ ⊢ e2 :int
(op +) (op ≥)
Γ ⊢ e1 + e2 :int Γ ⊢ e1 ≥ e2 :bool
(if) Γ ⊢ e1 :bool Γ ⊢ e2 :T Γ ⊢ e3 :T
Γ ⊢ if e1 then e2 else e3 :T
Γ(ℓ) = intref
(deref)
Γ ⊢!ℓ:int
69
(skip) Γ ⊢ skip:unit
(seq) Γ ⊢ e1 :unit Γ ⊢ e2 :T
Γ ⊢ e1 ; e2 :T
(var) Γ ⊢ x :T if Γ(x ) = T
Γ, x :T ⊢ e:T ′
(fn)
Γ ⊢ fn x :T ⇒ e : T → T ′
′
(app) Γ ⊢ e1 :T → T Γ ⊢ e2 :T
Γ ⊢ e1 e2 :T ′
Γ ⊢ e1 :T Γ, x :T ⊢ e2 :T ′
(let)
Γ ⊢ let val x :T = e1 in e2 end:T ′
70
4.7 Exercises
71
5 Data
Slide 162
Data – L3
So far we have only looked at very simple basic data types – int, bool, and unit, and functions
over them. We now explore more structured data, in as simple a form as possible, and revisit
the semantics of mutable store.
The two basic notions are the product and the sum type.
The product type T1 ∗ T2 lets you tuple together values of types T1 and T2 – so for example
a function that takes an integer and returns a pair of an integer and a boolean has type
int → (int ∗ bool). In C one has structs; in Java classes can have many fields.
The sum type T1 + T2 lets you form a disjoint union, with a value of the sum type either
being a value of type T1 or a value of type T2 . In C one has unions; in Java one might
have many subclasses of a class (see the l1.java representation of the L1 abstract syntax,
for example).
In most languages these appear in richer forms, e.g. with labelled records rather than simple
products, or labelled variants, or ML datatypes with named constructors, rather than simple
sums. We’ll look at labelled records in detail, as a preliminary to the later lecture on
subtyping.
Many languages don’t allow structured data types to appear in arbitrary positions – e.g. the
old C lack of support for functions that return structured values, inherited from close-to-
the-metal early implementations. They might therefore have to have functions or methods
that take a list of arguments, rather than a single argument that could be of product (or
sum, or record) type.
Products
Design choices:
• pairs, not arbitrary tuples – have int ∗ (int ∗ int) and (int ∗ int) ∗ int, but (a) they’re
different, and (b) we don’t have (int ∗ int ∗ int). In a full language you’d likely allow
(b) (and still have it be a different type from the other two).
• have projections #1 and #2, not pattern matching fn (x , y) ⇒ e. A full language
should allow the latter, as it often makes for much more elegant code.
• don’t have #e e ′ (couldn’t typecheck!).
72
Products – typing
(proj2) Γ ⊢ e:T1 ∗ T2
Γ ⊢ #2 e:T2
Products – reduction
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(pair1)
h(e1 , e2 ), si −→ h(e1′ , e2 ), s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(proj3) (proj4)
′ ′
h#1 e, si −→ h#1 e , s i h#2 e, si −→ h#2 e ′ , s ′ i
T ::= ... | T1 + T2
Here we diverge slightly from Moscow ML syntax – our T1 + T2 corresponds to the Moscow
ML (T1,T2) Sum in the context of the declaration
datatype (’a,’b) Sum = inl of ’a | inr of ’b;
Sums – typing
(inl) Γ ⊢ e:T1
Γ ⊢ inl e:T1 + T2 :T1 + T2
(inr) Γ ⊢ e:T2
Γ ⊢ inr e:T1 + T2 :T1 + T2
Slide 167
Γ ⊢ e:T1 + T2
Γ, x :T1 ⊢ e1 :T
Γ, y:T2 ⊢ e2 :T
(case)
Γ ⊢ case e of inl (x :T1 ) ⇒ e1 | inr (y:T2 ) ⇒ e2 :T
73
Sums – type annotations
Slide 168
To maintain the unique typing property. Otherwise
You might instead have a compiler use a type inference algorithm that can infer them,
or require every sum type in a program to be declared, each with different names for the
constructors inl , inr (cf OCaml).
Sums – reduction
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(inl)
hinl e:T , si −→ hinl e ′ :T , s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(inr)
hinr e:T , si −→ hinr e ′ :T , s ′ i
Slide 170 T →T fn x :T ⇒ e
T ∗T (, ) #1 #2
T +T inl ( ) inr ( ) case
bool true false if
74
Proofs as programs: The Curry-Howard correspondence
(var) Γ, x :T ⊢ x :T Γ, P ⊢ P
(fn)
Γ, x :T ⊢ e:T ′ Γ, P ⊢ P ′
Γ ⊢ fn x :T ⇒ e : T → T ′ Γ ⊢ P → P′
Slide 171
(app) Γ ⊢ e1 :T → T ′ Γ ⊢ e2 :T Γ ⊢ P → P′ Γ ⊢ P
Γ ⊢ e1 e2 :T ′ Γ ⊢ P′
Γ, x :T ⊢ e:T ′ Γ, P ⊢ P ′
(fn)
Γ ⊢ fn x :T ⇒ e : T → T ′ Γ ⊢ P → P′
Γ ⊢ e1 :T → T ′ Γ ⊢ e2 :T Γ ⊢ P → P′ Γ⊢P
(app)
Γ ⊢ e1 e2 :T ′ Γ ⊢ P′
Γ ⊢ e:T1 ∗ T2 Γ ⊢ e:T1 ∗ T2 Γ ⊢ P1 ∧ P 2 Γ ⊢ P1 ∧ P 2
(proj1) (proj2)
Γ ⊢ #1 e:T1 Γ ⊢ #2 e:T2 Γ ⊢ P1 Γ ⊢ P2
Γ ⊢ e:T1 Γ ⊢ P1
(inl)
Γ ⊢ inl e:T1 + T2 :T1 + T2 Γ ⊢ P1 ∨ P 2
The typing rules for a pure language correspond to the rules for a natural deduction calculus.
ML Datatypes
In L3 you cannot define IntList. It involves recursion at the type level (e.g. types for binary
trees). Making this precise is beyond the scope of this course.
75
Records
A generalization of products.
Note:
• Labels are not the same syntactic class as variables, so (fn x:T ⇒ {x = 3}) is not an
expression.
• In ML a pair (true, fn x:int ⇒ x) is syntactic sugar for a record {1 = true, 2 = fn x:int ⇒ x}.
• Note that #lab e is not an application, it just looks like one in the concrete syntax.
• Again we will choose a left-to-right evaluation order for consistency.
Records – typing
(recordproj)
Γ ⊢ e:{lab 1 :T1 , .., lab k :Tk }
Γ ⊢ #lab i e:Ti
• Here the field order matters, so (fn x:{ℓ1 :int, ℓ2 :bool} ⇒ x){ℓ2 = true, ℓ1 = 17} does
not typecheck.
• Here you can reuse labels, so {} ⊢ ({ℓ1 = 17}, {ℓ1 = true}):{ℓ1 :int} ∗ {ℓ1 :bool} is legal,
but in some languages (e.g. OCaml) you can’t.
Records – reduction
hei , si −→ hei′ , s ′ i
(record1) h{lab 1 = v1 , .., lab i = ei , .., lab k = ek }, si
Slide 176 −→ h{lab 1 = v1 , .., lab i = ei′ , .., lab k = ek }, s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(record3)
h#lab i e, si −→ h#lab i e ′ , s ′ i
76
5.3 Mutable Store
Mutable Store
Most languages have some kind of mutable store. Two main choices:
Slide 177
e ::= ... | ℓ := e |!ℓ | x
2 In C and Java,
• variables let you refer to a previously calculated value and let you
overwrite that value with another.
void foo(x:int) {
Slide 178
• implicit dereferencing, l = l + x
...}
• have some limited type machinery to limit mutability.
– pros and cons: ....
We are staying with option 1 here. But we will now overcome some limitations of references
in L1/L2:
• can only store ints – we would like to store any value
• cannot create new locations (all must exist at beginning)
• cannot write functions that abstract on locations fn l :intref ⇒!l
References
We are now allowing variables of T ref type, e.g.fn x:int ref ⇒!x. Whole programs should
now have no locations at the start. They should create new locations with ref.
77
References – Typing
(ref) Γ ⊢ e:T
Γ ⊢ ref e : T ref
(assign) Γ ⊢ e1 :T ref Γ ⊢ e2 :T
Γ ⊢ e1 := e2 :unit
Slide 180
(loc)
Γ(ℓ) = T ref
Γ ⊢ ℓ:T ref
References – Reduction
A location is a value:
v ::= ... | ℓ
Stores s were finite partial maps from L to Z. From now on, take them to
be finite partial maps from L to the set of all values.
Slide 181
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(ref2)
h ref e, si −→ h ref e ′ , s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(deref2)
h!e, si −→ h!e ′ , s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(assign2)
hℓ := e, si −→ hℓ := e ′ , s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(assign3)
he := e2 , si −→ he ′ := e2 , s ′ i
• A ref has to do something at runtime – ( ref 0, ref 0) should return a pair of two new
locations, each containing 0, not a pair of one location repeated.
• Note the typing and this dynamics permit locations to contain locations, e.g. ref( ref 3).
• This semantics no longer has determinacy, for a technical reason – new locations are
chosen arbitrarily. At the cost of some slight semantic complexity, we could regain
determinacy by working ‘up to alpha for locations’.
• Within the language you cannot do arithmetic on locations (can in C, can’t in Java)
or test whether one is bigger than another. In L3 you cannot even test locations for
equality (in ML you can).
• This store just grows during computation – an implementation can garbage collect.
78
We don’t have an explicit deallocation operation – if you do, you need a very baroque
type system to prevent dangling pointers being dereferenced.
For L1, our type properties used dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s) to express the
Slide 183 condition ‘all locations mentioned in Γ exist in the store s ’.
Now need more: for each ℓ ∈ dom(s) need that s(ℓ) is typable.
Moreover, s(ℓ) might contain some other locations...
Consider
Have made a recursive function by ‘tying the knot by hand’, not using let val rec . To do
this we needed to store function values. We couldn’t do this in L2, so this doesn’t contradict
the normalization theorem we had there.
Implementation
79
5.4 Evaluation Contexts
We end this chapter by showing a slightly different style for defining operational semantics,
collecting together many of the context rules into a single (eval) rule that uses a definition
of a set of evaluation contexts to describe where in your program the next step of reduction
can take place. This style becomes much more convenient for large languages, though for
L1 and L2 there’s not much advantage either way.
Evaluation Contexts
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(eval)
hE [e], si −→ hE [e ′ ], s ′ i
replacing the rules (all those with ≥ 1 premise) (op1), (op2), (seq2), (if3),
(app1), (app2), (let1), (pair1), (pair2), (proj3), (proj4), (inl), (inr), (case1),
Slide 188
(record1), (record3), (ref2), (deref2), (assign2), (assign3).
To (eval) we add all the computation rules (all the rest) (op + ), (op ≥ ),
(seq1), (if1), (if2), (while), (fn), (let2), (letrecfn), (proj1), (proj2), (case2),
(case3), (record2), (ref1), (deref1), (assign1).
A Little History
Formal logic 1880–
Fortran 1950s
Haskell 1987
Subtyping 1980s
And now? module systems, distribution, mobility, reasoning about objects, security, typed compilation,.......
80
5.5 L3: Collected definition
L3 syntax
T ::= int | bool | unit | T1 → T2 |T1 ∗ T2 |T1 + T2 |{lab 1 :T1 , .., lab k :Tk }|T ref
Expressions
(where in each record (type or expression) no lab occurs more than once)
In expressions fn x :T ⇒ e the x is a binder. In expressions let val x :T = e1 in e2 end
the x is a binder. In expressions let val rec x :T1 → T2 = (fn y:T1 ⇒ e1 ) in e2 end
the y binds in e1 ; the x binds in (fn y:T ⇒ e1 ) and in e2 . In case e of inl (x1 :T1 ) ⇒ e1 |
inr (x2 :T2 ) ⇒ e2 the x1 binds in e1 and the x2 binds in e2 .
L3 semantics
Stores s are finite partial maps from L to the set of all values.
Values v ::= b | n | skip | fn x :T ⇒ e|(v1 , v2 )|inl v :T | inr v :T |{lab 1 = v1 , .., lab k = vk }|ℓ
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(op1)
he1 op e2 , si −→ he1′ op e2 , s ′ i
he2 , si −→ he2′ , s ′ i
(op2)
hv op e2 , si −→ hv op e2′ , s ′ i
(seq1) hskip; e2 , si −→ he2 , si
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(seq2)
he1 ; e2 , si −→ he1′ ; e2 , s ′ i
81
(if1) hif true then e2 else e3 , si −→ he2 , si
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(if3)
hif e1 then e2 else e3 , si −→ hif e1′ then e2 else e3 , s ′ i
(while)
hwhile e1 do e2 , si −→ hif e1 then (e2 ; while e1 do e2 ) else skip, si
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
(app1)
he1 e2 , si −→ he1′ e2 , s ′ i
he2 , si −→ he2′ , s ′ i
(app2)
hv e2 , si −→ hv e2′ , s ′ i
(let1)
he1 , si −→ he1′ , s ′ i
hlet val x :T = e1 in e2 end, si −→ hlet val x :T = e1′ in e2 end, s ′ i
(let2)
hlet val x :T = v in e2 end, si −→ h{v /x }e2 , si
he2 , si −→ he2′ , s ′ i
(pair2)
h(v1 , e2 ), si −→ h(v1 , e2′ ), s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(proj3) (proj4)
h#1 e, si −→ h#1 e ′ , s ′ i h#2 e, si −→ h#2 e ′ , s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(inl)
hinl e:T , si −→ hinl e ′ :T , s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(case1) hcase e of inl (x :T1 ) ⇒ e1 | inr (y:T2 ) ⇒ e2 , si
−→ hcase e ′ of inl (x :T1 ) ⇒ e1 | inr (y:T2 ) ⇒ e2 , s ′ i
82
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(inr)
hinr e:T , si −→ hinr e ′ :T , s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(record3)
h#lab i e, si −→ h#lab i e ′ , s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(ref2)
h ref e, si −→ h ref e ′ , s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(deref2)
h!e, si −→ h!e ′ , s ′ i
he, si −→ he ′ , s ′ i
(assign3)
he := e2 , si −→ he ′ := e2 , s ′ i
L3 Typing
Type environments, Γ ∈ TypeEnv2, are pairs of a finite partial function Γloc from L to
Tloc and a finite partial function Γvar from X to T .
We use an abbreviated notation to access and manipulate such pairs, writing Γ(ℓ) for Γloc (ℓ)
and Γ(x ) for Γvar (x ), and similarly writing just Γ, x :T for the pair of Γloc and Γvar , x :T .
Γ ⊢ e1 :int Γ ⊢ e1 :int
Γ ⊢ e2 :int Γ ⊢ e2 :int
(op +) (op ≥)
Γ ⊢ e1 + e2 :int Γ ⊢ e1 ≥ e2 :bool
(if) Γ ⊢ e1 :bool Γ ⊢ e2 :T Γ ⊢ e3 :T
Γ ⊢ if e1 then e2 else e3 :T
83
(skip) Γ ⊢ skip:unit
(seq) Γ ⊢ e1 :unit Γ ⊢ e2 :T
Γ ⊢ e1 ; e2 :T
(var) Γ ⊢ x :T if Γ(x ) = T
Γ, x :T ⊢ e:T ′
(fn)
Γ ⊢ fn x :T ⇒ e : T → T ′
′
(app) Γ ⊢ e1 :T → T Γ ⊢ e2 :T
Γ ⊢ e1 e2 :T ′
Γ ⊢ e1 :T Γ, x :T ⊢ e2 :T ′
(let)
Γ ⊢ let val x :T = e1 in e2 end:T ′
(proj1) Γ ⊢ e:T1 ∗ T2
Γ ⊢ #1 e:T1
(proj2) Γ ⊢ e:T1 ∗ T2
Γ ⊢ #2 e:T2
(inl) Γ ⊢ e:T1
Γ ⊢ inl e:T1 + T2 :T1 + T2
(inr) Γ ⊢ e:T2
Γ ⊢ inr e:T1 + T2 :T1 + T2
Γ ⊢ e:T1 + T2
Γ, x :T1 ⊢ e1 :T
Γ, y:T2 ⊢ e2 :T
(case)
Γ ⊢ case e of inl (x :T1 ) ⇒ e1 | inr (y:T2 ) ⇒ e2 :T
84
(ref) Γ ⊢ e:T
Γ ⊢ ref e : T ref
(assign) Γ ⊢ e1 :T ref Γ ⊢ e2 :T
Γ ⊢ e1 := e2 :unit
Γ(ℓ) = T ref
(loc)
Γ ⊢ ℓ:T ref
5.6 Exercises
85
6 Subtyping and Objects
Our type systems so far would all be annoying to use, as they’re quite rigid (Pascal-like).
There is little support for code reuse, so you would have to have different sorting code for,
e.g., int lists and int ∗ int lists.
Polymorphism
Subtyping – Motivation
Recall
Γ ⊢ e1 :T → T ′
Γ ⊢ e2 :T
Slide 192 (app)
Γ ⊢ e1 e2 :T ′
so can’t type
even though we’re giving the function a better argument, with more
structure, than it needs.
86
Subsumption
‘Better’? Any value of type {p:int, q:int} can be used wherever a value
of type {p:int} is expected. (*)
Example
(s-refl)
Slide 195 T <: T
Subtyping – Records
{lab 1 :T1 , .., lab k :Tk , lab k+1 :Tk+1 , .., lab k+k′ :Tk+k′ }
<: (s-record-width)
87
Another example:
(s-rec-w)
{p:int, q:int} <: {p:int}
(s-rec-w) (s-rec-d)
{x:{p:int, q:int}, y:{r:int}} <: {x:{p:int, q:int}} {x:{p:int, q:int}} <: {x:{p:int}}
(s-trans)
{x:{p:int, q:int}, y:{r:int}} <: {x:{p:int}}
(s-record-order)
Slide 197 π a permutation of 1, .., k
{lab 1 :T1 , .., lab k :Tk } <: {lab π(1) :Tπ(1) , .., lab π(k) :Tπ(k) }
Subtyping – Functions
(s-fn)
T1′ <: T1 T2 <: T2′
T1 → T2 <: T1′ → T2′
Slide 198
f = fn x:{p:int} ⇒ {p = #p x, q = 28}
we have
{} ⊢ f :{p:int} → {p:int, q:int}
Slide 199
{} ⊢ f :{p:int} → {p:int}
{} ⊢ f :{p:int, q:int} → {p:int, q:int}
{} ⊢ f :{p:int, q:int} → {p:int}
as
{p:int, q:int} <: {p:int}
we have
Slide 200
{} ⊢ f :{p:int, q:int} → {p:int}
{} 6⊢ f :{p:int} → T for any T
{} 6⊢ f :T → {p:int, q:int} for any T
88
Subtyping – Products
(s-pair)
T1 <: T1′ T2 <: T2′
Slide 201 T1 ∗ T2 <: T1′ ∗ T2′
Subtyping – Sums
Exercise.
Subtyping – References
Semantics
Properties
Subtyping – Down-casts
The subsumption rule (sub) permits up-casting at any point. How about
down-casting? We could add
e ::= ... | (T )e
with typing rule
Slide 204 Γ ⊢ e:T ′
Γ ⊢ (T )e:T
then you need a dynamic type-check...
This gives flexibility, but at the cost of many potential run-time errors.
Many uses might be better handled by Parametric Polymorphism, aka
Generics. (cf. work by Martin Odersky at EPFL, Lausanne, now in Java
1.5)
The following development is taken from [Pierce, Chapter 18], where you can find more
details (including a treatment of self and a direct semantics for a ‘featherweight’ fragment
of Java).
89
(Very Simple) Objects
in
Using Subtyping
in
Object Generators
in
90
Reusing Method Code (Simple Classes)
class Counter
{ protected int p;
Counter() { this.p=0; }
int get () { return this.p; }
void inc () { this.p++ ; }
Slide 210
};
class ResetCounter
extends Counter
{ void reset () {this.p=0;}
};
91
Subtyping – Structural vs Named
A′ = {} with {p:int}
′′
A = A′ with {q:bool}
Slide 211 A′′′ = A′ with {r:int}
{} Object (ish!)
′
{p:int} q A ▼▼▼▼
♥♥♥
❖❖❖
❖❖❖ qqqq ▼▼▼
♥♥♥ qq
{p:int, q:bool} {p:int, r:int} A′′ A′′
6.1 Exercises
Exercise 31 ⋆For each of the following, either give a type derivation or explain why it is
untypable.
1. {} ⊢ {p = {p = {p = {p = 3}}}}:{p:{}}
2. {} ⊢ fn x:{p:bool, q:{p:int, q:bool}} ⇒ #q #p x : ?
3. {} ⊢ fn f:{p:int} → int ⇒ (f {q = 3}) + (f {p = 4}) : ?
4. {} ⊢ fn f:{p:int} → int ⇒ (f {q = 3, p = 2}) + (f {p = 4}) : ?
Exercise 32 ⋆For each of the two bogus T ref subtype rules on Slide 202, give an example
program that is typable with that rule but gets stuck at runtime.
Exercise 33 ⋆⋆What should the subtype rules for sums T + T ′ be?
Exercise 34 ⋆⋆...and for let and let rec ?
Exercise 35 ⋆⋆Prove a Progress Theorem for L3 with subtyping.
92
7 Concurrency
Our focus so far has been on semantics for sequential computation. But
the world is not sequential...
• multi-processor machines
• multi-threading (perhaps on a single processor)
• networked machines
Problems
More Problems!
93
Theme: as for sequential languages, but much more so, it’s a complicated
world.
Aim of this lecture: just to give you a taste of how a little semantics can
be used to express some of the fine distinctions. Primarily (1) to boost
Slide 216 your intuition for informal reasoning, but also (2) this can support rigorous
proof about really hairy crypto protocols, cache-coherency protocols,
comms, database transactions,....
Operations op ::= + |≥
Expressions
(thread) Γ ⊢ e:unit
Γ ⊢ e:proc
he2 , si −→ he2′ , s ′ i
(parallel2)
he1 e2 , si −→ he1 e2′ , s ′ i
94
Threads execute asynchronously – the semantics allows any interleaving
of the reductions of the threads.
NB from here on, we are using () instead of skip — that’s the ML syntax.
hl := 3498734590879238429384 | l := 7, {l 7→ 0}i
will reduce to a state with l either 3498734590879238429384 or 7, not
Slide 221 something with the first word of one and the second word of the other.
Implement?
95
The behaviour of (l := 1+!l ) (l := 7+!l ) for the initial store {l 7→ 0}:
r + w
h() (l := 7+!l), {l 7→ 1}i �• �• � h() (), {l 7→ 8}i
❦❦❦�
w ❦❦❦
❦
❦ ❦❦❦❦
❦❦
h(l := 1) (l := 7+!l), {l 7→ 0}i h() (l := 7 + 0), {l 7→ 1}i
+ ♦♦
♦♦� ❙❙❙
❙❙❙ r w ❦❦❦
❦❦❦
� ❘❘❘
❘❘❘ +
♦ ❙ ❙ ❦ ❘❘❘
♦♦ ♦♦ ❙❙❙
❙ ❦❦ ❦❦ ❘❘❘
♦♦ ❙❙� ❦❦ ❦ ❘�
w
h(l := 1 + 0) (l := 7+!l), {l 7→ 0}i h(l := 1) (l := 7 + 0), {l 7→ 0}i h() (l := 7), {l 7→ 1}i � h() (), {l 7→ 7}i
r ♦♦♦
♦♦� ❖❖❖
❖❖❖r + ❦❦❦
❦❦❦
� ❙❙❙
❙❙❙ + w ❧❧❧
❧❧❧
�
♦ ❖ ❖ ❦ ❦ ❙❙❙ ❧ ❧
♦ ♦ ❖❖❖ ❦❦❦ ❙ ❙❙❙ ❧❧
♦♦♦ � ❦❦❦ ❙� ❧❧❧
h(l := 1+!l) (l := 7+!l), {l 7→ 0}i h(l := 1 + 0) (l := 7 + 0), {l 7→ 0}i h(l := 1) (l := 7), {l 7→ 0}i
❖❖❖ � ❙❙❙ � ❘❘❘
❖❖❖ ♦♦♦♦ ❙❙❙ + ❦❦❦
❦❦❦ ❘❘❘
❖ ♦♦ ❙ ❙❙ ❦❦ ❘❘
r ❖❖❖ ♦♦ ♦ r +
❙❙ ❙ ❦❦ ❦ w ❘❘❘
❖� ♦♦ ❙❙ � ❦ ❦❦ ❘❘�
w
h(l := 1+!l) (l := 7 + 0), {l 7→ 0}i h(l := 1 + 0) (l := 7), {l 7→ 0}i hl := 1 (), {l 7→ 7}i � h() (), {l 7→ 1}i
❖❖❖ � ❙❙❙ �
❖❖❖ r ❦❦❦
❦❦❦ ❙❙❙ + ❧❧
❧❧❧
❖❖❖ ❦ ❦ ❙❙❙ ❧❧
+ ❖❖� ❦❦❦ w ❙❙❙ ❧❧❧
❦❦❦ ❙❙� ❧❧❧
h(l := 1+!l) (l := 7), {l 7→ 0}i hl := 1 + 0 (), {l 7→ 7}i
96
❙❙❙
❙❙❙ w
❙❙❙
❙❙❙
❙❙�
r + w
hl := 1+!l (), {l 7→ 7}i �• �• � h() (), {l 7→ 8}i
Note that the labels +, w and r in the picture are just informal hints as to how those
transitions were derived – they are not actually part of the reduction relation.
Some of the nondeterministic choices “don’t matter”, as you can get back to the same state.
Others do...
Morals
• Almost certainly you (as the programmer) didn’t want all those 3
outcomes to be possible – need better idioms or constructs for
programming.
Usually, though, you can depend on built-in support from the scheduler,
e.g. for mutexes and condition variables (or, at a lower level, tas or
cas).
See this – in the library – for a good discussion of mutexes and condition variables: A. Birrell,
J. Guttag, J. Horning, and R. Levin. Thread synchronization: a Formal Specification. In G.
Nelson, editor, System Programming with Modula-3, chapter 5, pages 119-129. Prentice-
Hall, 1991.
See N. Lynch. Distributed Algorithms for other mutual exclusion algorithms (and much else
besides).
Consider simple mutexes, with commands to lock an unlocked mutex and to unlock a locked
mutex (and do nothing for an unlock of an unlocked mutex).
Note that (lock) atomically (a) checks the mutex is currently false, (b) changes its state,
and (c) lets the thread proceed.
Also, there is no record of which thread is holding a locked mutex.
97
Need to adapt all the other semantic rules to carry the mutex state M
around. For example, replace
he2 , si −→ he2′ , s ′ i
(op2)
Slide 225 hv op e2 , si −→ hv op e2′ , s ′ i
by
he2 , s, M i −→ he2′ , s ′ , M ′ i
(op2)
hv op e2 , s, M i −→ hv op e2′ , s ′ , M ′ i
Using a Mutex
Consider
In all the intervening states (until the first unlock ) the second lock can’t proceed.
Look back to behaviour of the program without mutexes. We’ve essentially cut down to the
top and bottom paths (and also added some extra reductions for lock , unlock , and ;).
In this example, l := 1+!l and l := 7+!l commute, so we end up in the same final state
whichever got the lock first. In general, that won’t be the case.
lock m can block (that’s the point). Hence, you can deadlock.
Slide 227
e= (lock m1 ; lock m2 ; l1 :=!l2 ; unlock m1 ; unlock m2 )
(lock m2 ; lock m1 ; l2 :=!l1 ; unlock m1 ; unlock m2 )
Locking Disciplines
There are many possible locking disciplines. We’ll focus on one, to see
how it – and the properties it guarantees – can be made precise and
proved.
98
An Ordered 2PL Discipline, Informally
These are semantic properties again. In general, it won’t be computable whether they hold.
For simple ei , though, it’s often obvious. Further, one can construct syntactic disciplines
that are checkable and are sufficient to guarantee these.
he1 , s, M i −→ he1′ , s ′ , M ′ i
(parallel1)
he1 e2 , s, M i −→ he1′ e2 , s ′ , M ′ i
a
define a per-thread e−→ e ′ and use that to define
Slide 231 he, s, M i −→ he , s , M ′ i, with rules like
′ ′
ℓ:=n
(t-assign1) ℓ := n −→ skip
a
e1 −→ e1′
(t-parallel1) a
e1 e2 −→ e1′ e2
ℓ:=n
e −→ e ′ ℓ ∈ dom(s)
(c-assign)
he, s, M i −→ he ′ , s + {ℓ 7→ n}, M i
99
Note the per-thread rules don’t mention s or M . Instead, we record in the
label a what interactions with the store or mutexes it has.
Slide 232
τ
Conventionally, τ (tau), stands for “no interactions”, so e −→ e ′ if e does
an internal step, not involving the store or mutexes.
100
Global Semantics Thread-Local Semantics
τ
(op +) hn1 + n2 , s, M i −→ hn, s, M i if n = n1 + n2 (t-op +) n1 + n2 −→ n if n = n1 + n2
τ
(op ≥) hn1 ≥ n2 , s, M i −→ hb, s, M i if b = (n1 ≥ n2 ) (t-op ≥) n1 ≥ n2 −→ b if b = (n1 ≥ n2 )
he2 , s, M i −→ he2′ , s ′ , M ′ i a
(op2) e2 −→ e2′
hv op e2 , s, M i −→ hv op e2′ , s ′ , M ′ i (t-op2) a
v op e2 −→ v op e2′
!ℓ=n
(deref) h!ℓ, s, M i −→ hn, s, M i if ℓ ∈ dom(s) and s(ℓ) = n (t-deref) !ℓ −→ n
(assign1) hℓ := n, s, M i −→ hskip, s + {ℓ 7→ n}, M i if ℓ ∈ dom(s) ℓ:=n
(t-assign1) ℓ := n −→ skip
′ ′ ′
he, s, M i −→ he , s , M i a
(assign2) e −→ e ′
hℓ := e, s, M i −→ hℓ := e ′ , s ′ , M ′ i (t-assign2) a
ℓ := e −→ ℓ := e ′
τ
(seq1) hskip; e2 , s, M i −→ he2 , s, M i (t-seq1) skip; e2 −→ e2
he1 , s, M i −→ he1′ , s ′ , M ′ i a
e1 −→ e1′
(seq2) (t-seq2)
he1 ; e2 , s, M i −→ he1′ ; e2 , s ′ , M ′ i a
e1 ; e2 −→ e1′ ; e2
τ
(if1) hif true then e2 else e3 , s, M i −→ he2 , s, M i (t-if1) if true then e2 else e3 −→ e2
τ
(if2) hif false then e2 else e3 , s, M i −→ he3 , s, M i (t-if2) if false then e2 else e3 −→ e3
he1 , s, M i −→ he1′ , s ′ , M ′ i a
e1 −→ e1′
(if3) (t-if3)
hif e1 then e2 else e3 , s, M i −→ hif e1′ ′
then e2 else e3 , s , M i ′ a
if e1 then e2 else e3 −→ if e1′ then e2 else e3
(while) (t-while)
hwhile e1 do e2 , s, M i −→ hif e1 then (e2 ; while e1 do e2 ) else skip, i τ
while e1 do e2 −→ if e1 then (e2 ; while e1 do e2 ) else skip
a
he1 , s, M i −→ he1′ , s ′ , M ′ i e1 −→ e1′
(parallel1) (t-parallel1) a
he1 e2 , s, M i −→ he1′ e2 , s ′ , M ′ i e1 e2 −→ e1′ e2
a
he2 , s, M i −→ he2′ , s ′ , M ′ i e2 −→ e2′
(parallel2) (t-parallel2) a
he1 e2 , s, M i −→ he1 e2′ , s ′ , M ′ i e1 e2 −→ e1 e2′
τ
(c-tau) e −→ e ′
he, s, M i −→ he ′ , s, M i
ℓ:=n lock m
e −→ e ′ ℓ ∈ dom(s) e −→ e ′ ¬ M (m)
(c-assign) (c-lock)
he, s, M i −→ he ′ , s + {ℓ 7→ n}, M i he, s, M i −→ he ′ , s, M + {m 7→ true}i
!ℓ=n unlock m
e −→ e ′ ℓ ∈ dom(s) ∧ s(ℓ) = n e −→ e ′
(c-deref) ′
(c-unlock)
he, s, M i −→ he , s, M i he, s, M i −→ he ′ , s, M + {m 7→ false}i
101
Now can make the Ordered 2PL Discipline precise
The Theorem
(may be false!)
Language Properties
102
7.1 Exercises
Exercise 36 ⋆⋆Are the mutexes specified here similar to those described in C&DS?
Exercise 37 ⋆⋆Can you show all the conditions for O2PL are necessary, by giving for
each an example that satisfies all the others and either is not serialisable or deadlocks?
Exercise 38 ⋆⋆⋆⋆Prove the Conjecture about it.
Exercise 39 ⋆⋆⋆Write a semantics for an extension of L1 with threads that are more
like Unix threads (e.g. with thread ids, fork, etc..). Include some of the various ways Unix
threads can exchange information.
103
8 Semantic Equivalence
?
2+2 ≃ 4
In what sense are these two expressions the same?
� 2+2 � 4
esin(x) dx = esin(x) dx
0 0
?
How about (l := 0; 4) ≃ (l := 1; 3+!l )
They will produce the same result (in any store), but you cannot replace
one by the other in an arbitrary program context. For example:
C [ ] = +!l
Slide 241
C [l := 0; 4] = (l := 0; 4)+!l
6≃
C [l := 1; 3+!l ] = (l := 1; 3+!l )+!l
Those were all particular expressions – may want to know that some
general laws are valid for all e1 , e2 , .... How about these:
?
e1 ; (e2 ; e3 ) ≃ (e1 ; e2 ); e3
Slide 242 ?
(if e1 then e2 else e3 ); e ≃ if e1 then e2 ; e else e3 ; e
?
e; (if e1 then e2 else e3 ) ≃ if e1 then e; e2 else e; e3
?
e; (if e1 then e2 else e3 ) ≃ if e; e1 then e2 else e3
104
Temporarily extend L3 with pointer equality
op ::= ... |=
Γ ⊢ e1 :T ref
Slide 244
Γ ⊢ e2 :T ref
(op =)
Γ ⊢ e1 = e2 :bool
(op =) hℓ = ℓ′ , si −→ hb, si if b = (ℓ = ℓ′ )
?
f ≃ g
The last two examples are taken from A.M. Pitts, Operational Semantics and Program
Equivalence. In: G. Barthe, P. Dybjer and J. Saraiva (Eds), Applied Semantics. Lecture
Notes in Computer Science, Tutorial, Volume 2395 (Springer-Verlag, 2002), pages 378-412.
http://www.cl.cam.ac.uk/~amp12/papers/opespe/opespe-lncs.pdf
105
What does it mean for ≃ to be ‘good’?
Slide 247 2. programs that terminate must not be equivalent to programs that don’t
In this definition, part (b), we require that e1 and e2 result in the same value and moreover
the same store. This is because, if we were to equate two programs e1 and e2 that result
in different stores — say s1 (l )6= s2 (l ) — then we could distinguish them using the following
contexts, and the semantic equivalence would not be a congruence.
If T = unit then C = ; !l .
Slide 249 If T = bool then C = if then !l else !l .
If T = int then C = l1 := ; !l .
C ::= op e2 | e1 op |
if then e2 else e3 | if e1 then else e3 |
if e1 then e2 else |
Slide 250 ℓ := |
; e2 | e1 ; |
while do e2 | while e1 do
Say ≃T
Γ has the congruence property if whenever e1 ≃TΓ e2 we have,
′ ′ ′
for all C and T , if Γ ⊢ C [e1 ]:T and Γ ⊢ C [e2 ]:T then
′
C [e1 ] ≃TΓ C [e2 ].
106
Theorem 29 (Congruence for L1) ≃TΓ has the congruence property.
Proof Outline By case analysis, looking at each L1 context C in turn.
For each C (and for arbitrary e and s ), consider the possible reduction
sequences
107
On the other hand, if ¬(hℓ := e, si −→ω ) then by the above there is some n and
sk−1 such that he, si −→∗ hn, sk−1 i and hℓ := e, si −→ hskip, sk−1 + {ℓ 7→ n}i.
By e ≃TΓ e ′ we have he ′ , si −→∗ hn, sk−1 i. Then using (assign1) hℓ := e ′ , si −→∗
hℓ := n, sk−1 i −→ hskip, sk−1 + {ℓ 7→ n} = hek , sk i as required.
Back to the Examples
We defined e1 ≃TΓ e2 iff for all s such that dom(Γ) ⊆ dom(s), we have
Γ ⊢ e1 :T , Γ ⊢ e2 :T , and either
1. he1 , si −→ω and he2 , si −→ω , or
2. for some v , s ′ we have he1 , si −→∗ hv , s ′ i and
Slide 252 ∗ ′
he2 , si −→ hv , s i.
So:
2 + 2 ≃int
Γ 4 for any Γ
(l := 0; 4) 6≃int
Γ (l := 1; 3+!l ) for any Γ
Conjecture 30 e1 ; (e2 ; e3 ) ≃T
Γ (e1 ; e2 ); e3 for any Γ, T , e1 , e2 and e3
such that Γ ⊢ e1 :unit, Γ ⊢ e2 :unit, and Γ ⊢ e3 :T
Conjecture 31
((if e1 then e2 else e3 ); e) ≃TΓ (if e1 then e2 ; e else e3 ; e) for
Slide 253 any Γ, T , e , e1 , e2 and e3 such that Γ ⊢ e1 :bool, Γ ⊢ e2 :unit,
Γ ⊢ e3 :unit, and Γ ⊢ e:T
Conjecture 32
(e; (if e1 then e2 else e3 )) ≃TΓ (if e1 then e; e2 else e; e3 ) for
any Γ, T , e , e1 , e2 and e3 such that Γ ⊢ e:unit, Γ ⊢ e1 :bool,
Γ ⊢ e2 :T , and Γ ⊢ e3 :T
✉✉✉
❑❑
❑
;
≥ skip ; ❆❆
✞
!l 0 skip l :=
Slide 254
3. the function taking store s to the reduction sequence
he, si −→ he1 , s1 i −→ he2 , s2 i −→ ...; or
4. • the equivalence class {e ′ | e ≃TΓ e ′ }
• the partial function [[e]]Γ that takes any store s with
dom(s) = dom(Γ) and either is undefined, if he, si −→ω , or is
hv , s ′ i, if he, si −→∗ hv , s ′ i
A sufficient condition: they don’t mention any locations (but not necessary... e.g. if e1 does
but e2 doesn’t)
108
8.1 Contextual equivalence
The definition of semantic equivalence works fine for L1. However, when we come to L2 and
L3, the simple notion does not give a congruence.
Here is a basic definition of an equivalence for L3.
8.2 Exercises
Exercise 40 ⋆⋆Prove some of the other cases of the Congruence theorem for semantic
equivalence in L1.
Exercise 41 ⋆⋆Prove that if Γ1 ⊢ e1 :unit and Γ2 ⊢ e2 :unit in L1, and Γ1 is disjoint from
Γ2 , then e1 ; e2 ≃unit
Γ e2 ; e1 where Γ = Γ1 ∪ Γ2
Exercise 42 ⋆⋆Prove that the programs l :int ref ⊢ l := 0:unit and l :int ref ⊢ l := 1:unit,
considered as L3 programs, are not contextually equivalent. Hint: find a context that will
diverge for one of them, but not for the other.
9 Epilogue
Lecture Feedback
Slide 258 Please do fill in the lecture feedback form – we need to know how the
course could be improved / what should stay the same.
Need:
109
What can you use semantics for?
110
111
A Interpreter and type checker for L1 (ML)
Here is an interpreter and type checker for L1. You can download the source code from the
course website.
(* 2002-11-08 -- Time-stamp: <2006-10-25 09:22:33 pes20> -*-SML-*- *)
(* Peter Sewell *)
That will give you a MoscowML top level in which these definitions
are present. You can then type
doit ();
doit2 ();
to run the type-checker on the same simple example; you can try
other examples analogously. This file doesn’t have a parser for
l1, so you’ll have to enter the abstract syntax directly, eg
This has been tested with Moscow ML version 2.00 (June 2000), but
should work with any other implementation of Standard ML. *)
(* *********************)
(* the abstract syntax *)
(* *********************)
datatype expr =
Integer of int
| Boolean of bool
| Op of expr * oper * expr
| If of expr * expr * expr
| Assign of loc * expr
| Deref of loc
| Skip
| Seq of expr * expr
| While of expr * expr
(* **********************************)
(* an interpreter for the semantics *)
(* **********************************)
112
(* In the semantics, a store is a finite partial function from
locations to integers. In the implementation, we represent a store
as a list of loc*int pairs containing, for each l in the domain of
the store, exactly one element of the form (l,n). The operations
113
| NONE => NONE ))
| reduce (Deref l,s) =
(case lookup (s,l) of
SOME n => SOME(Integer n,s) (* (deref) *)
| NONE => NONE )
| reduce (Assign (l,e),s) =
(case e of
Integer n => (case update (s,(l,n)) of
SOME s’ => SOME(Skip, s’) (* (assign1) *)
| NONE => NONE)
| _ => (case reduce (e,s) of
SOME (e’,s’) => SOME(Assign (l,e’), s’) (* (assign2) *)
| NONE => NONE ) )
| reduce (While (e1,e2),s) = SOME( If(e1,Seq(e2,While(e1,e2)),Skip),s) (* (while) *)
| reduce (Skip,s) = NONE
| reduce (Seq (e1,e2),s) =
(case e1 of
Skip => SOME(e2,s) (* (seq1) *)
| _ => ( case reduce (e1,s) of
SOME (e1’,s’) => SOME(Seq (e1’,e2), s’) (* (seq2) *)
| NONE => NONE ) )
(* **********************************)
(* typing *)
(* **********************************)
(* types *)
datatype type_L1 =
int
| unit
| bool
datatype type_loc =
intref
(* ****************)
(* type inference *)
(* ****************)
114
(* infertype : typeEnv -> expr -> type_L1 option *)
115
B Interpreter and type checker for L1 (Java)
Here is an interpreter and type checker for L1, written in Java by Matthew Parkinson.
Note the different code organization between the ML and Java versions: the ML has a
datatype with a constructor for each clause of the abstract syntax grammar, and reduce
and infertype function definitions that each have a case for each of those constructors; the
Java has a subclass of Expression for each clause of the abstract syntax, each of which
defines smallStep and typecheck methods.
public class L1 {
Expression e =
new Seq(new While(new GTeq(new Deref(l2),new Deref(l1)),
new Seq(new Assign(l3, new Plus(new Deref(l1),new Deref(l3))),
new Assign(l1,new Plus(new Deref(l1),new Int(1))))
),
new Deref(l3))
;
try{
//Type check
Type t= e.typeCheck(env);
System.out.println("Program has type: " + t);
//Evaluate program
System.out.println(e + "\n \n");
while(!(e instanceof Value) ){
e = e.smallStep(s1);
//Display each step of reduction
System.out.println(e + "\n \n");
}
//Give some output
System.out.println("Program has type: " + t);
System.out.println("Result has type: " + e.typeCheck(env));
System.out.println("Result: " + e);
System.out.println("Terminating State: " + s1);
} catch (TypeError te) {
System.out.println("Error:\n" + te);
System.out.println("From code:\n" + e);
} catch (CanNotReduce cnr) {
System.out.println("Caught Following exception" + cnr);
System.out.println("While trying to execute:\n " + e);
System.out.println("In state: \n " + s1);
}
}
}
class Location {
String name;
116
Location(String n) {
this.name = n;
}
public String toString() {return name;}
}
class State {
java.util.HashMap store = new java.util.HashMap();
//Used for setting the initial store for testing not used by
//semantics of L1
State add(Location l, Value v) {
store.put(l,v);
return this;
}
class Environment {
java.util.HashSet env = new java.util.HashSet();
boolean contains(Location l) {
return env.contains(l);
}
}
class Type {
int type;
Type(int t) {type = t;}
public static final Type BOOL = new Type(1);
public static final Type INT = new Type(2);
public static final Type UNIT = new Type(3);
117
public String toString() {
switch(type) {
case 1: return "BOOL";
case 2: return "INT";
case 3: return "UNIT";
}
return "???";
}
}
Bool(boolean b) {
value = b;
}
118
class Seq extends Expression {
Expression exp1,exp2;
Seq(Expression e1, Expression e2) {
exp1 = e1;
exp2 = e2;
}
119
if(!( exp1 instanceof Value)) {
return new Plus(exp1.smallStep(state),exp2);
} else if (!( exp2 instanceof Value)) {
return new Plus(exp1, exp2.smallStep(state));
} else {
if( exp1 instanceof Int && exp2 instanceof Int ) {
return new Int(((Int)exp1).value + ((Int)exp2).value);
}
else throw new CanNotReduce("Operands are not both integers.");
}
}
public String toString(){return exp1 + " + " + exp2;}
120
Assign(Location l, Expression exp1) {
this.l = l;
this.exp1 = exp1;
}
Deref(Location l) {
this.l = l;
}
public String toString(){return "WHILE " + exp1 + " DO {" + exp2 +"}";}
121
C How to do Proofs
The purpose of this handout is give a general guide as to how to prove theorems. This
should give you some help in answering questions that begin with “Show that the following
is true . . . ”. It is based on notes by Myra VanInwegen, with additional text added by Peter
Sewell in §C.1. Many thanks to Myra for making her original notes available.
The focus here is on doing informal but rigorous proofs. These are rather different from
the formal proofs, in Natural Deduction or Sequent Calculus, that were introduced in the
Logic and Proof course. Formal proofs are derivations in one of those proof systems – they
are in a completely well-defined form, but are often far too verbose to deal with by hand
(although they can be machine-checked). Informal proofs, on the other hand, are the usual
mathematical notion of proof: written arguments to persuade the reader that you could, if
pushed, write a fully formal proof.
This is important for two reasons. Most obviously, you should learn how to do these proofs.
More subtly, but more importantly, only by working with the mathematical definitions in
some way can you develop a good intuition for what they mean — trying to do some proofs
is the best way of understanding the definitions.
Proofs differ, but for many of those you meet the following steps should be helpful.
1. Make sure the statement of the conjecture is precisely defined. In particular, make
sure you understand any strange notation, and find the definitions of all the auxiliary
gadgets involved (e.g. definitions of any typing or reduction relations mentioned in the
statement, or any other predicates or functions).
2. Try to understand at an intuitive level what the conjecture is saying – verbalize out
loud the basic point. For example, for a Type Preservation conjecture, the basic
point might be something like “if a well-typed configuration reduces, the result is still
well-typed (with the same type)”.
3. Try to understand intuitively why it is true (or false...). Identify what the most
interesting cases might be — the cases that you think are most likely to be suspicious,
or hard to prove. Sometimes it’s good to start with the easy cases (if the setting
is unfamiliar to you); sometimes it’s good to start with the hard cases (to find any
interesting problems as soon as possible).
4. Think of a good basic strategy. This might be:
(a) simple logic manipulations;
(b) collecting together earlier results, again by simple logic; or
(c) some kind of induction.
5. Try it! (remembering you might have to backtrack if you discover you picked a strategy
that doesn’t work well for this conjecture). This might involve any of the following:
(a) Expanding definitions, inlining them. Sometimes you can just blindly expand all
definitions, but more often it’s important to expand only the definitions which
you want to work with the internal structure of — otherwise things just get too
verbose.
(b) Making abbreviations — defining a new variable to stand for some complex gadget
you’re working with, saying e.g.
122
where e = (let x:int = 7+2 in x+x)
Take care with choosing variable names.
(c) Doing equational reasoning, e.g.
e = e1 by ...
= e2 by ...
= e3 as ...
Here the e might be any mathematical object — arithmetic expressions, or ex-
pressions of some grammar, or formulae. Some handy equations over formulae
are given in §C.2.2.
(d) Proving a formula based on its structure. For example, to prove a formula ∀x ∈
S.P (x) you would often assume you have an arbitrary x and then try to prove
P (x).
Take an arbitrary x ∈ S.
We now have to show P (x):
This is covered in detail in §C.2.3. Much proof is of this form, automatically
driven by the structure of the formula.
(e) Using an assumption you’ve made above.
(f) Induction. As covered in the 1B Semantics notes, there are various kinds of induc-
tion you might want to use: mathematical induction over the natural numbers,
structural induction over the elements of some grammar, or rule induction over
the rules defining some relation (especially a reduction or typing relation). For
each, you should:
i. Decide (and state!) what kind of induction you’re using. This may need
some thought and experience, and you might have to backtrack.
ii. Remind yourself what the induction principle is exactly.
iii. Decide on the induction hypothesis you’re going to use, writing down a pred-
icate Φ which is such that the conclusion of the induction principle implies
the thing you’re trying to prove. Again, this might need some thought. Take
care with the quantifiers here — it’s suspicious if your definition of Φ has
any globally-free variables...
iv. Go through each of the premises of the induction principle and prove each one
(using any of these techniques as appropriate). Many of those premises will
be implications, e.g. ∀x ∈ N.Φ(x) ⇒ Φ(x + 1), for which you can do a proof
based on the structure of the formula — taking an arbitrary x, assuming
Φ(x), and trying to prove Φ(x + 1). Usually at some point in the latter you’d
make use of the assumption Φ(x).
6. In all of the above, remember: the point of doing a proof on paper is to use the
formalism to help you think — to help you cover all cases, precisely — and also to
communicate with the reader. For both, you need to write clearly:
(a) Use enough words! “Assume”, “We have to show”, “By such-and-such we know”,
“Hence”,...
(b) Don’t use random squiggles. It’s good to have formulae properly nested within
text, with and no “⇒” or “∴” between lines of text.
7. If it hasn’t worked yet... either
(a) you’ve make some local mistake, e.g. mis-instantiated something, or used the
same variable for two different things, or not noticed that you have a definition
you should have expanded or an assumption you should have used. Fix it and
continue.
123
(b) you’ve discovered that the conjecture is really false. Usually at this point it’s
a good idea to construct a counterexample that is as simple as possible, and to
check carefully that it really is a counterexample.
(c) you need to try a different strategy — often, to use a different induction principle
or to strengthen your induction hypothesis.
(d) you didn’t really understand intuitively what the conjecture is saying, or what
the definitions it uses mean. Go back to them again.
8. If it has worked: read through it, skeptically, and check. Maybe you’ll need to re-write
it to make it comprehensible: proof discovery is not the same as proof exposition. See
the example proofs in the Semantics notes.
9. Finally, give it to someone else, as skeptical and careful as you can find, to see if they
believe it — to see if they believe that what you’ve written down is a proof, not that
they believe that the conjecture is true.
First, I’ll explain informal proof intuitively, giving a couple of examples. Then I’ll explain
how this intuition is reflected in the sequent rules from Logic and Proof.
In the following, I’ll call any logic statement a formula. In general, what we’ll be trying to
do is prove a formula, using a collection of formulas that we know to be true or are assuming
to be true. There’s a big difference between using a formula and proving a formula. In fact,
what you do is in many ways opposite. So, I’ll start by explaining how to prove a formula.
Here are the logical connectives and a very brief decription of what each means.
P ∧Q P and Q are both true
P ∨Q P is true, or Q is true, or both are true
¬P P is not true (P is false)
P ⇒Q if P is true then Q is true
P ⇔Q P is true exactly when Q is true
∀x ∈ S.P (x) for all x in S, P is true of x
∃x ∈ S.P (x) there exists an x in S such that P holds of x
C.2.2 Equivalences
These are formulas that mean the same thing, and this is indicated by a ≃ between them.
The fact that they are equivalent to each other is justified by the truth tables of the con-
nectives.
124
definition of ⇒ P ⇒Q ≃ ¬P ∨ Q
definition of ⇔ P ⇔Q ≃ (P ⇒ Q) ∧ (Q ⇒ P )
definition of ¬ ¬P ≃ P ⇒ false
de Morgan’s Laws ¬(P ∧ Q) ≃ ¬P ∨ ¬Q
¬(P ∨ Q) ≃ ¬P ∧ ¬Q
extension to quantifiers ¬(∀x.P (x)) ≃ ∃x.¬P (x)
¬(∃x.P (x)) ≃ ∀x.¬P (x)
distributive laws P ∨ (Q ∧ R) ≃ (P ∨ Q) ∧ (P ∨ R)
P ∧ (Q ∨ R) ≃ (P ∧ Q) ∨ (P ∧ R)
coalescing quantifiers (∀x.P (x)) ∧ (∀x.Q(x)) ≃ ∀x.(P (x) ∧ Q(x))
(∃x.P (x)) ∨ (∃x.Q(x)) ≃ ∃x.(P (x) ∨ Q(x))
these ones apply if (∀x.P (x)) ∧ Q ≃ (∀x.P (x) ∧ Q)
x is not free in Q (∀x.P (x)) ∨ Q ≃ (∀x.P (x) ∨ Q)
(∃x.P (x)) ∧ Q ≃ (∃x.P (x) ∧ Q)
(∃x.P (x)) ∨ Q ≃ (∃x.P (x) ∨ Q)
For each of the logical connectives, I’ll explain how to handle them.
∀x ∈ S.P (x) This means “For all x in S, P is true of x.” Such a formula is called a
universally quantified formula. The goal is to prove that the property P , which has some
xs somewhere in it, is true no matter what value in S x takes on. Often the “∈ S” is left
out. For example, in a discussion of lists, you might be asked to prove ∀l.length l > 0 ⇒
∃x. member(x, l). Obviously, l is a list, even if it isn’t explicitly stated as such.
There are several choices as to how to prove a formula beginning with ∀x. The standard
thing to do is to just prove P (x), not assuming anything about x. Thus, in doing the proof
you sort of just mentally strip off the ∀x. What you would write when doing this is “Let x be
any S”. However, there are some subtleties—if you’re already using an x for something else,
you can’t use the same x, because then you would be assuming something about x, namely
that it equals the x you’re already using. In this case, you need to use alpha-conversion1 to
change the formula you want to prove to ∀y ∈ S.P (y), where y is some variable you’re not
already using, and then prove P (y). What you could write in this case is “Since x is already
in use, we’ll prove the property of y”.
An alternative is induction, if S is a set that is defined with a structural definition. Many
objects you’re likely to be proving properties of are defined with a structural definition.
This includes natural numbers, lists, trees, and terms of a computer language. Sometimes
you can use induction over the natural numbers to prove things about other objects, such
as graphs, by inducting over the number of nodes (or edges) in a graph.
You use induction when you see that during the course of the proof you would need to use
the property P for the subparts of x in order to prove it for x. This usually ends up being
the case if P involves functions defined recursively (i.e., the return value for the function
depends on the function value on the subparts of the argument).
A special case of induction is case analysis. It’s basically induction where you don’t use the
inductive hypothesis: you just prove the property for each possible form that x could have.
Case analysis can be used to prove the theorem about lists above.
A final possibility (which you can use for all formulas, not just for universally quantified
ones) is to assume the contrary, and then derive a contradiction.
1 Alpha-equivalence says that the name of a bound variable doesn’t matter, so you can change it at will
(this is called alpha-conversion). You’ll get to know the exact meaning of this soon enough so I won’t explain
this here.
125
∃x ∈ S.P (x) This says “There exists an x in S such that P holds of x.” Such a formula is
called an existentially quantified formula. The main way to prove this is to figure out what
x has to be (that is, to find a concrete representation of it), and then prove that P holds of
that value. Sometimes you can’t give a completely specified value, since the value you pick
for x has to depend on the values of other things you have floating around. For example,
say you want to prove
∀x, y ∈ R.x < y ∧ sin x < 0 ∧ sin y > 0 ⇒ ∃z.x < z ∧ z < y ∧ sin z = 0
where R is the set of real numbers. By the time you get to dealing with the ∃z.x < z ∧ z <
y ∧ sin z = 0, you will have already assumed that x and y were any real numbers. Thus the
value you choose for z has to depend on whatever x and y are.
An alternative way to prove ∃x ∈ S.P (x) is, of course, to assume that no such x exists, and
derive a contradiction.
To summarize what I’ve gone over so far: to prove a universally quantified formula, you must
prove it for a generic variable, one that you haven’t used before. To prove an existentially
quantified formula, you get to choose a value that you want to prove the property of.
P ⇒ Q This says “If P is true, then Q is true”. Such a formula is called an implication,
and it is often pronounced “P implies Q”. The part before the ⇒ sign (here P ) is called
the antecedent, and the part after the ⇒ sign (here Q) is called the consequent. P ⇒ Q is
equivalent to ¬P ∨ Q, and so if P is false, or if Q is true, then P ⇒ Q is true.
The standard way to prove this is to assume P , then use it to help you prove Q. Note that
I said that you will be using P . Thus you will need to follow the rules in Section C.2.4 to
deal with the logical connectives in P .
Other ways to prove P ⇒ Q involve the fact that it is equivalent to ¬P ∨ Q. Thus, you can
prove ¬P without bothering with Q, or you can just prove Q without bothering with P .
To reason by contradiction you assume that P is true and that Q is not true, and derive a
contradiction.
Another alternative is to prove the contrapositive: ¬Q ⇒ ¬P , which is equivalent to it.
P ⇔ Q This says “P is true if and only if Q is true”. The phrase “if and only if” is usually
abbreviated “iff”. Basically, this means that P and Q are either both true, or both false.
Iff is usually used in two main ways: one is where the equivalence is due to one formula
being a definition of another. For example, A ⊆ B ⇔ (∀x. x ∈ A ⇒ x ∈ B) is the standard
definition of subset. For these iff statements, you don’t have to prove them. The other use
of iff is to state the equivalence of two different things. For example, you could define an
SML function fact:
fun fact 0 = 1
| fact n = n * fact (n - 1)
Since in SML whole numbers are integers (both positive and negative) you may be asked
to prove: fact x terminates ⇔ x ≥ 0. The standard way to do this is us the equivalence
P ⇔ Q is equivalent to P ⇒ Q ∧ Q ⇒ P . And so you’d prove that (fact x terminates ⇒
x ≥ 0) ∧ (x ≥ 0 ⇒ fact x terminates).
¬P This says “P is not true”. It is equivalent to P ⇒ false, thus this is one of the ways
you prove it: you assume that P is true, and derive a contradiction (that is, you prove
false). Here’s an example of this, which you’ll run into later this year: the undecidability
of the halting problem can be rephrased as ¬∃x ∈ RM. x solves the halting problem, where
RM is the set of register machines. The proof of this in your Computation Theory notes
follows exactly the pattern I described—it assumes there is such a machine and derives a
contradiction.
126
The other major way to prove ¬P is to figure out what the negation of P is, using equiva-
lences like De Morgan’s Law, and then prove that. For example, to prove ¬∀x ∈ N . ∃y ∈
N . x = y 2 , where N is the set of natural numbers, you could push in the negation to get:
∃x ∈ N . ∀y ∈ N . x 6= y 2 , and then you could prove that.
P ∨ Q This says “P is true or Q is true”. This is inclusive or: if P and Q are both true,
then P ∨ Q is still true. Such a formula is called a disjunction. To prove this, you can prove
P or you can prove Q. You have to choose which one to prove. For example, if you need to
prove (5 mod 2 = 0) ∨ (5 mod 2 = 1), then you’ll choose the second one and prove that.
However, as with existentials, the choice of which one to prove will often depend on the
values of other things, like universally quantified variables. For example, when you are
studying the theory of programming languages (you will get a bit of this in Semantics), you
might be asked to prove
where ML is the set of all ML programs. You don’t know in advance which of these will be
the case, since some programs do run forever, and some do evaluate to a value. Generally,
the best way to prove the disjunction in this case (when you don’t know in advance which
will hold) is to use the equivalence with implication. For example, you can use the fact
that P ∨ Q is equivalent to ¬P ⇒ Q, then assume ¬P , then use this to prove Q. For
example, your best bet to proving this programming languages theorem is to assume that
the evaluation of P doesn’t run forever, and use this to prove that P evaluates to a value.
You often end up using a formula to prove other formulas. You can use a formula if someone
has already proved that it’s true, or you are assuming it because it was in an implication,
namely, the A in A ⇒ B. For each logical connective, I’ll tell you how to use it.
∀x ∈ S.P (x) This formula says that something is true of all elements of S. Thus, when
you use it, you can pick any value at all to use instead of x (call it v), and then you can use
P (v).
∃x ∈ S.P (x) This formula says that there is some x that satisfies P . However, you do not
know what it is, so you can not assume anything about it. The usual approach it to just
say that the thing that is being said to exist is just x, and use the fact that P holds of x to
prove something else. However, if you’re already using an x for something else, you have to
pick another variable to represent the thing that exists.
To summarize this: to use a universally quantified formula, you can choose any value, and
use that the formula holds for that variable. To use an existentially quantified formula, you
must not assume anything about the value that is said to exists, so you just use a variable
(one that you haven’t used before) to represent it. Note that this is more or less opposite
of what you do when you prove a universally or existentially quantified formula.
¬P Usually, the main use of this formula is to prove the negation of something else.
An example is the use of reduction to prove the unsolvability of various problems in the
Computation Theory (you’ll learn all about this in Lent term). You want to prove ¬Q,
where Q states that a certain problem (Problem 1) is decidable (in other words, you want
to prove that Problem 1 is not decidable). You know ¬P , where P states that another
problem (Problem 2) is decidable (i.e. ¬P says that Problem 2 is not decidable). What you
127
do basically is this. You first prove Q ⇒ P , which says that if Problem 1 is decidable, then
so is Problem 2. Since Q ⇒ P ≃ ¬P ⇒ ¬Q, you have now proved ¬P ⇒ ¬Q. You already
know ¬P , so you use modus ponens2 to get that ¬Q.
P ⇒ Q The main way to use this is that you prove P , and then you use modus ponens to
get Q, which you can then use.
P ∧ Q Here you can use both P and Q. Note, you’re not required to use both of them, but
they are both true and are waiting to be used by you if you need them.
P ∨ Q Here, you know that one of P or Q is true, but you do not know which one. To use
this to prove something else, you have to do a split: first you prove the thing using P , then
you prove it using Q.
Note that in each of the above, there is again a difference in the way you use a formula,
verses the way you prove it. They are in a way almost opposites. For example, in proving
P ∧ Q, you have to prove both P and Q, but when you are using the formula, you don’t
have to use both of them.
C.3 An Example
There are several exercises in the Semantics notes that ask you to prove something. Here,
we’ll go back to Regular Languages and Finite Automata. (If they’ve faded, it’s time
to remind yourself of them.) The Pumping Lemma for regular sets (PL for short) is an
astonishingly good example of the use of quantifiers. We’ll go over the proof and use of the
PL, paying special attention to the logic of what’s happening.
My favorite book on regular languages, finite automata, and their friends is the Hopcroft
and Ullman book Introduction to Automata Theory, Languages, and Computation. You
should locate this book in your college library, and if it isn’t there, insist that your DoS
order it for you.
In the Automata Theory book, the Pumping Lemma is stated as: “Let L be a regular set.
Then there is a constant n such that if z is any word in L, and |z| ≥ n, we may write z = uvw
in such a way that |uv| ≤ n, |v| ≥ 1, and for all i ≥ 0, uv i w is in L.” The Pumping Lemma
is, in my experience, one of the most difficult things about learning automata theory. It
is difficult because people don’t know what to do with all those logical connectives. Let’s
write it as a logical formula.
∀L ∈ RegularLanguages.
∃n. ∀z ∈ L. |z| ≥ n ⇒
∃u v w. z = uvw ∧ |uv| ≤ n ∧ |v| ≥ 1 ∧
∀i ≥ 0. uv i w ∈ L
Complicated, eh? Well, let’s prove it, using the facts that Hopcroft and Ullman have
established in the chapters previous to the one wih the PL. I’ll give the proof and put in
square brackets comments about what I’m doing.
Let L be any regular language. [Here I’m dealing with the ∀L ∈ RegularLanguages by
stating that I’m not assuming anything about L.] Let M be a minimal-state deterministic
2 Modus ponens says that if A ⇒ B and A are both true, then B is true.
128
finite state machine accepting L. [Here I’m using a fact that Hopcroft and Ullman have
already proved about the equivalence of regular languages and finite automata.] Let n be
the number of states in this finite state machine. [I’m dealing with the ∃n by giving a very
specific value of what it will be, based on the arbitrary L.] Let z be any word in L. [Thus
I deal with ∀z ∈ L.] Assume that |z| ≥ n. [Thus I’m taking care of the ⇒ by assuming the
antecedent.]
Say z is written a1 a2 . . . am , where m ≥ n. Consider the states that M is in during the
processing of the first n symbols of z, a1 a2 . . . an . There are n + 1 of these states. Since
there are only n states in M , there must be a duplicate. Say that after symbols aj and ak
we are in the same state, state s (i.e. there’s a loop from this state that the machine goes
through as it accepts z), and say that j < k. Now, let u = a1 a2 . . . aj . This represents the
part of the string that gets you to state s the first time. Let v = aj+1 . . . ak . This represents
the loop that takes you from s and back to it again. Let w = ak+1 . . . am , the rest of word
z. [We have chosen definite values for u, v, and w.] Then clearly z = uvw, since u, v, and
w are just different sections of z. |uv| ≤ n since u and v occur within the first n symbols
of z. |v| ≥ 1 since j < k. [Note that we’re dealing with the formulas connected with ∧ by
proving each of them.]
Now, let i be a natural number (i.e. ≥ 0). [This deals with ∀i ≥ 0.] Then uv i w ∈ L. [Finally
our conclusion, but we have to explain why this is true.] This is because we can repeat the
loop from s to s (represented by v) as many times as we like, and the resulting word will
still be accepted by M .
Now we use the PL to prove that a language is not regular. This is a rewording of Example
2
3.1 from Hopcroft and Ullman. I’ll show that L = {0i |i is an integer, i ≥ 1} is not regular.
Note that L consists of all strings of 0’s whose length is a perfect square. I will use the PL.
I want to prove that L is not regular. I’ll assume the negation (i.e., that L is regular) and
derive a contradiction. So here we go. Remember that what I’m emphasizing here is not
the finite automata stuff itself, but how to use a complicated theorem to prove something
else.
Assume L is regular. We will use the PL to get a contradiction. Since L is regular, the PL
applies to it. [We note that we’re using the ∀ part of the PL for this particular L.] Let n
be as described in the PL. [This takes care of using the ∃n. Note that we are not assuming
2
anything about its actual value, just that it’s a natural number.] Let z = 0n . [Since the PL
says that something is true of all zs, we can choose the one we want to use it for.] So by the
PL there exist u, v, and w such that z = uvw, |uv| ≤ n, |v| ≥ 1. [Note that we don’t assume
anything about what the u, v, and w actually are; the only thing we know about them is
what the PL tells us about them. This is where people trying to use the PL usually screw
up.] The PL then says that for any i, then uv i w ∈ L. Well, then uv 2 w ∈ L. [This is using
the ∀i ≥ 0 bit.] However, n2 < |uv 2 w| ≤ n2 + n, since 1 ≤ |v| ≤ n. But n2 + n < (n + 1)2 .
Thus |uv 2 w| lies properly between n2 and (n + 1)2 and is thus not a perfect square. Thus
uv 2 w is not in L. This is a contradiction. Thus our assumption (that L was regular) was
incorrect. Thus L is not a regular language.
In this section, I will show how the intuitive approach to things that I’ve described above
is reflected in the sequent calculus rules. A sequent is Γ ⊢ Δ, where Γ and Δ are sets of
129
formulas.3 Technically, this means that
A1 ∧ A2 ∧ . . . An ⇒ B1 ∨ B2 ∨ . . . Bm (1)
The Δ, P in the first sequent in the hypotheses means that to the right of the ⊢ we have
the set consisting of the formula P plus all the formulas in Δ, i.e., if all formulas in Γ are
true, then P or one of the formulas in Δ is true. Similarly P, Γ to the left of the ⊢ in the
second sequent means the set consisting of the formula P plus all the formulas in Γ.
We read this rule from the bottom up to make sense of it. Say we want to prove one of the
formulas in Δ from the formulas in Γ, and we want to make use of a formula P that we’ve
already proved. The fact that we’ve proved P is shown by the left hypothesis (of course,
unless the left hypothesis is itself a basic sequent, then in a completed proof there will be
more lines on top of the left hypothesis, showing the actual proof of the sequent). The fact
that we are allowed to use P in the proof of Δ is shown in the right hand hypothesis. We
continue to build the proof up from there, using P .
Some other ways of getting formulas to the left of the ⊢ are shown in the rules (¬r) and
(⇒ r) below.
∀x ∈ S.P (x) The two rules for universally quantified formulas are:
P (v), Γ ⊢ Δ Γ ⊢ Δ, P (x)
(∀l) (∀r)
∀x.P (x), Γ ⊢ Δ Γ ⊢ Δ, ∀x.P (x)
3 In your Logic and Proof notes, the symbol that divides Γ from Δ is ⇒. However, that conflicts with the
use of ⇒ as implication. Thus I will use ⊢. You will see something similar in Semantics, where it separates
assumptions (of the types of variables) from something that they allow you to prove.
4 I won’t mention iff here: as P ⇔ Q is equivalent to P ⇒ Q ∧ Q ⇒ P , we don’t need separate rules for
it.
130
In the (∀r) rule, x must not be free in the conclusion.
Now, what’s going on here? In the (∀l) rule, the ∀x.P (x) is on the left side of the ⊢. Thus, we
are using it (along with some other formula, those in Γ) to prove something (Δ). According
to the intuition above, in order to use ∀x.P (x), you can use it with any value, where v is
used to represent that value. In the hypothesis, you see the formula P (v) to the left of the
⊢. This is just P with v substituted for x. The use of this corresponds exactly to using the
fact that P is true of any value whatsoever, since we are using it with v, which is any value
of our choice.
In the (∀r) rule, the ∀x.P (x) is on the right side of the ⊢. Thus, we are proving it. Thus,
we need to prove it for a generic x. This is why the ∀x is gone in the hypothesis. The x
is still sitting somewhere in the P , but we’re just using it as a plain variable, not assuming
anything about it. And this explains the side condition too: “In the (∀r) rule, x must not
be free in the conclusion.” If x is not free in the conclusion, this means that x is not free in
the formulas in Γ or Δ. That means the only place the x occurs free in the hypothesis is in
P itself. This corresponds exactly with the requirement that we’re proving that P is true
of a generic x: if x were free in Γ or Δ, we would be assuming something about x, namely
that value of x is the same as the x used in those formulas.
Note that induction is not mentioned in the rules. This is because the sequent calculus used
here just deals with pure logic. In more complicated presentations of logic, it is explained
how to define new types via structural induction, and from there you get mechanisms to
allow you to do induction.
∃x ∈ S.P (x) The two rules for existentially quantified formulas are:
P (x), Γ ⊢ Δ Γ ⊢ Δ, P (v)
(∃l) (∃r)
∃x.P (x), Γ ⊢ Δ Γ ⊢ Δ, ∃x.P (x)
Γ ⊢ Δ, P P, Γ ⊢ Δ
(¬l) (¬r)
¬P, Γ ⊢ Δ Γ ⊢ Δ, ¬P
Let’s start with the right rule first. I said that the way to prove ¬P is to assume P and
derive a contradiction. If Δ is the empty set, then this is exactly what this rule says: If
there are no formulas to the right hand side of the ⊢, then this means that the formulas in
Γ are inconsistent (that means, they cannot all be true at the same time). This means that
you have derived a contradiction. So if Δ is the empty set, the hypothesis of the rule says
that, assuming P , you have obtained a contradiction. Thus, if you are absolutely certain
about all your other hypotheses, then you can be sure that P is not true. The best way to
understand the rule if Δ is not empty is to write out the meaning of the sequents in terms
of the meaning of the sequent given by Equation 1 and work out the equivalence of the top
and bottom of the rule using the equivalences in your Logic and Proof notes.
The easiest way to understand (¬l) is again by using equivalences.
131
P ⇒ Q The two rules for implication are:
Γ ⊢ Δ, P Q, Γ ⊢ Δ P, Γ ⊢ Δ, Q
(⇒ l) (⇒ r)
P ⇒ Q, Γ ⊢ Δ Γ ⊢ Δ, P ⇒ Q
The rule (⇒ l) easily understood using the intuitive explanation of how to use P ⇒ Q given
above. First, we have to prove P . This is the left hypothesis. Then we can use Q, which is
what the right hypothesis says.
The right rule (⇒ r) is also easily understood. In order to prove P ⇒ Q, we assume P ,
then use this to prove Q. This is exactly what the hypothesis says.
P, Q, Γ ⊢ Δ Γ ⊢ Δ, P Γ ⊢ Δ, Q
(∧l) (∧r)
P ∧ Q, Γ ⊢ Δ Γ ⊢ Δ, P ∧ Q
Both of these rules are easily explained by the intuition above. The left rule (∧l) says that
when you use P ∧ Q, you can use P and Q. The right rule says that to prove P ∧ Q you must
prove P , and you must prove Q. You may wonder why we need separate hypotheses for
the two different proofs. We can’t just put P, Q to the right of the ⊢ in a single hypothesis,
because that would mean that we’re proving one of the other of them (see the meaning of
the sequent given in Equation 1). So we need separate hypotheses to make sure that each
of P and Q has actually been proved.
P, Γ ⊢ Δ Q, Γ ⊢ Δ Γ ⊢ Δ, P, Q
(∨l) (∨r)
P ∨ Q, Γ ⊢ Δ Γ ⊢ Δ, P ∨ Q
These are also easily understood by the intuitive explanations above. The left rule says that
to prove something (namely, one of the formulas in Δ) using P ∨ Q, you need to prove it
using P , then prove it using Q. The right rule says that in order to prove P ∨ Q, you can
prove one or the other. The hypothesis says that you can prove one or the other, because
in order to show a sequent Γ ⊢ Δ true, you only need to show that one of the formulas in
Δ is true.
132