0% found this document useful (0 votes)
6 views171 pages

PatersonReview_Vol12_Full

Uploaded by

Pal Gabriel
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
6 views171 pages

PatersonReview_Vol12_Full

Uploaded by

Pal Gabriel
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 171

Volume 12, 2012

Norman Paterson School of International Affairs

Carleton University
5306 River Building
1125 Colonel By Drive
Ottawa, Ontario, Canada
K1S 5B6
diplomatonline.com/mag/paterson-review
The Paterson Review of International Affairs, formally E-merge, is a scholarly jour-
nal exclusively showcasing the work of graduate students in the field of international
affairs. Managed by students of the Norman Paterson School of International Affairs,
the Paterson Review is dedicated to publishing articles on a wide range of emerg-
ing issues in the theory and practice of international affairs. Copy requests and
submissions may be sent electronically to [email protected] or by mail to
Paterson Review c/o Norman Paterson School of International Affairs, 5306 River
Building, Carleton University, 1125 Colonel By Drive, Ottawa, Ontario, K1S 5B6,
Canada.

Copyright © 2012, Paterson Review of International Affairs


1. International Relations – Periodicals. 2. World Politics – Periodicals. 3. Policy
Sciences – Periodicals.
Contents
Letter from the Editors iv

Approche pangouvernementale canadienne : Comment favoriser


une intégration positive des organisations publiques impliquées
dans un processus de réforme organisationnelle 1
Caroline Leprince
Faculté de science politique et de droit, Université du Québec à Montréal

Durability in Darfur? Assessing the Darfur Peace Agreement 19


Justin Mohammed
Norman Paterson School of International Affairs, Carleton University

Controlling Small Arms and Light Weapons Proliferation: The


Potential of the Arms Trade Treaty 35
Nathan A. Sears
Norman Paterson School of International Affairs, Carleton University

To Rid the World of the Drug Scourge: A Human Security


Perspective on the War on Drugs in Colombia and Mexico 61
Ginette Léa Gautreau
School of International Development and Global Studies,
University of Ottawa

Beyond Rawls’s Law of Peoples: Freedom, Capabilities, and Human


Security 85
Marcel Sangsari
Norman Paterson School of International Affairs, Carleton University

Indigenous Peoples’ Struggles for Autonomy: The Case of the U’wa


People 109
Juan Martin Arellano Martinez
Norman Paterson School of International Affairs, Carleton University

The Quiet Tsunami: The Ecological, Economic, Social, and Political


Consequences of Ocean Acidification 123
Natassia Ciuriak
School of Public Policy and Administration, Carleton University

Climate Change, Migration, and Megacities: Addressing the Dual


Stresses of Mass Urbanization and Climate Vulnerability 145
Miles DePaul
Balsillie School of International Affairs, Wilfrid Laurier University
Editorial Board
Editors-in-Chief
Jeff K. Ahonoukoun, Alan Ho, and Michael Olender

Treasurer
Alan Ho

Contributors
Layout Designer
Amanda Shendruk

Contributing Editors Blind Reviewers


Gabrielle Biron-Hudon James Braun
Katherine Cullen Philip Cook
Justine Gilbert Sebastian Cray
Helen Habte-Selassie Irma F. Cruz-Lopez
Miguel Iriondo Claude Dumulon-Lauzière
Yasar Khan Hayley Flett
Philip Martin Denis Giroux
Marielle Milot Anna Golubova
Iván Narváez Leticia Hernandez
Jan Nitoslawski Catherine Holden
Karl Payeur Hussein Kasim
Kristjan Surko David Kuttner
Nicole Tishler Kristen Lennox
Stephanie Tissot Ryan MacLean
Martin V. Manolov
Azalyn Manzano
Philip Martin
Taryn Russell
Julie Savard-Shaw
Erica See
Nadia Teodori
Gordon Thomas
Zhannah Voukitchevitch
Taryn Russell
Brendan Warren
Kevin Jerome Basil Williams
William Wilson
Acknowledgements
Expert Reviewers
Endre Begby, PhD, Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy,
Simon Fraser University
Dorina A. Bekoe, PhD, Research Staff Member, Institute for Defense
Analyses
James J. Brittain, PhD, Associate Professor, Department of Sociology,
Acadia University
John Cameron, PhD, Associate Professor, Department of International
Development Studies, Dalhousie University
Heather Devere, PhD, Director of Practice, National Centre for Peace and
Conflict Studies, University of Otago
Thomas de Waal, BA, Senior Associate, Russia and Eurasia Program,
Carnegie Endowment for International Peace
Denise Garcia, PhD, Assistant Professor, Political Science and International
Affairs, Northeastern University
Tara Holton, PhD, Defence Scientist, Defence R&D Canada – Toronto
Glenn McDonald, PhD, Yearbook Coordinator and Senior Researcher,
Small Arms Survey, Graduate Institute of International and
Development Studies
Edward Moxon-Browne, MA, Jean Monnet Chair of European Integration,
Centre for European Studies, University of Limerick
Katherine Richardson, PhD, Professor in Biological Oceanography, Center
for Macroecology, Evolution and Climate / Leader of Sustainability
Science Centre, University of Copenhagen
Jon J. Scott, PhD, Adjunct Professor (Retd.), School for International Studies,
Simon Fraser University
Mohammad Zaman, PhD, Freelance Consultant and Executive Director,
Society for Bangladesh Climate Justice
Christoph Zürcher, PhD, Full Professor, Graduate School of Public and
International Affairs, University of Ottawa / Université d’Ottawa

Special thanks to
Sophie Hashem
Genevieve Leroux
Alex Martin
Norean Shepherd
Stephanie Tissot
Canadian Centre for Treaty Compliance
Centre for Security and Defence Studies
Diplomat & International Canada
Norman Paterson School of International Affairs
Letter from the Editors
The 2011–12 period has been a tumultuous one for international affairs
practitioners and scholars. The Middle East and North Africa witnessed the fall
of decades-long dictatorships during the Arab Spring, drug-related violence
in Latin America is at an all-time high, and a new African country was created
with the partition of Sudan. At the same time, climate change, the global
economy, and development issues demand ever more attention, particularly
with the shift of politico-economic power from the global North to global
South. Critical analysis of international issues is necessary not only to make
sense of them, but to suggest ways in which governments, institutions, and
civil society organizations can adequately address them. Recommendations
that carefully consider the problems at hand, their causes, their implications,
and the distributional issues between developed and developing countries
have the potential to affect policy, as well as the scholarly debate within the
field of international relations. Students at the graduate level are well placed
to think critically and contribute innovative ideas to policy discussions.
The Paterson Review of International Affairs, based out of the Norman
Paterson School of International Affairs (NPSIA) at Carleton University in
Ottawa, Canada, is a double-blind peer-reviewed journal that is published
annually to disseminate the research of graduate students. Its focus on policy
allows students interested in public and international affairs to explore
practical alternatives for policy-making. Of the 44 submissions received in
the summer of 2011, eight were selected for publication. The authors of these
papers critically analyzed issues that are steadily gaining prominence and
proposed options for moving forward.
International security, the perennial focus of international relations for
practitioners and scholars alike, is examined in innovative ways. Caroline
Leprince assesses the Canadian government’s pan-governmental approach to
fragile and failed states. She argues that the effectiveness of Canadian missions
abroad can be improved by putting special emphasis on departmental cultures
during pre-mission training. Justin Mohammed examines the determinants
of durable peace agreements and, using the Darfur Peace Agreement as a
case study, recommends the compilation of a rank-ordered index of conflict
management measures and further context-specific research to guide policy-
makers. Nathan Sears considers the difficulties of controlling small arms and
light weapons proliferation and areas for the Arms Trade Treaty to address. He
recommends contingency plans, increased co-operation among and technical
assistance from developed countries, and civil society action on monitoring,
verification, and responding to non-compliance. Ginette Gautreau adopts
a human security perspective to critique the War on Drugs, suggesting the
establishment of new national research bodies, broadened socio-economic
policies, judicial reforms, and a paradigmatic shift in anti-drug policy from a
state-centred to a human-centred approach.
New perspectives on global development challenges highlight
promising directions for policy. In critiquing the philosophy of John Rawls,
Marcel Sangsari investigates whether the better-off have a duty to provide
development assistance and offers recommendations, including the provision
of international aid based on novel criteria, to maximize the capabilities of the
world’s poorest. Juan Arellano highlights indigenous peoples’ intensifying
resistance to the processes of neoliberal globalization. He indicates that state
recognition of these peoples’ collective rights is crucial and that mutual co-
operation between indigenous peoples and international organizations as
well as integrated capacities enabled by information and communications
technologies could garner global support for these peoples’ aspirations.
Climate change continues to be perceived as the greatest collective
challenge that the world faces. Natassia Ciuriak details the consequences
of ocean acidification to give urgency to climate change policy-making. She
recommends building advocacy coalitions, bottom-up education campaigns,
cutting subsidies to fossil-fuel producers, and investment in environmental
protection. Miles DePaul adopts a long-term perspective on climate-induced
migration and the stresses it will place on megacities, demonstrating that
comprehensive climate change mitigation and adaptation policies and a
normative shift on climate-related mobility are necessary.
Volume 12 of the Paterson Review is the result of hard work put in
by many graduate students, some who wrote the articles published in this
journal and others who selected papers in a double-blind review process or
helped with editing and revision. Notably, this volume marks the first time
that the Paterson Review has published a French article, demonstrating a new
commitment to publishing scholarship in both of Canada’s official languages.
Since 2007, the Paterson Review has been published in hard-copy format
and circulated to public and international affairs schools around the world.
The journal is also available online through Diplomat & International Canada
magazine at www.diplomatonline.com/mag/paterson-review. Since 2009, the
journal has been indexed at Library and Archives Canada.
The editors-in-chief of the Paterson Review would like to thank the
authors, expert reviewers, contributing editors, blind reviewers, and designer
who dedicated their time and expertise to this publication. We also thank
the staff at NPSIA for their administrative support, Diplomat & International
Canada for its continued partnership, and our sponsors NPSIA, the Canadian
Centre for Treaty Compliance, and the Centre for Security and Defence
Studies for making this journal possible.

Jeff K. Ahonoukoun, Alan Ho, and Michael Olender


Editors-in-Chief
1
Paterson Review of International Affairs (2012) 12: 1–17.

Approche pangouvernementale canadienne:


Comment favoriser une intégration
positive des organisations publiques
impliquées dans un processus de réforme
organisationnelle
Caroline Leprince
Faculté de science politique et de droit, Université du Québec à Montréal

Au cours des dernières années, le gouvernement canadien a adopté une


approche pangouvernementale pour intervenir dans les États fragiles
ou en déroute. Compte tenu de la grande diversité des ministères et
agences appelés à travailler dans un contexte pangouvernemental,
des risques de résistances institutionnelles étaient prévisibles. Cet
article utilise la culture organisationnelle comme angle d’analyse afin
d’examiner les sensibilités des organisations publiques impliquées
dans un processus de réforme organisationnelle, une facette qui fut
l’objet de peu d’étude jusqu’à présent. En dernier lieu, certaines
recommandations sont présentées afin de mieux encadrer le personnel
qui se déploiera dans le cadre d’une mission pangouvernementale.

Introduction
Depuis quelques années déjà, le gouvernement canadien emploie une
nouvelle stratégie d’intervention afin de mieux répondre aux situations
complexes de crise et de reconstruction post-conflit. L’Énoncé de politique
internationale du Canada de 2005 a introduit une stratégie d’intervention
dite « pangouvernementale » qui est plus adaptée aux « nouvelles » réalités
internationales. En adoptant une vision plus holistique des conflits, cette
approche formalise une collaboration plus étroite entre les éléments de la
défense, de la diplomatie et du développement (3D) afin d’intervenir dans les
États fragiles ou en déroute (Canada 2005a, 23).1
Bien que cette stratégie pangouvernementale ait été développée
comme outil d’intervention optimal pour des environnements de sécurité
complexes, il ne peut être présumé qu’une intégration suivra naturellement
entre les parties participant à l’approche. Les diverses organisations réunies
sous un effort pangouvernemental possèdent toutes une culture, des valeurs
et des pratiques qui leurs sont propres. Ces différences peuvent favoriser
l’émergence de tensions entre les partenaires qui partagent parfois des
2
objectifs divergents (Flemming 2000, 39 ; Leslie, Gizewski et Rostek 2008, 14).
Cet article se questionne sur la manière dont ces tensions
organisationnelles affectent les dynamiques d’interaction entre les principaux
acteurs prenant part à l’approche pangouvernementale. Ce texte soutient que
ces difficultés sont liées, en grande partie, aux contradictions présentes dans les
cultures organisationnelles des ministères et agences (i.e., mandats, valeurs,
pratiques d’intervention). Dès lors, ces divergences organisationnelles ont
pour effet de limiter les possibilités pour les partenaires de poursuivre leur
objectif de collaboration.
Afin d’examiner les sensibilités des organisations publiques
réunies dans un effort pangouvernemental, cette étude utilise la culture
organisationnelle comme angle d’analyse. Cette perspective a le mérite
de tenir compte du point de vue des organisations dans ce processus de
réforme, plutôt que de se concentrer uniquement sur une vision qui englobe
l’approche dans son ensemble. Pour conclure, cet article présentera des
recommandations pour mieux encadrer les acteurs gouvernementaux
canadiens qui se déploieront dans un contexte pangouvernemental, en leur
offrant une formation mieux adaptée à leurs besoins.

Courants de littérature critiques des processus de


réforme organisationnelle
Même si la stratégie pangouvernementale repose grandement sur la
collaboration entre les parties participant à l’approche, il s’avère que de
nombreux obstacles nuisent à l’efficacité interministérielle (Thompson et Gill
2010).2 Dans un contexte pangouvernemental, les organisations publiques
traditionnellement indépendantes sont incitées à collaborer. Ces pressions
peuvent indisposer certains des ministères et agences qui craignent que les
rôles et fonctions qui leur sont attribués dans le cadre de cet effort conjoint ne
correspondent pas aux objectifs et mandats poursuivis par leur organisation
(Baumann 2008, 71). Ils peuvent réagir négativement à la restructuration
non seulement parce qu’ils redoutent que la nouvelle structure réduise
leur autonomie, mais aussi parce qu’ils appréhendent de se faire assimiler
et que leurs valeurs et préoccupations organisationnelles ne soient plus
reflétées (Christensen et Laegreid 2006, 17). D’ailleurs, cette approche est
particulièrement critiquée par la communauté du développement qui craint
que l’harmonisation des politiques réduise leur autonomie et leur capacité
d’agir conformément à leurs objectifs de lutte contre la pauvreté (Patrick et
Brown 2007, 131). Cette communauté juge que l’approche pangouvernementale
instrumentalise les ressources destinées au développement international
et les détourne pour servir des intérêts avant tout sécuritaires et politiques
(Brown 2008).3
Dans la littérature, deux courants formulent des suggestions pour
améliorer la collaboration interministérielle dans le contexte d’une approche
pangouvernementale. Le premier, qui est le courant dominant, adopte une
vision relativement technique du problème (Canada 2007 ; Friis et Jarmyr
3
2008 ; JTFA 2009 ; OECD 2006 ; Patrick et Brown 2007 ; Rintakoski et Autti
2008). Afin de pallier au déficit de collaboration, celui-ci suggère d’ajouter
davantage de mécanismes de coordination, ainsi que de mettre en place
des structures pour améliorer les processus d’interaction et de planification
entre les ministères.4 Paradoxalement, la littérature portant sur la confiance
organisationnelle démontre que l’ajout de structures et de mécanismes de
contrôle tend plutôt à jouer l’effet contraire. En fait, ce fardeau additionnel
contribuerait à diminuer la confiance entre les membres (Das et Teng 1998,
495-496). Il existe donc un seuil où plus de coordination n’engendrera pas
de bénéfices additionnels. Ainsi, la poursuite de la cohérence au-delà d’une
certaine limite aura plus d’effets négatifs que positifs (de Coning et Friis 2011,
14).
La seconde approche considère que le fossé entre la politique
pangouvernementale et ses échecs en pratique est causé par des contradictions
inhérentes aux mandats, aux intérêts et aux valeurs fondamentales des
acteurs. Ces incohérences posent des contraintes quant à la collaboration
possible entre les partenaires poursuivant un effort pangouvernemental
(ibid., 13). Puisque chaque acteur provient d’une communauté distincte –
diplomatique, militaire et du développement – chacun a intégré les principes
et les philosophies propres à sa profession et sphère d’activité. Il serait naïf
de croire que ces différences fondamentales, qui façonnent les identités
des organisations, puissent être résolues par la coordination. Ignorer ces
profondes différences risque de créer de nouvelles tensions entre les acteurs
internes qui soutiennent l’effort pangouvernemental. Pour qu’un processus
de réforme soit réussi, il faut d’abord reconnaître la spécificité propre à
chaque culture et ensuite instaurer progressivement un esprit de collectivité
auprès des nouveaux partenaires (Christensen et Laegrid 2006, 13 ; Das et
Teng 1998, 507).
En somme, ces deux approches – l’une basée sur l’ajout de mécanismes
de coordination et l’autre axée sur la valorisation des traditions culturelles
des organisations – peuvent améliorer l’efficacité de la collaboration entre les
partenaires si elles sont appliquées de façon complémentaire. Une fois que
les structures et mécanismes en place contribuent au bon fonctionnement de
l’approche pangouvernementale, il ne faut pas non plus oublier la dimension
humaine. Celle-ci est très importante pour renforcer la confiance entre les
membres participant à l’approche. La sélection de personnes compétentes
dans les postes clés – nommées boundary spanners dans la littérature5 – demeure
essentielle afin de concilier les différents points de vue organisationnels et
favoriser une collaboration interministérielle efficace.

Culture organisationnelle, habitus et ethnocentrisme


Afin d’approfondir la compréhension des tensions vécues par les ministères
et agences gouvernementaux dans un contexte de réforme organisationnelle,
cette étude se fonde sur le cadre d’analyse de la culture organisationnelle,
développé par Edgar Schein. Jusqu’à présent, la culture a fait l’objet de très
4
peu d’analyse dans la littérature portant sur le maintien de la paix.6 Ce constat
est étonnant puisque la culture organisationnelle est citée dans de nombreux
articles comme étant le principal obstacle à la coordination civilo-militaire
(Baumann 2008 ; Duffey 2000 ; Jenny 2001 ; Thompson et Gill 2010 ; Van der
Kloet 2006). Une telle perspective a le mérite d’inspirer des alternatives aux
réponses institutionnelles traditionnellement proposées pour atténuer les
différences interministérielles. De plus, ce cadre d’analyse permet de tenir
compte du point de vue des organisations et de démontrer que, parfois, les
mentalités en « silo » peuvent également avoir leur utilité (Christensen et
Laegreid 2006, 21).
Le concept de culture organisationnelle est révélateur de la raison
d’être d’une organisation, duquel découle le sens des objectifs qu’elle
poursuit dans son environnement (Duffey 2000, 148 ; Bentley 2010, 3).
Larry Minear et Thomas Weiss (1993, 69) décrivent le concept de culture
organisationnelle comme étant la façon dont une organisation se perçoit et
désire être perçue dans son environnement : « [it is] an organization’s way of
approaching its tasks, its relationships with other agencies, its self-image and
public image and its standard operating procedures. » En plus de guider les
procédures et les routines d’une organisation, la culture organisationnelle se
reflète également dans le choix des ressources et des capacités qu’elle décide
d’acquérir (Baumann 2008, 72). En somme, elle s’observe dans les valeurs
fondamentales, les symboles et les pratiques collectives partagés par les
membres d’une organisation.
C’est à travers un processus d’enculturation7 que les membres d’une
organisation apprennent et internalisent les règles et les modèles de conduite
prescrits par leur culture organisationnelle (Duffey 2000, 148). Dans les
théories sur les organisations, Schein s’est particulièrement intéressé à leur
analyse culturelle. Rappelons ici sa définition de la culture organisationnelle :
« La culture organisationnelle est le pattern de principes ou postulats de base
qu’un groupe donné a créé, découvert, ou développé, en apprenant à traiter
ses problèmes d’adaptation à l’environnement extérieur et d’intégration
interne, et qui se sont avérés suffisamment efficaces pour être considérés
valables et qui, par conséquent, peuvent être enseignés aux nouveaux
membres comme la bonne manière de percevoir, de penser et de sentir, par
rapport à ces problèmes (Schein 1991, 176). » Les valeurs et les principes
sous-jacents de l’organisation sont donc intériorisés par le membre et, en
retour, influencent la façon dont ce dernier perçoit, prend des décisions et
se comporte quotidiennement dans son environnement (Davis 2010, 48).
Bien que la culture de l’organisation n’engendrera pas de comportements
prédéterminés, ce processus d’apprentissage façonnera durablement les
réponses cognitives et émotives des membres de l’organisation face à leur
environnement externe (Schein 1991, 191). En fait, ce processus d’enculturation
se renforcera au fur et à mesure que les membres devront réagir à certaines
situations. Par conséquent, « plus longue est notre vie au sein d’une culture
donnée et plus cette culture est ancienne, plus elle aura d’influence sur nos
perceptions, pensées et sentiments (Bélanger et Mercier 2006, 336). » Face à
5
des circonstances inhabituelles et sous des conditions de fortes pressions, les
réactions et mécanismes d’adaptation d’un individu seront guidés par les
habitudes et façons de faire inculquées par sa culture organisationnelle.
Deux concepts complémentaires à la culture organisationnelle, soient
l’habitus et l’ethnocentrisme, sont utilisés dans cette analyse pour étudier
les organisations publiques dans un processus de réforme institutionnelle.
A. B. Fetherston et Carolyn Nordstrom (1995) sont les premiers à avoir
utilisé la notion d’habitus du sociologue Pierre Bourdieu pour réexaminer
la compréhension de la résolution de conflits dans les missions de paix. Le
concept d’habitus a été défini par Bourdieu (2000, 261) comme un « système de
dispositions durables et transposables qui, en intégrant toutes les expériences
passées, fonctionne à chaque moment comme une matrice de perceptions,
d’appréciation et d’actions. » Ce processus établit un cadre culturel duquel
sont puisés des schèmes d’action qui permettent à un individu d’agir de façon
« appropriée » dans son environnement. Or, ces dispositions socialement
construites font tellement partie intégrante de la vie quotidienne qu’elles
sont prises pour acquis ; pour ainsi dire, l’enculturation d’un individu se
fait surtout de façon inconsciente. Pierre Dasen (1993) prévient également
qu’un individu ne peut se rendre compte de sa propre enculturation à moins
d’être exposé à une autre culture. Paradoxalement, les personnes chez qui
l’enculturation est la plus forte sont celles qui ne prendront pas conscience de
l’influence qu’exerce la culture sur leur vie. Conséquemment, les individus
doivent sortir de leur milieu pour comprendre leur monde. Ils ont recours
à l’altérité, ce qui leur permet de voir le monde à travers des dichotomies
(Mussweiler et Bodenhausen 2002), et de définir ce qu’ils sont de ce qu’ils ne
sont pas (Hill 2007, 28).
Le concept d’ethnocentrisme, introduit en sociologie par William
Sumner (1906), s’exprime par une tendance à comprendre le monde à travers
le biais normatif des valeurs de sa propre société pour analyser les autres
sociétés. Cela s’explique par les forts liens qui unissent une société et qui
procurent, en retour, des sentiments de sécurité, de familiarité et d’ordre à ses
membres (Kimmel 1998, 59). Tel que présenté par Roy Preiswerk et Dominique
Perrot (1975, 49), l’ethnocentrisme permet d’interpréter les communautés
hors-groupes (outgroup) qui sont jugées à travers les concepts, les normes et les
critères de l’endogroupe (ingroup). En d’autres termes, « l’ethnocentrisme est
défini comme l’attitude d’un groupe consistant à s’accorder une place centrale
par rapport aux autres groupes, à valoriser positivement ses réalisations et
particularismes, et menant à un comportement projectif à l’égard des hors-
groupes qui sont interprétés à travers le mode de pensée de l’endogroupe
(ibid.). » Ainsi, les membres de l’endogroupe utilisent leurs propres référents
culturels pour conceptualiser le monde dans lequel ils vivent. Ces individus
ont tendance à prendre pour acquis que les schèmes de comportements qu’ils
ont appris et internalisés sont meilleurs que ceux des autres. En fait, l’adoption
d’un comportement par une personne à l’extérieur de l’endogroupe, qui
dévierait de ce qui est approprié dans le schème culturel d’un individu, serait
jugé illogique et incompréhensible par ce dernier.
6
Application de la culture organisationnelle pour
analyser les dynamiques interministérielles dans un
contexte pangouvernemental
L’application du concept d’habitus de Bourdieu dans un contexte
pangouvernemental permet d’approfondir la compréhension des schèmes
culturels entre les différentes communautés qui interprètent la mission à
travers les lunettes de leur propre culture organisationnelle, c’est-à-dire leur
propre habitus (Fetherston et Nordstrom 1995, 95). Cette particularité propre
aux opérations multidimensionnelles a été soulignée par Robert Rubinstein
(1993, 553) : « A peacekeeping mission may mean many different things to
different people, because each may have a different political understanding
of the situation. Peacekeeping operations take place in the context of the
daily lives of multiple communities: diplomatic, military, and local. Each
of these communities embodies culturally constituted ways of behaving
and understanding the objectives and practices of operations. Sometimes
the intersection of these cultural spheres is problematic. » Chaque acteur a
son propre habitus qui lui fournit le contexte référentiel duquel il puise ses
croyances et ses modèles de conduite. Ces références sont internalisées et
construites par le biais de la culture organisationnelle et permettent à l’acteur
de répondre efficacement aux exigences qui lui sont prescrites dans le cadre
de la mission.
Afin d’illustrer la notion d’habitus, Fetherston et Nordstrom (1995, 107)
citent en exemple le rôle de l’entraînement chez les militaires. Dans le cadre
de leur formation, les soldats sont entraînés à se battre contre des ennemis ;
l’entraînement tend à déshumaniser les hors-groupes et à justifier le recours à
la force contre eux. Par conséquent, l’habitus du soldat vient à conceptualiser
le monde sous une forte dichotomie nous/eux. Ainsi, les schèmes d’action
internalisés et appris par les soldats pendant leur entraînement militaire
deviennent des pratiques communes fortement enracinées dans la culture
militaire – et qui se trouvent grandement renforcées en zone de conflit. Les
valeurs fondamentales enseignées derrière cet entraînement sont d’importants
indicateurs des hypothèses sous-jacentes de la culture militaire.
À force de se côtoyer, chaque communauté – diplomatique, militaire et
du développement – a développé une culture organisationnelle unique qui
s’est renforcée au contact des autres communautés. Chacune opère donc selon
ses référents culturels en répondant à une situation selon sa compréhension
organisationnelle et ses politiques d’intervention (Thompson et Gill 2010,
8). Dans un contexte pangouvernemental où tous les partenaires travaillent
conjointement, nous avons tenté de comprendre de quelles manières les
différentes cultures organisationnelles affectaient la coopération. Des études
sur la coopération civilo-militaire ont révélé que le manque de familiarité
entre les différentes communautés peut inciter les membres à développer
une méfiance face aux autres groupes et à faire usage de stéréotypes négatifs
(Duffey 2000, 149 ; Jenny 2001, 27). Ces pratiques ethnocentriques viennent
7
d’un besoin de se sécuriser face à une peur de l’autre.
Par exemple, si des militaires, des diplomates et des spécialistes en
développement se voient confier la mission de sécuriser un village dans
un environnement de contre-insurrection, ils auront tendance à envisager
différentes approches pour arriver à leur fin. Notamment, ils auront des
attentes différentes quant au temps nécessaire pour atteindre cet objectif et leurs
indices de succès varieront les uns par rapport aux autres. Conséquemment, les
moyens employés par les membres de différentes communautés pour mener
à bien leurs objectifs peuvent devenir la source de frustration importante
entre les individus (Smith 2007, 373). Cette incompréhension, éprouvée par un
acteur face aux raisonnements qui façonnent les choix d’un acteur extérieur à
sa communauté d’appartenance, peut effriter la confiance de ce dernier qui juge
l’autre inapte à anticiper correctement la réponse à une crise.
Force est de constater qu’a priori même les partenaires provenant d’un
même État tendent à sous-estimer la force de leur habitus organisationnel.
Il semble qu’il ne soit pas aussi facile qu’on le laisse prétendre pour les
partenaires gouvernementaux de dépasser leurs différends organisationnels.8
En fait, une meilleure préparation serait nécessaire pour améliorer leur
aptitude à travailler conjointement. Ainsi, la prochaine section s’attardera à
présenter la façon dont les acteurs peuvent outrepasser leurs comportements
ethnocentriques afin de travailler efficacement sur le terrain.

Outiller les acteurs pour travailler dans un contexte


pangouvernemental
Afin de favoriser une adaptation positive des organisations impliquées dans
ce nouveau contexte pangouvernemental, la mise en œuvre de certaines
initiatives peut aider à bâtir la confiance et les facteurs de cohésion entre
les partenaires gouvernementaux. La confiance entre les partenaires est un
élément essentiel à la performance générale d’une équipe pangouvernementale
(Thompson et Gill 2010, 7).9 En effet, les membres dépendent grandement des
uns et des autres pour atteindre leurs objectifs. Pour aider à consolider ces
liens de confiance, il s’est révélé particulièrement bénéfique pour le personnel
d’une mission pangouvernementale de recevoir une formation culturelle
ainsi que d’augmenter les opportunités d’entraînement et de socialisation
entre les partenaires. De telles initiatives peuvent aider les acteurs à
prendre conscience des raisons pour lesquelles les barrières culturelles et
institutionnelles affectent la coordination interministérielle.
Avant une affectation à l’étranger, la majorité des organisations offre une
formation à leur personnel pour qu’il soit efficace sur le plan culturel. Celle-
ci se concentre principalement sur l’approfondissement des connaissances
culturelles du pays hôte ainsi que sur l’enseignement des techniques de
communication interculturelle avec les populations locales. Notons qu’au
Canada, ces formations culturelles sont actuellement enseignées dans un
cadre de perfectionnement professionnel au sein de la fonction publique et
dans le milieu de la défense. En effet, le centre d’apprentissage culturel du
8
ministère des Affaires étrangères et du Commerce international (MAECI)
enseigne à leur personnel comment être efficace sur le plan interculturel
(Vulpe et al. 2001), alors que les Forces canadiennes sensibilisent leur troupe
au concept de l’intelligence culturelle (Davis 2010).10
Pourtant, comme l’a démontré Tamara Duffey (2000), il semble que ce
type de formation soit insuffisant pour outiller les personnes qui travailleront
dans un contexte pangouvernemental. La contribution de l’auteure est
particulièrement intéressante puisqu’elle reconnaît l’importance de préparer
et d’entraîner toutes les personnes destinées à travailler dans les opérations
de maintien de la paix aux autres cultures organisationnelles présentes sur
le terrain : « As peacekeepers and humanitarian workers find themselves
responding to the same crisis, it is imperative that these disparate components
of the complex humanitarian network learn how to work effectively together
in order to mutually reinforce each other’s aims and objectives. This requires,
first and foremost, an increased awareness and understanding of the cultures
of the other (ibid., 163). » Les formations existantes sensibilisent déjà chaque
participant au rôle que joue sa culture organisationnelle lorsqu’il interagit avec
des personnes de cultures étrangères. L’ensemble des notions transmises lors
de ces formations peut donc être appliqué aux interactions interministérielles.
Dans le cadre de leur apprentissage, les participants prennent conscience de
l’influence de leur propre conditionnement culturel et de la façon dont celui-
ci a formé leur mode de pensée, leurs perceptions d’un conflit et leur façon
de réagir lorsqu’ils sont confrontés à une situation difficile. Nous soutenons
que les formations existantes doivent être adaptées afin qu’un cours puisse se
concentrer exclusivement à la dimension des interactions interministérielles.
Une telle formation, axée sur les effets de la culture organisationnelle
dans les interactions interministérielles, apporterait des bénéfices concrets
à la préparation des partenaires appelés à travailler dans un contexte
pangouvernemental. Ainsi, les dirigeants prendraient conscience qu’un
même concept peut être interprété différemment selon les référents culturels
de leurs collègues. Par exemple, Andrea Baumann (2008, 73) a illustré que
la notion de sécurité pouvait prendre des significations différentes selon la
culture organisationnelle qui la définit : « Security tends to be understood by
the military in a kinetic way; by diplomats as a matter of law enforcement and
public order; and by development experts in the sense of human security, a
concept that embraces both the physical safety and well-being of individuals.
» Il est nécessaire que les directeurs des différentes organisations soient
capables, préalablement à leur départ en mission, de saisir les raisonnements
propres à d’autres cultures organisationnelles, sans quoi ils ressentiront
inévitablement une incompréhension face aux pratiques adoptées par leurs
partenaires sur le terrain (Smith 2007, 373). Progressivement, la formation
suggérée permettrait d’apprécier la multiplicité des réponses fournies pour
répondre à un même problème et, souvent, de réaliser que ces solutions sont
complémentaires les unes aux autres. Simultanément, ces enseignements
culturels peuvent aider les ministères et agences gouvernementaux à
développer des interactions plus efficaces, avec d’autres acteurs présents dans
9
l’environnement où se déroule la mission, notamment avec la population
locale, les organisations non gouvernementales et les médias.
À titre d’exemple, Andy Tamas (2009, 179-180), un expert en
développement qui a travaillé auprès de l’Équipe consultative stratégique en
Afghanistan, a constaté que certains aspects liés à la culture militaire pouvaient
être dommageables aux initiatives de reconstruction et de développement.
Selon l’auteur, les militaires ont une culture fondée sur l’action ; ils sont
formés pour agir et obtenir des résultats (ibid., 57). Confrontés à un vide
institutionnel ou à la lenteur des travaux de reconstruction, les militaires ont
tendance à vouloir prendre en charge la situation et résoudre les problèmes
eux-mêmes. Toutefois, ces solutions ont souvent pour effet d’apporter leur lot
de difficultés inattendues (Lane et Sky 2006, 50). Une formation s’appuyant
sur l’intelligence culturelle, qui leur ferait prendre conscience des influences
de leur culture sur leurs comportements, outillerait davantage les militaires
(Davis 2010, 59). Ainsi, avant d’agir, ils pourraient réfléchir aux actions
que poseraient d’autres acteurs dans la même situation. Pour les agents de
développement, le processus d’apprentissage est plus important encore que
la réussite d’un projet puisque cela renforce les capacités d’administration
des autorités locales. En faisant usage de comparaisons, cela peut mener à un
changement de perception du problème initial et permettre l’adoption d’un
comportement mieux adapté à la situation. En effet, la meilleure solution
consiste parfois à ne pas passer à l’action, ce qui est contre-intuitif pour les
militaires (Tamas 2009, 180).
Afin de compléter cette formation, certaines mesures pourraient
être mises en œuvre par le gouvernement canadien afin de familiariser les
fonctionnaires aux autres ministères et agences fédéraux. La participation à
des initiatives pangouvernementales est souvent perçue par les fonctionnaires
comme une distraction de leur mandat institutionnel et un obstacle à une
promotion rapide (Patrick et Brown 2007, 141). Afin de surmonter ces
résistances institutionnelles, il serait nécessaire de mettre sur pied des
mécanismes qui joignent la participation à l’approche pangouvernementale
et l’avancement de carrière. Par exemple, la création de positions de liaison au
sein des ministères et agences pourraient jouer un rôle de socialisation et ainsi
aider les fonctionnaires à mieux comprendre les cultures organisationnelles
de leurs partenaires.

Entraînement conjoint
Dans la littérature, il est largement reconnu que l’entraînement conjoint est
l’un des meilleurs moyens pour améliorer la coordination civilo-militaire
(Das et Teng 1998 ; Duffey 2000 ; Jenny 2001 ; Patrick et Brown 2007 ; Leslie,
Gizewski et Rostek 2008 ; Thompson, Febbraro et Blais 2011). À ce titre, le
Canada a exigé que tous ses employés qui se déployaient à Kandahar, en
Afghanistan, participent aux activités prévues dans le programme de pré-
déploiement. Parmi ces activités, Maple Guardian était un exercice organisé
par les Forces canadiennes qui préparait les militaires et les fonctionnaires
10
gouvernementaux à l’environnement opérationnel de l’Afghanistan.11 Cet
entraînement a permis au personnel d’acquérir une meilleure compréhension
des mandats et des capacités de chaque ministère, avec lesquels ils
étaient généralement peu familiers, et de mieux saisir le rôle joué par leur
organisation dans le cadre de la stratégie canadienne en Afghanistan. À leur
retour de mission, certains membres, qui avaient participé à Maple Guardian,
ont affirmé que d’avoir rencontré leurs homologues avant leur déploiement
avait aidé à améliorer significativement la coordination interministérielle en
Afghanistan, particulièrement, lors de situations tendues.12
Depuis la fin de la mission de combat à Kandahar, il semble qu’il n’y ait
plus d’entraînement destiné expressément aux ministères et agences appelés
à travailler ensemble à l’étranger. L’opportunité unique d’apprentissage
qu’offre un entraînement conjoint ou une formation culturelle, devrait être
accessible non seulement au personnel s’apprêtant à être déployé, mais
également à ceux et celles qui travaillent dans les bureaux de direction à
Ottawa. En effet, il semble que les différends culturels soient encore plus
présents au niveau stratégique que sur le terrain (Jenny 2001, 27 ; Hill 2007,
3). De telles opportunités pourraient être bénéfiques, par exemple, au Groupe
de travail sur la stabilisation et la reconstruction ainsi qu’au Commandement
de la Force expéditionnaire du Canada. Ces mesures aideraient à créer des
liens de confiance entre les différentes organisations tout en les familiarisant
avec les perspectives issues d’autres cultures organisationnelles.

Conclusion
Jusqu’à présent, les débats sur les approches pangouvernementales
ont eu tendance à ne traiter que superficiellement de la dimension des
cultures organisationnelles. Cet article considère que, pour améliorer la
capacité opérationnelle de l’approche pangouvernementale, les processus
de réforme organisationnelle devront d’abord valoriser la spécificité de
chaque organisation pour ensuite instaurer progressivement un esprit de
collectivité auprès de ses nouveaux membres. Cette étude préconise la
culture organisationnelle comme angle d’analyse afin de mieux saisir, du
point de vue des organisations, les tensions qui peuvent survenir entre les
ministères et agences. L’application du concept d’habitus dans un contexte
pangouvernemental permet d’approfondir la compréhension des schèmes
culturels entre les différentes communautés, lesquelles interprètent la
mission qui leur est assignée à travers leur propre culture organisationnelle,
c’est-à-dire leur propre habitus. Le manque de familiarité entre les différentes
communautés peut inciter les individus à développer une attitude de
méfiance face aux autres groupes et à faire usage de stéréotypes négatifs. Ces
comportements ethnocentriques viennent d’un besoin de se sécuriser face à
l’inconnu.
Afin de mieux outiller le personnel appelé à travailler dans un
contexte pangouvernemental, une formation, davantage centrée sur la
culture, faciliterait une prise de conscience des participants vis-à-vis de leur
11
enculturation et de la façon dont cette dernière influence leurs interactions
interpersonnelles. Simultanément, une telle sensibilisation pourrait les aider
à développer des interactions plus efficaces, avec d’autres acteurs présents
dans l’environnement où se déroule la mission, notamment avec la population
locale, les organisations non gouvernementales et les médias. L’augmentation
des opportunités de socialisation, telles que la tenue d’entraînements
conjoints et les opportunités d’échange entre ministères et agences, représente
d’autres moyens reconnus pour améliorer la coordination civilo-militaire.
Ces initiatives aident à tisser des liens de confiance entre les différentes
organisations tout en les familiarisant avec les perspectives d’autres cultures
organisationnelles. Enfin, l’approche pangouvernementale est un nouveau
concept qui, si l’on y accorde dès maintenant suffisamment d’importance,
pourrait renforcer la qualité des interventions futures dans les situations de
crise et de reconstruction post-conflit.
12
Notes
1. Cette stratégie pangouvernementale a d’abord été présentée, par le
gouvernement libéral en 2005, sous son éponyme accrocheur de l’approche
3D. Elle faisait référence à l’étroite collaboration entre les éléments de défense,
de diplomatie et de développement. Lorsque le gouvernement conservateur
est entré au pouvoir l’année suivante, il a désormais utilisé l’appellation
« approche pangouvernementale. » Essentiellement, cette approche est plus
holistique ; elle se base sur l’esprit de l’approche 3D, mais intègre l’expertise
additionnelle des ministères et agences jugés les plus aptes pour répondre
à une situation donnée, par exemple la police, la justice, l’immigration,
l’agriculture, les services correctionnels.
2. Megan Thompson et Ritu Gill (2010, 5) ont identifié de nombreux obstacles
qui ont nuis à l’efficacité de la collaboration interministérielle. Cela inclut des
agendas politiques conflictuels, ou du moins des objectifs incompatibles ; des
disparités dans les structures organisationnelles (hiérarchiques et centralisés
vs horizontaux et décentralisés) ; des systèmes de gestion et de communication
inconciliables ; peu ou aucune mémoire corporative ; l’absence de mécanisme
pour retenir les leçons apprises ; un manque de financement et de personnel ;
et une compétition au niveau des ressources.
3. Stephen Brown (2008) affirme que la plus grande intégration des politiques
au Canada a eu pour effet de réduire l’autonomie de l’Agence canadienne
de développement international (ACDI). Entre 2001 et 2004, les enveloppes
budgétaires de l’ACDI ont augmenté de façon considérable, passant de 2,6
à 4,1 milliards. Toutefois, l’accroissement des budgets et la coordination
interministérielle ont créé un paradoxe : alors que les ressources augmentent
et que l’agence gagne en importance, la marge de manœuvre de l’ACDI
diminue. Cela peut s’expliquer par le fait que, sous le libellé de l’approche
pangouvernementale, le gouvernement canadien instrumentalise les
ressources de l’ACDI afin de promouvoir des intérêts de politique étrangère
non reliés au développement.
4. Sarah Hill (2007, 20), qui a réalisé une étude sur le processus de réforme
institutionnelle au sein du ministère de la Défense nationale, a observé
que l’ajout de nouvelles structures organisationnelles n’était pas garante de
changement dans la culture corporative. Les pratiques et les procédures,
adoptées par les membres de l’organisation, ont plus d’impact sur la culture
organisationnelle que les structures en elles-mêmes. Conséquemment, les
membres déjoueront les nouvelles structures organisationnelles qui ne sont
pas compatibles avec leurs pratiques et procédures institutionnelles. Cela
signifie que les structures à elles seules ne peuvent garantir l’atteinte des
objectifs poursuivis par les initiatives pangouvernementales (Christensen et
Laegrid 2006, 13).
5. Dans la littérature portant sur les alliances organisationnelles, le boundary
spanner a la responsabilité de s’assurer qu’un climat de confiance règne entre
les membres d’une approche pangouvernementale. Cette personne doit
être apte à communiquer efficacement, avoir une connaissance approfondie
13
des structures organisationnelles et une aptitude à la résolution de conflit
(Thompson et Gill 2010, 12). Lara Olson et Hrach Gregorian (2007) ont
constaté que dans les relations civilo-militaires, les boundary spanners
provenaient autant du personnel militaire, humanitaire que diplomatique.
Les habiletés de ces boundary spanners ont tendance à être particulièrement
cruciales au début de la coordination interministérielle, avant l’établissement
de structures organisationnelles plus formelles.
6. De façon générale, les références à la culture dans le corpus de littérature
portant sur le maintien de la paix se divisent en deux catégories. La première
inclut l’analyse des interactions entre les soldats de maintien de la paix et la
population locale (Duffey 2000 ; Jenny 2001 ; Kimmel 1998 ; Rubinstein 1989),
alors que la seconde porte sur la résolution de conflit (Black et Avruch 1998 ;
Cohen 2001 ; Woodrow et Moore 2002).
7. L’enculturation se définit comme un processus qui transmet à un individu
des représentations idéologiques (valeurs, connaissance, normes) et des
modèles de conduite pour fonctionner comme membre d’une culture (Rhum
1997, 149).
8. La culture organisationnelle peut aider à comprendre ce phénomène. Les
cultures organisationnelles des diplomates, des agents de développement
et des militaires sont bien distinctes les unes des autres. Conséquemment,
ces derniers risquent de partager davantage de référents culturels avec
leurs homologues internationaux – au niveau du langage, de leurs valeurs,
des règles d’usage employées et de leur compréhension du monde –
qu’avec leurs partenaires de même nationalité regroupés dans une stratégie
pangouvernementale. Par exemple, un diplomate canadien et un diplomate
japonais partageront davantage de référents culturels qu’un militaire et un
agent de développement du même pays.
9. La confiance est généralement définie comme le sentiment de pouvoir se
fier à quelqu’un en se basant sur la supposition que l’autre se comportera
d’une façon qui rencontre ou, du moins, ne trahit pas nos attentes (Thompson
et Gill 2010, 7). Dès qu’une organisation est suffisamment grande, il devient
impossible de contrôler chacune des activités qui ont lieu dans l’entreprise.
La confiance constitue alors un élément central à la coopération. Une fois que
la confiance est bien établie entre les partenaires, cela facilite leur capacité
d’effectuer des ajustements et d’acquérir une plus grande souplesse dans la
synchronisation de leurs tâches, lors de moments critiques (Krishnan, Martin
et Noorderhaven 2006, 896).
10. L’intelligence culturelle se définit comme la capacité de reconnaître les
croyances, les valeurs, les attitudes et les comportements qui sont communs à
un groupe et, surtout, la capacité subséquente d’appliquer ces connaissances
culturelles en vue d’atteindre un objectif précis (Spencer 2010, 15).
11. L’exercice militaire Maple Guardian a réuni une participation militaire
et civile à deux reprises : le premier exercice a eu lieu en juin 2009, à la
base de Wainwright en Alberta et le second, en février 2010, au Fort Irwin
en Californie. Ces exercices ont regroupé environ deux milles militaires et
soixante-dix fonctionnaires provenant du MAECI, de l’ACDI, du Service
14
correctionnel du Canada et des unités de police civile coordonnées par la
Gendarmerie royale du Canada.
12. Dans le cadre d’un projet avec la Direction des concepts et schémas de
la Force terrestre des Forces canadiennes, l’auteure a participé aux deux
exercices Maple Guardian en 2009 et 2010 comme observatrice de l’approche
pangouvernementale.

Remerciements
Une version antérieure de cet article a été présentée au Congrès annuel de
la Société québécoise en science politique de 2011, à l’Université du Québec
à Montréal. L’auteure tient à remercier le professeur Stéphane Roussel,
Philippe Beaulieu-Brossard ainsi que les évaluateurs anonymes pour leurs
commentaires judicieux sur les versions antérieures. L’auteure aimerait
également remercier la Paterson Review of International Affairs pour publier ce
premier article francophone dans leur revue.

Liste des références


Baumann, Andrea Barbara. 2008. « Clash of Organisational Cultures? The
Challenge of Integrating Civilian and Military Efforts in Stabilisation
Operations. » RUSI Journal 153, n° 6 : 70-73.
Bélanger, Laurent et Jean Mercier. 2006. Auteurs et textes classiques de la théorie
des organisations. St-Nicolas : Les Presses de l’Université Laval.
Bentley, Bill. 2010. « La théorie des systèmes, la pensée systémique et la
culture. » Dans L’intelligence culturelle et le leadership, sous la direction
de Karen D. Davis, 1-9. Kingston : Presse de l’Académie canadienne
de la Défense.
Black, Peter W. et Kevin Avruch. 1998. « Culture, Power and International
Negotiations: Understanding Palau – US Status Negotiations. » Dans
Culture in World Politics, sous la direction de Dominique Jacquin-
Berdal, Andrew Oros et Marco Verweij, 34-60. New York : St. Martin’s
Press.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 2000. Esquisse d’une théorie de la pratique, précédé de trois
études d’ethnologie kabyle. Paris : Seuil.
Brown, Stephen. 2008. « CIDA under the Gun. » Dans Canada among Nations
2007 : What Room for Manœuvre?, sous la direction de Jean Daudelin et
Daniel Schwanen, 91-107. Montreal : McGill-Queen’s University Press.
Canada. 2005. Fierté et influence : notre rôle dans le monde - survol ; Énoncé
de politique internationale du Canada. Ottawa : Ministère des affaires
étrangères et du commerce international.
———. 2007. Evaluation of CF/DND Participation in the Kandahar Provincial
Reconstruction Team. Ottawa : Department of National Defence.
Christensen, Tom et Per Laegreid. 2006. « The Whole-of-Government
Approach – Regulation, Performance, and Public-Sector Reform. »
Working Paper, n° 6, Stein Rokkan Centre for Social Studies, Bergen.
15
Cohen, Raymond. 2001. « Negotiating across Cultures. » Dans Turbulent
Peace: The Challenges of Managing International Conflict, sous la
direction de Chester A. Crocker, Fen Osler Hampson et Pamela Hall,
469-481. Washington, DC : United States Institutes of Peace Press.
Das, T.K. et Bing-Sheng Teng. 1998. « Between Trust and Control:
Developing Confidence in Partner Cooperation in Alliances. Academy
of Management Review 23, n° 3 : 491-512.
Dasen, Pierre R. 1993. « L’ethnocentrisme de la psychologie. » Dans
Psychologie clinique et interrogations culturelles, sous la direction de
Micheline Rey-Von Allmen, 155-174. Paris : L’Harmattan.
Davis, Karen D. 2010. « Les fondements culturels. » Dans L’intelligence
culturelle et le leadership, sous la direction de Karen D. Davis, 47-64.
Kingston : Presse de l’Académie canadienne de la Défense.
de Coning, Cedric et Karsten Friis. 2011. « Coherence and Coordination:
The Limits of the Comprehensive Approach. » Journal of International
Peacekeeping 15 : 243-272.
Duffey, Tamara. 2000. « Cultural Issues in Contemporary Peacekeeping. »
International Peacekeeping 7, n° 1 : 142-168.
Fetherston, A. B. et Carolyn Nordstrom. 1995. « Overcoming Habitus
in Conflict Management: UN Peacekeeping and War Zone
Ethnography. » Peace and Change 20, n° 1 : 94-119.
Flemming, Jeanne M. 2000. « Intégration horizontale. » Optimum 30, n° 2 :
29-40.
Friis, Karsten et Pia Jarmyr. 2008. Comprehensive Approach: Challenges
and Opportunities in Complex Crisis Management. Oslo : Norwegian
Institute of International Affairs.
Hill, Sarah A. 2007. « Corporate Culture in the CF and DND: Descriptive
Themes and Emergent Models. » DRDC CORA Technical Report
2007-19. Ottawa : Defence Research Development Canada.
Jenny, Joëlle. 2001. « Civil-Military Cooperation in Complex Emergencies:
Finding Ways to Make it Work. » European Security 10, n° 2 : 23-33.
Joint Task Force Afghanistan. 2009. « Preliminary Report: Application of the
Whole of Government (WoG) Approach: Afghanistan. » Kandahar
Airfield : Theater Lessons Learned Report 03/09.
Kimmel, Paul R. 1998. « Cultural and Ethnic Issues of Conflict and
Peacekeeping. » Dans The Psychology of Peacekeeping, sous la direction
de Harvey J. Langholtz, 57-71. London : Praeger.
Krishnan, Rekha, Xavier Martin et Niels G. Noorderhaven. 2006. « When
Does Trust Matter to Alliance Performance? » Academy of Management
Journal 49, n° 5 : 894-917.
Lane, Roger et Emma Sky. 2006. « The Role of Provincial Reconstruction
Teams in Stabilization. » RUSI Journal 151, n°3 : 46-51.
Leslie, Andrew, Peter Gizewski et Michael Rostek. 2008. « Developing a
Comprehensive Approach to Canadian Forces Operations. » Canadian
Military Journal 9, n° 1 : 11-20.
Minear, Larry et Thomas G. Weiss. 1993. Humanitarian Action in Times of War:
A Handbook for Practitioners. London: Lynne Rienner.
16
Mussweiler, Thomas et Galen V. Bodenhausen. 2002. « I Know What You
Are, but What Am I? Self-Evaluative Consequences of Judging In-
Group and Out-Group Members. » Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology 82, n° 1 : 19-32.
OECD (Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development). 2006.
« Whole of Government Approach to Fragile States. » Paris : OECD
Development Assistance Committee.
Olson, Lara et Hrach Gregorian. 2007. Side by Side or Together? Working for
Security, Development and Peace in Afghanistan and Liberia. University of
Calgary : Peacebuilding, Development and Security Program.
Patrick, Stewart et Kaysie Brown. 2007. Greater than the Sum of Its Parts?
Assessing “Whole of Government” Approaches to Fragile States. New York
: International Peace Academy.
Preiswerk, Roy et Dominique Perrot. 1975. Ethnocentrisme et Histoire :
L’Afrique, l’Amérique indienne et l’Asie dans les manuels occidentaux.
Paris : Anthropos.
Rhum, Michael. 1997. « Enculturation. » Dans The Dictionary of Anthropology,
sous la direction de Thomas Barfield, 149. Oxford : Blackwell.
Rintakoski, Kristiina et Miko Autti. 2008. « Seminar Publication on
Comprehensive Approach: Trends, Challenges and Possibilities for
Cooperation in Crisis Prevention and Management. » Helsinki : Crisis
Management Initiative.
Rubinstein, Robert A. 1989. « Culture, International Affairs, and Multilateral
Peacekeeping: Confusing Process and Pattern. » Cultural Dynamics 2,
n° 1 : 41-61.
———. 1993. Cultural Aspects of Peacekeeping : Notes on the Substance of
Symbols. Millenium: Journal of International Studies 22, n° 3 : 547-562.
Schein, Edgar H. 1991. « Plaidoyer pour une conscience renouvelée de ce
qu’est la culture organisationnelle. » Dans Changement planifié et
développement des organisations : Pouvoirs et cultures organisationnels,
sous la direction de Roger Tessier et Yvan Tellier, 175-196. Québec :
Presses de l’Université du Québec.
Smith, Amanda. 2007. « Strategic Communication : Interagency
Rhetoric and Consistent Interpretation. » Dans The Interagency
and Counterinsurgency Warfare: Stability, Security, Transition and
Reconstruction Roles, sous la direction de Joseph Cerami et Jay W.
Boggs, 337-386. Charleston : CreateSpace.
Spencer, Emily. 2010. « De la cervelle et du muscle : L’intelligence culturelle
ou l’outil par excellence dans l’environnement opérationnel
contemporain. » Revue militaire canadienne 11, n° 1 : 15-23.
Sumner, William Graham. 1906. Folkways. Boston : Ginn & Company.
Tamas, Andy. 2009. Warriors and Nation Builders: Development and the Military
in Afghanistan. Kingston : Canadian Defence Academy Press.
Thompson, Megan, Angela Febbraro et Anne-Renée Blais. 2011.
« Interagency Training for the Canadian Comprehensive Approach in
Afghanistan. » Dans Security Operations in the 21st Century: Canadian
17
Perspectives on the Comprehensive Approach, sous la direction de Michael
Rostek et Peter Gizewski, 203-213. Montréal et Kingston : McGill-
Queen’s University Press.
Thompson, Megan M. et Ritu Gill. 2010. « The Role of Trust in Whole of
Government Missions. » Dans Mission Critical: Smaller Democracies’
Role in Global Stability Operations, sous la direction de Christian
Leuprecht, Jodok Troy et David Last, 3-22. Montréal et Kingston :
McGill-Queens University Press.
Van der Kloet, Irene. 2006. « Building Trust in the Mission Area: A Weapon
against Terrorism? » Small Wars and Insurgencies 17, n° 4 : 421-436.
Vulpe, Thomas, Daniel Kealey, David Protheroe et Doug Macdonald.
2001. Profil de la personne efficace sur le plan culturel. Ottawa : Centre
d’apprentissage interculturel de l’Institut canadien du service
extérieur.
Woodrow, Peter et Christopher Moore. 2002. « Mapping Cultures: Strategies
for Effective Intercultural Conflict Resolution. » Dans Second Track /
Citizens’ Diplomacy: Concepts and Techniques for Conflict Transformation,
sous la direction de John Davies et Edward Kaufman, 149-160.
Lanham : Rowman & Littlefield.
19
Paterson Review of International Affairs (2012) 12: 19–34.

Durability in Darfur? Assessing the Darfur


Peace Agreement
Justin Mohammed
Norman Paterson School of International Affairs, Carleton University

The underlying factors that produce durable peace agreements have,


for some time, remained elusive. Scholars have conducted both case and
empirical studies in attempting to better understand the determinants of
peace agreement durability, but results have been largely inconclusive.
This article surveys the literature concerning the durability of peace
agreements and presents three distinct hypotheses: peace agreements
are epiphenomenal, successful peace agreements depend on activities
of external actors, and successful peace agreements depend on their
content. The article applies these three hypotheses to the Darfur
Peace Agreement, concluding that this case represents a failed peace
agreement. The failure of the Darfur Peace Agreement is best explained
by a lack of international/regional support. In response, this article
advocates for the creation of an index to help practitioners prioritize the
variables that are most likely to result in durable peace. To achieve this
goal, future research is needed to determine why certain mechanisms
are more successful than others. In particular, it would be helpful to
have a better understanding of what confluence of variables will provide
the highest probability of success in a given context.

Introduction
Given the recent history of civil wars, the trend toward negotiated settlements,
as opposed to decisive victories, is becoming clear. Between 2000 and 2005,
the number of conflicts ended by a negotiated peace outnumbered those
ended by military victory by a factor of four to one (Sisk 2008, 195). The
trend toward this ratio began in the 1990s, when 41 conflicts were settled
by negotiation compared to 23 ending in outright military victory (Harbom,
Hogbladh, and Wallensteen 2006, 618). Prima facie, this trend suggests that
conflict management practitioners are utilizing more effective strategies for
settling conflicts. However, among the myriad of approaches that have been
undertaken, it remains unclear which work best, and why.
Peace settlements are not all equally effective. While some have resulted
in a permanent cessation of hostilities, others have fallen apart within months.
Why is this the case? The academic literature on this question is decidedly
unclear. Some scholars have argued that the contents of peace agreements
20
are a crucial determinant of the durability of any given agreement. Others
have argued that the success of an agreement depends upon the timing of
the settlement. Still others have suggested that the strongest predictor of a
successful peace agreement is the degree to which one party to the conflict has
been effectively eliminated; the more decisive the victory, the more durable
the peace. The primary objective of this article is to test these hypotheses
using the 2006 Darfur Peace Agreement (DPA) as a case study.1
There are a number of reasons for which the DPA has been selected for
this case study. First, the DPA represents one of the international community’s
most recent attempts to secure a peace agreement. As such, it provides a
contemporary example of a peace agreement in which the details and text
of the agreement are readily available. Second, because this agreement was
signed in 2006, an appropriate observation period has lapsed. Thus, the degree
of success attained by this particular agreement can be properly assessed.
Finally, as an ongoing, contemporary, and failed agreement, the DPA is one
of the few cases that present an opportunity to provide timely reflection and
advice, so as to deliver present-day impact.
By understanding the determinants of a successful agreement, conflict
management practitioners can focus on the elements that are most likely to
result in durable peace, and thus be better able to tailor their approaches to
conflict management. In the absence of such knowledge, practitioners will
be left with the dismal prospect of simply applying whatever techniques are
available and hoping for a positive result. In an era that ostensibly supports
the primacy of evidence-based decision making, such an approach is rightfully
viewed as unacceptable. This article attempts to bridge the academic/policy
gap, identified by scholars such as Joseph Nye (2008, 650–51), by providing
the type of systematic analysis that is often unavailable in policy circles.
The above observations inspire the research question: what explains
the outcome of the DPA? The first section of this article reviews some of the
contending explanations concerning the durability of peace agreements.
This literature review yields three hypotheses that will be tested: (1) peace
agreements are epiphenomenal; (2) successful peace agreements depend
on external actors; and (3) successful peace agreements depend on their
content. The article’s second section evaluates the DPA, arguing that it is
a failed peace agreement. The third section seeks to determine whether or
not any of the hypotheses from the academic literature can account for this
failure. Little support is found for the first hypothesis, but strong support is
found for the second, and mixed support is found for the third. The article’s
final section offers policy recommendations and suggests areas for future
research. Ultimately, this article advocates for the creation of an index to help
practitioners prioritize the factors that are most likely to result in durable
peace, necessitating future research on why certain mechanisms are more
successful than others.
21
Literature Review and Hypotheses
The purpose of the following literature review is to outline three main
explanatory categories that will eventually be tested with regard to the DPA.
It should be noted that the hypotheses outlined below are not mutually
exclusive; some overlap between them is possible.2 While a presentation of
mutually exclusive hypotheses is easier to evaluate, it should be noted that
such an arrangement does not accurately represent the interrelatedness of the
explanatory categories, nor would it reflect the reality that durable peace is
often achieved through a combination of factors. The categories only provide
a general framework to logically test the hypotheses.

Hypothesis I: Peace agreements are epiphenomenal

The first hypothesis argues that peace settlements are irrelevant to the
durability of peace. This hypothesis stems from the realist theory of
international relations, which broadly posits that actions taken within the
international system are best explained by the national interests of individual
states in the context of anarchy. Realists argue that peace agreements have
no intrinsic value. This assertion analogizes the argument made by John
Mearsheimer (1994) that international institutions are epiphenomenal.
Accordingly, peace agreements are merely “scraps of paper” which are not
binding in the system of international anarchy and will not influence the
behaviour of parties to a conflict (Fortna 2003, 338). Realists consequently
argue that the only reason parties sign peace agreements is to further their
self-interests. For example, a signatory may want to create illusions of
goodwill, create a tactical opportunity to remobilize, or may fear potential
sanctions from the international community. As realism is one of the dominant
theories of international relations, the realist notion that peace agreements are
epiphenomenal is an important hypothesis to examine.
Other scholars have demonstrated the epiphenomenal nature of
peace agreements through analyses of conflicts’ contextual variability. One
variable concerns the notion of timing, or what William Zartman (2008, 22)
calls “ripeness,” whereby peace is unlikely to be durable in the absence
of a “mutually hurting stalemate.” According to Zartman (ibid.), this
phenomenon arises when “parties find themselves locked in a conflict from
which they cannot escalate to victory and this deadlock is painful to both of
them (although not necessarily in equal degree or for the same reasons).”
Another approach emphasizes the nature of the dispute. For example,
Paul Collier and Ank Hoeffler (2002) have sought to determine whether
conflict is motivated by “greed” (material resources) or “grievance” (ethnic,
religious, cultural divisions). Although their research is not concerned with
the durability of peace agreements, the logic of their argument suggests that
peace agreements would be irrelevant when greed and/or grievance underlie
a dispute. These specifications provide more nuanced explanations as to why
peace agreements may be epiphenomenal to a durable settlement.
In sum, this explanatory category holds that the durability of peace
22
settlements depends on the relative position and abilities of the belligerents.
Positions and abilities include factors such as military strength, access to
resources, and the influence of domestic stakeholders or constituency groups.
Common to this explanatory category is that prospects for peace depend
inherently and entirely upon the positions of the parties and the motivating
factors behind the conflict.

Hypothesis II: Successful peace agreements depend on outside actors

The second hypothesis posits that the durability of an agreement is


determined by the involvement of external actors. Fen Hampson (1996, 19)
argues that conflicts generally are part of a larger “regional security complex.”
According to this hypothesis, peace agreements will be most successful when
a combination of international and regional actors are engaged in a concerted
strategy to terminate the conflict (ibid., 206–17). Engagement may include,
but is not limited to: opening diplomatic channels, hosting peace talks, or
threatening the use of force in order to bring an end to hostilities. The absence
of such commitments, regardless of the terms of agreement, risks a high rate of
failure. This is an important hypothesis to investigate because if it holds true,
then a tangible policy recommendation flows naturally: parties interested in
peace should seek regional and international support.
A concept related to external engagement is the presence or absence
of third-party guarantees. Barbara Walter (2002, 26–27) suggests that durable
peace is most closely associated with the inclusion of a third-party guarantor.
She argues that combatants will only sign a peace accord in the presence of
credible commitments from international actors that ensure their safety and
that guarantee them a role in the new post-conflict power structure. Therefore,
the durability of an agreement depends on the demonstrable willingness of
third parties to act as guarantors of the peace agreement. Although there is
growing consensus among scholars that third-party guarantees are necessary
for durable peace, problems of political will and capacity continue to inhibit
the degree to which the requisite commitments can be achieved (Hartzell and
Hoddie 2007, 88–91).
Other forms of third-party engagement, while helpful, are contingent
upon different factors. For example, Michael Doyle and Nicholas Sambanis
(2000) find that pure enforcement operations can end violence, but cannot
promote longstanding peace. Virginia Fortna (2004, 189–93) notes that
the success of peacekeeping operations depends on the timing of force
deployment and the level of violence existing at the time. Although some
academics have found that ongoing third-party mediation is an ineffective
tool (ibid., 195), others have suggested that it is a crucial form of post-conflict
dispute resolution (Hampson 1996, 227–29). In support of the latter view,
scholars have pointed out that while haphazard third-party mediation may
undermine a peace settlement, if done properly, it can actually help identify
alternatives, modify perspectives, package and sequence issues, and generally
build trust between belligerents (ibid., 12–13). Therefore, any conclusion with
23
respect to third-party interventions and durable peace must be tempered with
the knowledge that exogenous factors may also contribute to the ultimate
success or failure of a peace agreement.

Hypothesis III: Successful peace agreements depend on their content

The content of agreements is perhaps the most highly malleable factor


determining the durability or fragility of peace agreements. Fortna (2004,
113), who is a central proponent of this hypothesis, argues that the content of
peace and ceasefire agreements directly affects the durability of the ensuing
peace. This argument is largely constructed in opposition to the arguments
made in support of the first hypothesis.
Fortna’s argument revolves around two main assertions. First, she
states that the baseline prospects for peace, referring to those pre-existing
conditions that characterize the conflict, either have little predictive value
in determining whether peace will ensue or actually make peace less likely.
Second, the mechanisms incorporated into a peace agreement can help
predict whether or not a given agreement will succeed (ibid., 172). She uses
large-N statistical methods to support her assertions and controls for baseline
prospects to improve the validity of her conclusions. Her work represents
one of the only attempts to quantitatively test hypotheses about the effect of
peace accord provisions on the cessation of hostilities. Regarding agreement
content, Fortna (2003, 342–44) finds that agreements can help ensure peace
in three principal ways: changing incentives, reducing uncertainty about the
actions and intentions of belligerents, and controlling accidental violations.
From her statistical analysis, Fortna finds that internal control over
rogue groups and arms control measures have no effect on supporting a
lasting peace. She also finds that the withdrawal of forces to ceasefire lines
is generally unlikely to contribute to durable peace (ibid., 357). In contrast,
there is significant evidence to suggest that the establishment of demilitarized
zones and joint commissions with representatives from each side are effective
measures in ensuring peace (Fortna 2004, 179; Fortna 2003, 362). Lastly, Fortna
(2003, 362) finds that the more specific and formal the agreement, the more
likely it is to succeed.
Other scholars have found further reasons for which the contents of peace
agreements matter. Arend Lijphart (1991, 494), for example, has emphasized
the importance of power-sharing provisions. It has been argued, however,
that such arrangements can only endorse peace in the short term (Sisk 2008,
196). Other hypotheses concerning the content of peace agreements have been
derived from Hampson’s (1996, 218–20) case study of five conflict settlements.
His research reveals that agreements generally require the support of all parties
to the conflict, as those who do not have their interests met will have a high
incentive to defect. Moreover, he finds that there must be a place for both
“winners” and “losers” in any power-sharing agreement. Finally, he notes that
peace agreements must be sufficiently flexible to permit some renegotiation
during the implementation phase, because inflexibility can lead to breaches and
24
outright failure. Arguments about flexibility and robustness have been affirmed
by Suzanne Werner and Amy Yuen (2005, 288–89), who find that the terms of
a settlement must be flexible enough to accommodate changing realities, or
must make the cost of returning to war high enough to dissuade parties from
defecting. Therefore, any conclusions about the connection between the content
of peace agreements and durable peace must recognize that content analysis
must include both mechanisms (i.e., peacekeeping forces and demilitarized
zones) and principles (i.e., inclusivity and rigidity).

Concluding remarks on the literature

The above discussion illustrates that the literature’s hypotheses can be put
into three distinct categories. The first hypothesis suggests that the durability
of peace depends entirely upon the situations of the parties to a conflict. By
contrast, the second hypothesis suggests that the involvement of regional and
international actors can best predict the durability of a negotiated settlement.
Finally, the third hypothesis suggests that the nature and mechanisms
within the peace agreement itself are the most important factors in ensuring
a sustainable peace. As illustrated above, there are a variety of nuanced
arguments in support of the three general hypotheses, all of which should be
taken into account when conducting a case analysis.
The following section seeks to apply the hypotheses derived from the
academic literature to the case of the DPA. The analysis proceeds in three
parts. First, the content of the DPA and the context in which it was signed
will be presented. Second, it will be argued that the DPA is an example of an
unsuccessful settlement because it failed to satisfy two conditions: the parties
did not abide to the terms of the agreement and cessation of hostilities was
not sustained. Lastly, the three hypotheses will be applied to the case study to
assess their persuasiveness in explaining why the DPA failed.

Case Study: Sudan and the Darfur Peace Agreement


The Darfur Peace Agreement

Conflict in Darfur, Sudan, dates back to the post-independence era, when


Darfuris fought on the side of the Government of Sudan during the first
North-South war, and includes the Arab-Fur war of 1987, when drought
caused clashes over fertile lands. It has been marked by neglect, be it by former
colonial powers or the central government in Khartoum. When the National
Islamic Front came to power in 1989, it operationalized its Arab supremacist
ideology in Darfur by treating it “as if it were an appendage of pagan Africa
. . . [resulting in the] rejection of old traditions of coexistence and the bonds
of Islam” (Daly 2007, 260). In the late 1990s, the Janjaweed was created as a
coalition of Arab militias, which conducted numerous attacks against the non-
Arab Zaghawa and Masalit peoples of Darfur with impunity (ibid., 262–69).
Protest by these non-Arab groups was ignored by the Government of Sudan,
25
which was complicit in their persecution, and eventually led to the unification
of these groups in military opposition to their persecutors.
In February 2003, the Sudan Liberation Movement/Army (SLM/A) and
the Justice and Equality Movement (JEM) rebel groups launched a successful
attack on Jebel Marra province in Darfur (Toga 2007, 214). The groups
demanded that the Government of Sudan end its policy of oppression and
genocide against the black African population of Darfur and halt the activities
of the Janjaweed militia (ibid.). Initially, fighting occurred primarily between
the Darfur rebel groups and the Sudanese Armed Forces supported by their
Janjaweed proxy force. Eventually the latter shifted their tactics to target
civilians, in what became a well-documented division of labour: the Sudanese
Armed Forces would conduct aerial attacks on villages with helicopter
gunships and the Janjaweed would follow up to rape, pillage, and execute
the survivors (ibid., 183). Hundreds of thousands have lost their lives as a
result of the fighting, and between two and three million people have been
displaced both within Darfur and across the border in neighbouring Chad.3
On 5 May 2006, the DPA was signed by Majzoub al-Khalifa, advisor to
Sudanese President Omar al-Bashir, and by Minni Minnawi, chairperson of
one of the SLM/A’s factions (ibid., 242). Despite being parties to the negotiation,
the JEM and the SLM/A’s other faction rejected the DPA (Daly 2007, 310).4
The agreement was achieved following seven rounds of peace negotiations,
known as the Abuja Talks, chaired by the African Union (ibid., 302). The
document contains the following six chapters: (1) Power Sharing; (2) Wealth
Sharing; (3) Comprehensive Ceasefire and Final Security Arrangements; (4)
Darfur-Darfur Dialogue and Consultations; (5) General Provisions; and (6)
Implementation Modalities and Timelines.

A failed settlement

Evaluation of peace agreement success is a contentious matter for scholars of


conflict management. Some consider the fact that any peace agreement was
signed at all, despite the rejection of the agreement’s content by two parties,
constitutes a success. However, a more rigorous test for the durability of
peace settlements requires, at minimum, that two obvious conditions be met.
First, a successful peace agreement is one where the signatories abide by the
terms of the agreement. Second, a successful agreement is one that results
in the cessation of violence between the parties.5 If these conditions are not
achieved, a peace settlement cannot be qualified as successful because it will
have failed to achieve both peace and agreement.
According to the criteria outlined above, the DPA clearly constitutes
a failed settlement. First, signatories to the agreement have not abided by
its provisions. The DPA required the Government of Sudan to completely
disarm the Janjaweed within 159 days of signing the agreement. It also
stipulated that the Government of Sudan would establish a US$300 million
Darfur Reconstruction and Development Fund (DRDF) available to the
authorities in Darfur, along with an additional US$200 million each year
for two years after ratification. Furthermore, the DPA called for increased
26
patrolling and protection of internally displaced persons (IDP) camps by the
African Union Mission in Sudan (AMIS). Unfortunately, the parties involved
have not abided by these terms. The International Crisis Group reported in
2007 that the Janjaweed had not been disarmed, that DRDF funding had not
been allocated, and that the AMIS was unable to fulfill its obligations under
the DPA due to a lack of capacity and resources (ICG 2007, 22).
The level of violence in Darfur since the signing of the DPA is also
indicative of the agreement’s failure. Some have argued that the agreement
has actually heightened conflict (Nathan 2007, 266); since May 2006, over half
a million people have been displaced (ICG 2007, 6), and in September 2006,
the Government of Sudan launched major offensives in Darfur, including
bombing villages and terrorizing IDP camps (Nathan 2007, 246). The violence
is not one-sided. Despite having signed the DPA, the SLM/A faction headed
by Minnawi has been accused of carrying out many attacks (ICG 2007, 11).
Violence continues to the present: in May 2010 alone, over 600 people were
killed as a result of conflict in Darfur (BBC 2010a). Thus, it is clear that the
DPA has failed to achieve a durable peace.

Explaining failure

Having established that the DPA represents a failed peace agreement, it is


possible to critically assess to what extent the hypotheses discussed above are
able to explain this outcome.

Hypothesis I

The first hypothesis argues that peace agreements have no impact on the
durability of peace. The failure of the DPA would appear to provide a high
degree of support for this hypothesis. Since the agreement failed, it would
seem logical to conclude that it was futile and meaningless. However, in order
to accept Zartman’s ripeness argument, the absence of a mutually hurting
stalemate should be conclusively proven. If a mutually hurting stalemate
were present, the hypothesis would lead to the conclusion that peace should
be durable.
Some scholars have suggested that the situation in Darfur was ripe
for resolution between 2005 and 2006 (Brooks 2008, 415). In other words, the
parties to the conflict were, and remain, in a mutually hurting stalemate. For
the Government of Sudan, the chief pressure came from the international
community. After successfully concluding the 2005 Comprehensive Peace
Agreement that ended the decades-long civil war between northern and
southern Sudan, the Government of Sudan faced significant pressure from
the international community to focus its attention on resolving the conflict
in Darfur (ibid.). Moreover, the Government of Sudan was vulnerable to
the pressures of domestic politics. Upcoming national elections meant that
the ruling National Congress Party needed to demonstrate to Darfuris that
their concerns were being taken seriously (ibid., 422). The government was
also concerned with the decision by the United Nations Security Council
27
(UNSC) to refer the situation in Darfur to the International Criminal Court
(ICC) (UN 2005). In July 2008, the ICC’s chief prosecutor brought charges
against al-Bashir for war crimes, crimes against humanity, and genocide and
a subsequent arrest warrant was issued in July 2010.6
The rebel groups were also hurting from the stalemate. Despite
fighting a common enemy, they had been divided among one another, and
groups themselves had been prone to splintering and factionalism. This lack
of solidarity was due to competition for power and leadership, and suspicion
that the government was making separate deals with individual leaders.
The divide between the SLM/A and the JEM and the split of the SLM/A into
two factions supports the observation that the position of the rebels was
weakening. Despite their unified position early in the rebellion, patterns
of violent clashes between the SLM/A and JEM continued until the signing
of the DPA (Flint 2007, 159). Animosity was based, in part, on ideological
divides between the secular SLM/A and the Islamist JEM, resulting in a
weak tactical alliance. It has been observed that the SLM/A “was never more
than a loose alliance between its two main tribal components,” with Abdul
Wahid al-Nur representing the Fur tribe and Minnawi representing the
Zaghawa tribe (ibid., 152). Lastly, rebel leaders have also been indicted by
the ICC, including former JEM commander-in-chief Abdallah Banda Abakaer
Nourain (ICC 2011). Therefore, while the DPA provides support for the first
hypothesis, the ripeness argument does not provide a complete explanation
as to why the peace settlement failed. If the first hypothesis were correct, the
hurting stalemate between the Government of Sudan and the rebels should
have resulted in peace, but it clearly did not.
As mentioned above, one modification of the first hypothesis
emphasizes the nature of the dispute, suggesting that peace agreements are
epiphenomenal to the durability of peace agreements when hostilities are
based on greed or grievance. Both greed and grievance underlie the conflict
in Darfur. Similar to what was observed above, if the first hypothesis were
correct, then peace in Darfur should not be achieved. Although this is indeed
the outcome that was observed, the logic of the hypothesis may not be
applicable in the case of the DPA because the agreement itself attempted to
resolve financial and social inequalities. As such, the lack of durable peace
might be attributed to dissatisfaction with the agreement itself rather than a
proclivity for hostilities between the parties based on greed or grievance. This
would lend support to the third hypothesis, rather than the first.

Hypothesis II

The second hypothesis predicts that successful agreements involve


commitments from regional and international actors. The failure of the DPA
provides strong support for this hypothesis, not only because it supports
the notion that peace agreements require a guarantor, but also that negative
influences from regional and international actors may contribute to the
erosion of peace settlements.
The conflict in Darfur must be analyzed as part of a broader regional
28
security complex that is closely tied to the situation in Chad. Chad and Sudan
have long been uneasy neighbours, with each country accusing the other
of supporting and harbouring rebel groups in their respective territories.
Khartoum is accused of supporting the United Front for Democratic Change
rebels in Chad, while N’Djamena is accused of supporting the JEM and the
SLM/A in Sudan. Chad allegedly supports these movements in exchange for
support in fighting the Chadian rebel groups that are seeking to overthrow the
government (Hanson 2007). Although the hypothesis holds that peace is most
durable when regional stakeholders are actively engaged in a concerted effort
to terminate the conflict, the reverse also applies. Chad’s support of both the
JEM and the SLM/A lends credibility to the argument that the DPA’s failure can
be attributed to destabilizing regional influences (Heavens 2009).7 Chad and
Sudan have indicated that they will seek to normalize relations, but no concrete
steps have been taken to reduce the power of proxy militias operating out of
each country (BBC 2010b). Therefore, at best Chad has been indifferent to the
peace process in Darfur; at worst, it has been actively undermining it.
The failure of the DPA also lends support to the hypothesis that peace
agreements are most durable when the international community credibly
commits to enforce their terms. In the case of the DPA, such commitments are
noticeably missing. While then U.S. deputy secretary of state Robert Zoellick
was present at the negotiations, the most credible support provided by the
United States was a letter from then president George W. Bush claiming
that any party breaking the agreement would be “held accountable” by the
UNSC (Kessler 2006). This commitment, if it can be characterized as one, is
not only ambiguous but incredible. The United States could not guarantee
enforcement because it could not be sure that other permanent members of
the UNSC would not veto any attempt to punish violations. Similarly, the
African Union, which played a prominent role in negotiations, did not meet
its commitments to provide AMIS with adequate resources. Finally, although
Canada, Egypt, Eritrea, France, Libya, the Netherlands, Norway, and the
United Kingdom were involved in the negotiations at some stage (Daly
2007, 303), the extent to which these actors were willing to underwrite the
agreement is unclear. The lack of support from the international community
is also reflected in the joint United Nations-African Union Mission in Darfur
(UNAMID), which was reported to be lacking key capacities in 2007 (UN
News Service 2007). Despite receiving five Mi-35P helicopters from Ethiopia,
by February 2010 UNAMID still lacked 18 utility helicopters that it required
to fully operationalize its mandate (UNAMID 2010). The absence of concrete
commitments from both regional and international actors could fully explain
why the JEM and part of the SLM/A refused to sign the DPA, and why the
signatories were not committed to abiding by its terms.

Hypothesis III

The final hypothesis states that the content of the agreements themselves
has a significant impact on the durability of peace. The failure of the DPA
provides mixed support for this hypothesis. Notably, the agreement did not
29
contain the demarcation of demilitarized zones, which Fortna found to be an
important mechanism for increasing the durability of peace. According to the
agreement, the production of a final map establishing demilitarized zones,
and the physical demarcation of these zones, was not to begin until 37 days
after the agreement was signed. Parties were not expected to withdraw from
these zones for between 47 and 82 days after the conclusion of the agreement.
By not prioritizing a demilitarized zone within the agreement, the parties
failed to include an element that could have significantly improved prospects
for durable peace.
Other mechanisms that have been found to improve prospects for
peace are present in the agreement, but did not result in durable peace. The
DPA established a joint commission with representatives from both sides, a
measure that the academic literature suggests should improve peace prospects
(Hampson 1996). The DPA Joint Commission, mandated to examine disputes
concerning the interpretation of the agreement, has met regularly and has
been active in investigating violations. Twelve investigations were conducted
between October 2006 and January 2007 (OAU 2007), although admittedly the
parties have been recalcitrant in taking responsibility for alleged violations.
Another predictor of durable peace agreements is their level of formality.
The DPA bears all the hallmarks of a formal agreement: it was signed by the
leaders of two key parties, resulted from multiple rounds of negotiations
involving extensive preparations, and was supervised and witnessed by
prominent members of the international community (Daly 2007, 302). These
factors predict that peace should be durable.
The DPA also provides mixed support for other elements discussed
under the third hypothesis. Since it was not signed by the JEM and one faction
of the SLM/A, the agreement did not have support from all parties to the
conflict. This is a highly plausible explanation for its failure. At the same time,
many other mechanisms that increase peace prospects were incorporated into
the DPA. For example, the agreement envisioned an elaborate mechanism
for power-sharing. The agreement’s first chapter specifically recognizes the
importance of power-sharing as “vital for national unity” and envisions
devolution of power from the Government of Sudan to a Transitional
Darfur Regional Authority (TDRA). It stipulated that the chairperson of the
TDRA would receive the fourth highest position within the government, a
position that was granted to Minnawi (Hottinger 2006). The agreement also
appears flexible: the creation of the Joint Commission indicates a pragmatic
recognition that some violations might occur accidentally (Daly 2007, 312). By
granting this body investigative and reporting functions, accidental violations
would less likely result in repudiation. The settlement was also flexible in
that it provided for ad hoc arrangements that allow non-signatories to submit
declarations of commitment to its principles and hence is not restricted to
signatories alone (ibid., 306).
30
Conclusion
This article has sought to explore some of the leading hypotheses about the
determinants of peace settlement durability. To this end, it has examined the
case of one demonstrably failed peace agreement, the DPA, and attempted
to evaluate three hypotheses explaining its failure. Although the scope
of this article could only consider the single case of the DPA, it should be
recognized that the context in which this agreement was signed is based
upon an ongoing, longer history of conflict that involves not only Darfur,
but other regions of Sudan as well. The analysis demonstrates that while
the first hypothesis might partially explain the failure of the DPA, its logic
must be further refined. Since this article argued that the situation in Darfur
constituted a mutually hurting stalemate, according to the ripeness argument,
the DPA should have been a case in which peace was durable. The failure of
the DPA does not, in and of itself, invalidate the ripeness argument. It does,
however, suggest that a mutually hurting stalemate is a necessary, but not
necessarily sufficient, condition for durable peace. In other words, a mutually
hurting stalemate enticed the parties to enter negotiations, but was not
sufficient to promote lasting peace. If this assessment is correct, then scholars
and practitioners can and should accept that peace agreements are not
automatically epiphenomenal. Efforts to secure peace settlements would only
be in vain when one party has the ability and incentive to continue escalation.
Furthermore, the greed and grievance hypothesis could not be adequately
assessed because the agreement itself sought to address these problems
in the context of Darfur. Further research could be conducted on ceasefire
agreements that do not seek to address social and economic inequalities in
order to properly assess the logic of this hypothesis.
With respect to the second hypothesis, the DPA confirms the importance
of external actors in achieving durable peace. The (in)action of regional and
international stakeholders involved in the Darfur conflict—Chad has caused
negative interference and the United States has failed to offer credible
commitments—provides a persuasive explanation for the settlement’s failure.
This finding has important implications for conflict management practitioners.
It suggests that while attention should be focused on resolving the dispute
between parties to the conflict, equal attention should be spent on securing
credible commitments from the international community and ensuring that
regional influences are supportive of peace efforts. Scholars should further
investigate the concept of a regional security complex and explore the ways
in which a supportive regional security complex can be fostered during and
after peace negotiations.
Finally, there is mixed support for the third hypothesis. By not
providing for the immediate use of demilitarized zones, the parties failed
to include an element that has been found to improve prospects for durable
peace. The utility of demilitarized zones could not be evaluated in the DPA
case study because the agreement’s provisions on this issue did not come into
force at the time the agreement was signed. Although the Joint Commission has
31
highlighted violations of the settlement, it has not been able to solicit general
compliance. A power-sharing mechanism, despite being clearly articulated in
the agreement, has failed to pacify the parties. However, the explanation that
the DPA failed because some of the participants in the conflict did not sign the
agreement appears to be the most relevant. Overall, while many factors might
support a durable agreement, failure to meaningfully consult all participants
in a conflict presents a serious risk to any agreement.
Additional research on the third hypothesis should be conducted
in order to better explain why certain mechanisms, such as demilitarized
zones and joint commissions, are more successful than others. As such,
process-tracing methodology should be used to determine the causal
sequence between a given mechanism and a peaceful outcome. Scholars and
practitioners need to know specifically how and why a mechanism influences
signatories to a peace agreement. The development of a rigorous evidence
base will help practitioners justify their selection of mechanisms in conflict
settlement. This evidence base can be created through the compilation of a
rank-ordered index of measures to indicate the most effective mechanisms
contributing to a successful agreement. Such indicators could ostensibly help
practitioners secure agreement on measures that would most likely result in
a durable settlement, especially in time- or resource-constrained situations.
Scholars could also use the index to judge peace prospects in a given situation
following a negotiated settlement.
An important caveat should be observed: the creation of an index
cannot supplant the value of context-specific research. Conflict origins and
motivations are significantly different across cases. As such, formal tools
like indexes are inferior to a context-specific approach to conflict resolution.
Nevertheless, in situations where information about the conflict is unavailable
or resources are limited, a list of conflict management measures ranked
according to their historic track record may prove to be a useful tool for
practitioners.
Although the scope of this article is limited to the case of the DPA, it
should be recognized that the context in which this agreement was signed is
based upon an environment that involves not only Darfur, but other regions
of Sudan as well. Thus, future research could analyze other peace agreements
that have been part of Sudan’s history, such as the 2005 Comprehensive Peace
Agreement between the North and South (which resulted in the independence
of South Sudan in 2011), the 2007 Eastern Sudan Peace Agreement, or the
peace agreement signed between the Government of Sudan and the Liberation
and Justice Movement, another rebel group operating out of Darfur, in July
2011. This article’s methodology could easily be replicated for any of these
agreements and has the potential to provide greater insight into the durability
of peace agreements in the Sudanese context.
32
Notes
1. In July 2011, a second Darfur Peace Agreement was signed between
the Government of Sudan and the Liberation and Justice Movement. For
disambiguation, generally the 2006 agreement is referred to as the Abuja
Agreement and the second agreement is referred to as the Doha Agreement.
This article is concerned exclusively with the 2006 Abuja Agreement.
2. For example, while the involvement of third parties logically fits with the
second hypothesis, it is also possible that the terms of a peace agreement contain
provisions that pertain exclusively to the role of third parties. Also, proponents
of epiphenomenal peace agreements (hypothesis I) would assert that the need
for third-party involvement (hypothesis II) supports their own claim.
3. Estimates on the number of deaths and displacements are impossible
to report accurately because of the complexity of gathering reliable data.
Refugees International (2012) reports that more than 2.6 million people
have been displaced within Darfur and that another 250,000 are refugees in
Chadian camps. Determining the number of deaths is even more complicated,
especially because battle-related deaths are difficult to separate from deaths
from other factors, like disease and malnutrition.
4. The JEM, along with one faction of the SLM/A (led by al-Nur), denounced
the agreement, claiming that power- and wealth-sharing and compensation
provisions were insufficient, and that the Government of Sudan had not
provided enough guarantees to disarm the Janjaweed.
5. The framework utilized in this article borrows from the guidelines
established by Hampson (1996, 9–10). Admittedly, this is not the only criteria
by which peace settlements can be evaluated. However, these two criteria
should be the minimum required to qualify any agreement as successful.
6. In 2007, charges were also laid against then Sudanese minister of state for
humanitarian affairs Ahmad Harun and alleged Janjaweed leader Ali Kushayb.
7. Although President Idriss Déby was involved in mediating a ceasefire
between the SLM/A and the Government of Sudan in September 2003, it is
reasonable to assert that the Government of Chad has not, overall, been an
active supporter of the peace process.

Acknowledgements
The author would like to thank Dr. David Carment for his comments on
the earliest draft versions of this article, as well as the editors of the Paterson
Review and anonymous reviewers for their helpful feedback, suggestions, and
clarifications. Any errors or omissions are those of the author alone.

References
BBC (British Broadcasting Corporation). 2010a. “Darfur Death Toll Rises to
Two-year High in Sudan.” BBC News, June 7. http://www.bbc.co.uk/
news/10259604.
33
———. 2010b. “Sudan and Chad to End Hostilities.” BBC News, February 10.
http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/8507363.stm.
Brooks, Sean P. 2008. “Enforcing a Turning Point and Imposing a Deal: An
Analysis of the Darfur Abuja Negotiations of 2006.” International
Negotiation 13 (3): 413–40.
Collier, Paul, and Ank Hoeffler. 2002. “Greed and Grievance in Civil War.”
Working Paper 160, Centre for the Study of African Economies,
University of Oxford, Oxford.
Doyle, Michael W., and Nicholas Sambanis. 2000. “International
Peacebuilding: A Theoretical and Qualitative Analysis.” American
Political Science Review 94 (4): 779–801.
Daly, M. W. 2007. Darfur’s Sorrow: A History of Destruction and Genocide.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Flint, Julie. 2007. “Darfur’s Armed Movements.” In War in Darfur and the
Search for Peace, edited by Alex de Waal, 140–72. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
Fortna, Virginia P. 2003. “Scraps of Paper? Agreements and the Durability of
Peace.” International Organization 57 (2): 337–72.
———. 2004. Peace Time: Cease-Fire Agreements and the Durability of Peace.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Hampson, Fen O. 1996. Nurturing Peace: Why Peace Settlements Succeed or Fail.
Washington, DC: United States Institute for Peace.
Hanson, Stephanie. 2007. “Sudan, Chad and the Central African Republic.”
Council on Foreign Relations, January 2. http://www.cfr.org/sudan/
sudan-chad-central-african-republic/p12309.
Harbom, Lotta, Stina Hogbladh, and Peter Wallensteen. 2006. “Armed Conflict
and Peace Agreements.” Journal of Peace Research 43 (5): 617–31.
Hartzell, Caroline A., and Mathew Hoddie. 2007. Crafting Peace: Power-
Sharing Institutions and the Negotiated Settlement of Civil Wars.
University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.
Heavens, Andrew. 2009. “Sudan Accuses Chad of Supplying Darfur
Rebels.” Reuters, January 29. http://af.reuters.com/article/topNews/
idAFJOE50S0GS20090129.
Hottinger, Julian Thomas. 2006. “The Darfur Peace Agreement: Expectations
Unfulfilled.” In Accord, edited by Mark Simmons and Peter Dixon,
46–49. London: Conciliation Resources.
ICC (International Criminal Court). 2011. “Situation in Darfur, Sudan.”
Accessed December 17, 2011. http://www.icc-cpi.int/menus/icc/
situations%20and%20cases/situations/situation%20icc%200205.
ICG (International Crisis Group). 2007. “Darfur’s New Security Reality.”
Africa Report No. 134. November 26. http://www.crisisgroup.
org/~/media/Files/africa/horn-of-africa/sudan/Darfurs%20New%20
Security%20Reality.
Kessler, Glenn. 2006. “Sudanese, Rebels Sign Peace Plan for
Darfur.” Washington Post, May 6. http://www.washingtonpost.com/
wp-dyn/content/article/2006/05/05/AR2006050500305.html.
34
Lijphart, Arend. 1991. “The Power-Sharing Approach.” In Conflict and
Peacemaking in Multiethnic Societies, edited by Joseph V. Montville,
491–509. New York: Lexington Books.
Mearsheimer, John. 1994. “The False Promise of International Institutions.”
International Security 19 (1): 5–49.
Nathan, Laurie. 2007. “The Making and Unmaking of the Darfur Peace
Agreement.” In War in Darfur and the Search for Peace, edited by Alex
de Waal, 245–66. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Nye, Joseph S., Jr. 2008. “International Relations: The Relevance of Theory
to Practice.” In The Oxford Handbook of International Relations, edited
by Christian Reus-Smit and Duncan Snidal, 648–60. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
OAU (Organization of African Unity). 2007. “Communiqué of
the Fifth Meeting of the Darfur Peace Agreement Joint
Commission.” February 7. http://www.operationspaix.net/DATA/
DOCUMENT/3196~v~Communique_de_la_5eme_reunion_de_la_
Commission_Conjointe_sur_l_Accord_de_Paix_au_Darfour__en_
anglais_.pdf.
Refugees International. 2012. “Sudan.” Accessed May 29, 2012. http://www.
refugeesinternational.org/where-we-work/africa/sudan.
Sisk, Timothy D. 2008. “Power Sharing after Civil Wars: Matching Problems
to Solutions.” In Contemporary Peacemaking: Conflict, Peace Processes and
Post-War Reconstruction, edited by John Darby and Roger Mac Ginty,
195–209. 2nd ed. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Toga, Dawit. 2007. “The African Union Mediation and the Abuja Peace
Talks.” In War in Darfur and the Search for Peace, edited by Alex de
Waal, 214–44. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
UN (United Nations). 2005. “Secretary-General Welcomes Adoption of
Security Council Resolution Referring Situation in Darfur, Sudan, to
International Criminal Court Prosecutor.” March 31. SG/SM/9797.
http://www.un.org/News/Press/docs/2005/sgsm9797.doc.htm.
UNAMID (African Union-United Nations Mission in Darfur). 2010.
“UNAMID Celebrates Deployment of Tactical Helicopters.” Press
release, February 25. http://unamid.unmissions.org/Default.aspx?tabi
d=899&ctl=Details&mid=1072&ItemID=7898.
UN News Service. 2007. “Joint UN-AU Peacekeeping Force in Darfur Still
Missing Key Capacities.” ReliefWeb, October 8. http://reliefweb.int/
node/245552.
Werner, Suzanne, and Amy Yuen. 2005. “Making and Keeping Peace.”
International Organization 59 (2): 261–92.
Zartman, I. William. 2008. “The Timing of Peace Initiatives: Hurting
Stalemates and Ripe Moments.” In Contemporary Peacemaking: Conflict,
Peace Processes and Post-War Reconstruction, edited by John Darby and
Roger Mac Ginty, 22–35. 2nd ed. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
35
Paterson Review of International Affairs (2012) 12: 35–59.

Controlling Small Arms and Light Weapons


Proliferation: The Potential of the Arms
Trade Treaty
Nathan A. Sears
Norman Paterson School of International Affairs, Carleton University

This article examines the potential of the Arms Trade Treaty (ATT)
to strengthen international control over global small arms and light
weapons (SALW) proliferation. Research was based primarily on
existing scholarly work on SALW control, the ATT, and arms control
generally, as well as on observations of the third and fourth sessions of
the ATT Preparatory Committee. The first section of this article analyzes
the value of the ATT to strengthen international SALW control, looking
at the development of SALW control as a global security initiative,
the existing system of SALW control, its weaknesses, and how the
ATT could strengthen it. The second section examines the challenges
and opportunities that face the ATT with respect to negotiations,
implementation, monitoring and verification, and compliance. The
article argues that the ATT, while not a perfect instrument of SALW
control, presents significant opportunities to increase transparency
and promote a “responsible arms trade,” thereby reducing the negative
effects of SALW proliferation on human suffering, peace, security, and
sustainable development. Moreover, the partnership that has developed
between small- and medium-power states and civil society can help to
address the challenges that the ATT faces from weak state capacities
and control-averse states.

List of Acronyms and Abbreviations


ATT Arms Trade Treaty
ATT Prep-Com Prep-Com United Nations Arms Trade Treaty
Preparatory Committee
CCM Convention on Cluster Munitions
DDR disarmament, demobilization, and reintegration
ECOWAS Economic Community of West African States
EU European Union
Firearms Protocol Protocol Against the Illicit Manufacture of, and
Trafficking in Firearms, Their Parts and Components,
and Ammunition
36
Inter-American Convention
Inter-American Convention Against the Illicit
Manufacturing of, and Trafficking in Firearms,
Ammunition, Explosives, and Other Related-Materials
ICJ International Court of Justice
IHL International Humanitarian Law
IHRL International Human Rights Law
Interpol International Criminal Police Organization
MBT Convention of the Prohibition of the Use, Stockpiling,
Production and Transfer of Anti-Personnel Mines and
on their Destruction
NGO non-governmental organization
NISAT Norwegian Initiative on Small Arms Transfers
OSCE Organization for Security and Co-operation in Europe
PoA Programme of Action to Prevent, Combat and
Eradicate the Illicit Trade in Small Arms and Light
Weapons in All Its Aspects
SALW small arms and light weapons
SIPRI Stockholm International Peace Research Institute
The Monitor Landmine and Cluster Munition Monitor
The Register United Nations Register of Conventional Arms
Tracing Instrument International Instrument to Enable States to Identify
and Trace, in a Timely and Reliable Manner, Illicit
Small Arms and Light Weapons
UN United Nations
UNGA United National General Assembly
UNODA United Nations Office of Disarmament Affairs
UNSC United Nations Security Council

Introduction
On 6 December 2006, the United Nations (UN) General Assembly (UNGA)
passed Resolution 61/89, “Towards an Arms Trade Treaty [ATT],” in a
majority vote of 139 states in favour, one against (the United States), and 24
abstentions (UNGA 2006). On 2 December 2009, by another majority vote
and with the support of the United States, the UNGA adopted Resolution
64/48, whereby member states agreed “to convene a UN Conference on
the Arms Trade Treaty” in 2012 to negotiate a “legally binding instrument
on the highest possible common international standards for the transfer of
conventional arms” (UNGA 2009, para. 4). One of the main reasons behind
the call for the ATT is to strengthen international control over the global
proliferation of small arms and light weapons (SALW) through regulation
of or restraint over the legal SALW trade and to eliminate or prevent their
illicit trade.1 SALW kill between 500,000 and 750,000 people annually and
are a “contributory factor to armed conflict, the displacement of people,
organized crime and terrorism, thereby undermining peace, reconciliation,
37
safety, security, stability and sustainable social and economic development”
(Geneva Declaration Secretariat 2011, 1–2).
This article analyzes the potential of the ATT to strengthen international
control over global SALW proliferation. Part one examines the development
of SALW control as a global security priority, the existing system of SALW
control and its weaknesses, and the potential of the ATT to strengthen this
system. It argues that the ATT is poised to become the key international
instrument to control SALW proliferation. The ATT has great potential to
increase transparency in arms transfers through legally binding reporting
requirements and to promote a “responsible arms trade” through a normative
legal framework of “transfer criteria,” which have been an important part
of UN member states’ dialogue in the Arms Trade Treaty Preparatory
Committee (ATT Prep-Com). Nevertheless, flaws with the ATT include
its inability to address civilian ownership or reduce the millions of SALW
already in circulation globally.
Part two considers the challenges and opportunities that the ATT
faces in terms of negotiation, implementation, monitoring and verification,
and compliance. The ATT is likely to face negotiation challenges from
control-averse states, and implementation challenges from developing
countries’ weak state capacities, and is unlikely to have a treaty mandate
to develop monitoring, verification, and compliance systems. Despite these
state-oriented difficulties, the partnerships that have developed between
small- and medium-power states and transnational non-governmental
organizations (NGOs) have the potential to be a dominant force in
negotiations. Moreover, civil society has the capacity to assume monitoring
and verification functions and respond to instances of non-compliance.
This article concludes that the ATT has the potential to strengthen the
international system of control over SALW proliferation, thereby reducing
the frequency and severity in which these weapons are employed in war,
armed violence, crime, terrorism, and repression.

Part I: The Value of the ATT to Strengthen International


SALW Control
The development of SALW control as a global security initiative

The contemporary security discourse identifies the control of SALW


proliferation as a global security initiative.2 Historically, however, SALW
were irrelevant to the international security discourse. The original Cold
War “arms control” agenda of the 1960s looked to reduce the risks, severity,
and costs of war between states through legally binding, verifiable treaties
of agreed military constraints in the “numbers, types, deployment or use” of
nuclear weapons and related military technologies (Krause 2011, 26). SALW
were neglected since they were perceived to be inconsequential to the balance
of military power between the two blocs of states led by the United States and
the Soviet Union, respectively.3
38
The Cold War was dominated by a realist, or state-centric, security
paradigm, which conceived of “the state as the subject of security and anarchy
the eternal condition of international relations” (Krause and Williams 1996,
232). According to this view, states seek to increase their security vis-à-vis other
states by strengthening their relative military power. The end of the Cold War
led to a broadening and deepening of the security discourse. Types of security
threats were broadened to include non-state actors; and the subject of security
was deepened, most notably to define security in terms of the protection of
civilians, or “human security” (ibid., 230).4 Thus it became popular in the
post–Cold War arms control discourse to talk of “humanitarian arms control
and disarmament” to reduce the risks to civilians of certain “inhumane” and
“indiscriminate” weapons (Cooper and Mutimer 2011, 10; Krause 2011, 35).
The Convention on the Prohibition of the Use, Stockpiling, Production and
Transfer of Anti-Personnel Mines and on their Destruction (MBT), signed in
1997, and the Convention on Cluster Munitions (CCM), signed in 2008, are
examples of this new arms control agenda.
Recently, arms control has been reconceptualized as “controlling the
means of violence,” implying a broader scope to address questions of “who
can possess, use, develop and transfer the technologies of violence, under what
circumstances, against whom, and for what ends” (ibid., 29). The objectives
of this reconceptualization are as follows: “1. To reduce the likelihood that
the instruments of armed violence are used against individuals, communities,
or states; 2. To reduce the effects of armed violence should it be employed;
and 3. To reduce the resources employed in the development, acquisition and
deployment of the instruments of armed violence” (Cooper and Mutimer 2011,
11). As the threats to global security have changed, the arms control agenda
has followed suit in an effort to contain the primary tools of destruction.
SALW control has thus become an issue of prominence in the
contemporary security discourse (Garcia 2006, 29). In 1993, then Malian
president Alpha Oumar Konaré requested that then UN secretary-
general Boutros Boutros-Ghali send a UN mission to observe the effects of
uncontrolled SALW proliferation in his country. At the time, scholars such
as Edward Laurence (1992) were also beginning to focus on the security
implications of the international arms trade, particularly the SALW trade. In
1995, Boutros-Ghali called for international attention to the need to control
SALW proliferation and for the disarmament of these weapons, which “are
actually killing people in the hundreds of thousands,” at the ground level
(UNGA 1995). By the late 1990s, SALW control became one of the most
important security priorities of a large number of states (Garcia 2006, 18–19).

The existing system of SALW control

The 1990s and 2000s produced a number of multilateral political and legal
agreements on SALW control.5 The UN Register of Conventional Arms
(henceforth the Register) was established in 1991 as a voluntary reporting
system by states on conventional arms transfers. Its raison d’être was to build
39
confidence among states by increasing transparency in the international
arms trade (Holtom 2010, 61). The Register’s framework consisted of seven
categories of conventional arms that omitted SALW.6 It has only recently
created a standardized reporting form for SALW transfers (UNODA 2011).
While it is a step toward a norm of transparency in arms transfers, the
Register is weakened by its voluntary nature—it has experienced low state
participation in regions of tension and a decrease in reporting in recent years
(ibid., 82).
In 1998, the Economic Community of West African States (ECOWAS)
declared the Moratorium on Importation, Exportation and Manufacture of
Light Weapons in West Africa to stop the flow of SALW into West Africa,
which were exacerbating armed conflicts in countries such as Sierra Leone
and Liberia (ECOWAS 1998). In 2006, ECOWAS member states signed the
Convention on Small Arms and Light Weapons, Their Ammunition and
Other Related Materials, which, inter alia, banned SALW transfers into, from,
and through the territories of states parties in order to “prevent and combat
excessive and destabilising accumulation of [SALW] within ECOWAS”
(ECOWAS Executive Secretariat 2006, Article 2.1, 3.1). Moreover, ECOWAS
provides a humanitarian justification for the convention as it links SALW
transfers to international humanitarian law (IHL) and international human
rights law (IHRL) (ibid., Article 6; Garcia 2011, 122–23). ECOWAS set the stage
for the Nairobi Declaration (2000) and Nairobi Protocol (2004) for the Great
Lakes and Horn of Africa regions, and the Africa-wide Bamako Declaration
(2000), which reinforced the positions of the majority of African states to
strengthen SALW control (ibid., 116–17).
The European Union (EU) produced a Code of Conduct on Arms
Exports in 1998, which came into force in December 2008. The Code of
Conduct established uniform supply-side standards for arms transfers,
recognizing the “special responsibility of arms exporting states” (Council of
the European Union 1998, 1). The code establishes a number of normative
principles to be applied on a case-by-case basis in transfer license decisions.
Criterion two requires states to assess “the respect of human rights in the
country of final destination,” and to “not issue an export licence if there is
a clear risk that the proposed export might be used for internal repression”
(ibid., 3–4). Also in 1998, the EU enacted the legally binding European Union
Joint Action on Small Arms, which banned SALW transfers to non-state actors
(Garcia 2011, 115). The EU has demonstrated significant leadership in SALW
control, both in terms of norm creation and the fact that more rigorous EU
control has dramatically reduced SALW proliferation to countries with poor
human rights records (ibid., 141). In 2000, the Organization for Security and
Co-operation in Europe (OSCE) adopted the “OSCE Document on Small
Arms and Light Weapons” (supplemented by its 2003 Handbook of Best
Practices on Small Arms and Light Weapons), a comprehensive system of SALW
control, including regulations on manufacture, marking and record keeping,
transfer control criteria, stockpile security, surplus weapons reduction, and
transparency (OSCE 2000).
40
The Inter-American Convention Against the Illicit Manufacturing of
and Trafficking in Firearms, Ammunition, Explosives, and Other Related
Materials (hereafter Inter-American Convention) entered into force in 1998.
This legally binding agreement requires states parties to adopt measures “to
prevent, combat, and eradicate the illicit manufacturing of and trafficking in
firearms, ammunition, explosives, and other related materials,” including,
inter alia, the creation of domestic legislation to criminalize illicit trafficking
activities and systems for firearms marking and record keeping, transfer
licensing, stockpile security, and information exchange (Garcia 2011, 113;
OAS 1997). It has been ratified by a majority of states in the Americas, with
the noteworthy exceptions of the United States and Canada (ibid.).
The Protocol Against the Illicit Manufacturing of, and Trafficking in
Firearms, Their Parts and Components and Ammunition (henceforth Firearms
Protocol) entered into force in 2005 as a supplement to the United Nations
Convention Against Organized Crime. The Firearms Protocol was the first
international legally binding instrument on SALW. The Firearms Protocol
aggregates the measures taken by various regional agreements to create a
common international framework “to prevent, combat and eradicate the illicit
manufacturing of and trafficking in firearms, their parts and components and
ammunition” (UNGA 2001b; Garcia 2011, 117).
The UN’s Programme of Action to Prevent, Combat and Eradicate the
Illicit Trade in Small Arms and Light Weapons in All Its Aspects (PoA) is the
outcome document of the July 2001 UN Small Arms Conference. Edward
Laurence and Rachel Stohl (2002, 5) have identified six areas in which the
PoA has established the basis for policy-making on SALW control: regulating
trade; marking and tracing; brokering; destruction and reduction of surplus
stocks; stockpile security; and information exchange and transparency. The
PoA recognizes the need for a multi-level approach to SALW control by
calling on states to take action at the national, regional, and international
levels (ibid., 41–42; UNGA 2001a). The consensus nature of the document has
served to frame the debate on SALW control at the international level through
the establishment of norms in customary international law.7 Following the
2001 SALW Conference, the legally binding International Instrument to
Enable States to Identify and Trace, in a Timely and Reliable Manner, Illicit
Small Arms and Light Weapons (henceforth Tracing Instrument) entered into
force in 2005. The Tracing Instrument requires states parties to take more
comprehensive steps in marking and record keeping; co-operate in tracing
operations, information exchange, and technical assistance; create national
points of contact; and co-operate with the International Criminal Police
Organization (Interpol).
The UN Security Council (UNSC) is empowered to declare legally
binding arms embargoes—the prohibition of arms transfers to a defined
state(s). Twenty-seven arms embargoes have been declared since 1990.
Embargoes are used to counter threats to global security, strengthen legitimate
government authority, and achieve peaceful settlements to armed conflicts
(Fruchart, Holtom, Wezeman 2007, v). However, the UNSC has a poor record
41
of sanctioning states that violate embargoes (Schroeder and Lamb 2006, 77).
Disarmament, demobilization, and reintegration (DDR) is a strategy employed
in UN peacekeeping operations to disarm ex-combatants and disband armed
groups. There have been more than 60 DDR programs worldwide since the
late 1980s (Krause 2011, 32). However, DDR has been criticized for being a
highly political process, salient in determining post-conflict distributions of
political and military power, often rewarding intransigence, and conceiving
of a “Weberian monopoly of violence” as its model of state power (ibid., 32;
Stavrianakis 2011, 195, 202).

Weaknesses of the existing international system of SALW control

Existing instruments of SALW control have focused on criminalizing illicit


transfers, marking and record keeping, stockpile security and reductions,
international co-operation and assistance, transparency and information
exchange, and transfer controls. However, transparency and transfer controls
remain relatively weak, as do linkages between normative doctrines, such as
IHL and IHRL, and SALW control (see UNGA 2001a, II.2, II.11; Garcia 2011,
123; Laurence and Stohl 2002, viii). Apart from the regional systems established
in Europe and Africa and UNSC arms embargoes, regulation of interstate
SALW transfers is weak (Marsh 2002, 217). Moreover, significant areas of
SALW control have been ignored at the international level. The intransigence
of a few states in the 2001 Small Arms Conference, most notably the United
States, prevented agreement on the regulation of civilian firearms and the ban
of transfers to non-state actors in the PoA (Garcia 2006; UNGA 2001a).
The so-called “politically binding,” rather than legally binding, nature
of several key instruments, including the Register and PoA, is another
weakness of international SALW control since these documents are unable
to compel compliance (Parker 2011, 32). However, legally binding treaties
are evidently insufficient in ensuring compliance, as demonstrated by the
occurrence of UNSC arms embargo violations (Schroeder and Lamb 2006,
77). Arguably, a greater problem is the weakness of monitoring, verification,
and compliance systems. The PoA does not have a mandate for monitoring
and verification. Instead, assessments of implementation are done through
a combination of biennial meetings, five-year review conferences, and the
work of NGOs and the UN PoA Implementation Support System, which
provides information on states’ implementation efforts (UN 2012). The PoA
Implementation Support System falls far short of the arms control standards
set by the International Atomic Energy Agency and the Organisation for the
Prohibition of Chemical Weapons, which have mandates for inspections of
states’ nuclear and chemical facilities.
A final problem is the narrow framing of the international SALW
control agenda as the control of “illicit” SALW through preventing SALW
diversion, defined as the movement of SALW from legal control by states and
state-sanctioned owners to illicit control by non-state-sanctioned owners.8
The distinction between licit and illicit SALW is often blurred. The current
42
framework does not sufficiently address the fact that SALW almost always
originate in legal possession before being diverted to illicit possession, hence
controlling illicit SALW requires control of legal SALW as well (see Garcia
2011, 49; Marsh 2002; Small Arms Survey 2002; Stavrianakis 2011). Similarly,
the focal role of states in legal SALW regulation has limited the reach of
international regulations in the critical areas of state-to-state transfers and
civilian firearms possession. Lastly, the narrow association of illicit SALW with
non-sanctioned non-state actors fails to address the illegitimate use of SALW
by state actors. As Mike Bourne (2011, 216) rightly points out, the separation
of legal and illicit SALW “bear[s] only limited and partial relationships to the
potential use of weapons in violence,” and “de-emphasizes the violence that
is often conducted with legally held and traded weapons.” Control-averse
states have thus succeeded in having international SALW control instruments
reaffirm their “legitimate rights” to use, produce, and transfer SALW.

The potential value of the ATT

The ATT could address a number of the weaknesses of the current


international system of SALW control. The UNGA conceives of the ATT as
a legally binding treaty that sets the highest possible international standards
of regulation governing the transfer of conventional arms (UNGA 2006, 4).
Thus, the ATT is poised to become the key international instrument covering
SALW transfers. Most importantly, the ATT has the potential to expand the
scope of the international SALW control agenda to include broad regulation
of legal trade. The hope is that the ATT can increase transparency in the
international arms trade through legally binding reporting requirements
and promote a “responsible arms trade” through a strong normative legal
framework of “transfer criteria,” whereby states parties would be required to
apply thorough risk assessments when making arms transfer decisions (ATT
Prep-Com 2011, V, VI).
The transfer criteria would likely be the ATT’s key substantive
section. There is a wide range of normative possibilities for consideration.
Possibilities include: the probability that a prospective arms transfer can be
diverted to an unintended end-user; that transfers could be used to commit
acts of aggression, armed violence, or repression, whether domestically or
internationally; the end-user state’s compliance record with respect to the UN
Charter, IHL, IHRL, UNSC arms embargoes, and international law in general;
the end-user state’s participation and implementation of existing instruments
of SALW control; the end-user state’s respect for democratic rights and norms;
that the end-user state is not a site of armed conflict, terrorism, or organized
crime; that the prospective arms transfer is proportionate to the end-user
state’s legitimate internal and external security needs; that the transfer would
not unduly divert scarce public funds from other needed areas, such as public
health and education; and an absolute ban of arms transfers to non-state
actors (ATT Prep-Com 2011, V; Council of the European Union 1998; Garcia
2011, 46, 68–71; Parker 2007, 10–11; and Wallacher and da Silva 2008, 3).
43
This is an ambitious list of transfer criteria for the ATT. Nevertheless,
the core normative principle that needs to be satisfied in order to establish a
responsible arms trade is that arms should not be transferred if there exists a
clear risk that they would be used to facilitate human suffering, or to undermine
peace, security, or sustainable social and economic development (ibid., III, V;
Garcia 2011, 37). The greatest challenge to building a norm of responsible
arms trading is the need to reconcile state sovereignty with the arms trade.
The ATT will have to reaffirm states’ rights to acquire arms for self-defence
and collective security, and to participate in peacekeeping operations (ATT
Prep-Com 2011, II.2; UNGA 2009, 1). The ATT therefore needs to make clear
distinctions between states’ rights to acquire arms for legitimate purposes
and illegitimate acquisitions that have no legal justification under the treaty’s
transfer criteria.
Despite its potential to increase transparency and promote a responsible
arms trade, the ATT is not the perfect instrument for SALW control. First,
SALW would likely be only one aspect within the scope of the ATT, which is
to apply broadly to conventional arms (ATT Prep-Com 2011, IV). Therefore, it
may be difficult for the ATT to cover all aspects of the SALW trade, including
the trade in their parts, components, and ammunition, while simultaneously
being expected to cover all aspects of the trade in other conventional weapons.
Moreover, the ATT would not address key conditions enabling SALW
proliferation. As it continues to be a state-centric process, it would not create
international standards of control over domestic civilian possession, since
those would sacrifice US support for the ATT process (Garcia 2011, 49). It also
does not reduce existing stocks of SALW or limit future production (ibid.,
65), although associated market restrictions reduce the economic incentives
to produce arms. The easy acquisition of SALW by civilians in countries
with low standards of firearms regulations, and the millions of SALW
already in global circulation, will continue to fuel proliferation. Nevertheless,
introducing international regulation of the ammunition trade could make
millions of illicitly held and irresponsibly used SALW superfluous, if their
users are denied bullets. The ATT could save more lives as a mechanism of
ammunition control than arms control. Setting high international standards
for the ammunition trade should therefore be a key priority for the ATT (ATT
Prep-Com 2011, IV; Parker 2007, 6).

Part II: The Challenges and Opportunities for the Arms


Trade Treaty
Negotiation of the ATT

Keith Krause’s (2002, 247–48) description of the 2001 UN Small Arms


Conference could easily be applied to the current atmosphere of the ATT
Prep-Com: “The last-minute intransigence of the United States (which almost
blocked final consensus), the silent opposition of states such as China, the
44
activism of the European Union . . . and like-minded states, the persistent
resistance of the Arab League to concrete measures, and the impassioned pleas
of affected states—this time mainly in Africa.” Nevertheless, the Prep-Com
has shown that most states envision the ATT as an instrument to strengthen
SALW control (ATT Prep-Com 2011). In the debate on the scope of the ATT,9
a clear majority of states have supported the inclusion of SALW, with the
notable exceptions of China, Egypt, Ethiopia, and Iran (see Armstreaty.org).
The inclusion of ammunition and other munitions has received less support
(ibid.).
Many developing countries in Africa, the Caribbean, Central and South
America, and the Pacific face severe internal security threats from armed
conflict and violent crime. They therefore perceive the ATT as a means of
increasing security through controlling SALW proliferation, particularly
with regard to non-state actors. Conversely, many states depend on foreign
acquisitions of weapons and materials to supply their armed forces. For
example, many states in the Middle East and North Africa, such as Algeria,
Egypt, India, Iran, Iraq, Israel, Pakistan, Saudi Arabia, and Syria, consistently
have military imports into the hundreds of millions of U.S. dollars annually
(SIPRI 2011). These states, many of which—such as India and Pakistan—
suffer from acute security dilemmas (Garcia 2011, 66), are likely to resist the
ATT’s interference with their ability to acquire arms. At the same time, many
of these states are also considered “high risk” according to potential ATT
transfer criteria, which adds incentives to block successful negotiations. Not
surprisingly, there has been consistent intransigence from a number of states
in these regions, most notably from Algeria, Egypt, India, Iran, Pakistan, and
Syria.
States also have commercial interests at stake in negotiations. Asid Efrat
(2010, 122) observes a correlation between arms exporting states, particularly
those with stated owned industries, and resistance to stronger SALW
regulation. Russia, with a state-owned arms industry that exported over
US$60 billion worth of conventional arms between 2000 and 2010, has stated
that the ATT should be limited to controlling the illicit conventional arms
trade (SIPRI 2011). Furthermore, while EU states have been moral leaders in
the ATT process, a number of them consistently rank within the top 10 global
arms suppliers, including France, Germany, Italy, the Netherlands, Sweden,
and the United Kingdom (ibid.). If states with growing arms industries such
as Brazil, China, or India do not sign the ATT, then EU states’ arms industries
would face significant commercial handicaps, since they would be held to
higher standards than states outside the ATT.
The final danger is the consensus decision-making procedures that
were agreed at the end of the fourth session of the ATT Prep-Com. Operational
paragraph five of Resolution 64/48 states that “the United Nations Conference
on the Arms Trade Treaty will be undertaken in an open and transparent
manner, on the basis of consensus, to achieve a strong and robust treaty [emphasis
added]” (UNGA 2009, 5). The interpretation of this paragraph was the most
contentious point of the fourth session of the Prep-Com, dividing states into
45
two camps. The first group held that Resolution 64/48 means that all decisions
at the ATT negotiation conference, whether on substantive or procedural
matters, should be taken by a consensus of states. The second group claimed
that in UN practice consensus is not synonymous with unanimity, but rather
a process of reaching agreement without formal objections by states. These
states generally believe that consensus was an objective to be worked toward,
but that veto power should not be conceded to each state (Sears 2012b, 5). The
Prep-Com finally agreed on rules of procedure on decision-making for the
ATT negotiation conference whereby all substantive decisions are taken by
consensus and that every effort is made to ensure that procedural decisions
are taken by consensus. However, a mechanism for two-thirds majority
voting of all states present and voting was included for when the president of
the conference decides that all efforts toward consensus have been exhausted.
The president also has the authority to rule on whether a matter is substantive
or procedural (ATT Prep-Com 2012, VII). The danger that intransigent states
will be able to block or substantially weaken a treaty through consensus
decision-making on substantive matters thus remains a real threat to the
negotiation of a mechanism to strengthen international SALW control.
On the other hand, the great number of small- and medium-power states
and transnational NGOs that support the ATT have the potential to become
the dominant force in the 2012 ATT negotiation conference. Matthew Bolton
and Thomas Nash (2010, 178) argue that small- and medium-power states
and civil society generally share an interest in establishing legal international
norms to “tie great and regional powers down to stable and predictable
international regulations,” while great and regional powers resist norms in
order to maintain flexibility in their foreign policy. UN treaty negotiations
in the post–Cold War world have thus seen the development of strategic
partnerships between governments and transnational NGOs, also referred to
as two-track diplomacy. Notably, such partnerships helped produce the MBT
and CCM, despite formidable resistance from China, Russia, and the United
States.
A significant body of literature has examined the successes of these state-
civil society coalitions.10 Their success is attributed to the combination of their
respective strengths: states possess financial resources and authoritative status
to negotiate treaties, while civil society has the capability to frame a debate
in moral terms and communicate its message to a wider audience (Bolton
and Nash 2010; Price 1998, 638–39; and Rutherford 2000, 96, 102–03). These
coalitions can place enormous political pressure on resistant governments,
which may risk damaging domestic reputations and diplomatic relations
if they are seen as being on the wrong side of a moral issue. Such pressure
can be decisive in democratic societies. Moreover, if negotiations get bogged
down by intransigent states, like the MBT and CCM cases demonstrate, it is
possible to pursue negotiations as a process between like-minded states.
This sort of strategic partnership between small- and medium-power
states and transnational NGOs has already emerged within the ATT process
(Garcia 2011, 66–67). A number of state coalitions have supported common
46
positions for a strong ATT in the Prep-Com, including the African Group,
Caribbean Community, EU, and Group of Like-Minded States led by Mexico
(ATT Prep-Com 2011). They have been supported by various transnational
NGOs, such as the Control Arms Campaign and the International Actions
Network on Small Arms. These coalitions have been able to dominate SALW
discussions in the Prep-Com because their numbers give them greater
speaking time compared to control-averse states. The coalitions have framed
the SALW debate in terms of the challenges to security and development
caused by SALW proliferation and personal tragedies of victims of SALW
violence (ibid.). Control-averse states have reserved their statements to states’
sovereign rights to self-defence rather than confronting the moral issues of
SALW proliferation.
It is possible that in the event of deadlock, negotiations could be
organized outside the UN framework through the participation of like-
minded states. However, this would not be an ideal solution to the problem
of state intransigence since such negotiations would exchange the ATT’s
universality for its comprehensiveness. This potential scenario begs the
question of whether the goal of greater SALW control is better served by a
treaty of high, non-universal standards on the international arms trade or
by less-stringent, universal standards. Certainly losing the support of major
arms-exporting states such as China, Russia, and the United States is a
problem that should be avoided, and an important reason to avoid the like-
minded states negotiation model.
An apparent opportunity for ATT negotiations comes from a less
expected front: the European arms industry. Representatives of this
industry have explained that they have a commercial interest in a treaty
that promotes predictability in arms transfer laws; common standards of
competition between firms, whereby the lowest moral standard does not
lead to competitive advantage; and corporate social responsibility, which is
important to industry investors.11 The industry’s support, as key stakeholders
in the international arms trade, may be a welcome development for the ATT.
However, this support should be viewed critically. Commercial interest in
the ATT by definition looks to make the arms trade easier and less costly for
business, but SALW control generally favours making it more difficult and
costly. For example, the European arms industry may perceive the ATT as
a chance to lower their comparatively high regulatory standards. Thus, the
industry may have very different objectives for the ATT than, for example,
NGOs that see it as an opportunity to control SALW proliferation (Sears
2012a, 4).
Notably, there was debate in the Prep-Com over how the ATT should
apply to non-state actors. The African Group called for an absolute ban
on arms transfers to non-state actors. However, as the Swedish delegation
pointed out, industry is also a non-state actor. The key is for the ATT to
carefully define “non-state actors” and the treaty to be applied in a way that
will make arms transfers to violent non-state actors that concern the African
Group—insurgents, terrorists, and rebels, whether acting as individuals or
47
groups, seeking to undermine legally constituted government authority—
illegal, while not placing overly burdensome restrictions on the normal
activities of transnational firms. Yet, as the Nigerian delegation suggested, if
these firms decide to associate themselves with violent non-state actors, their
actions should be considered illegal under the ATT (ibid.).

Implementation of the ATT

Implementation of the ATT would occur primarily at the national level. First,
national authorities may be required to apply ATT transfer criteria in case-
by-case risk assessments (ATT Prep-Com 2011, V; Wallacher and da Silva
2008, 14). If national governments determine there to be substantial risk that a
given transfer would violate these criteria, then the transfer would be illegal
under the ATT. Second, states parties may be required to adopt or refine
national legislation to be consistent with the ATT, such as criminalizing arms
transfers without government authorization (ATT Prep-Com 2011, VI.3).
Third, states parties may need to create or refine national agencies to monitor,
keep records, and enforce laws on arms transfers (ibid., VI. A). Fourth, states
parties may be obligated to strengthen transit and transhipment security
of conventional arms (Saferworld 2011, 11–12; Holtom and Bromley 2011b,
1). Finally, annual reporting of information on all arms transfers under
a standardized framework would be a basic requirement of the ATT (ATT
Prep-Com 2011, VI.B).12 Reporting may also include information on national
transfer control systems, law enforcement efforts, and other steps taken
towards implementation (Holtom and Bromley 2011a, vii; Kirkham 2008, 8).
The biggest challenge for ATT implementation and for SALW control
broadly is that effective national implementation requires a high level of state
development. First, implementation requires sufficient human, technical, and
financial resources, as well as low levels of corruption in state bureaucracies,
such law enforcement and customs offices, as well as legislatures (ibid., 4;
Parker 2011, 15–17, 25). Second, states require effective control over their
territorial jurisdiction, including borders, coastlines, and airspace (Lamb
and Schroeder 2006, 70–72; Parker 2011, 19–21). These characteristics are
mainly found in developed states. While developed states are capable of
implementing the ATT to reduce the cascading effect of SALW diffusion from
suppliers in developed states to markets in developing states, this would not
eliminate the world’s SALW proliferation problems. SALW proliferation can
be expected to continue between the world’s less developed countries, which
already have saturated SALW markets and would be incapable of effectively
implementing the SALW controls of the ATT.
Sarah Parker (ibid., 15) has argued that “[f]or the most part, lack of
capacity and resources is a challenge that can be addressed by international
cooperation and assistance, if it is well coordinated.” The Prep-Com has
identified weak state capacities as a key challenge to be addressed through
international co-operation and assistance.13 However, it is unrealistic to think
that the ATT can solve this problem simply through treaty provisions. The
48
MBT’s Article VI on international co-operation and assistance uses weak
language such as “each state party in a position to do so shall provide
assistance” (Mine Ban Treaty 1997, 6.3–6.5). The fact that many states parties
have failed to meet their initial demining and stockpile destruction deadlines
and countless landmine victims still struggle without adequate assistance
demonstrates that this is an insufficient strategy for solving state capacity
problems (Landmine and Cluster Munition Monitor Editorial Board 2010,
1–2). What is required is a substantial bolstering of state bureaucracies and
territorial control in the world’s less developed countries. To accomplish this,
the ATT would require much greater financial and technical commitments
from developed states than was the case with the MBT. This seems unlikely
(ATT Prep-Com 2011). The PoA’s problem with implementation through co-
operation is demonstrative of the challenges that await the ATT (Parker 2011,
16–17).

Monitoring and verification of the ATT

Monitoring is the collection of information on states parties’ treaty


implementation efforts, while verification is an analytic process of determining
states parties’ treaty compliance (Lewis and Findlay 2003, 2–4; Tulliu and
Schmalberger 2001, 185–86). Monitoring and verification systems have three
basic functions: to detect non-compliance, to deter non-compliance, and to
build confidence through demonstrations of compliance (ibid.; Lewis and
Findlay 2003, 2–4). The ATT has a number of monitoring and verification
possibilities. The first is states parties’ so-called “national technical means,”
or the unilateral collection of information on other states parties through
available means, including intelligence agencies (ibid., 6, 20). National
technical means would permit committed parties to track the compliance of
less-committed parties. However, this may be damaging to a treaty that seeks
to build confidence and increase co-operation.
The second possibility is the creation of an independent organization
with a formal monitoring and verification mandate. Arguably the best
examples of this type of monitoring and verification are the roles played by
the International Atomic Energy Agency in relation to the Treaty on the Non-
Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons and the Organisation for the Prohibition of
Chemical Weapons with regard to the Chemical Weapons Convention. These
bodies have permanent executives and secretariats that collect and analyze
information submitted directly by states parties, and gathered through more
intrusive means, including fact-finding missions, on-site inspections, requests
for clarification of compliance, and advanced monitoring technologies
(Rockwood 2007, 209; Tabassi 2007, 283–86). Unfortunately, the ATT is
unlikely to establish such a body because of states’ cautious attitudes towards
monitoring and verification. The word “inspections” has, for example, been
taboo in the Prep-Com (ATT Prep-Com 2011). The best that can realistically
be hoped for is that negotiations will create an Implementation Support
Unit that will collect and review reports submitted by states parties on their
49
implementation of the ATT (ibid.).
The third opportunity is for civil society to take on the tasks of
monitoring and verification. The best example of this is the Landmine and
Cluster Munition Monitor (hereafter the Monitor), the de facto monitoring
organization for the MBT for over 11 years and the CCM for over three
years. The Monitor systematically collects, organizes, and analyzes publicly
available information on states’ implementation and publishes high quality
annual reports available to the public. The Monitor employs an international
network of in-country researchers, managed by an editorial staff, to carry
out its research (Landmine Monitor Editorial Board 2009, vi–vii; Meier and
Tenner 2001, 213–15). High standards are demanded of researchers, who must
verify and cross-check all information, rely on open-source materials, and do
extensive footnoting. Researchers are encouraged to question the reliability
of their sources and to act “in a professional and dispassionate manner”
with “thorough, accurate and impartial” fact finding (Landmine and Cluster
Munition Monitor 2011).
However, ATT compliance is substantially more difficult to monitor
because of the high volume of conventional arms transfers, complicated
transit routes, and numerous transaction parties in the international arms
trade. Moreover, the smaller and the more numerous the items, the more
difficult they are to monitor—indicating a challenge for monitoring SALW
and ammunition transfers. Moreover, state implementation of transfer
criteria, through risk assessments and subsequent authorizations, would
produce a substantial verification challenge for civil society.
Fortunately there are examples of NGOs that have experience
monitoring the international arms trade. The Stockholm International Peace
Research Institute (SIPRI) maintains an annually updated database of publicly
available information on international conventional arms transfers (excluding
SALW) dating back to 1950 (SIPRI 2011). SIPRI’s objectives for this program
are to identify suppliers and recipients of major conventional arms, increase
the transparency of the international arms trade, and identify destabilizing
arms buildups (Holtom and Bromley 2011a, 27). Its database can be used to
check the details of specific arms transfers, or the total imports and exports by
country (ibid.). The Norwegian Initiative on Small Arms Transfers (NISAT)
has a database that specifically monitors SALW transfers, their ammunition,
and related-materials. NISAT’s database uses primarily publicly available
customs data on SALW exports and imports made available through the UN
Commodity Trade Statistics Database. NISAT also cross-checks the import
and export data to verify its consistency (ibid., 28–29).
While the work of SIPRI, NISAT, and other NGOs provide reassuring
examples that monitoring the international arms trade is possible, monitoring
and verifying compliance with the ATT requires the development of a unique
model. The primary function of such a civil society initiative should be to
monitor and verify that national risk assessments and transfer authorizations
and denials are carried out objectively, and that states’ arms transfers are in
accordance with the ATT’s transfer criteria. Secondly, it should compare states
50
parties’ national reports—if made public—with open source information on
arms transfers to verify their accuracy. Thirdly, it could evaluate the strengths
and deficiencies of states’ transfer control systems (ibid., 26). This sort of
monitoring and verification would be most effectively pursued as in-depth,
random investigations of states’ ATT implementation, including, for example,
assessments of states’ actual arms transfers—authorizations, denials, and
deliveries—against transfer criteria to verify that national transfer control
systems comply with the ATT when making transfer decisions. Verifying that
transfer denials are based on objective risk assessments rather than so-called
“political abuse” could help gain the support of control-averse states.
While annual evaluation of all states parties would likely be too ambitious
of an agenda for a civil society initiative, random assessments of a number
of states parties could still provide sufficient probability of detecting non-
compliance, and therefore strengthen the deterrent from non-compliance and
build confidence among states parties. A civil society initiative that focuses on
these areas would also minimize its overlap with the work of existing NGOs,
including SIPRI and NISAT, which measure international arms transfers
irrespective of specific treaties such as the ATT.
Civil society monitoring and verification of the ATT has a number
of advantages. First, NGOs have the freedom to determine their own
mandate (Meier and Tenner 2001, 215–16). For example, the Monitor collects
information on the activities of both states parties and non-parties, a liberty
which no treaty mandate would provide (Woodward 2001, 106). Second,
they can report their findings to the public, increasing accountability through
greater transparency, while an official organization may be required to keep
its information in confidence. Finally, they have the freedom to determine
their information sources, while an official body may be forced to depend
on information provided by states parties (Meier and Tenner 2001, 213–15).
Conversely, civil society may not have access to confidential information or
locations that may only be available to an official body, and may face greater
budget constraints than an organization funded by states parties (ibid., 217).
Ideally, the ATT would have a two-track monitoring and verification system,
with an official intergovernmental organization and a flexible NGO. In reality
states are likely to oppose the creation of an official system. Thus, the NGO
community should actively engage the topic of civil society monitoring and
verification. A treaty without such a system would be significantly weakened,
allowing states parties substantial freedom to interpret their obligations and
implement a treaty as they see fit. The Monitor offers an instructive model
for a future system: it should be established from within the ATT campaign,
it should be based on an international network of in-country researchers,
it should have leadership capable of managing the network from a central
headquarters, it should make regular and reliable public reports of a
consistent quality, and it should maintain close relationships with supportive
states, which can be important sources of information, funding, and political
support.14
51
Compliance with the ATT

Non-compliance refers to when a states party fails to meet, or is in open


violation of, its treaty obligations (Tulliu and Schmalberger 2001, 185; Lewis
and Findlay 2003, 33). Failure to address non-compliance can erode states
parties’ confidence in a treaty and encourage further non-compliance by
weakening the deterrent of expected sanctions. Compliance systems, or a
system of responses to non-compliance, exist in order to weaken or eliminate
the incentives for treaty defection. Effective compliance systems should be
able to assess the severity of non-compliance cases, distinguish between
unintentional and deliberate non-compliance, have a range of appropriate
responses, and be able to respond to a high frequency of cases (ibid., 40).
A moderate compliance tool that has been suggested in the Prep-Com
is to establish “consultation” and “clarification” procedures, or requests
for information between states parties “regarding the implementation and
operation of [the ATT]” (ATT Prep-Com 2011, I). Clarification procedures
could be initiated by a state party if it believes that another state party has
violated the ATT’s transfer criteria. The latter party would then be required to
provide information on its decision-making process for this transfer. A dispute
settlement mechanism is another useful compliance tool that has been suggested
in the Prep-Com (ibid., J). The referral of cases to the International Court of
Justice is one possible dispute settlement mechanism for the ATT (Kirkham
2008, 24–25). Meetings of states parties and treaty review conferences are an
essential part of a compliance system. They provide forums for states parties
to collectively address non-compliance cases with the states of concern (ATT
Prep-Com 2011, G–H; Kirkham 2008, 17). In more extreme cases, sanctions can
be considered (ibid., 25). Case referrals to the UNSC carry the potential weight
of an arms embargo, which is a fitting way to enforce a norm of responsible
arms trading because it indicates that participation in the international arms
trade is a privilege of responsible states rather than a right of all states.
Civil society provides an alternative in the likely event that the ATT
does not elaborate a well-defined, robust compliance system (ATT Prep-
Com 2011). Civil society has greater flexibility to be frank and forceful
compared to states, which must balance goals of treaty compliance with the
maintenance of good interstate relations. In the cases of the MBT and CCM,
states parties have left the naming and shaming role to the International
Campaign to Ban Landmines and the Cluster Munition Coalition, which use
their speaking rights at meetings of states parties and review conferences to
identify non-compliance, with the tacit or even direct encouragement of some
states (Hansen 2011; Meier and Tenner 2001, 215–16). Similarly, the Monitor
publishes the details of states parties’ non-compliance in its annual reports,
and identifies “non-adherence” by states that are not parties to the MBT
and CCM.15 Responding to non-compliance could arguably be civil society’s
most important contribution to the ATT. As Jacqueline Hansen (2011) of the
Monitor has said, “It is our job to hold [states] accountable . . . And we won’t
shy from making that a point.”
52
Conclusion
UNGA Resolution 64/48 has set the agenda to negotiate the ATT aspiring
to “the highest possible common international standards for the transfer
of conventional arms” in July 2012. The ATT can strengthen the existing
international system of SALW control by increasing transparency in the
international arms trade through legally binding reporting requirements
and, more importantly, by elaborating a strong normative legal framework
of ATT transfer criteria to foster an international norm of a responsible arms
trade. The key principle of a responsible arms trade is that arms should not be
transferred if there is a clear risk that such weapons would be used to facilitate
human suffering, undermine peace and security, or threaten sustainable social
and economic development. While not tackling important areas of SALW
control, such as civilian possession or disarmament, such a framework would
nevertheless increase international control over SALW transfers, reducing
the frequency and severity in which these weapons can be employed in war,
armed violence, crime, terrorism, and repression. Moreover, the ATT that
covers ammunition could have the potential to make hundreds of millions of
illicit SALW superfluous by controlling the flow of bullets.
There are, however, serious challenges to realizing the ATT. The first
comes from the potential of control-averse states to derail, stall, or weaken
the ATT during negotiations, particularly in the event of consensus voting
procedures. The strategic partnerships that have developed between small-
and medium-power states and transnational NGOs will be key to overcoming
this challenge. Thus far, these coalitions have been able to dominate the SALW
debate in the Prep-Com, successfully framing it in moral terms, and exerting
significant political pressure on democratically elected governments. In the
event of failure, it remains possible that a group of like-minded states could
negotiate the ATT outside of the UN.
The ATT also faces serious implementation challenges from
developing countries’ weak state capacities. While the ATT could be
implemented by developed countries to reduce or eliminate the cascading
effect of future SALW diffusion to developing countries, SALW transfers are
likely to continue between the world’s least developed countries. It will be
difficult, but not impossible, for international co-operation and assistance to
effectively address this state capacity problem.
It also seems unlikely that the ATT would elaborate well-defined,
robust systems of monitoring, verification, and compliance. The absence of
such systems would seriously weaken the ATT and its deterrent of detection
and sanctions for non-compliance. Civil society has a critical role to play in
monitoring, verification, and responding to non-compliance. The NGO
community should immediately begin putting together a system based loosely
on the Monitor and draw useful lessons from SIPRI’s and NISAT’s programs
on monitoring conventional arms transfers. The ATT that covers SALW and has
a group of like-minded states and transnational NGOs to enforce it offers real
potential to strengthen the international system of SALW control.
53
Notes
1. SALW have been defined broadly in international law. The International
Instrument to Enable States to Identify and Trace, in a Timely and Reliable
Manner, Illicit Small Arms and Light Weapons defines “small arms” as
weapons designed for individual use, such as revolvers, pistols, rifles and
carbines, sub-machine guns, assault rifles and light machine guns. “Light
weapons” are designed for use by two or three persons, such as heavy
machine guns, hand-held and mounted grenade launchers, portable anti-
aircraft and anti-tank guns and rocket systems, recoilless rifles, and mortars
(UNGA 2005, II).
2. There is a long list of scholarly work that has identified uncontrolled SALW
proliferation as a global security threat, and/or control of SALW proliferation
as a global security initiative. See, for example, Atwood (2006), Bourne (2011),
Bromley and Griffiths (2010), Cooper (2011), Cooper and Mutimer (2011), Garcia
(2006), Efrat (2010), Garcia (2006; 2009; 2011), Hughes (2004), Kartchner (1996),
Krause (1999; 2002; 2011), Schroeder and Lamb (2006), Laurence and Stohl (2002),
Lock (1999), Marsh (2002), Rotfeld (2001), and Wallacher and da Silva (2008).
3. For a seminal study of the development of the initial Cold War arms control
agenda, see Bull and Goold-Adams (1961). For discussion of SALW being
outside the scope of the Cold War arms control agenda, see Bourne (2011,
216), Garcia (2011, 32–33), and Krause (2011, 26).
4. For explanations of the post–Cold War development of the human security
agenda, see Cooper (2011, 140) and Garcia (2011, 12–13).
5. This article does not attempt to provide a comprehensive account of all
existing instruments of SALW control. This has been done elsewhere (see, for
instance, Garcia 2011).
6. The Register’s seven-category framework on conventional arms includes
battle tanks, armoured combat vehicles, large-calibre artillery systems, combat
aircraft, attack helicopters, warships, and missiles and missile launchers. This
framework reflected a focus on destabilizing buildups of larger conventional
systems, mostly relevant to interstate rivalries.
7. For further discussion, see Garcia (2011, 118–19), Krause (2002, 249), and
Laurence and Stohl (2002, ix).
8. The framing of the diversion problem focuses on the ways in which SALW
move from legal to illicit possession (through such means as falsification of
documentation, bribery of corrupt officials, redirection of flights, or simply the
illegal production, purchasing, theft, looting, and smuggling of weapons) and
the physical and market characteristics of SALW that facilitate their diversion
(such as their size and weight, which makes them relatively easy to smuggle
by land, air, or sea; their durability and low maintenance requirements,
which give them long life cycles so that they often travel from armed conflict
to conflict; and the enormous quantities already in illicit circulation). See,
for example, Husbands (1996, 242–43), Joseph and Susiluoto (2002, 130–31),
Marsh (2002, 223–24), Schroeder and Lamb (2006, 71–72), and Small Arms
Survey (2002, 134–38).
54
9. The scope of an ATT refers to the types of weapons, materials, and
technologies, and the types of international transactions and activities to be
covered by a treaty. Suggested weapons, materials, and technologies have
included tanks; military vehicles; artillery systems; military aircraft (manned
or unmanned); military helicopters (manned or unmanned); naval vessels
(surface and submarine vessels armed or equipped for military use); missiles
and missile systems (guided or unguided); small arms; light weapons;
ammunition; munitions; parts and components; technology and equipment;
and dual-use goods (ATT Prep-Com 2011, IV. 1). Suggested international
transactions and activities have included import; export; transfer; brokering;
manufacture under foreign license; and technology transfer (ibid., IV. 2).
However, the definition of “transfer,” as it has been proposed, includes
import and export, as well as a number of other items, such as re-export,
temporary transfer, transhipment transit, transport, leases, loans, and gifts
(ATT Prep-Com 2011, Annex A).
10. See, for instance, Bolton and Nash (2010), O’Dwyer (2006), Price (1998),
Rutherford (2000), and Short (1999).
11. Representatives of the European arms industry spoke at a side event at the
third session of the ATT Prep-Com and explained their commercial interests
in the ATT (ATT Prep-Com 2011). In July 2011, 21 investors of Principles for
Responsible Investment, representing US$1.2 trillion in assets, called for a
strong, legally binding, and comprehensive ATT (Principles for Responsible
Investment, 2011).
12. A standardized reporting framework for the ATT may require information
on, inter alia, suppliers and recipients, transit routes, the types and numbers of
weapons, the years of order and delivery, and the value of transfers (Holtom
and Bromley 2011a, vii).
13. Key areas that have been identified are co-operation in information
exchange and law enforcement operations (with Interpol able to facilitate
interstate co-operation), financial assistance and technical training, and an
Implementation Support Unit to assist in the ATT’s implementation (ATT
Prep-Com 2011, VI; Saferworld 2011, 11–12).
14. On 27 July 2011, I interviewed Jacqueline Hansen, Program Manager
(Canada) for Landmine and Cluster Munition Monitor, to learn about how
the Monitor monitors, verifies, and responds to non-compliance with the
MBT and CCM. The objective of this interview was to draw lessons from the
Monitor that could be applied in the creation of a similar civil society function
with respect to the ATT.
15. As a result, beyond the gradual increase in the number of signatories to
these treaties, non-parties—such as the United States, Russia, and China—
have made real moves to demonstrate their adherence to treaty norms,
declaring moratoriums on the use or transfer of landmines, halting production,
destroying stockpiles, and providing assistance for demining activities and to
landmine victims (Landmine Monitor Editorial Board 2009, 1–2).

Acknowledgements
55

First, I would like to thank my family and girlfriend, Araceli Durango, for
their continuous support. I would also like to thank Ray Acheson of Reaching
Critical Will for getting me into the third and fourth sessions of the ATT
Prep-Com; Dr. Trevor Findlay for his instructive course on disarmament,
arms control, and non-proliferation; Foreign Affairs and International Trade
Canada and The Simons Foundation for the opportunity to compete in their
2011 Graduate Research Award Debate on the effective and enforceable
scope of the ATT; the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council for
its generous scholarship; and, finally, the members of the editorial board of
the Paterson Review of International Affairs for all of their hard work in putting
this together.

References
ATT Prep-Com (Preparatory Committee on the Arms Trade Treaty). 2011.
“Chair’s Draft Paper.” July 14. http://www.adh-geneve.ch/RULAC/
pdf/Chairman-Draft-ATT-blog.pdf.
———. 2012. “Revised Provisional Rules of Procedure of the Conference.”
February 17. http:/ www.reachingcriticalwill.org/legal/att/prepcom4/
docs/ROP.pdf.
Armstreaty.org. 2012. “Tracking States’ Positions on Key Issues Concerning
the Arms Trade Treaty.” http://armstreaty.org.
Atwood, David C. 1999. “Implementing Ottawa: Continuity and Change in
the Roles of NGOs.” Disarmament Forum 4: 19–31.
———. 2006. “NGOs and Multilateral Disarmament Diplomacy: Limits
and Possibilities.” In Thinking Outside the Box in Multilateral
Disarmament and Arms Control Negotiations, edited by John Borrie and
Vanessa Martin Randin, 33–54. Geneva: United Nations Institute for
Disarmament Research.
Bolton, Matthew, and Thomas Nash. 2010. “The Role of Middle Power–NGO
Coalitions in Global Policy: The Case of the Cluster Munitions Ban.”
Global Policy 1 (2): 172–84.
Bourne, Mike. 2011. “Controlling the Shadow Trade.” Contemporary Security
Policy 32 (1): 215–40.
Bromley, Mark, and Hugh Griffiths. 2010. “End-User Certificates: Improving
Standards to Prevent Diversion.” SIPRI Insights on Peace and
Security No. 2010/3, Stockholm International Peace Research Institute,
Stockholm.
Bull, Hedley, and Richard Goold-Adams. 1961. The Control of the Arms Race:
Disarmament and Arms Control in the Missile Age. London: Weidenfeld
& Nicolson for the Institute for Strategic Studies.
Cooper, Neil. 2011. “Humanitarian Arms Control and Processes of
Securitization: Moving Weapons along the Security Continuum.”
Contemporary Security Policy 32 (1): 134–58.Cooper, Neil, and David
Mutimer. 2011. “Arms Control for the 21st Century: Controlling the
56
Means of Violence.” Contemporary Security Policy 32 (1): 3–19.
Council of the European Union. 1998. “European Union Code of Conduct on
Arms Exports.” 8675/2/98. June 5. http://www.consilium.europa.eu/
uedocs/cmsUpload/08675r2en8.pdf.
ECOWAS (Economic Community of West African States). 1998. “Declaration
of a Moratorium on Importation, Exportation and Manufacture of
Light Weapons in West Africa.” October 31. http://www.iss.co.za/AF/
Arms/ECOWASmora.pdf.
ECOWAS Executive Secretariat. 2006. “ECOWAS Convention on Small Arms
and Light Weapons, Their Ammunition and Other Related Materials.”
June 14. http://www.iag-agi.org/bdf/docs/ecowas_convention_small_
arms.pdf.
Efrat, Asif. 2010. “Toward Internationally Regulated Goods: Controlling the
Trade inSmall Arms and Light Weapons.” International Organization 64
(1): 97–131.
Fruchart, Damien, Paul Holtom, and Siemon T. Wezeman. 2007. United
Nations Arms Embargoes: Their Impact on Arms Flows and Target
Behaviour. Stockholm: Stockholm International Peace Research
Institute.
Garcia, Denise. 2006. Small Arms and Security: New Emerging International
Norms. Abingdon: Routledge.
———. 2009. “Arms Restraint and Regional International Law Making: The
Case of the Economic Community of West African States.” African
Security Review 18 (2): 78–91.
———. 2011. Disarmament Diplomacy and Human Security: Regimes, Norms,
and Moral Progress in International Relations. New York: Routledge.
Geneva Declaration Secretariat. 2011. Global Burden of Armed Violence 2011:
Lethal Encounters. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hansen, Jacqueline (Program Manager [Canada] for Landmine and Cluster
Munition Monitor). 2011. In discussion with the author, Ottawa, July
27.
Holtom, Paul. 2010. “Nothing to Report: The Lost Promise of the UN
Register of Conventional Arms.” Contemporary Security Policy 31 (1):
61–87.
Holtom, Paul, and Mark Bromley. 2011a. “Implementing an Arms Trade
Treaty: Lessons on Reporting and Monitoring from Existing
Mechanisms.” SIPRI Policy Paper 28, Stockholm International
Peace Research Institute, Stockholm. http://books.sipri.org/files/PP/
SIPRIPP28.pdf.
———. 2011b. “Transit and Trans-Shipment Control in an Arms Trade
Treaty.” SIPRI Background Paper, July. Stockholm: Stockholm Peace
Research Institute. http://books.sipri.org/files/misc/SIPRIBP1107a.pdf.
Hughes, Helen. 2004. “Small Arms: Monitoring the UN Action Programme.”
In Verification Yearbook 2004, edited by Trevor Findlay, 127–42.
London: Verification Research, Information and Training Centre.
Husbands, Jo L. 1996. “Preventing the Spread of Arms: Delivery Means and
57
Conventional Weapons.” In Arms Control Toward the 21st Century,
edited by Jeffrey A. Larsen and Gregory J. Rattray, 228–250. Boulder:
Lynne Rienner Press.
Joseph, Kate, and Taina Susiluoto. 2002. “A Role for Verification and
Monitoring in Small Arms Control?” In Verification Yearbook 2002,
edited by Trevor Findlay and Oliver Meler, 129–44. London:
Verification Research, Information and Training Centre.
Kartchner, Kerry M. 1996. “The Objectives of Arms Control.” In Arms Control
Toward the 21st Century, edited by Jeffrey A. Larsen and Gregory J.
Rattray, 19–34. Boulder: Lynne Rienner Press.
Kirkham, Elizabeth. 2008. Making it Work: Monitoring and Verifying
Implementation of an Arms Trade Treaty. United Kingdom: Saferworld.
Krause, Keith. 2002. “Multilateral Diplomacy, Norm Building, and UN
Conferences: The Case of Small Arms and Light Weapons.” Global
Governance 8 (2): 247–63.
———. 2011. “Leashing the Dogs of War: Arms Control from Sovereignty to
Governmentality.” Contemporary Security Policy 32 (1): 20–39.
Krause, Keith, and Michael C. Williams. 1996. “Broadening the Agenda of
Security Studies: Politics and Methods.” Mershon International Studies
Review 40 (2): 229–54.
Landmine and Cluster Munition Monitor. 2011. “Research Orientation
Guide.” http://www.the-monitor.org/index.php/LM/Resources-for-
Monitor-Researchers/Research-resources/Monitor-2011-Research-
Orientation-Guide-PDF.
Landmine and Cluster Munition Monitor Editorial Board. 2010. Landmine
Monitor 2010. Canada: Mines Action Canada.
Landmine Monitor Editorial Board. 2009. Landmine Monitor Report 2009:
Toward a Mine-Free World. Canada: Mines Action Canada.
Laurence, Edward. 1992. The International Arms Trade. New York: Lexington
Books.
Laurence, Edward, and Rachel Stohl. 2002. “Making Global Public Policy:
The Case of Small Arms and Light Weapons.” Small Arms Survey
Occasional Paper No. 7. http://faculty.maxwell.syr.edu/rdenever/PPA-
730-27/Laurance%20and%20Stohl.pdf.
Lewis, Patricia, and Trevor Findlay, eds. 2003. Coming to Terms with Security:
A Handbook of Verification and Compliance. Geneva: United Nations
Institute for Disarmament Research.
Lock, Peter. 1999. Pervasive Illicit Small Arms Availability: A Global Threat.
Helsinki:
European Institute for Crime Prevention and Control.
Marsh, Nicholas. 2002. “Two Sides of the Same Coin? The Legal and Illegal
Trade in Small Arms.” Brown Journal of World Affairs 19 (1): 217–28.
Meier, Oliver, and Clare Tenner. 2001. “Non-Governmental Monitoring
and International Agreements.” In Verification Yearbook 2002, edited
by Trevor Findlay and Oliver Meier, 207–227. London: Verification
Research, Information and Training Centre.
OAS (Organization of American States). 1997. “The Inter-American
58
Convention Against the Illicit Manufacturing of and Trafficking in
Firearms, Ammunition, Explosives, and Other Related Materials.”
November 14. http://www.oas.org/juridico/english/treaties/a-63.html.
O’Dwyer, Diana. 2006. “First Landmines, Now Small Arms? The
International Campaign to Ban Landmines as a Model for Small-Arms
Advocacy.” Irish Studies in International Affairs 17: 77–97.
OSCE (Organization for Security and Co-operation in Europe). 2002. “OSCE
Document on Small Arms and Light Weapons.” FSC.JOUR/314.
November 24. http://www.osce.org/fsc/36735.
Parker, Sarah. 2007. Analysis of States’ Views on an Arms Trade Treaty. New
York: United Nations.
———. 2011. Improving the Effectiveness of the Programme of Action on Small
Arms: Implementation Challenges and Opportunities. Geneva: United
Nations Institute for Disarmament Research.
Price, Richard. 1998. “Reversing the Guns Sights: Transnational Civil Society
Targets Land Mines.” International Organization 52 (3): 613–44.
Principles for Responsible Investment. 2011. “Global Investor Statement on
the Arms Trade: Statement Calls for a Strong, Legally Binding and
Comprehensive Arms Trade Treaty.” July. http://www.unpri.org/
files/2011-07-13_ATT_second_investor_statement_final.pdf.
Rockwood, Laura. 2007. “The Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear
Weapons (NPT) and the IAEA Safeguards Agreements.” In Making
Treaties Work: Human Rights, Environment and Arms Control, edited by
Geir Ulfstein, 301–23. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rotfeld, Adam Daniel. 2001. “The Future of Arms Control and International
Security.” In A Future Arms Control Agenda: Proceedings of Novel
Symposium 118, 1999, edited by Ian Anthony and Adam Daniel
Rotfeld, 3–14. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rutherford, Ken R. 2000. “The Evolving Arms Control Agenda: Implications
of the Role of NGOs in Banning Antipersonnel Landmines.” World
Politics 53 (1): 74–114.
Saferworld. 2011. An Implementation Framework for the Arms Trade
Treaty. London: Saferworld. http://www.saferworld.org.uk/
downloads/An%20Implementation%20Framework%20for%20the%20
ATT.pdf.
Schroeder, Matt, and Guy Lamb. 2006. “The Illicit Arms Trade in Africa: A
Global Enterprise.” African Analyst 1 (3): 69–78.
Sears, Nathan A. 2012a. “Not-State Actors, the Arms Industry and an
Arms Trade Treaty.” Arms Trade Treaty Monitor 4 (5): 4. http://
www.reachingcriticalwill.org/disarmament-fora/att/prepcom4/att-
monitor?catid[0]=68.
———. 2012b. “Operative Paragraph 5.” Arms Trade Treaty Monitor 4 (3): 5.
http://www.reachingcriticalwill.org/disarmament-fora/att/prepcom4/
att-monitor?catid[0]=68.
Short, Nicola. 1999. “The Role of NGOs in the Ottawa Process to Ban
Landmines.” International Negotiation 4 (3): 481–500.
SIPRI (Stockholm International Peace Research Institute). 2011. “SIPRI Arms
59
Transfers Database.” Accessed 2011. http://www.sipri.org/databases/
armstransfers.
Small Arms Survey. 2002. Small Arms Survey 2002: Counting the Human Cost.
Geneva: Small Arms Survey.
Stavrianakis, Anna. 2011. “Small Arms Control and the Reproduction of
Imperial Relations.” Contemporary Security Policy 32 (1): 193–214.
Tabassi, Lisa. 2007. “The Convention on the Prohibition of the Development,
Production, Stockpiling and Use of Chemical Weapons and on their
Destruction (Chemical Weapons Convention).” In Making Treaties
Work: Human Rights, Environment and Arms Control, edited by Geir
Ulfstein, 273–300. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tulliu, Steve, and Thomas Schmalberger. 2001. Coming to Terms with Security:
A Lexicon for Arms Control, Disarmament and Confidence-Building.
Geneva: United Nations Institute for Disarmament Research.
UN (United Nations). 2012. “Programme of Action Implementation Support
System: PoA-ISS.” http://www.poa-iss.org/poa/poa.aspx.
UNGA (United Nations General Assembly). 1995. “Supplement to an
Agenda for Peace: Position Paper of the Secretary-General on the
Occasion of the Fiftieth Anniversary of the United Nations.” January
3. http://www.un.org/Docs/SG/agsupp.html.
———. 2001a. “Programme of Action to Prevent, Combat and Eradicate the
Illicit Trade in Small Arms and Light Weapons in All Its Aspects.” July
20. http://www.poa-iss.org/poa/poahtml.aspx.
———. 2001b. “Protocol against the Illicit Manufacturing of and Trafficking
in Firearms, Their Parts and Components and Ammunition,
Supplementing the United Nations Convention against Transnational
Organized Crime.” A/Res/55/255. June 8. http://www.unodc.org/pdf/
crime/a_res_55/255e.pdf.
———. 2006. “Towards an Arms Trade Treaty: Establishing Common
International Standards for the Import, Export and Transfer of
Conventional Arms.” A/Res/61/89. December 18. http://www.ony.unu.
edu/Resolution_61_89.pdf.
———. 2009. “The Arms Trade Treaty.” A/Res/64/48. December 2. http://
www.un.org/Docs/journal/asp/ws.asp?m=A/RES/64/48.
UNODA (United Nations Office of Disarmament Affairs). 2011. “UN
Register of Conventional Arms.” http://www.un.org/disarmament/
convarms/Register.
Wallacher, Hilde, and Clare da Silva. 2008. Progressing Towards an Arms Trade
Treaty. Oslo: International Peace Research Institute.
Woodward, Angela. 2001. “Verifying the Ottawa Treaty.” In Verification
Yearbook 2001, edited by Trevor Findlay and Oliver Meier, 99–115.
London: Verification Research, Training and Information Centre.
61
Paterson Review of International Affairs (2012) 12: 61–83.

To Rid the World of the Drug Scourge:


A Human Security Perspective on the War
on Drugs in Colombia and Mexico
Ginette Léa Gautreau
School of International Development and Global Studies,
University of Ottawa

When then U.S. president Richard Nixon declared the War on Drugs
in 1971, Colombia and Mexico became the first countries to experience
American-led crop eradication campaigns. This was the beginning of
40 years of warfare against drug trafficking organizations in Latin
America. Since then, prohibitive drug policies have been responsible for
widespread human rights violations and the displacement and deaths
of thousands of individuals, while persistently ignoring many of the
fundamental social, economic, and political roots of the drug trade.
This article explores the human security implications of the War on
Drugs in Colombia and Mexico, as carried out under Plan Colombia
and the Mérida Initiative. By applying a human security perspective to
the War on Drugs, it highlights the ways the War on Drugs adversely
affects the populations of Colombia and Mexico and seeks to challenge
traditional notions of security that dominate current drug policies and
debates. It reiterates the need to adopt more progressive drug policies
in Colombia and Mexico and concludes with a reflection on alternative
policy proposals as both countries try to move forward from their
lengthy drug wars.

Introduction
The War on Drugs has undercut civil liberties and human rights,
strengthened the armed forces in countries with a history of harsh
military rule, supported militarization of local police forces, spread the
use of torture by law enforcement, provided support to powerful leaders
who are themselves heavily implicated in the drug trade, contributed to
a significant social conflict and political instability, and undercut the
native means of making a living. (Singer 2008, 83)

When then U.S. president Richard Nixon declared the “War on Drugs” on
Mexican drug traffickers in 1971, he argued that drug abuse had become the
country’s “public enemy No. 1” and drugs presented a lethal threat to the
United States (Jelsma 2011, 6). From the beginning, the War on Drugs1 had
62
the ambitious goal to “rid the world of the drug scourge,” specifically aiming
at the eradication of cannabis, heroin, and cocaine (Seccombe 1997, 287). U.S.
anti-drug policies have since served to justify widespread crop eradication
campaigns and military interventions in several countries.
Forty years later, it has become increasingly clear that the War on
Drugs has failed in numerous ways. As journalist Charles Bowden notes, it
is not difficult to see that all of the drugs that were available in 1971 are still
available today in larger quantities, of better quality, and for much cheaper
(Bowden 2010). Despite reductions in drug cultivation consumption, and the
capture of cartel leaders and drug shipments, as cited by the United Nations
Office on Drugs and Crime (UNODC) and the U.S. government, the War
on Drugs has been unable to prevent the growth of complex transnational
drug trafficking networks and protect millions of individuals from harm
(UNODC 2010c). With over 50,000 casualties from the drug war in Mexico
since 2007 (Molzahn, Ríos, and Shirk 2012, 1) and over 200,000 individuals
fleeing their homes every year because of drug-related violence in Colombia
(IDMC 2010a), it has become clear to a growing number of policy-makers,
scholars, and civil society actors that the War on Drugs has been lost. Yet,
despite growing attention to its harmful human security implications, the
War on Drugs continues to compromise the security of countless individuals
worldwide.
The questions that guide this article are: What are the human security
implications of the War on Drugs in Colombia and Mexico? And in which
ways can a human security perspective influence policies to better address
these implications? To answer these questions, it is necessary to first define
human security and identify the main debates on this concept to provide
a comprehensive framework for the research that follows. Second, a brief
overview of the War on Drugs outlines the important role played by the United
States in the Colombian and Mexican drug conflicts through its controversial
military assistance agreements, Plan Colombia and the Mérida Initiative.
Subsequently, by drawing on examples from both countries, this article
analyzes the impacts and consequences of the War on Drugs with respect to
human security. The article concludes with a reflection on policy implications
and reiterates the need for the U.S. to adopt policies better geared to address
consumption within its borders and to reduce violence and adverse impacts
of the War on Drugs in Colombia and Mexico.
To achieve these objectives, this article draws from an array of relevant
research, including media sources because of the current and dynamic
nature of the topic. Reports from civil society organizations and international
organizations, mainly the UNODC, help support the arguments with relevant
data. Recent reviews by American, Colombian, and Mexican scholars
complemented with older analyses provide a comprehensive analysis of the
War on Drugs in Colombia and Mexico.
Overall, this article argues that the very policies put in place to ensure
security for Colombian and Mexican populations have not only failed but
have exacerbated certain forms of human insecurity, thus highlighting
63
the need to challenge conventional notions of security that drive the War
on Drugs and adopt more progressive drug policies. A human security
approach can complement traditional notions of security and contribute to
the development of the policies needed to overcome some of the most blatant
failures of the War on Drugs in Colombia and Mexico. Current policies focus
on law enforcement and combating drug trafficking organizations (DTOs), but
face powerful, wealthy cartels and an expansive transnational drug market,
leading to minimal, if any, progress. Rather, drug policies should focus above
all on reducing violence and addressing the underlying conditions that allow
narcotrafficking to persist.2

Human Security: A Contested Concept


The highly regarded Global Commission on Drug Policy (2011, 2) recently
stated that “[t]he war on drugs has failed,” echoing what numerous politicians,
including former presidents Vicente Fox (Mexico, 2000–06), Ernesto Zedillo
(Mexico, 1994–2000), and César Gaviria (Colombia, 1990–94), activists, such as
Javier Sicilia of the Movimiento por la Paz in Mexico, academics, and thousands
of concerned citizens have been affirming for years. The commission (ibid.),
made up of 19 high-level individuals, including former presidents Zedillo
and Gaviria, notes that “[v]ast expenditures on criminalization and repressive
measures directed at producers, traffickers and consumers of illegal drugs
have clearly failed to effectively curtail supply or consumption. Apparent
victories in eliminating one source or trafficking organization are negated
almost instantly by the emergence of other sources and traffickers.” Despite
these failures, American-backed anti-drug policies in Colombia and Mexico
continue to ignore how these policies impact human security. By challenging
this security focus, this article builds on the growing acknowledgement of
the failures of the War on Drugs and demonstrates how the narrow notion of
security that steers current drug policies is counter-productive for addressing
the complex security issues in drug conflicts and aggravates problems of
human insecurity.
The concept of human security emerged in the 1990s from the roots
of human rights, humanitarian relief, human development, and conflict
resolution discourse (Owen 2004, 377). The concept extends beyond these
realms to challenge traditional notions of state security that dominate
international relations. Human security has been widely contested; there is
still no consensus on a comprehensive definition of the term and its policy
applications (Balzacq 2003-2004; Duffield and Waddell 2006; Paris 2001). In
its broadest form, human security is defined as “prioritizing the security of
people, especially their welfare and well-being, rather than that of state . . .
[and] implies a broadening and re-prioritization of determinants of security”
(Duffield and Waddell 2006, 1). Evidently, the comprehensiveness of the
term leads to ambiguity. Roland Paris (2001, 90) notes that, being one of the
earliest prominent documents to define the concept, the definition of human
security in the United Nations Development Programme’s (UNDP) Human
64
Development Report 1994 remains the most cited and “authoritative.”3 In its
report, the UNDP (1994, 24) broadly defines the concept as freedom from fear
and freedom from want. It identifies seven specific components of human
security which this article uses to assess the breadth of human security
implications of the War on Drugs: economic, political, environmental, health,
food, personal, and community security.
The ambiguous definition has left policy-makers divided on how best
to apply human security principles to policy. As Fen Hampson notes (2004,
350), while many human security problems are caused by specific actors, such
as drug cartels or military officials in the context of the War on Drugs, there
are larger political and social structures that impede policy effectiveness. In
other words, changing the behaviour of actors may improve human security
conditions, but may not be sufficient. In fact, Hampson (ibid.) adds, “there
are [other] conditions for change that need to be met: the restructuring of
legal and political institutions, the reconstruction of the economic basis for
livelihoods, and the redefinition of prevailing social norms. Only in this way
is it possible to create a sustainable basis for human security.”
This article will demonstrate how the War on Drugs has focused almost
exclusively on combating DTOs, which is a legitimate endeavour supported
by both policy-makers and citizens (Ai Camp 2010), but, because of its
narrow focus on state security, has failed to address significant underlying
conditions. Better human security can only be achieved by broadening the
focus of security.

From the U.S. War on Drugs to the Colombian and


Mexican Drug Wars: A Brief Overview of American
Anti-drug Policies
The rapid expansion of drug use in the United States during the 1960s and
1970s threatened U.S. conservative doctrine and moral society (Carpenter
2003, 11–15). With thousands of heroin addicts returning from Vietnam, drug
abuse became the U.S. government’s top priority, and if it could not curtail
demand, its solution was to eradicate the supply (ibid.). Nixon first declared
a “war” on drugs in 1971 and targeted Mexico, which supplied over 80 per
cent of the U.S. heroin market at the time (Smith 1999, 194), and became the
first country where aerial crop spraying was applied in 1976 (Ai Camp 2010,
298). In 1983, the first U.S. anti-drug military deployment took place under
the Ronald Reagan administration in the Andean region, where most of the
cocaine that reached the United States originated (Carpenter 2003, 18–22).
Despite these efforts to eradicate the illicit drug trade, the industry quickly
developed into a complex multi-billion dollar transnational market; by the
1980s, the U.S. drug market was valued at US$80 billion (ibid., 20). The
implementation of drug-related policies in both Mexico and Colombia has
since been largely intertwined because of the complex interrelation of drug
production and DTOs between these two countries (Jelsma 2011; Smith 1999;
65
Carpenter 2003). Two recent policy agreements are analyzed in this article:
4

(1) Plan Colombia, a US$7.5 billion bilateral assistance package adopted in


2000 by then Colombian president Andrés Pastraña Arango and then U.S.
president Bill Clinton; and (2) the Mérida Initiative, a US$1.5 billion assistance
package agreed upon by then U.S. president George W. Bush and Mexican
President Felipe Calderón in 2007 (Olson and Wilson 2010, 3).

Plan Colombia5

Colombia witnessed a boom in its lucrative cocaine industry throughout the


1980s and 1990s, with various guerrilla groups and paramilitaries exploiting
the drug trade to obtain more power and control (Leech 2002, 13–18).
Colombia’s largest guerrilla groups include the Revolutionary Armed Forces
of Colombia (FARC) and the National Liberation Army. The paramilitaries,
such as the United Self-Defence Forces of Colombia (AUC), are responsible
for much of Colombia’s political tensions and the growth of the narcotics
industry, accountable for an estimated 76 per cent of the country’s political
and drug-related homicides between 1995 and 2001 (Colombian Commission
of Jurists data cited in Livingstone 2003, 6). To this day, guerrilla groups and
paramilitaries control large areas of the country including much of the south-
eastern highlands and portions of its Pacific coast. As of 2009, Colombian coca
cultivation spread over approximately 62,000 hectares and cocaine trafficking
to the United States alone is estimated to be worth nearly US$500 million
annually (UNODC 2011b, 245).
The Colombian government has unsuccessfully attempted to contain
the narcotics industry by proposing peace accords, capturing lead DTO
members, destroying coca plantations, and engaging in direct military
action against DTOs (Leech 2002, 41–44). Sarah Peterson (2002, 431) notes
that Plan Colombia was a response to years of “scant success” and the
government’s commitment to “get serious about coca eradication.” The Plan’s
primary objective was to “push into Southern Colombia” and gain control
of the drug-producing regions within the country (ibid.; Ramírez 2011,
216). According to Martin Jelsma (2011, 7), Plan Colombia was essentially
a “combined counterdrug and counterinsurgency strategy, including the
highly controversial policy of mass aerial herbicidal spraying of coca and
poppy fields.” In addition, María Clemencia Ramírez (2011, 215) stresses that
“the plan became a military strategy to break up alliances that were said to
be destabilizing the state and threatening continental security.” Only 26 per
cent of Plan Colombia’s budget was reserved for socio-economic programs,
such as alternative development and human rights promotion (ibid., 216).
The remaining funds were primarily invested in military and police activities
and aerial spraying campaigns (ibid., 432). Furthermore, although clauses
within Plan Colombia existed to ensure that the military and police respected
human rights, the result remains deplorable: an estimated three million to
five million individuals have been forcibly displaced by the drug war in the
past 25 years (Amnesty International 2011).
66
Plan Colombia came to an end in 2007 with mixed results. For
instance, the Uribe government managed to shrink the FARC to around
9,000 insurgents and push them out of the most populated areas, and the
AUC was demobilized (Isacson and Poe 2009). As a result, the rates of
extortion, violence, and kidnappings were greatly reduced. However, the
environmental and humanitarian damage of the campaign left thousands
frustrated and in dire socio-economic conditions, and Colombia is now facing
new generations of insurgency groups ranging from 4,000 to 9,000 individuals
in different regions of the country (ibid.). Finally, Plan Colombia only led to
a slight drop in coca cultivation in the Andes. Upon realizing that military
action alone could not address Colombia’s narcotics trade and insurgencies,
the U.S. and Colombian governments shifted toward more integrated actions
and broader consultation with the public, including more investment in
human rights protection and humanitarian aid (ibid.). These are significant
improvements and align with the human security approach described in this
article. However, security intervention, drug-related crimes, and widespread
violence and displacements still occur in rural Colombia ensuring that the
conflict continues to be very relevant today. In addition, Colombia’s policy
shift has failed to moderate Mexico’s approach, as explained in the following
section, where military intervention still prevails.

Mérida Initiative6

The drug trade in Mexico grew steadily from the 1930s to 1970s, prompting
aggressive crop eradication campaigns by the U.S. and Mexican governments,
which led to plummeting supplies of illicit drugs. However, despite the
apparent success of these operations, crop eradication in Mexico was matched
with a boost in drug production in Colombia (Smith 1999, 195). The growth
of the Colombian cocaine industry quickly turned Mexican territory into
the most important trafficking route to the United States and strengthened
connections between Mexican and Colombian DTOs. This new role for
Mexican DTOs as cocaine traffickers increased the stakes of territorial control,
leading to violent tensions among cartels and today’s gruesome drug war
(ibid.; Carpenter 2003). The moment Calderón took office in December 2006,
he was explicit about one of his highest priorities: to confront the cartels and
end their control over much of Mexico’s landscape.
Calderón’s strategy was to mobilize the country’s army and security
forces with the goal of dismantling the cartels. Within months of assuming
his presidency, he deployed 45,000 troops in the most affected states,
including Chihuahua, Michoacán, and Sinaloa (Olson and Wilson 2010, 3).
Instead of reducing crime and violence, increased tensions among DTOs and
government officials led to an explosion of drug-related deaths, the number
of which has grown dramatically since the Mérida Initiative was launched.
Since 2007, there have been over 50,000 drug related deaths in Mexico, mostly
along northern border towns (Molzahn, Ríos, and Shirk 2012, 1). This violence
represents a direct threat to state security and U.S.–Mexican relations. Eric
67
Olson and Christopher Wilson (2010, 3) explain that “as violence increased,
so did U.S. concern about its neighbor and most important trading partner,
as well as trepidation about the impact of violence on communities along
the U.S. side of the border.” This fear led Bush and Calderón to develop the
Mérida Initiative to combat drug trafficking. This commitment provides
military and law enforcement equipment, training, and assistance in technical
operations, among other things, over a three-year period. Since entering office
in January 2009, U.S. President Barack Obama has expanded the discussion
into what is called “Beyond Mérida,” which continues the initial strategy and
includes four pillars: disrupting and dismantling DTOs; institutionalizing the
rule of law; building a 21st-century border; and building strong and resilient
communities (ibid., 4–5).
In essence, despite improvements aspired to in “Beyond Mérida,” both
of these agreements still suggest a prioritization of state security over human
security. In both instances, the majority of funds are directed toward military
assistance, crop eradication, and narcotics control, whereas only a small
percentage is dedicated to social programs and assistance. By increasing the
role of the military in anti-drug missions, both Colombia and Mexico have
created militarized societies in which the security of civilians is compromised.
As Simon Wells (2006, 52) argues: “Not only did the dealers not fear the
war on drugs, but they positively counted on it in order to increase market
prices and weed out smaller rivals. We therefore have a classic example of
how excessive militarization of security is counterproductive both relative to
its stated objectives and in that it makes the safety of individuals ever more
precarious.” He (ibid.) elaborates that this militaristic approach to illicit drugs
continues to ignore the mobility and flexibility of drug cultivation illustrated
by the interconnectedness of the drug trade between Colombia, Mexico, and
their neighbours. Contrary to its goals, the War on Drugs has contributed
to the development of more decentralized, complex, and ruthless DTOs,
rendering the role of identifying and confronting them all the more difficult
and dangerous for military officials and civilians.

A Failed War: Human Security Implications of the War


on Drugs
The drug trade in both Colombia and Mexico is linked to a complex web
of factors that have allowed the industry to grow and fester as a violent
and debilitating war, including issues of underdevelopment and weak
institutions. As Ralph Seccombe (1997, 288) writes, “[T]he illegality of crops
like coca, opium poppy and marijuana tends to push their production into
territories where law enforcement is weak. This generally means developing
countries – typically poor countries which have significant internal security
problems.” Echoing Hampson’s above-mentioned “other conditions”
argument, it can therefore be deduced that the insecurity, which has led to
thousands of casualties in Colombia and Mexico, is exacerbated by these
68
countries’ underlying socio-economic and political conditions.7 The policies
of the War on Drugs have failed to address the underlying factors of the drug
trade, instead focusing on combating DTOs, a worthy though incomplete
approach. By adopting a human security approach to the War on Drugs
and drawing on the categories described by the UNDP report, the following
section questions the effectiveness of the current policies and highlights the
ways they have failed to ensure human security in Colombia and Mexico by
inadequately addressing the countries’ underlying conditions that allow the
drug industry to grow.

Economic and political security

Both Colombia and Mexico bear high levels of poverty, unemployment, and
economic inequality. These socio-economic conditions, along with weak
political and judicial institutions, foster an environment in which drug
cultivation and trafficking are not only possible, but for many have become
attractive or necessary options to meet basic needs. It is estimated that over
80,000 Colombian families rely on illicit crop cultivation for their livelihoods
(UNODC 2011a). The economic incentive is clear: “[A]s long as the price for
coca leaves is ten times as high as that for cocoa, coffee, and rice for Andean
farmers, they will continue to cultivate it” (Diego Garcia Savan in Wells 2006,
60). In this sense, drug trafficking effectively provides economic security,
simply defined in the UNDP report as “assured basic income” (UNDP
1994, 25). Those without economic security often accept any work they can
find, including informal work, badly paid, or unproductive work. Informal
employment could be as high as 50 per cent in Colombia and 30 per cent in
Mexico (World Bank 2012), which undoubtedly leads to increased economic
insecurity and related problems such as criminal activity and migration.
In its effort to eradicate drug trafficking, the War on Drugs threatens
the economic security of thousands of individuals in Colombia and Mexico
who depend on the illegal but profitable drug industry for their livelihoods.
As Peterson (2002, 437) explains, attempts to implement crop substitution
programs through alternative development initiatives in Colombia have
been met with numerous geographical, ecological, and climate-related
obstacles. Many villages are too far removed from market access points, a
situation made worse by the mountainous topography, making it difficult
to sell alternative crops, and there are few profitable types of legal crops that
can grow in the rocky soil of the Andes. Conversely, coca plants can grow
very easily—they become productive within two years—and the expertly
established drug trafficking channels allow products to move very quickly
(ibid., 428, 437). Plan Colombia failed to take these factors into account in
its crop eradication campaigns and many drug-producing regions in Mexico
continue to lack sufficient funding for alternative development initiatives. As
such, the cultivation of illicit crops and the salaries of sicarios (cartel hit men)
continue to be very attractive in the face of unemployment and poverty (Kelly,
Maghan, and Serio 2005; Hill 2010). However, as Wells (2006, 57) indicates,
69
“this does not necessarily imply that the US should support these industries
. . . [rather,] they should be aware of the extent to which people’s economic
security is linked to drug cultivation and . . . the importance of offering them
[viable] alternative economic opportunities.”
In this light, it is clear that drug policies should focus more on economic
security by addressing problems of poverty, inequality, and unemployment.
By maintaining a narrow perspective on the drug industry as a threat to
state security, rather than a problem related to underdevelopment or socio-
economic conditions, the War on Drugs continues to neglect the roots of the
drug industry. Writing about the Mexican context, Vanda Felbab-Brown
(2010, 7) supports this reconceptualization of security: “Addressing the socio-
economic needs of the marginalized areas of both the northern urban belt
as well as southern rural areas is critical for reducing the recruitment pool
for the DTOs, severing the bonds between marginalized communities and
criminal elements, and resurrecting the hope of many Mexican citizens that
the Mexican State and legal behavior can best advance their future.” Felbab-
Brown also underscores one of the most important factors in Mexico’s strategy:
the bulk of the anti-drug activities are taking place in northern Mexico’s
troubled states, but little action is being addressed in the southern states or
poorer communities of the country. A similar situation occurred in Colombia,
where security conditions improved in major cities, but rural communities—
particularly in the Puntomayo region—have seen little progress.
Much like economic insecurity, political insecurity contributes to the
drug trade and is exacerbated as a consequence of the War on Drugs. Political
security is defined as a person’s ability to “live in a society that honours
their basic rights” (UNDP 1994, 32), meaning the protection of human rights
and the absence of political repression. According to UNDP (ibid., 33), one
of the most important indicators of political insecurity is the “priority the
government accords military strength.” Both Colombia and Mexico opted to
address the drug war with military intervention, resulting in the emergence
of a range of issues such as corruption and human rights violations. The
report also adds that political insecurity is most common in periods of unrest
(ibid., 32). Colombia faced decades of political violence and instability until
the 1980s, while in Mexico the Partido Revolucionario Institucional dominated
Mexican politics for 71 years until the election of Fox in 2000. Both countries
experienced an unstable transition to democracy, which allowed space for
crime to grow (Carpenter 2003; Melo 1998). Seccombe (1997, 291) argues that it
is common for fragile democracies to experience “significant conflict between
the illegal drug industry’s goals and behaviours and . . . government’s
attempts to democratize the political and social systems, leading to violence
and increased ungovernability.” Upon democratization, both Colombia and
Mexico had no choice but to confront DTOs and in both cases the countries
entered into conflicts that have increased instability. This argument is
echoed by James Fearon and David Laitin (2003, 76), who hypothesize that
“financially, organizationally, and politically weak central governments
render insurgency more feasible and attractive due to weak local policing
70
or inept and corrupt counterinsurgency practices.” Aggressive policies
implemented by both countries, then, are actually a reflection of structural
weaknesses in the face of powerful DTOs and popular discontent (Felbab-
Brown 2010, 6, 21). In this sense, military intervention, as a reflection of political
insecurity, is contributing to the very existence of the narcotics industry by
bolstering political discontent within its borders, further weakening the state.
Conversely, a human security approach built on prioritizing basic rights and
strengthening government institutions could help address some of the issues
associated with political insecurity.
It is impossible to deny that DTOs are the first cause of political insecurity
in this context. Their presence and the violent conflicts they provoke greatly
impede government functions while also aggravating persistent problems of
transparency and impunity in relation to crime, human rights abuses, and
corruption. Despite efforts by the Colombian and Mexican governments
to reduce corruption, numerous government officials, police officers, and
military personnel continue to collaborate with DTOs. Governments have not
sufficiently focused on the problem of corruption and its role in exacerbating
the drug trade (Seccombe 1997, 28). Corruption has tremendous impacts
on a population’s domestic political security and severely infringes upon
Colombia and Mexico’s civil rights by rendering the political system tainted
and undemocratic as individuals affiliated with the drug trade could enter into
politics through threats, money laundering, or even meddling with electoral
campaigns. Furthermore, it undermines confidence in the state judicial
system and aggravates impunity as a growing number of crimes and human
rights abuses go unaddressed (Amnesty International 2009). Corruption also
threatens the population’s right to information when journalists face either
censorship by the government or bribes by cartels to alter information about
drug-related crimes in favour of their respective interests (Estévez 2010, 6–7).
The seriousness of corruption leads Ted Carpenter (2003, 180) to argue that
“the degree of penetration of law enforcement by [DTOs renders] supposed
antidrug efforts in Mexico farcical.”
Like corruption, drug trafficking permeates national borders and
impacts Colombia and Mexico’s relations with other countries. As Seccombe
(1997, 292–93) argues, in addition to the harm done by conflict, U.S. anti-drug
policies can have international ramifications through impacts on economic,
political, and strategic affairs. For instance, Roderic Ai Camp (2010) and
Carpenter (2003) discuss the formidable challenge of reconciling U.S.
demands with Mexican interests in the War on Drugs due to the complex and
tense history between the two countries. The authors note that this history,
distinguished by the supremacy of U.S. interests over Mexican interests,
results in mistrust and animosity between the Mexican and U.S. militaries,
and that many Mexicans perceive the War on Drugs to be an American
war against drug consumption being fought in Mexico with Mexican
resources and against the Mexican people. The same can be argued about
Colombians (ibid., 22). In effect, the War on Drugs also has severe domestic
policy implications by eroding state funds and shifting focus away from
71
social services and programs, including rural development policies, toward
increased militarization of the country. This constitutes one of the main
paradoxes of current anti-drug policies: they demand sacrifices to the human
component, including human rights, when these problems are at the root of
the drug war. The human security approach, on the other hand, complements
national security policies with social policies by taking into account the
human component of the drug war.
The War on Drugs is compromising economic security through its crop
eradication campaigns, high security costs, and underfunded alternative
development programs. In addition, corruption, national and international
political tensions, and the neglect of larger social and political conditions
are eroding political security in both Colombia and Mexico. It is crucial for
the governments of both countries to collaborate with the United States to
address their weaknesses by strengthening institutions and re-evaluating the
alternative development component of their drug policies. In doing so, they
could better target deeper issues that allow the drug trade to succeed within
their borders.

Environmental, health, and food security

Environmental, health, and food security are inextricably linked to economic,


personal, and community security as each inherently feeds into healthy living
and sustainable livelihoods. Crop eradication campaigns not only compromise
the economic security of crop cultivators and small-scale farmers in Colombia
and Mexico, but also have widespread ramifications that severely undermine
these three forms of human security by causing forced displacement of
farming communities, environmental damage, and disruption of traditional
livelihoods. Since aerial crop spraying is not a component of the Mérida
Initiative in Mexico, this section will focus on the devastating environmental
and social impacts of crop eradication campaigns in Colombia.
Environmental security means having access to a “healthy physical
environment” (UNDP 1994, 28). The biggest threats to environmental
security, presented by crop eradication, include water scarcity, environmental
degradation, contamination, deforestation, and access to land. Peterson
(2002, 433) provides extensive details on the environmental impacts of a non-
selective toxic herbicide called glyphosate, commonly known as Monsanto’s
Roundup, used in aerial crop spraying under Plan Colombia (UNODC 2008,
101). Targeting illicit crops when sprayed, the herbicide is often carried by
wind and water streams, destroying thousands of hectares of legal crops
along the way. For example, officials in the Colombian state of Puntomayo
note that more than 30,000 hectares of legal crops were destroyed within
six weeks of aerial spraying in 2001 (Peterson 2002, 431). The destruction of
both legal and illicit crops forces farmers to seek new, uncontaminated land.
In the case of illicit plants like coca, the displacement of crops often leads
DTOs to seek more distant and hidden spaces in forests and isolated areas of
the country. David Olsen, director of the World Wildlife Fund conservation
72
science program, states that “for every hectare of forest sprayed, another is
lost to pesticide drift and another to additional clearing to compensate for
displaced crops” (cited in ibid., 433). It is estimated that over 81,000 hectares
of land are dedicated to coca cultivation in Colombia alone (UNODC 2010b,
228), potentially infringing on one of the world’s most beautiful landscapes
endowed with rich and varied biodiversity among the Amazon Forest,
Andes mountains, and Caribbean and Pacific coastlines. This displacement
threatens wildlife and the livelihoods of more individuals, and hinders other,
more productive uses of the land such as agriculture and tourism. A human
security approach would eliminate harmful crop eradication techniques and
could include greater environmental protection policies.
In addition to deforestation and contamination, toxic herbicides such
as glyphosate have damaging effects on human health security, defined as
a life free from disease and access to good nutrition, health services, and a
safe environment (UNDP 1994, 27). Human exposure to the spray can cause
“headaches and dizziness as well as eye, respiratory, skin and digestive
problems . . . and ingestion may cause diarrhea, shortness of breath, vomiting,
and weakness” (Peterson 2002, 433). People are undoubtedly exposed to this
herbicide through soil and water contamination and food sources such as
dairy products. The Colombian government downplayed these damaging
impacts on health and, despite evidence of glyphosate’s toxicity, continued
to use the product throughout Plan Colombia with the highest concentration
of aerial spraying campaigns occurring in the Puntomayo region between
1998 and 2007 (UNODC 2008). According to UNODC’s World Drug Report
2011, over 100,000 hectares of Colombian coca fields are still sprayed every
year (UNODC 2011b, 245). In addition, other means of crop eradication in
both Colombia and Mexico, including field burning, persist and continue to
jeopardize the economic security of those who depend on these crops. Crop
spraying should never have been part of the plan, as it was an expensive and
harmful initiative with trivial impacts on the global drug trade.
Aside from water and land contamination and widespread
deforestation, crop eradication also negatively impacts food security (Peterson
2002, 430; Ramírez 2011, 222; Wells 2006, 55). Food security is understood here
as “all people at all times [having] both physical and economic access to food”
(UNDP 1994, 27). Crop eradication destroys some of the Andean region’s
most important food sources, including fish, livestock, and plants valuable
to surrounding communities. For instance, the coca plant is nutritionally,
medicinally, and spiritually important for Andean indigenous communities
who consume it by chewing the leaves or ingesting it in the form of tea
(Peterson 2002, 430; Ramírez 2011, 55).8 The dangers of the drug conflicts
have compromised many regions’ access to health care, markets, and stable
employment, forcing populations to rely on indigenous traditions and local
food supplies for their health and well-being. As mentioned above, many
profitable legal crops cannot grow in the rocky soil of mountainous terrain.
Furthermore, accessing markets to sell crops is complicated by distance and
inadequate infrastructure, such as a lack of communications technology
73
and poor road conditions. Rather than investing in crop eradication, the
government should increase investment in infrastructure development that
facilitates access to markets and health care, as well as increase investment
in social safety nets, alternative development programs, and local agriculture
that together enhance economic, environmental, health, and food security.
By threatening environmental, health, and food security, the War
on Drugs threatens livelihoods and exacerbates problems of poor market
access, poverty, and internal displacement. Therefore, crop eradication as
promoted by the War on Drugs cannot be divorced from economic security.
By stopping crop eradication policies, particularly with toxic herbicides such
as glyphosate, governments can support these essential forms of security and
ensure a healthier environment for various communities. By prioritizing these
forms of human security over the unsustainable destruction of illicit crops,
governments can focus on developing real, long-term alternatives based on
licit crop cultivation and better market access. By improving livelihoods,
countries would have fewer families relying on or turning to the drug trade
for subsistence, thus abating the intensity of the drug conflicts. To this day,
the state security approach has failed to generate such results.

Personal and community security

Over 50,000 people have lost their lives in Mexico since 2007 (Molzahn, Ríos,
and Shirk 2012, 1) and an estimated 230,000 individuals have fled the gun-
ridden northern border towns (IDMC 2010a). In Colombia, approximately
16,000 lives were lost in 2008 because of drug-related violence (UNODC
2010a, 10), the lowest tally in over two decades—still far too many—and over
200,000 individuals are leaving their homes every year, with total estimates
ranging from three million to five million people in the past 25 years (IDMC
2010b). The primary cause of these casualties and displacements is the
violence brought on by the drug wars, yet the impact of crop eradication and
the failure of the War on Drugs to improve personal and community security
in Colombia and Mexico are also to blame. This section will focus mainly on
Mexico due to the contemporary nature of the conflict, but it should be noted
that Colombia continues to deal with human rights violations, displacements,
and violence to this day.
Personal security refers to freedom from physical harm, including
political violence and human rights abuses, while community security is
defined as the freedom of association to a group that can provide cultural
identity, support, and protection (UNDP 1994, 30–31). A report by the
Internal Displacement Monitoring Centre (IDMC 2010a) demonstrates
how the War on Drugs can impact these forms of security by arguing that
Mexican authorities are failing to “acknowledge, assess or document the
needs of the people displaced, instead focusing their efforts on fighting the
drug cartels.” These displacements present severe threats to personal and
community security since violence tears apart or destroys entire families and
communities. Governments’ inability to provide for their needs and to prevent
74
displacements further jeopardizes these forms of human security. As Peterson
(2002, 435) argues, the “destabilization of Colombian [and Mexican] society
and culture through the escalation of civil war and the inflation of an already
enormous internal refugee population are further consequences of drug war
policy.” The human security approach would aim to reduce the number of
displacements through less militarized and more socio-economically aimed
policies and bolster state institutions to embody programs that help and
protect the displaced.
The main actors responsible for a climate of personal insecurity in this
context are undoubtedly DTOs; however, this insecurity is worsened by the
militarization of civic affairs. Recent reports by Human Rights Watch (2011)
and Amnesty International (2009) denounce the rise in human rights violations
by the Mexican military participating in the fight against DTOs, echoing
similar concerns earlier in Colombia.9 According to Amnesty International
(ibid., 5), “there are increasing reports of serious human rights violations,
such as enforced disappearance, unlawful and extrajudicial killings, torture,
other ill-treatment and arbitrary detention being committed by members of
the Mexican military.” These abuses are committed against citizens across
Mexico believed to be directly involved or linked to the narcotics industry;
unfortunately, innocent civilians are often also victims. The report explains
that a growing number of complaints have been filed in Ciudad Juárez
and that “[t]hese new reports of human rights violations by the military .
. . occurred in the context of military law enforcement activities to support
civilian efforts to combat organized crime and drug cartels” (ibid., 6).
Similarly, Seccombe (1997, 291) reiterates that human rights are
frequent casualties of the War on Drugs, adding that, “the cultivation of the
illicit crop [like coca] may bring the farmers [who cultivate the crops] into
conflict with the authorities, who are under pressure to eradicate it. Human
rights abuses can then occur.” While security forces face some of the most
ruthless drug cartels in Latin America, working in dangerous conditions in
order to protect the Colombian and Mexican populations and integrity of the
state, they are also responsible for perpetuating abuses and overlooking their
investigations. A longstanding culture of impunity and the weakness of state
judicial systems mean that abuses are rarely investigated and perpetrators
seldom convicted. This leads to the continuation of criminality and growing
frustration against the government, thus fuelling the drug trade. A human
security approach would prioritize human rights protection and justice for
crimes committed.
The presence of military forces in the drug wars has also intensified
tensions between cartels and government officials. Increasing pressure from
the security forces and rival cartels has made DTOs more ruthless, violent,
and willing to resort to kidnappings, torture, and terrorism across Mexico,
such as the 2011 bomb attack in Monterrey, in order to create an environment
of fear and to gain territorial control. Furthermore, pressures in certain areas
of the country have resulted in DTOs invading other, more peaceful areas
such as Aguascalientes (Kellner and Pipitone 2010). The military may not be
75
directly responsible for these crimes, but its presence provokes conflict by
inviting more frequent and aggressive confrontations with DTOs. In the end,
civilians continue to suffer the burden of the War on Drugs.
Many individuals, including government officials, police officers,
farmers and ordinary civilians, tend to face dual pressures in this battle for
information and power. As Seccombe (1997, 292) writes, they face “the threat
of assassination or other violence, coupled with the offer of financial reward
for a favourable decision [in favour of cartel demands].” As a result, Colombia
and Mexico are left with corrupt, weak, untrusted governments and societies
paralyzed by impunity, crime, and associated social problems, all of which
compromise the security and well-being of individuals and communities. A
growing sense of fear, frustration, and mistrust is felt by Colombians and
Mexicans. The inability of the War on Drugs to assuage such feelings results
in personal and community insecurity. The current approach is so focused
on military action that it has failed to ensure these forms of security and has
actually led to human rights abuses, displacements, and deaths. A human
security approach in Colombia and Mexico would prioritize the safety of
populations and address socio-economic concerns and violence first.

Conclusion: Alternative Policy Options and the Need


to Admit Defeat
This article challenged common conceptions of security that guide the War on
Drugs as encapsulated in the two bilateral U.S. military assistance packages,
Plan Colombia and the Mérida Initiative. Anti-drug policies, which are
qualitatively very different but inexorably linked, need to be reconsidered in
Colombia, Mexico, and the United States, and there are countless suggestions
coming from every direction as to what the governments of these countries
should do. Organizations such as the International Narcotics Control Board
and many politicians in the United States have argued for more aggressive
military action and the enforcement of prohibition laws (Seccombe 1997,
295). Others like the Netherlands, Australia, Portugal, and human rights
organizations are increasingly promoting more progressive policies ranging
from the “conventional” harm reduction policies and alternative development
programs (Obokata 2007; Peterson 2002) to the “radical” free trade and full
legalization of all illicit drugs (Wells 2006). There are logical rationales for
each alternative, yet there is no clear solution to this complex transnational
problem. A limiting factor in the development of alternative policies is that
prohibition is deeply rooted in U.S. public discourse dating back over a century
(Jelsma 2011). Consequently, it will be difficult to promote any momentous
changes in policy, and whatever progress takes place will certainly happen
gradually.
In spite of this, and given the urgent nature of drug-related violence,
a growing number of experts, academics, and concerned individuals are
promoting accelerated policy changes. As seen in the June 2011 War on Drugs:
Report of the Global Commission on Drug Policy, recent attempts by U.S. states
76
such as California to legalize cannabis (McKinley 2010), and the emergence
of organizations like the Red por la Paz con Justicia y Dignidad10 in Mexico and
Common Sense for Drug Policy in Colombia, demand for an end to the War
on Drugs and the adoption of alternative anti-drug policies is increasing.
While the Obama administration continues to advance a prohibitionist and
militaristic approach on drugs, there have been significant steps forward
in drug policy approaches in both Colombia and Mexico (Jelsma 2011).
Recently, for example, Calderón adopted an anti-corruption initiative that the
Colombian government initiated in 2000 by dismissing hundreds of allegedly
corrupt individuals and increasing police officers’ salaries to minimize the
incentives of corruption (ibid.; Kellner and Pipitone 2010). Numerous media
reports show that government officials are beginning to acknowledge the
weaknesses of the War on Drugs and are engaging more with civil society
and experts to explore alternative policies. Although these are important
developments, they are incomplete, mostly rhetorical, and insufficient.
Daily media coverage of drug-related violence, especially in Mexico,
means that anti-drug policies have become a leading political issue and were
undoubtedly a deciding factor in the July 2012 Mexican and will be, though
to a lesser degree, in the U.S. elections. Anti-drug policies certainly played a
pivotal role in the 2010 Colombian presidential election, when Colombians
elected Juan Manuel Santos, former president Alvaro Uribe’s minister of
national defense, as president with 69 per cent of the vote. Much like his
predecessor, Santos will continue taking a hard-line approach against rebels
and DTOs (McDermott 2010), demonstrating that this approach still appeals
to a large portion of the population. This is explained by the fact that crime
rates in Colombian cities have fallen drastically since Uribe’s entry into
office because of increased military presence in those cities (UNODC 2010a).
However, crime reduction in cities does not translate into crime reduction in
rural parts of Colombia, such as the still violent Puntomayo region, and much
less into a victory over crime, violence, and other factors such as poverty
and corruption nationwide. In addition, the UNODC notes that despite a 58
per cent reduction in Colombian coca production between 2000 and 2009,
production has increased by 112 per cent in Bolivia and 38 per cent in Peru,
negating much of the progress in Colombia (UNODC 2010c, 20). This example
demonstrates the need for better coordinated regional strategies.
To effectively combat drug crime within their borders, Colombia and
Mexico also need to broaden and diversify their national strategies. Given the
success in reducing crime in Colombian cities, a continuation of multifaceted
action, including the establishment of a national research, analysis, and
strategic bodies, such as the Government of Colombia’s Dirección de Justicia,
Seguridad y Gobierno, to better understand DTOs and the drug trade, could
contribute to safer cities in Mexico and be replicated in different settings in Latin
America. To avoid the balloon effect, whereby drug production and violence
are merely displaced to other territories, military efforts must be matched
with national socio-economic policies along the lines of improvements in
education, economic productivity, small-scale agriculture, and employment
77
opportunities, all well-known concerns in Mexican society. By addressing
issues of economic and food security and improving standards of living
and capacity building in rural communities, there will be fewer incentives
to be or get involved in criminal activities, and personal and community
security will improve. For instance, investments in crop substitution, small-
scale farming, and the elimination of aerial spraying campaigns could help
prevent the future growth of the drug trade. Moreover, the Colombian and
Mexican governments need to continue their efforts to combat corruption
and better address problems of impunity and human rights violations by
adopting a human security approach to drug policies. The establishment of
effective judicial reforms11 to bring crimes to justice create a stronger sense of
confidence, trust, and security across those countries.
It has become increasingly clear that the United States and other
consuming countries need to acknowledge their pivotal role in the drug
trade. As long as demand remains high, supply will continue to flow to these
markets and the violence will not stop (Wells 2006; Global Commission on
Drug Policy 2011). As Zedillo argued at the 20th Special Session of the UN
General Assembly in 1998: “The human, social, and institutional costs in
meeting [demands for illicit drugs] are paid for by the producing and transit
countries. It is our men and women who die first in combating drug trafficking.
It is our communities that are first to suffer from violence, our institutions
that are first to be undermined by corruption. It is our governments that
are the first bulwark in this war” (Carpenter 2003, 213). Indeed, the United
States accounts for nearly 40 per cent of the global demand for cocaine, worth
approximately US$37 billion (UNODC 2010c, 20). If the U.S. government is
going to wage war against DTOs across its border, it is imperative that efforts
be matched with initiatives on U.S. soil. Programs such as Hope, adopted
in a number of states, including Hawaii, Alaska, Arizona, California, and
Washington, have delivered positive outcomes and shown proven reductions
in drug use, criminal activity and incarceration (Kleiman 2011, 97).12 Mark
Kleiman (ibid.) argues that “if Hope were to be [systematically] implemented
. . . the resulting reduction in drug use could shrink the market—and thus the
revenue of Mexico’s [DTOs]—by as much as 40 percent.” The United States
could reduce demand at home through such evidence-based treatment and
engage more freely with the decriminalization and legalization debates and
policy alternatives, looking at Europe for inspiration, where Portugal and the
Netherlands have successfully implemented drug decriminalization policies.
Since decriminalizing drugs, Portugal has effectively solved its problem
of overcrowded prisons and dramatically reduced the country’s drug
consumption levels (Jelsma 2011, 9). Unfortunately, legalization is not on the
political agenda due to a range of social conventions and security concerns
that dominate the U.S. Congress. However, what the United States could
feasibly do, according to Kleiman, is better focus its security efforts on the
most violent cartel, largely agreed to be the Zetas, or violence players within
the cartels. In other words, promote differential law enforcement. Kleiman
(2011, 98) argues that “[b]y focusing drug-dealing arrests, prosecutions, and
78
prison terms on the most violent individuals and groups, governments can
achieve the double benefit of incapacitating the worst actors and deterring the
rest—not from drug dealing (an incarcerated or deterred dealer will merely
be replaced) but from violence, or from the flagrant dealing practices that
give rise to violence and disorder.” These are two valid examples of how the
United States can act as a world leader on drug policies that other countries
around the world could emulate. The United States should collaborate with
a greater number of countries and civil society organizations to find the best
combination of military, economic, political, and social policies. At the core
of the drug trade are profound social, economic, and political issues that are
beyond the range of crop spraying or soldiers in the streets of Ciudad Juárez.
The United States has been fighting the War on Drugs for 40 years and for
40 years it has failed. It is time to implement new policies rooted in human
security principles and geared above all to end the brutal violence suffered
across Colombia and Mexico.
79
Notes
1. The “War on Drugs” refers to the specific U.S. anti-drug policies carried out
in Colombia and Mexico, while “drug war” refers to the battle between cartels
for power and control in these countries, encapsulating all the violence,
terrorism, and criminal activities associated with “turf wars.”
2. By focusing on U.S. policies, this article seeks to emphasize the powerful
role of the United States as the main proponent of prohibition and author of
the War on Drugs. It also focuses on Colombia and Mexico because they have
been the main theatre of the War on Drugs. Their experiences and policies are
deeply interlinked, and they both serve to demonstrate the adverse effects
of aggressive policies originating from the War on Drugs. However, it is
important to note that the War on Drugs expands beyond these three countries.
Since the 1970s, the United States has pressured countries around the world
such as Jamaica, Nigeria, Burma, Haiti, and Venezuela. U.S. anti-drug policies
have included military missions, efforts to tighten drug laws, increasing
arrest quotas, and applying sanctions to countries which have adopted more
relaxed policies. Currently, the country is implementing similarly aggressive
policies against poppy cultivation in Afghanistan. Europe, Canada, and
Australia were all reluctant to join the War on Drugs and have generally more
relaxed policies, particularly in recent years (Jelsma 2011).
3. Other key documents include former UN secretary-general Boutros Boutros-
Ghali’s 1992 report An Agenda for Peace, the International Commission on
Intervention and State Sovereignty’s 2001 report, The Responsibility to Protect,
and the Commission on Human Security’s 2003 report Human Security Now.
4. Carpenter (2003, 114–18) refers to “push-down, pop up” policies, also
known as the “balloon effect,” whereby declines in Mexican marijuana
production during the 1980s were matched with an increase in Colombian
production of marijuana. In other words, no matter how efficient policies are
in one region, the production of drugs tends to relocate elsewhere. Following
this logic, many are sceptical about the Mérida Initiative’s success in Mexico.
5. Plan Colombia’s breakdown in 2001: US$1.02 billion for bilateral economic
assistance; US$184 million for defense operations; US$180 million for
assistance to Peru, Bolivia, and Ecuador; US$70 million for the regional
operations of the U.S. Treasury Department and U.S. Customs and Border
Protection; approximately 75 per cent of the rest of the aid was directed
toward the Colombian military and police, including US$330 million in
aid allocations; the remaining 25 per cent was earmarked for alternative
development, refugee aid, human rights protection, judicial reform, law
enforcement, and the peace process (Peterson 2002, 431).
6. The 2011 Mérida Initiative budget requested US$346 million in foreign
assistance to Mexico. Its breakdown is as follows: US$26.3 million for
development assistance; US$10 million in economic support; US$8 million in
military financing; US$3.5 million in global health and child survival; US$1.1
million in military education and training; US$292 million in International
Narcotics Control and Law Enforcement programs; and US$5.7 million for
80
non-proliferation, antiterrorism, demining, and related programs (Olson and
Wilson 2010, 4).
7. It is important to note that drug production does not only take place
in developing countries and there are high rates of drug cultivation and
production in developed countries. For example, Canada is the world leader
in methamphetamine production (UNODC 2008, 127).
8. Peterson (2002, 430) highlights some of the important nutritional values of
the coca plant: “It contains an abundance of certain vitamins and minerals,
including calcium, and its mastication provides an important supplement
to many local diets, which may be deficient of vital nutrients . . . Chewing
the coca leafs also suppresses the appetite, which is important in societies
with unstable food supplies, and helps to mitigate the deleterious effects
of high altitude on the human body. [Many] indigenous societies have also
recognized and utilized its psychotropic qualities in medicinal and religious
activities.”
9. According to Amnesty International’s (2011) report, in 2008 there were
1,230 official complaints of human rights abuses by the military filed to the
National Human Rights Commission, a significant rise from 367 complaints
in 2007 and 182 complaints in 2006. Countless more abuses go unreported.
Also, the number of complaints that have been investigated and individuals
that have been convicted remains alarmingly low.
10. The Red por la Paz con Justicia y Dignidad is a Mexican civil society
organization, which includes concerned individuals like Javier Sicilia, a
renowned Mexican poet who works to raise awareness about human security
implications of the War on Drugs and advocates for alternative drug policies.
The movement’s motto is “No Mas Sangre” (“No More Blood”).
12. Judicial reforms are currently under way in Mexico, being carried through
with the assistance of the United States, Canada, and the European Union
and in collaboration with the Organization of American States. There has
been some progress in training judges and lawyers, but real change remains
a much deeper cultural and long-term challenge.
13. The Hope program involves random drug testing with guaranteed short
jail sentences (a few days) for detected use and includes positive incentives
(reduction in testing frequency) for those with repeatedly clean tests. Those
who test positive are forced to stop using drugs or face longer incarceration
periods. In Hawaii, the program succeeded in getting 80 per cent its long-
term methamphetamine users clean and out of confinement in one year. By
reducing incarceration rates, the program effectively pays for itself (Kleiman
2011).

Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Dr. Marie-Eve Desrosiers for her insightful feedback
and encouragements with this project as well as Dr. Stephen Baranyi for his
ongoing support of my research endeavours.
81
References
Ai Camp, Roderic. 2010. “Armed Forces and Drugs: Public Perceptions and
Institutional Challenges.” In Shared Responsibility: U.S.-Mexico Policy
Options for Confronting Organized Crime, edited by Eric L. Olson, David
A. Shirk, and Andrew Selee, 291–326. Washington, DC: Woodrow
Wilson Press.
Amnesty International. 2009. Mexico: New Reports of Human Rights Violation
by the Military. London: Amnesty International Publications.
———. 2011. “Columbia.” In Annual Report 2011: The State of the World’s
Human Rights, 108–112. London: Amnesty International Publications.
http://www.amnesty.org/en/region/colombia/report-2011.
Balzacq, Thierry. 2003-2004. « Qu’est-ce que la sécurité nationale? » Revue
internationale et stratégique 52 : 33-50.
Bowden, Charles. 2010. “Charles Bowden on ‘Murder City: Ciudad Juarez and
the Global Economy’s New Killing Fields.’” Interview by Democracy
Now, April 14. http://www.democracynow.org/2010/4/14/charles_bowden_
murder_city_ciudad_jurez.
Carpenter, Ted. 2003. Bad Neighbor Policy: Washington’s Futile War on Drugs in
Latin America. New York: Palgrave MacMillan.
Duffield, Mark, and Nicholas Waddell. 2006. “Securing Humans in a
Dangerous World.” International Politics 43 (1): 1–23.
Estévez, Dolia. 2010. “Protecting Press Freedom in an Environment of
Violence and Impunity.” In Shared Responsibility: U.S.-Mexico Policy
Options for Confronting Organized Crime, edited by Eric L. Olson,
David A. Shirk, and Andrew Selee, 271–289. Washington DC: Mexico
Institute, Woodrow Wilson Center for International Scholars.
Fearon, James, and David Laitin. 2003. “Ethnicity, Insurgency, and Civil
War.” American Political Science Review 97 (1): 75–90.
Felbab-Brown, Vanda. 2010. “Stemming the Violence in Mexico, but
Breaking the Cartels.” George Mason University Center for Infrastructure
Protection and Human Security Report 9 (3): 5–7.
Global Commission on Drug Policy. 2011. War on Drugs: Report of the Global
Commission on Drug Policy. Rio de Janeiro: Centro Edelstein
Publications.
Hampson, Fen. 2004. “A Concept in Need of Global Policy Response.”
Security Dialogue 35 (3): 349–50.
Hill, Sarah. 2010. “The World for Drugs: How Juarez became the Deadliest
City.” Boston Review, July/August. http://bostonreview.net/BR35.4/hill.
php.
Human Rights Watch. 2011. “Mexico.” World Report 2011: Events of 2010.
New York: Human Rights Watch. http://www.hrw.org/en/world-
report-2011/mexico.
IDMC (Internal Displacement Monitoring Centre). 2010a. “Briefing
Paper by the Norwegian Refugee Council’s Internal Displacement
Monitoring Centre on Forced Displacement in Mexico due to Drug
82
Cartel Violence.” IDMC Briefing, December. http://www.internal-
displacement.org/briefing/mexico.
———. 2010b. “Colombia: Government Response Improves but Still Fails to
Meet Needs of Growing IDP population.” December 10. http://www.
internal-displacement.org/8025708F004BE3B1/(httpInfoFiles)/4BCA7D
F31521CC16C12577F5002CED98/$file/Colombia_Overview_Dec2010.
pdf.
Isacson, Adam, and Abigail Poe. 2009. “After Plan Colombia: Evaluating
‘Integrated Action,’ the Next Phase of U.S. Assistance.” International
Policy Report. December. Washington, DC: Center for International
Policy. http://justf.org/files/pubs/091203_col.pdf.
Jelsma, Martin. 2011. “The Development of International Drug Control:
Lessons Learned and Strategic Challenges for the Future.” Working
paper prepared for the First Meeting of the Commission, Global
Commission on Drug Policy, Geneva, January 24–25. http://www.
globalcommissionondrugs.org/wp-content/themes/gcdp_v1/pdf/
Global_Com_Martin_Jelsma.pdf.
Kellner, Tomas, and Francesco Pipitone. 2010. “Inside Mexico’s Drug War.”
World Policy Journal 27 (1): 30.
Kelly, Robert J., Jess Maghan, and Joseph D. Serio. 2005. Illicit Trafficking: A
Reference Handbook. Santa Barbara: ABC-CLIO.
Kleiman, Mark. 2011. “Surgical Strikes in the Drug Wars: Smarter Policies
for Both Sides of the Border.” Foreign Affairs 90 (5): 89–101.
Leech, Garry M. 2002. Killing Peace: Colombia’s Conflict and the Failure of U.S.
Intervention. New York: Information Network of the Americas.
Livingstone, Grace. 2003. Inside Colombia: Drugs, Democracy and War. London:
Latin American Bureau.
McDermott, Jeremy. 2010. “Government Candidate Santos Wins Colombia
Election.” BBC News, June 21. http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/10362250.
McKinley, Jesse. 2010. “Battle Over California Marijuana Initiative Goes
Down to the Wire.” New York Times, October 30. http://www.nytimes.
com/2010/10/31/us/politics/31pot.html.
Melo, Jorge Orlando. 1998. “The Drug Trade, Politics and the Economy: The
Colombian Experience.” In Latin America the Multinational Drug Trade,
edited by Elizabeth Joyce and Carlos Malamud, 63–98. New York:
MacMillan Press.
Molzahn, Cory, Viridiana Ríos, and David A. Shirk. 2012. “Drug Violence in
Mexico: Data and Analysis Through 2011.” San Diego: Trans-Border
Institute, University of San Diego.
Obokata, Tom. 2007. “Illicit Cycle of Narcotics from a Human Rights
Perspective.” Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights 25 (2): 159–88.
Olson, Eric L., and Christopher E. Wilson. 2010. “Beyond Merida: The
Evolving Approach to Security Cooperation.” Working Paper on
U.S.-Mexico Security Cooperation, May. Washington, DC: Woodrow
Wilson Center for International Scholars. http://www.wilsoncenter.
org/sites/default/files/Beyond%20Merida.pdf.
83
Owen, Taylor. 2004. “Human Security – Conflict, Critique and Consensus:
Colloquial Remarks and a Proposal for Threshold-Based Definition.”
Security Dialogue 35 (3): 373–87.
Paris, Roland. 2001. “Human Security: Paradigm Shift or Hot Air?”
International Security 26 (2): 87–102.
Peterson, Sarah. 2002. “People and Ecosystems in Colombia: Casualties of
the Drug War.” Independent Review 6 (3): 427–40.
Ramírez, María Clemencia. 2011. Between the Guerrillas and the State: The
Cocalero Movement, Citizenship, and Identity in the Colombian Amazon.
Durham: Duke University Press.
Seccombe, Ralph. 1997. “Troublesome Boomerang: Illicit Drug Policy and
Security.” Security Dialogue 28 (3): 287–99.
Singer, Merill. 2008. Drugs and Development: The Global Impact on Sustainable
Growth and Human Rights. Long Grove: Waveland Press.
Smith, Peter H. 1999. “Semiorganized International Crime: Drug Trafficking
in Mexico.” In Transnational Crime in the Americas, edited by Tom
Farer, 193–216. New York: Routledge.
UNDP (United Nations Development Programme). 1994. Human
Development Report 1994: New Dimensions of Human Security. New
York: Oxford University Press.
UNODC (United Nations Office on Drugs And Crime). 2008. Coca Cultivation
in the Andean Region: A Survey of Colombia, Bolivia and Peru. Vienna:
UNODC Publications.
———. 2009. World Drug Report 2009. Vienna: United Nations Publications.
———. 2010a. Crime and Instability: Case Studies of Transnational Threat.
Vienna: United Nations Publications.
———. 2010b. The Globalization of Crime – A Transnational Organized Crime
Threat Assessment.
Vienna: United Nations Publications.
———. 2010c. World Drug Report 2010. Vienna: United Nations Publications.
———. 2011a. Colombia: From Illicit Drugs to Sustainable Livelihoods. Accessed
February 2012. http://www.unodc.org/unodc/en/frontpage/2011/
September/colombia_-from-illicit-drugs-to-sustainable-livelihoods.
html.
———. 2011b. World Drug Report 2011. Vienna: United Nations Publications.
Wells, Simon. 2006. “A Human Security Approach to US Illegal Drugs
Policy.” Human Security Journal 1: 51–64.
World Bank. 2012. “Data: Vulnerable Employment, Total (% of Total
Employment).” Accessed March 2012. http://data.worldbank.org/
indicator/SL.EMP.VULN.ZS.
85
Paterson Review of International Affairs (2012) 12: 85–107.

Beyond Rawls’s Law of Peoples: Freedom,


Capabilities, and Human Security
Marcel Sangsari
Norman Paterson School of International Affairs, Carleton University

This article considers whether the better-off have a duty of assistance


toward impoverished individuals or, from another angle, whether the
poorest are entitled to better conditions. The article looks through
normative and theoretical lenses to provide practical replies to “why?”,
“how (by what means)?”, and “how much?” international assistance
should be provided to individuals living in the least developed countries.
The article compares the requirements of global justice from Rawls’s
The Law of Peoples to those of the capabilities approach developed by
Nussbaum and Sen. It argues that Rawls’s duty of assistance and
human rights requirements are too limited given the needs of the bottom
billion, that shifting focus to capabilities centred on the freedom of the
individual helps to bridge the gap, and that ultimately, concurrent
advancement of human development, human rights, and human
security—what is referred to as a “capabilities-plus” approach—is
required to raise the capabilities of individuals within least developed
countries and of these countries. Guided by this approach, the article
offers policy recommendations, including the provision of international
aid based on the criteria of aid effectiveness, optimal aid allocation, and
practicality.

Introduction
While the gap in the United Nations Development Programme’s (UNDP)
Human Development Index (HDI)1 between developed and developing
countries narrowed by about a fifth between 1990 and 2010 and all but three
(the Democratic Republic of the Congo [DRC], Zambia, and Zimbabwe) of the
135 countries with available data had higher levels of human development in
2010 than in 1970, the “bottom movers” remain aplenty (UNDP 2010, 29–30).
This article focuses on the countries with low levels of human development,
or the “bottom billion” of humanity—70 per cent of whom live in Africa, a
smaller portion in Central Asia, and a scattering elsewhere (Collier 2007, 11).
It has three objectives. First it will assess whether the better-off have a duty of
assistance toward impoverished individuals or, from another angle, whether
the poorest are entitled to better conditions. Secondly, it will develop an
approach to guide policy-making in international assistance efforts. Finally, it
will recommend policies informed by this approach. This article looks through
86
normative and theoretical lenses and seeks to reconcile ethical, political, and
economic dimensions in replying to “why?”, “how (by what means)?”, and
“how much?” international assistance should be provided to individuals,
institutions, or governing bodies within the least developed countries
(LDCs). From an ethical dimension, it compares the requirements of global
justice from the Rawlsian and capability approaches. From the political and
economic dimensions, it seeks to match philosophical theory to the limits of
practicable possibility (Rawls 1999, 11) and to efficient outcomes, respectively.
The article begins by examining the duty of assistance and human rights
requirements from John Rawls’s The Law of Peoples. It then compares these to
arguments from Martha Nussbaum’s Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality,
Species Membership and Amartya Sen’s Development as Freedom and The Idea of
Justice. It argues that although The Law of Peoples presents important insights,
Rawls’s duty of assistance and human rights requirements are too limited
to address the needs of the bottom billion and, moreover, his international
social contract contains irreconcilable procedural problems. Focus should be
shifted to capabilities centred on the freedom of the individual. Ultimately,
concurrent advancement of human development, human rights, and human
security—what is here referred to as a “capabilities-plus” approach—is
required to raise the capabilities of individuals within LDCs and of LDCs.
The article recommends a robust duty of assistance as part of the solution for
LDCs, including the provision of international aid based on the criteria of aid
effectiveness, optimal aid allocation, and practicality.

Rawls’s Law of Peoples


Building on his landmark works2 on justice for a liberal democratic society,
Rawls provides principles that he believes well-ordered, reasonable, and
rational peoples3 (a type of idealized, enlightened nation-state) would choose
to underpin international justice in his 1993 essay “The Law of Peoples,”
which are further developed in his 1999 book The Law of Peoples.4 He (1993,
32) defines a “well-ordered” people as one that (1) is peaceful and not
expansionist, (2) retains a system of law that is legitimate in the eyes of its own
citizens, and (3) honours basic human rights. To arrive at these principles,
he uses a two-stage hypothetical social contract in his “ideal” theory. In the
first stage, representatives of well-ordered, liberal peoples are placed in an
original position behind a “veil of ignorance” that limits their information
base, thus providing fair conditions and an impartial starting point.5 These
liberal peoples consider familiar and traditional principles from the history
and practice of international law (Rawls 1999, 41). In the second stage, well-
ordered, non-liberal, decent6 peoples engage in their own social contract by
considering the principles to which well-ordered, liberal peoples have already
agreed. He (ibid., 69) concludes that liberal and non-liberal (but decent)
peoples would accept the same principles. According to Rawls (ibid., 37), the
final agreement, or the “Law of Peoples,” would be similar to the principles
currently underlying public international law: there would be a central focus
87
on state (or a people’s) rights, including the right to independence and non-
intervention, prohibitions on war, and agreement to observe international
treaties and to honour basic human rights.
Rawls then considers two cases of “non-ideal” theory: non-compliance
and unfavourable conditions. In the case of non-compliance with the agreed-
upon global principles, he (ibid., 81) writes that “an outlaw state that violates
these rights is to be condemned and in grave cases may be subjected to forceful
sanctions and even to intervention.” In the case of unfavourable conditions
faced by developing countries (or what he calls “burdened societies”7), he
proposes a duty of assistance. Non-ideal theory and the duty of assistance
are the primary concerns of this article. In the world as is, a country may
be an outlaw state (e.g., an aggressor state), a burdened society (e.g., a well-
governed LDC), or both (e.g., some failed or fragile states). For Rawls (ibid.,
3), the long-term objective is to bring outlaw states and burdened societies
into the “Society of Peoples,” envisioned as a global community of well-
ordered, cooperative peoples that follows the ideals and principles of the Law
of Peoples. The breadth and depth of his theory, its relevance to the world as
is, and its attempt to establish a fair process for selecting principles of global
justice make this work of scholarship an excellent starting point to analyze
and inform development policies.

Rawls’s Duty of Assistance


The duty of assistance and the needs of LDCs

Rawls’s duty of assistance obligates peoples “to assist other peoples living
under unfavourable conditions that prevent their having a just or decent
political and social regime” (ibid., 37). The form of the duty of assistance
is vague, underdeveloped, and limited. He (ibid., 108–10) only notes his
skepticism of the ability of funds to rectify political and social injustices and
expresses his preference for offering “certain kinds of advice” to influence
change within ineffective regimes and to promote human rights, such as
equal justice for women to relieve population pressures.8 The limited scope
and form of the duty of assistance is explained by Rawls’s views on the aim
of international assistance, the causes of deprivation, and the need to define
limits to international distributive justice. He (ibid., 107) writes that the aim of
international assistance is “to realize and preserve just (or decent) institutions,
and not simply to increase, much less maximize indefinitely, the average level
of wealth.” But why is he satisfied with ensuring that each people is “well-
ordered”?
Rawls’s answer is that a people in the international original position has
fundamental interests that rest on its ability to freely realize its own reasonable
conception of political justice; each society is only able to do this once it is
well-ordered (ibid., 34–35). And once well-ordered, a people is accepted
into the Society of Peoples. On the main cause of deprivation, Rawls (ibid.,
108) writes that “the causes of the wealth of a people . . . lie in their political
88
culture and in the religious, philosophical, and moral traditions that support
the basic structure of their political and social institutions, as well as in the
industriousness and cooperative talents of its members, all supported by their
political virtues . . . [T]here is no society anywhere in the world—except for
marginal cases—with resources so scarce that it could not, were it reasonably
and rationally organized and governed, become well-ordered.” For Rawls,
every people is endowed with sufficient human capacities and resources
to become well-ordered and for it to realize just or decent institutions. His
view is that being well-ordered does not require great resources, but rather a
political culture that advances citizens’ interests. Rawls views the largely self-
sufficient basic structure of a people as the most important arena for regulating
citizens’ life prospects over time.9 Hence, he rejects calls for more egalitarian
international distributive justice.10 There is no target in The Law of Peoples to
raise the standard of living of individuals in other countries beyond what
is necessary to sustain good institutions (ibid., 119). Once a people is well-
ordered, Rawls believes that it should be free to pursue its own conception of
the good, with whatever standard of living or quality of life this might entail.
It is important to reiterate that the focus here is on LDCs. In Rawls’s ideal
theory, well-ordered liberal and non-liberal peoples have sufficient resources
and sufficiently functional institutions to remedy social injustices. Therefore,
he is justified in rejecting a global distributive principle that raises the least
well-off individual of a well-ordered people which is more pastoral or less
hard-working relative to others, or embodies religious and social values that
lead to a higher rate of population growth (ibid., 117–18). However, this article
will show that in non-ideal theory Rawls’s duty of assistance is insufficient.
The first shortcoming of Rawls’s duty of assistance is its inadequacy to
address the needs of the bottom billion. To assess whether or not Rawls’s duty
of assistance is sufficient and to determine areas to focus policy, the causes
of deprivation in LDCs can be assessed. As a first principle, the primary goal
for LDCs and the core challenge of development should be economic growth,
the sine qua non for poverty reduction (Collier 2007, 11). It is necessary to
supplement this goal with additional goals such as growth with equity,
social progress, and sustainable development.11 On this point, development
economics features a debate on the “poverty trap” and “bad government”
as alternative causal explanations for the persistence of low, stagnant, or
negative economic growth in LDCs. On the one hand, Jeffrey Sachs (2005)
argues that a large number of the extreme poor are unable to escape from
material deprivation because they are “trapped” by disease, climate stress,
environmental degradation, and extreme poverty itself. The poverty trap,
he contends, is the result of low domestic savings—self-sustained economic
growth cannot be spurred without investment to fund the accumulation of
physical and human capital. He understands that the “financing gap”12 can be
addressed with international aid. In the “big push” aid theory, which assumes
that aid will lead to investment and subsequently to growth, sufficient levels
of aid will break the poverty trap.
It is clear that LDCs lack the capital required for economic development,
89
yet the empirical validity of the existence of a poverty trap and the utility of
the financing gap model have recently come under scrutiny. William Easterly
(2006b) finds that there are problems with the poverty trap explanation
because there is no compelling evidence that countries are stuck at low-
income levels. He notes that the poorest countries have not had stationary
income streams, regardless of the presence of international aid. Moreover,
poor countries’ economic performance has fluctuated, which implies that they
are not in poverty traps (ibid., 19–21). Regarding the financing gap model, it is
not clear that there is a link between aid and investment, that aid goes toward
investment one for one, or that there is a statistically significant link between
investment and growth (Easterly 1999, 430–33). Easterly argues that it is
not a useful model13 because if aid is seen as permanent income, recipients
have incentives to consume rather than invest and to maintain or increase
the financing gap, which promotes moral hazard. Given the challenge of
inferring causality in the poverty trap explanation and the difficulties with
the financing gap model, an alternative explanatory theory is needed.
Easterly (2006b) finds that bad government is a significant factor in
explaining low growth rates in low-income countries—the result holds only
when corruption is taken into consideration. He (ibid., 23–30) defines bad
government as reflective of scoring poorly on corruption (using data from the
International Country Risk Guide) and democracy (using data from Polity
IV) measures. Hence, he and Dambisa Moyo,14 among others, are skeptical
of the provision of aid to poorly governed countries. They suggest bottom-
up, micro-level solutions (Easterly 2006a) and alternative ways15 of financing
investment for development (Moyo 2009). Given the many dimensions of bad
government, it is necessary to broaden and deepen Easterly’s definition to
discern the quality of overall governance. To do this, the six dimensions of
governance in the World Bank’s Worldwide Governance Indicators project
could be considered: political stability and absence of violence, voice and
accountability, government effectiveness, rule of law, control of corruption,
and regulatory quality. For economists in the governance camp, reasonably
good scores on these dimensions are a prerequisite for growth. The views
of Easterly and Moyo align with those of Rawls in suggesting that growth
is made possible if there is good governance (here it can be assumed that a
“decent social and political culture” includes good governance). These are
important insights in development economics; however, they only provide a
partial account of the causes of poverty. More is needed to inform solutions
for LDCs.
Just or decent institutions and good governance are important
considerations, but there are additional factors that lead to the deprivation of
LDCs. Even some of Rawls’s supporters agree that his duty of assistance and
arguments in The Law of Peoples require either reworking or elaboration. Huw
Lloyd Williams (2011) extends the capability approach that Rawls later adopts
in his domestic non-ideal theory to enable individuals to meet the social
minimum. He (ibid., 156) argues that there are additional obstacles to freedom
that affect “state capability,” defined as the substantive freedom of peoples
90
and extent of their actions. Such obstacles include resources, civil society, and
the global economy (ibid., 128). Williams sees Rawls’s position as open to
incorporating a multi-level analysis that conceptualizes a more robust duty
of assistance to build state capability (ibid., 154). Such incorporation would
help elaborate Rawls’s duty of assistance, though it is questionable whether
he would accept such proposals. His overwhelming emphasis on political
culture and domestic institutions, rejection of the application of capabilities
to peoples (Rawls 1999, 13), and skepticism regarding international aid all
suggest that he would not. Williams recognizes this, noting: “[T]he extent to
which we can attribute this view to Rawls . . . is a question of interpretation.
. . . I would submit that this approach to burdened societies is in the spirit of
his work” (ibid., 156). Rawls and Williams, however, both focus too narrowly
on states, a point that will be later revisited.
Paul Collier presents (2007, 5) another explanatory theory: LDCs are
stuck in poverty because they face one or a combination of four traps—the
natural resources trap, the conflict trap, the trap of being landlocked with bad
neighbours, and the trap of being a small country with bad governance. This
theory is the most likely explanation for the persistence of low, stagnant, or
negative growth in LDCs. Crucially, it goes beyond simplistic mono-causal
explanations and recognizes that contextual differences, the role of external
state and non-state actors, and the international economic structure may
affect the quality of governance, policies, and institutions. Collier’s (2007,
201) broad policy prescriptions are to promote good governance, harness
natural resources for equitable benefit, reform internal and external economic
and trade policies, provide effective development aid, and implement
international laws and charters that promote transparency and accountability.
These policies tackle the realities facing LDCs.
It is also necessary to consider aid effectiveness to determine whether
or not Rawls is justified in minimizing the role of international aid. While
macro studies of the impact of aid on growth are fiercely debated, evaluations
of micro aid projects have yielded more positive results. Paul Mosley (1986,
22) coined the term “micro-macro paradox” to highlight the observation that
micro or project evaluations tend to show that aid has a positive impact, which
is not or cannot be confirmed by macro studies. Accordingly, some policy-
makers only support aid that funds, for instance, vaccination campaigns, cash
transfers for school attendance, and investments in infrastructure. However,
the problem of aggregation—positive results from micro aid projects often
do not add up to macroeconomic growth and may not be replicable in other
contexts—indicates that micro projects cannot be the sole focus. Scholars are
split on whether aid boosts growth and it is evident that “every aid effort is
a calculated risk or . . . experiment” (Roodman 2007, 3), but there is a general
(not universal) consensus in the development community that policies matter
for aid effectiveness (see, for example, Burnside and Dollar 2000; Collier and
Dollar 2004). Aid may lead to growth in recipient countries with good fiscal,
monetary, and trade policies, including sound budget management, low debt
levels, low levels of inflation, a relatively open economy, and secure property
91
rights and enforceable contracts (ibid.). Recognizing this, Collier (1997, 64)
advises donors to adopt a policy of selectivity or ex-post conditionality in the
allocation of aid to recipient countries, whereby governments are rewarded
with aid if they pursue good policies.
Rawls’s duty of assistance sees little to no role for international aid, not
even on a selective basis. Although it may be argued, in the spirit of Rawls,
that conditionality erodes sovereignty and therefore undermines burdened
societies, this can only be accepted to a certain extent. Donors are accountable
to their citizens for how and where they provide aid and it is reasonable to
expect that aid is facilitating growth and consequently alleviating poverty.
While the intrusion on sovereignty should be minimized, certain conditions
for aid—especially those related to a select group of indisputably sound
economic policies—may be necessary. In cases where there is progress in a
recipient country though macroeconomic “slippage” on some conditions,
perhaps due to a shock to the economy, the aid framework should be flexible
enough so that donors refrain from cutting off aid, an action which might
jeopardize reforms that have already been implemented (Leandro, Schafer,
and Frontini 1999, 289). Furthermore, donor conditionality, if used, should
align with the recipient-led long-term poverty reduction plan. Taken together,
sound political and economic policies, just or decent institutions, and good
governance should provide fertile conditions for sustained economic growth.
To address the additional goals of growth with equity, social progress, and
sustainable development and challenges such as multidimensional poverty
and the four traps into which an LDC may fall, international aid needs to
go beyond Rawls’s duty of assistance and Williams’s elaboration. To address
these goals and challenges, this article examines Rawls’s human rights
requirements before turning to capability ethics.

The duty of assistance and human rights

In The Law of Peoples, well-ordered peoples agree to honour basic human


rights, which include the right to life (i.e., to the means of subsistence and
security), to liberty (i.e., to freedom from slavery, serfdom, and forced
occupation, and to a sufficient—not necessarily equal—measure of liberty
of conscience to ensure freedom of religion and thought), and to personal
property (Rawls 1999, 65). Rawls’s “special class of urgent rights” ensures the
security of ethnic groups from mass murder and genocide (ibid., 78–79). These
rights are preconditions for becoming well-ordered and subsequently joining
the Society of Peoples. His duty of assistance aims to secure human rights
in burdened societies, including subsistence needs such as health care, food,
clothing, shelter, and minimum economic security (ibid., 65). Importantly,
Rawls (ibid., 80) refers to the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR),
stating that his group of rights includes Articles 3 to 18 (although it cannot
fully include Article 7, which covers equality before the law); all other rights
in the UDHR are discounted as “liberal aspirations” or rights that presuppose
certain institutions. Notably, he omits certain civil and political rights such
92
as the right to democracy in the institutional and deliberative sense,16 the
right to full equality under the law (since unequal liberty is permitted),
freedom of speech and expression, and freedom of assembly. All societies
that ensure at minimum associationist or hierarchical forms of governmental
consultations, he judges, are to be tolerated and accepted as members in the
Society of Peoples. In addition, Rawls excludes many economic and social
rights such as the right to social security (UDHR Article 22), the free choice of
employment and the right to equal pay for equal work (Article 23), and the
right to education (Article 26). He concedes that his list of rights is relatively
limited. In a footnote, Rawls (ibid., 75) acknowledges the argument that “full
democratic and liberal rights are necessary to prevent violations of human
rights . . . , an empirical fact supported by historical experience,” but since he
views decent peoples in a conceptual way, he narrows his concern to whether
or not liberal peoples should tolerate these non-liberal peoples politically and
accept them in the Society of Peoples.
Rawls’s commitment to a limited selection of human rights is related
to his notion of a “realistic utopia”—he understands that a Law of Peoples
must “depict an achievable social world” (ibid., 6). His realistic utopia is
characterized by reasonable pluralism and self-determination for each
people, both requiring a liberal toleration and an absence of paternalism,
hence Rawls concludes that the protection of “urgent rights” makes his Law
of Peoples sufficiently liberal (ibid., 79). To this end, the principles underlying
international relations must achieve an overlapping consensus of liberal and
non-liberal peoples. In addition, Rawls (ibid., 68) asserts that the agreement to
honour human rights derives not from any particular comprehensive moral,
religious, or philosophical doctrine, but rather from peoples’ recognition that
the fulfillment of these rights is a necessary condition of any domestic system
of social co-operation. He (ibid.) makes this important distinction in an
attempt to safeguard against viewing human rights as liberal or democratic,
or a Western political tradition biased against other cultures. If decent peoples
saw human rights in that light, Rawls believes that his principles of justice
would not achieve an overlapping consensus. Furthermore, the limited list
of human rights is a result of these rights’ specific role in the Law of Peoples:
they serve to narrow and restrict justifications for war and to specify limits to
a regime’s internal autonomy (ibid., 79). Thus, these rights hold political (and
moral) force for all peoples; if an outlaw state violates them, condemnation
and, in grave cases, forceful sanctions and intervention are justified (ibid., 81).
To his credit, Rawls recognizes the need for the international
community to take moral responsibility for ensuring the fulfillment of human
rights in all societies. Erin Kelly (2004, 177) argues further that human rights
must be conceived narrowly if they are to play their required role in the Law
of Peoples. She extends Rawls’s theory by committing countries to a broader
set of foreign policy imperatives, including prohibitions on engagement (e.g.,
profiting in relations with regimes that violate human rights), support of
international efforts and provision of reparations in cases where countries are
directly implicated in human rights violations, and duties for wealthier states
93
to offer aid in a variety of forms to poor states, if doing so will further the cause
of human rights (ibid., 177–80). Kelly elaborates Rawls’s duty of assistance in
a helpful way, yet she adheres to a limited list of human rights because of
the “normative requirement of joint acceptability” (ibid., 179). In effect, this
echoes Rawls’s valuable insights on the need for reasonable pluralism and on
the importance of self-determination. However, it is not necessary to proceed
so timidly with a limited list of rights.
Rawls’s and Kelly’s starting point needs to be recast: a liberal foreign
policy should not be encumbered by what non-liberal, decent peoples would
accept in a social contract. Policy-makers may go beyond such a limited
selection of human rights. There is sufficient space to safeguard reasonable
pluralism and respect self-determination while striving to make all human
rights universal,17 indivisible,18 and interdependent.19 For instance, liberal
and non-liberal peoples may disagree on whether full democratic, economic,
and social rights are universal; however, liberal peoples can still tolerate
non-liberal peoples’ principles (but not those of outlaw states) and actively
encourage all human rights, without intervention or resorting to sanctions.
Rawls (1999, 82–83) views this as amounting to a foreign policy that aims to
impose on all societies the liberal rights of citizens in liberal constitutional
democracies in order to gradually liberalize non-liberal peoples. Granted, but
why would this be wrong if the rights are grounded in basic shared interests
such as human dignity (Buchanan 2006, 159)? For Rawls, this kind of moral
conception of human nature is incompatible with his political conception of
justice because, as noted, human rights in the Law of Peoples are grounded
in social co-operation, not in comprehensive doctrines, which are precluded
in the social contract. But this is an inadequate approach toward international
justice, and an alternative grounding for human rights—in individuals’
capabilities to do what they value—will be discussed. When rights are agreed
upon as inherent to basic human needs and aspirations, the debate moves
beyond whether human rights are “liberal aspirations” or just “rights talk.”
Agreement on various human rights declarations and covenants has been
achieved—of course with some reservations—proving that peoples may
strive toward a more ambitious “realistic utopia.”
Whether or not all human rights can be enshrined in law is not the
most important issue. They should be used as normative claims that give rise
to state obligations. Human rights should serve as strong moral claims for
spearheading legislation and increasing public attention toward individuals
subject to violations of their rights (Sen 2009, 364–65). If states do not protect
and enforce these rights, they should be persuaded—and in the worst cases
coerced—by the international community to live up to their obligations. On
this point, Nussbaum (2006) makes an important distinction between the
justification and the implementation of norms. The Law of Peoples treats the
question of whether or not a people is worthy of toleration in the Society of
Peoples (based on whether it implements relevant norms and human rights
standards) as equivalent to whether or not the international community
should intervene, either militarily or with economic or political sanctions.
94
However, the international community may simultaneously promote a wider
set of aspirational human rights, make justified criticisms of peoples who
are not adhering to their obligations, and refrain from intervening militarily
or imposing sanctions. In such instances, the international community
could use other means to seek compliance such as persuasion through
public campaigns, diplomatic exchanges, international covenants, and
targeted aid (ibid., 256–59). For example, Nussbaum (ibid., 256) highlights
international campaigns against the use of the death penalty in the United
States. Furthermore, intervention is not always the best option and there may
be prudential arguments against it in even the gravest cases (ibid., 259). For
instance, in consideration of the genocide and mass rapes in Gujarat, India,
in March 2002, Nussbaum (ibid., 259) judges that intervention would have
likely created more problems than it would have solved and that there were
adequate domestic democratic accountability processes in place, hence the
international community was right not to intervene. States can evidently
justify a wider set of human rights as applicable to each people and implement
that set in a variety of ways, without resorting to intervention in a people’s
affairs.
In addition to the shortcomings of Rawls’s duty of assistance and
human rights requirements, the Rawlsian social contract approach contains
irreconcilable procedural problems. Nussbaum (2006, 250) indicates that
Rawls’s international social contract excludes burdened societies, which
therefore have no say in setting the political and economic rules of the game
and take existing rules as given. This cannot be considered a just state of
global affairs because it undermines the Rawlsian notions of “equal peoples”
and “justice as fairness,” or the notion that if the process is fair, the outcome
will be just. The Law of Peoples cannot answer a crucial question about Rawls’s
process: how can justice for LDCs be derived if they are excluded from the
process? It is unfair to exclude burdened societies from the social contract,
but a dilemma exists: since those societies may not be symmetrically situated
or able to represent themselves fairly, they may not have the political power
and capacity to enter into a binding agreement. For that reason, a contract
for mutual advantage cannot include them as equal participants (ibid.).
What is needed is a complete redesign of the system of global justice to fairly
and fully include LDCs. This would require a significant departure from
Rawls’s Society of Peoples and a different account of the purposes of social
co-operation, mutual advantage, and reciprocity and of a realistic utopia
(ibid.). The international community thus stands at a frontier of justice that
the Rawlsian approach cannot cross.
Rawls’s exclusion of burdened societies from the social contract is similar
to the reality of decision making within the current global political and economic
architecture. The International Monetary Fund, World Bank, World Trade
Organization (WTO), Group of Eight, and United Nations Security Council
have traditionally been dominated by developed countries, though recently
there have been certain moderate reforms.20 As Thomas Pogge (2004, 278–79)
argues, considering that developed countries set the rules to their advantage,
95
their dominance of the international order gives them a moral (negative) duty
to reduce the harm caused to developing countries and not to take advantage
of injustice at the expense of the poor. He suggests that developed countries
reform the inequitable international structure to better favour developing
countries. The Rawlsian insight on burden sharing is important to keep in
mind, however, if not for purely practical reasons. Wealthier countries that
make larger contributions to international organizations and confederations
can reasonably expect to receive greater returns and have more input into
operations and resource allocation (Rawls 1999, 115). In the world as is, there
is room to preserve this situation while giving poorer countries a greater say
in matters that affect their development. From another angle, the Rawlsian
approach focuses too narrowly on states and, to a lesser extent, multilateral
organizations. Onora O’Neill (2005, 246) argues that policy-makers need
to recognize and engage non-state actors that also play an important role in
providing economic justice. A more equitable global order would see both
Pogge’s and O’Neill’s suggestions implemented. Firstly, developed countries
would include developing countries in global economic governance forums
(e.g., the Group of Twenty and the Bretton Woods institutions) and offer them
preferential terms in the WTO and in regional and bilateral trade negotiations.
Secondly, the full range of state and non-state actors—including civil society,
non-governmental organizations (NGOs), entrepreneurs, multinational
corporations, religious and charitable groups, academia, research centres, and
the media—in developed and developing countries would help the bottom
billion overcome multidimensional poverty and the four traps.

Capabilities without Borders


Given the shortcomings of Rawls’s duty of assistance, human rights
requirements, and social contract approach, policy-makers require an
alternative ethical approach. The capabilities approach, as developed
on different tracks by Nussbaum and Sen, provides an ethical basis for
achieving global justice. Before moving on, it is important to make clear two
first principles that underpin the arguments that follow. One is the Kantian
notion that all moral agents are equally free to determine their own ends
and all moral agents are ends in themselves. The other is that, assuming
fundamental human nature involves motivations of gratitude and reciprocity
and consideration of loved ones and those in closer proximity first, a
reasoned approach to global justice values impartial notions of need, rather
than familiarity or moral desert (Singer 2005). The location of the needy is
irrelevant—if one can help, one ought to do so (even if one does not) (ibid.,
28). These principles are sufficient in scope and can replace Rawls’s starting
point, the original position. In contrast to the Rawlsian framework, it seems
reasonable to draw upon these principles if they are grounded in basic human
interests and if doing so achieves just outcomes.
96
Capabilities are a better metric of international justice than primary goods

The capabilities approach better addresses the needs of LDCs than Rawls’s
duty of assistance and his use of primary goods. The capabilities approach
aims to expand the freedoms of each individual and has human development
as its primary objective. “Capability” is a power to do or to have something,
rather than the actual “doing” or “having.” Sen is concerned with those
capabilities that individuals would have reason to value while Nussbaum
considers those necessary to achieve a life worthy of human dignity. An
important distinction between Rawlsian and capability theorists relates
to the metric of justice and the distinction between means and ends for
inequality. According to Sen (1980), the appropriate metric of justice can
be determined by asking: “Equality of what?” In The Idea of Justice, he
distinguishes “utility-based” or “resource-based” approaches focused on
inequalities of primary goods from the “freedom-based” approach focused
on inequalities of capabilities. Rawls (2001, 58–59) remedies inequalities
within a society through the use of primary goods, chief among which are
the “all-purpose means” of wealth and income.21 Aside from his limited
duty of assistance, Rawls does not endorse a redistribution principle in his
international theory. While she also does not endorse a specific redistribution
principle, Nussbaum (2006, 74, 316) argues that prosperous countries have a
responsibility to provide a substantial portion of their gross domestic product
to poorer countries in order to realize capabilities that are necessary for a life
worthy of human dignity. She (ibid., 17) suggests a figure of 2 per cent of
gross domestic product, acknowledging that it is arbitrary and debatable but
maintaining that the principle is not. Space constraints preclude an analysis of
Nussbaum’s open-ended list of capabilities,22 but they are generally accepted
in this article because they capture the core elements of human development.
Rawls’s narrow list of human rights and preference for primary goods, on the
other hand, do not.
The most effective way for policy-makers to measure progress toward
goals for LDCs, such as growth with equity, social progress, and sustainable
development, is to utilize the capabilities lens. As recognized by the UNDP
in its human development concept,23 income alone is an incomplete and
crude measure of an individual’s well-being. Moreover, primary goods
have difficulty addressing the problem of interpersonal variation, the fact
that conversion of primary goods into freedom differs from individual to
individual. For example, a disabled person with the same level of income as
a non-disabled person may not possess a similar level of freedom. The UNDP
uses income, health, and educational indicators. However, to fully represent
an individual’s well-being in terms of freedom, policy-makers should look at
the capabilities available to various individuals. A final reason why capabilities
are a more useful metric than primary goods is the distinction between means
and ends highlighted by Sen in The Idea of Justice and Development as Freedom.
Primary goods are an indirect means toward other things, perhaps increasing
an individual’s freedom, while capabilities directly impact an individual’s
97
freedom, his or her actual opportunities for living well. For these reasons,
policy-makers should focus on capabilities rather than primary goods.
This new focus can result in more effective policies. In contrast to
Rawls’s focus on states (or peoples), individuals deserve greater attention,
and the maximization of capabilities, or “substantive freedoms,” should be
seen as both the means and ends of development (Sen 2000, 3). By focusing
on individuals’ capabilities, policy-makers can better recognize that poverty
is multi-faceted and that the poor face overlapping deprivations. They can, in
turn, better address multidimensional poverty. In the short term, the bottom
billion care most about securing basic necessities such as food, clean water
and sanitation, primary and secondary education, treatment for illnesses, and
jobs. In the medium to long term, capabilities such as political control over
one’s environment may become a priority in order to ensure the preservation
of self-determination. The UNDP’s HDI is a useful tool to measure the various
aspects of multidimensional poverty and compare countries’ conditions.
Policy-makers may use HDI data to identify similarly situated countries (in
geographic, climatic, and historical terms), single out those with higher levels
of human development, and then learn from those countries’ policies. In 2010,
the UNDP introduced the Multidimensional Poverty Index, which considers
multiple deprivations and their overlap. Additional instruments introduced
by the UNDP that year include the inequality-adjusted HDI, a measure of
the level of human development that accounts for inequality, and the Gender
Inequality Index, which measures disadvantages facing women and girls.
These new indices go further in measuring the effects of policies on human
development and are equally useful for the formation of country-specific
policies.

The nexus between development, freedom, and human rights

If the focus of development should be maximizing capabilities and the


main objective should be achieving equitable, sustainable economic growth
alongside social progress, then what is the link between development,
freedom, and human rights? Human rights are derived from normative
notions of the freedom of the individual. In other words, human rights can
be derived from capabilities since different capabilities allow an individual
to strive toward different freedoms. For instance, from Nussbaum’s
capability of control over one’s environment, the human rights of freedom
of speech and freedom of assembly can be derived. From her capability of
senses, imagination, and thought, the right to education can be derived. It
is important to recognize, however, that although all human rights can be
derived from capabilities, capabilities cannot always be translated into rights,
nor would this be desirable. Considering Nussbaum’s capability of affiliation,
for example, it is not reasonable to obligate each individual to show concern
for and engage with every other individual, but it is reasonable to protect the
rights to freedom of assembly and freedom of expression.
The advancement of civil, political, economic, social, and cultural rights
98
in the second half of the 20th century has been fundamental in increasing
the freedom of all individuals. The legal and normative underpinnings of
individuals’ different freedoms are found in the international human rights
architecture, which includes the Charter of the United Nations, the UDHR,
the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights and its two optional
protocols, and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural
Rights and its optional protocol. Within these and other instruments there
are various normative proclamations that the international community can
use to increase individuals’ freedom. For example, Article 25 of the UDHR
states that “Everyone has the right to a standard of living adequate for health
and well-being of himself and of his family, including food, clothing, housing
and medical care and necessary social services, and the right to security in
the event of unemployment, sickness, disability, widowhood, old age or
lack of livelihood in circumstances beyond his control” (UN 2012). Likewise,
Article 26 affirms the right to free and compulsory elementary education and
indicates that higher education should be made equally accessible to all on the
basis of merit (ibid.). The crucial point is that human rights which improve
individuals’ capabilities should be promoted, though one must remain realistic
about which rights official state actors may reasonably be expected to promote
publicly. Moreover, for human rights to be enforceable, instruments like those
mentioned above should be made binding through ratification. Liberal rights
need not necessarily be forced by peoples upon other peoples. Peoples can
promote a wider set of human rights and aim to have protections legislated
and then enforced through monitoring bodies and courts. Such actions are a
necessary check on state power and impunity and should ultimately improve
individuals’ capabilities. A liberal foreign policy should be confident and have
purpose—the promotion of fundamental human rights and the advancement
of human development are causes that are worthy of effort. In this conception,
Rawls’s “urgent” human rights are supplemented with the promotion of a
wider set of rights that create opportunities—and hence improve capabilities—
and the freely determined development of all individuals.
How far should governments and other actors go in improving the
capabilities of the bottom billion? Nussbaum (2006, 293–94) argues that to
construct a minimally just world the international community should secure
her 10 central capabilities up to an appropriate threshold level for all of the
world’s peoples. Thresholds, she says, are different for different capabilities.
First of all, political, religious, and civil liberties should be secured equally for
all individuals. For capabilities related to property and instrumental goods,
“what seems appropriate is enough.” For capabilities linked to the idea of
equal human dignity such as primary and secondary education and access to
basic health care, the international community should “aggressively pursue
equality between nations.” These threshold targets are practicable. Policy-
makers can use them as a starting point and then consider the maximization
of all capabilities as the end goal (Sen 2009, 232–33). Furthermore, what
should be the role of international aid? Aid can kick-start development and
help to provide the conditions for sustained economic growth, but it is not a
99
panacea, as evidenced by the Sachs/Easterly/Collier debate. Aid is one part of
a poverty reduction strategy and it is critical to find ways to make aid more
effective. Aid effectiveness can be increased by providing aid through various
channels depending on whether a people is well-ordered or not (Radelet
2004) and whether aid modalities match a country’s needs. Rawls’s duty
of assistance, with little to no role for aid, removes an important financing
option for LDCs, especially in cases where peoples are well-ordered but
stuck in one of the four aforementioned traps. The construction of a global
ethics based on the capabilities approach and the promotion of a wide set of
human rights is the best way to increase the freedom of the bottom billion and
facilitate development. A holistic human development approach should be
complemented by moral and legal justification found in human rights treaties
and instruments. To achieve global justice for the bottom billion, policies
should be informed by a novel “capabilities-plus” approach.

Toward a “Capabilities-Plus” Approach: Human


Development, Human Rights, and Human Security
A “capabilities-plus” approach supports the concurrent advancement of
human development, human rights, and human security and encourages
policy-makers to conduct policy with the maximization of Nussbaum’s
central capabilities and the promotion of freedoms as end goals. It is morally
justifiable and strongly protects and empowers individuals in LDCs, in turn
facilitating equitable, sustainable economic growth alongside social progress.
The approach’s human security component is critical because it proposes a
paradigm shift from a focus on state security to a focus on individual security;
it complements, not replaces, traditional notions of state security.24 In its 2003
report Human Security Now, the independent Commission on Human Security
(CHS), on which Sen was a co-chair, defines human security as the protection
of “the vital core of all human lives in ways that enhance human freedoms
and human fulfillment” (CHS 2003, 4). Like capability ethics, the human
security paradigm aims to protect fundamental freedoms by promoting
human rights and ensuring good governance and access to basic services
(ibid.). Its added value is its enlarged focus on protecting individuals from
all severe and pervasive threats and situations including “downside risks”
such as external shocks (ibid.). Examples of shocks include natural disasters,
regional and global financial crises, commodity price changes, political and
civil unrest, and assassinations. The CHS report explores several conflict-
related aspects of human security, including violence, refugees and internally
displaced persons, and post-conflict situations, and several poverty-related
aspects such as economic insecurity, ill health, and lack of education. It is
important to recognize that these aspects are often two sides of the same coin:
conflict perpetuates poverty and poverty sows the seeds of conflict. Outlaw
states and burdened societies may be one and the same, and suffer from
both conflict and poverty. Examples include failing or failed states such as
Afghanistan, Côte d’Ivoire, the DRC, Myanmar, North Korea, Sudan, and
100
Yemen. It is the bottom billion who feel the greatest impact of downside
risks and are most prone to external shocks because of weak state capacity,
relatively high internal and external risk factors for instability, and relatively
weak external stabilizing factors.25
Policy-makers should complement human development and human
rights policies that expand individuals’ freedoms with a focus on human
security. The CHS (ibid., 130–43) proposes a framework to take action on
the protection and empowerment of all individuals. To protect individuals,
policy-makers must focus on the development or reform of norms, processes,
and institutions needed to build state capacity and increase resilience. Based
on the preceding arguments, this could roughly be categorized as a moral
negative duty for developed countries to reform the international economic
architecture so as not to harm the poorest living in LDCs and a moral positive
duty for all countries to assist the bottom billion and help LDCs develop just
institutions, adopt good policies, and practice good governance. To empower
individuals, the CHS says, policy-makers should enhance human capabilities
and enable individuals to make their own informed choices. Based on prior
arguments, this may roughly be categorized as a moral positive duty for
developed countries and relevant non-state actors to address the challenges
related to the four traps facing LDCs, and for LDCs to develop just institutions,
adopt good policies, and practice good governance.
In practice, the protection and empowerment of individuals has
yielded notable results. For instance, the United Nations Trust Fund for
Human Security plays an important role in coordinating and channelling
financial resources to field-based human security projects. An example is its
support for a community empowerment and peace-building project in the
Ituri region of the DRC that combines the efforts of various United Nations
agencies (the UNDP, Food and Agriculture Organization, United Nations
Children’s Fund, United Nations Population Fund, United Nations High
Commissioner for Refugees, and World Food Programme), the United Nations
Organization Mission in the Democratic Republic of the Congo, and the
World Health Organization. Their efforts are alongside those of the provincial
government and local, national, and international NGOs. The project places
communities at the centre of post-conflict recovery and addresses the full
range of insecurities faced by individuals (UNGA 2010, 16). The project has an
integrated and holistic approach to meeting basic human needs in the region.
Specifically, it is strengthening public safety, improving health and education,
supporting economic recovery, and promoting a culture of peaceful coexistence
between diverse groups (ibid.). As to its impact on individuals’ lives, “efforts
provide opportunities to decrease inequalities, strengthen social networks and
improve State-society relations, all of which are required to produce the peace
dividend needed to bolster confidence in consolidating peace and transitioning
to sustainable development” (ibid.). International participation in such
projects must ensure equal respect for internal processes and indigenous-led
development in order to preserve self-determination.
Achieving global justice requires the protection and empowerment of
101
all individuals offered by a “capabilities-plus” approach, which recognizes
that every individual matters equally. Rawls’s Law of Peoples cannot support
such an approach because his duty of assistance calls for the termination of
international assistance for burdened societies once peoples become well-
ordered. Although he supports the humanitarian protection of individuals
from downside risks such as famine, Rawls does not advocate striving toward
a wide range of civil, political, economic, social, and cultural rights. This is
inadequate in attempts to address multidimensional poverty and the four
traps that LDCs may fall into. The bottom billion—the poorest and most
vulnerable—require remedies prescribed by a “capabilities-plus approach”
that has a focus on human security at its core. Crucially, the approach
retains the Rawlsian emphasis on the development of institutions and state
capacity building, which are necessary to protect individuals to an extent, but
prioritizes the protection of individuals from shocks, conflict, and poverty
and the empowerment of individuals through human development and
promotion of a wide set of human rights.

Policy Recommendations

1. The goal of the duty of assistance should be to maximize the


capabilities of the bottom billion

• Utilize the ethical lens of a “capabilities-plus” approach—the


concurrent advancement of human development, human rights, and
human security
• Channel a greater share of resources to human security projects
that align with LDCs’ domestically-led poverty reduction plans
and include, where appropriate, United Nations agencies,
multiple donors, NGOs, and local governments, communities, and
entrepreneurs in LDCs; consider using the United Nations Trust Fund
for Human Security as a central coordinator
• Allocate the majority of international assistance to LDCs
• Provide aid to governments that adopt good economic policies and
practice good governance
• Provide aid in the form of general and sector budget support and/or
technical co-operation to LDCs with just institutions
• Focus on specific projects and interventions in badly governed LDCs
and channel aid through NGOs
• Use discretion in cases where peoples are not well-ordered
• Ensure that aid effectiveness is a key consideration in choosing
modality
• Provide advice on sound monetary, fiscal, trade, and macroeconomic
policies to ensure aid effectiveness
• Assist LDCs in trade capacity building and trade facilitation
• Encourage regional and global economic integration if it is for LDCs’
benefit
102
2. The international economic architecture should reflect an equality of
peoples

• Include LDCs in decision-making processes that affect their


development
• Provide trade preferences for LDCs through the World Trade
Organization
• Initiate or encourage preferential bilateral and regional trade
negotiations in areas that LDCs have existing or potential comparative
advantage
103
Notes
1. An alternative to gross domestic product, the HDI captures progress in
three basic capabilities: to live a long and healthy life, to be educated and
knowledgeable, and to enjoy a decent standard of living (see UNDP 2012b).
2. Arguably, the strongest contemporary political conception of justice within
a liberal democratic society is John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice (1971). The
conception was refined in Political Liberalism (1993). His final statement on the
subject is Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (2001).
3. In The Law of Peoples, Rawls uses the term “peoples” and not states or nations
because he recognizes their political and cultural nature and assigns to them a
certain moral character. He understands that peoples are reasonable, rational,
and decent. They are not, as per the traditional conceptualization of states,
solely guided by rational self-interest (in the pursuit of war and economic
dealings, for example) and they respect limitations to sovereignty (for
instance, in cases of human rights violations and crimes against humanity).
Each “people” consists of representatives of a single society in the Society of
Peoples. For more on the difference between peoples and states, see Rawls
(1999, 23–30).
4. Rawls aims to develop a reasonably just foreign policy for a liberal society,
though the principles are also intended to govern relations between peoples
in the Society of Peoples.
5. For instance, they know that they are liberal or not liberal and that they
have a resource base sufficient for them to be well-ordered, but they do not
know the size of their territory or population, or their strength and level of
economic development relative to other well-ordered societies (Rawls 1999,
32–33).
6. Rawls (1999, 59–60) defines a decent people as one whose “basic institutions
meet certain specified conditions of political right and justice and lead its
people to honor a reasonable and just law for the Society of Peoples.” Liberal
peoples are to tolerate and accept non-liberal, decent peoples in the Society
of Peoples.
7. Burdened societies are those that, while “not expansive or aggressive, lack
the political and cultural conditions, the human capital and know-how, and,
often, the material and technological resources needed to be well-ordered”
(Rawls 1999, 106).
8. Rawls (1999, 109–10) mentions reducing gender inequalities and reforming
a people’s population policies through domestic action, but this is not a
requirement of the human rights principle of the Law of Peoples.
9. Rawls’s demand for international distributive justice is less egalitarian
than his difference principle in the domestic case. In Justice as Fairness: A
Restatement, Rawls’s second principle of justice, the difference principle,
reads: “Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions: first,
they are to be attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of
fair equality of opportunity; and second, they are to be to the greatest benefit
of the least-advantaged members of society” (Rawls 2001, 42–43).
104
10. The limitations have inspired cosmopolitan theorists to attempt to improve
Rawls’s duty of assistance. Other scholars view justice as first being owed
to a national community. Rawls (1999, 115–20) replies to Charles Beitz and
Thomas Pogge in The Law of Peoples. Given the need for a “realistic utopia,” it
is reasonable to accept Rawls’s argument that there is reason to question the
practicality and necessity of such far-reaching schemes without targets such
as global difference and resource distribution principles (Beitz 1975; 1979) or
a global resource dividend (Pogge 1994; 2008).
11. For more information on these goals, see UNDP (2012a).
12. The “financing gap” is the difference between (low) domestic savings
and (even lower) domestic investment in a developing country. Foreign aid
can help in the accumulation of physical and human capital, which can spur
economic growth.
13. Variations of the financing gap model are used by international financial
institutions, regional development banks, and most aid agencies to calculate
the investment necessary to achieve a desired growth rate.
14. Moyo (2009, 48–49) argues that aid itself is the cause of poverty and
corruption because it has instilled a culture of dependency in LDCs and
leads to “unlimited opportunities for personal wealth accumulation and
self-aggrandizement.” Aid itself is almost surely not the cause. Rather, the
cause of poverty and corruption is most likely aid that is provided either to
already corrupt governments or to governments lacking just institutions and
adequate accountability mechanisms needed to prevent corruption.
15. Moyo (2009) seeks alternative ways to finance investment in LDCs, such as
placing emphasis on the private sector, foreign direct investment, government
bonds, trade liberalization, and banking solutions (microfinance and
remittances). However, whether or not the first three options would be viable
depends heavily on the trust in LDC governments to honour and enforce
contracts and property rights and to provide stable regulatory environments
and policies conducive to high returns. LDCs secure such trust in rare cases.
16. In the narrow institutional sense, democracy is tantamount to elections
and public balloting. In the broader deliberative sense, democracy is seen
as “government by discussion” and an exercise of public reason; that is, it
is inclusive of political participation, dialogue, and public interaction. See
Sen (2009, 324–27, 345–48) for more on this distinction and the relationship
between democracy and development.
17. The universality of human rights acknowledges that human rights apply
to all human beings independent of specific cultural, historical, or other
backgrounds.
18. The indivisibility of human rights refers to the claim that human rights
from different classes (and even within classes) cannot be separated because
all human rights are of equal importance.
19. The interdependency of human rights affirms that the realization (or the
violation) of one human right is affected by the realization or violation of others.
20. Recent reforms include the emergence of the Group of Twenty in 2008
and efforts to make the international financial institutions more inclusive and
105
thereby more legitimate.
21. Rawls (2001, 58–59) describes five categories of primary goods: basic rights
and liberties, freedom of movement and free choice of occupation against a
background of diverse opportunities, powers and prerogatives of offices and
positions of authority and responsibility, income and wealth, and the social
bases of self-respect.
22. Nussbaum’s 10 central capabilities are: life; bodily health; bodily integrity;
senses, imagination, and thought; emotions; practical reason; affiliation; other
species; play; and control over one’s environment (political and material). See
Nussbaum (2006) for elaboration.
23. See UNDP (2012a) for more information.
24. The CHS (2003) recognizes that human security differs from state security
in four ways: its concern is the individual and the community rather than the
state, it includes “menaces” (threats or conditions) to people’s security that
have not always been classified as threats to state security, its range of actors
is expanded beyond the state, and it prioritizes both protecting people and
empowering them to fend for themselves.
25. For more information, see Prime Minister’s Strategy Unit (2005).

Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Catherine Vanner, Professors Jay Drydyk and
Yiagadeesen Samy, and the editorial board of the Paterson Review for their
assistance in making this project come to fruition. I am grateful for your
support, advice, and patience.

References
Beitz, Charles R. 1975. “Justice and International Relations.” Philosophy and
Public Affairs 4 (4): 360–89.
———. 1979. Political Theory and International Relations. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Buchanan, Allen. 2006. “Taking the Human out of Human Rights.” In
Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, edited by Rex Martin and
David A. Reidy, 150–67. Williston, VT: Wiley-Blackwell.
Burnside, Craig, and David Dollar. 2000. “Aid Policies, and Growth.”
American Economic Review 90 (4): 847–68.
CHS (Commission on Human Security). 2003. Human Security Now. New
York: Commission on Human Security.
Collier, Paul. 1997. “The Failure of Conditionality.” In Perspectives on Aid
and Development, edited by Catherine Gwyn and Joan M. Nelson.
Washington, DC: Overseas Development Council.
———. 2007. The Bottom Billion: Why the Poorest Countries Are Failing and
What Can Be Done About It. New York: Oxford University Press.
———. 2011. Catching Up: What LDCs Can Do, and How Others Can Help.
London: Commonwealth Secretariat.
106
Collier, Paul, and David Dollar. 2004. “Development Effectiveness: What
Have We Learnt?” The Economic Journal 114 (496): F244–71.
Easterly, William. 1999. “The Ghost of the Financing Gap: Testing the
Growth Model Used in International Financial Institutions.” Journal of
Development Economics 60 (2): 423–38.
———. 2006a. The White Man’s Burden: Why the West’s Efforts to Aid the Rest
Have Done So Much Ill and So Little Good. New York: Penguin Press.
———. 2006b. “Planners versus Searchers in Foreign Aid.” Asian
Development Review 23 (2): 1–35.
Kelly, Erin. 2004. “Human Rights as Foreign Policy Imperatives.” In The
Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy, edited by Deen K.
Chatterjee, 177–92. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Leandro, José E., Hartwig Schafer, and Gaspar Frontini. 1999. “Towards a
More Effective Conditionality: An Operational Framework.” World
Development 27 (2): 285–99.
Mosley, Paul. 1986. “Aid Effectiveness: The Micro-Macro Paradox.” Institute
of Development Studies Bulletin 17 (2): 214–25.
Moyo, Dambisa. 2009. Dead Aid: Why Aid Is Not Working and How There Is a
Better Way for Africa. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
Nussbaum, Martha C. 2006. Frontiers of Justice: Disabilities, Nationalities,
Species Membership. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
O’Neill, Onora. 2004. “Global Justice: Whose Obligations?” In The Ethics
of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy, edited by Deen K.
Chatterjee, 242–59. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pogge, Thomas. 1994. “An Egalitarian Law of Peoples.” Philosophy and Public
Affairs 23 (3): 195–224.
———. 2004. “Assisting the Global Poor.” In The Ethics of Assistance:
Morality and the Distant Needy, edited by Deen K. Chatterjee, 260–88.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 2008. “Eradicating Systemic Poverty: Brief for a Global Resource
Dividend.” Chap. 8 in World Poverty and Human Rights. 2nd ed.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Prime Minister’s Strategy Unit. 2005. Investing in Prevention: An International
Strategy to Manage Risks of Instability and Improve Crisis Response.
London: Cabinet Office.
Radelet, Steven. 2004. “Aid Effectiveness and the Millennium Development
Goals.” Working Paper No. 39, Centre for Global Development,
Washington, DC.
Rawls, John. 1993. “The Law of Peoples.” Critical Inquiry 20 (1): 36–68.
———. 1999. The Law of Peoples: with “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited”.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
———. 2001. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Edited by Erin Kelly.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Roodman, David. 2007. “Macro Aid Effectiveness Research: A Guide for the
Perplexed.” Working Paper No. 134, Center for Global Development,
Washington, DC.
107
Sachs, Jeffrey D. 2005. The End of Poverty: Economic Possibilities for Our Time.
New York: Penguin Press.
Sen, Amartya. 1980. “Equality of What?” Vol. 1 of Tanner Lectures on
Human Values. Edited by Sterling McMurrin. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
———. 2000. Development as Freedom. New York: Anchor Books.
———. 2009. The Idea of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Singer, Peter. 2004. “Outsiders: Our Obligations to Those beyond Our
Borders.” In The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy,
edited by Deen K. Chatterjee, 11–32. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
UN (United Nations). 2012. “The Universal Declaration of Human Rights.”
http://www.un.org/en/documents/udhr/.
UNDP (United Nations Development Programme). 2010. Human
Development Report 2010; The Real Wealth of Nations: Pathways to Human
Development. New York: United Nations Development Programme.
———. 2012a. “About Human Development.” Accessed June 4, 2012. http://
hdr.undp.org/en/humandev.
———. 2012b. “Human Development Index.” Accessed May 27, 2012. http://
hdr.undp.org/en/statistics/hdi.
UNGA (United Nations General Assembly). 2010. “Human Security: Report
of the Secretary-General.” A/64/701. March 8.
Williams, Huw Lloyd. 2011. On Rawls, Development and Global Justice: The
Freedom of Peoples. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
109
Paterson Review of International Affairs (2012) 12: 109–122.

Indigenous Peoples’ Struggles for


Autonomy: The Case of the U’wa People
Juan Martin Arellano Martinez
Norman Paterson School of International Affairs, Carleton University

Latin American indigenous peoples are demanding recognition of their


collective rights to self-determination on their territories. Conflicts over
the past two decades have centred on land and autonomy. Indigenous
peoples’ history and sense of identity are contained in their territories,
which also ensure their economic viability as independent peoples. In
the fight for their cultural survival, they are finding new means of
asserting their collective rights in the face of threats posed by neoliberal
globalization. This article explores the negative and positive effects
that neoliberal globalization has had on indigenous peoples. The article
applies Santos’s sociology of absences and sociology of emergences
to explain the emergence of indigenous peoples’ social movements in
Latin America. The U’wa people’s struggle for autonomy in Colombia
is used as a case study.

Introduction
“We are seeking an explanation for this ‘progress’ that goes against life.
We are demanding that this kind of progress stop. That oil exploration
in the heart of the Earth is halted, that the deliberate bleeding of the
Earth stops.”
—Statement of the U’wa people, August 1998 (Reinsborough 2002)

Indigenous groups around the world face increasing political, economic,


and social discrimination from the dominant societies in which they live.
No communities have been impacted more negatively by the current global
economic system than the world’s remaining 370 million indigenous peoples
(Mander 2005, 3). Those in Latin America are among the most disadvantaged
and discriminated communities in that region. As Latin American economies
continue to grow, more natural resources are needed to fuel economic
growth, which threatens these peoples’ livelihoods since most of the region’s
remaining resources are found on these peoples’ lands (ibid., 3). Indigenous
peoples’ territories contain their history and sense of identity and ensure
their economic viability as independent peoples (Burger 1987, 14). For many
groups, their territories, including everything on them and beneath them,
have sacred value. For the U’wa people of Colombia, oil (ruiría) means the
blood of Mother Earth and to extract it violates their most sacred beliefs
110
(Reinsborough 2002). For multinational corporations, oil is a commodity
that generates lucrative profits. These epistemological differences have led
indigenous groups to demand respect for their cultures through recognition
of their collective rights to self-determination on their territories. To forcibly
relocate these groups is to separate them from their histories. If such separation
occurs, they “will either perish in body or . . . mind and [their] spirits will
be altered so that [they] end up mimicking foreign ways” (Burger 1987, 4).
Self-determination is necessary for them to ensure cultural survival. Notably,
Latin American indigenous peoples are finding new ways of asserting their
collective rights in the face of threats posed by neoliberal globalization.
This article explores the negative and positive effects that globalization
has had on indigenous peoples in Latin America. It builds on the academic
globalization literature and applies Boaventura de Sousa Santos’s theories
of the sociology of absences and sociology of emergences to explain the
emergence of indigenous peoples’ movements demanding autonomy. First, it
assesses the effects of neoliberal globalization on Latin American indigenous
peoples. It then explains the emergence of these peoples’ movements.
The case of the U’wa people is then presented. This article concludes with
recommendations for how governments should approach their indigenous
populations to address demands for autonomy and recognition of rights and
traditional territories.

Globalization and Its Effects on Indigenous Peoples


There is little consensus among academics on globalization’s contemporary
effects because of differences in interpretations of globalization. According
to Jan Aart Scholte (2000, 41), “debates on this subject are littered with all
manner of definitions, chronologies, explanations and evaluations.” Indeed,
no definition of globalization can be completely unambiguous, objective,
fixed, and final (ibid., 42). Moreover, the term may be misleading if taken
literally because some of the processes that it purports to describe may
not be new at all (Dirlik 2006). Scholte (2000, 41) argues that contemporary
globalization can best be described as “deterritorialization,” or as the growth
of “supraterritorial relations” among people. This reconfiguration of time and
space is unprecedented. The growing extensiveness and intensity of global
interconnectedness is the result of the continued increase and speeding up of
global interactions and processes. The evolution of worldwide transportation
systems and information and communications technologies (ICTs) has
increased the velocity of the diffusion of information, ideas, goods, people,
and technological innovations. Although these changes have benefited many,
they have had negative implications for others, such as indigenous peoples
who rarely benefit from global processes or participate in global interactions.
In Latin America, the integration of global economic forces increased
with the spread of neoliberal reforms during the 1980s and the implementation
of the Washington Consensus throughout the 1990s. In the 1980s, indebted
developing countries were offered loans by the International Monetary Fund
111
and the World Bank on the condition that they follow these institutions’
Structural Adjustment Programs, which included neoliberal policies such
as trade liberalization, financial deregulation, and privatization of public
enterprises. In 1989, John Williamson listed 10 reforms that many policy-
makers in Washington thought were needed in Latin America at that time.
This set of reforms, known as the Washington Consensus, included fiscal
discipline, reordering public expenditure priorities, tax reform, liberalizing
interest rates, a competitive exchange rate, trade liberalization, liberalizing
foreign direct investment, privatization, deregulation, and provision of secure
property rights (Williamson 2006). These reforms were intended to address
the macroeconomic deficiencies and debt problems that many developing
countries were facing. However, their results were not as planned. Paul Cooney
(2006) indicates that during the last two decades, “the neoliberal model has
dominated economic policies in Latin America and in general, has produced
lower wages, an increase in unemployment and poverty for the majority of
Latin Americans, as well as financial crises and depressions.” The overall level
of poverty in Latin America increased from 40.5 per cent in 1980 to 48.3 per
cent in 1990, while in rural areas poverty levels increased from 59.9 per cent in
1980 to 65.4 per cent a decade later. The overall level of extreme poverty rose
from 18.6 per cent in 1980 to 22.5 per cent in 1990 (ibid.).
During the 1980s and 1990s, Latin America experienced a period of
globalization, which Cooney understands was in fact a period of neoliberal
globalization. He (ibid.) describes neoliberal globalization as the “renovation
of economic liberalism” in response to the global economic crisis of the late
1960s and early 1970s. It not only changed the structure of the international
system but also the lives of people all over the world. Neoliberal globalization
introduced “the privatization of public enterprises; the liberalization of trade
and financial flows; the deregulation of product, capital and labor markets;
and the downsizing of the state, particularly with regards to economic and
social programming” (Veltmeyer 2005, 6). It cannot, however, be reduced to
its economic aspect. It must be understood to include ecological, political,
social, and cultural aspects as well. The growth and reach of these aspects is a
consequence of the growing extensiveness and intensity of global interactions
and processes, that is, a consequence of the deterritorialization of time and
space, as Scholte has it.
Scholte (2000, 9) explains that supraterritorial relations between people
have had negative consequences such as ecological degradation, persistent
poverty, worsened working conditions, arbitrary inequalities, democratic
deficits, and cultural destruction. Similarly, some observers see neoliberal
globalization as responsible for the loss of cultural diversity and autonomy.
Globalization being the development of a single global culture follows from the
argument that since globalization began in the West, it mainly encourages the
diffusion of Western ideas, values, lifestyles, technologies, and epistemologies.
Proponents of this argument contend that globalization’s epistemologies
are informed by hegemonic Americentric and Eurocentric knowledge and
ideologies that are naturalized and universalized (Seabrook 2004; Santos
112
2003). They also argue that Western knowledge discredits other knowledges
by portraying them as incoherent and inefficient compared to the scientific
method prominent in Western thinking. For Santos, this stigmatization of
non-Western knowledges is the sociology of absences. He (ibid., 238) explains
that the sociology of absences consists of an inquiry that aims to explain that
which does not exist; things that cannot be proven through the application
of the scientific method are considered to be non-existent or non-credible
alternatives to what exists. An example is how the Western ideals of modernity
and globalization deny the sophistication and rationality of indigenous worlds
by categorizing bodies of indigenous knowledge as beliefs or superstitions
based on myths (Blaser, Feit, and McRae 2008). Such categorization of non-
Western knowledges further marginalizes indigenous peoples.
Neoliberal globalization also threatens to accelerate processes of
recolonization in Latin America. Debates on globalization have rarely
considered indigenous peoples’ knowledges and experiences when discussing
the nature of change and related experiences in a globalized world. Resources
found on or beneath these peoples’ territories are often appropriated without
compensation or even consultation. Indigenous peoples’ reluctance to sacrifice
their traditional lands and cultures as governments and multinational
corporations appropriate their territories and resources in the name of
development projects from which they will not benefit exposes them to
further oppression (Beauclerk and Narby with Townsend 1988, 6). As a
result, when these peoples describe their experiences in a globalized world
and conceptualize their understandings of globalization, they emphasize a
continuation of the exercise of power and subjugation that extends over many
centuries (Blaser, Feit, and McRae 2008). They talk about globalization with a
sense of apathy, from a perspective of having seen the physical, psychological,
and spiritual damage it has brought, and with fears that domination will
continue undermining their cultures (ibid.). As such, globalization has
encouraged the growth of loci of governance besides the state, the spread of
forms of community other than the nation, and the development of knowledges
besides modern rationality (Scholte 2000, 8). The Zapatista movement in the
Mexican state of Chiapas since 1994 is an example. The Zapatistas do not seek
to seize state power. Rather, they want to build a different, non-hierarchical
world based on the rotation of representatives by emphasizing the importance
of building communities from the bottom up (Zibechi 2010, 3).

The Emergence of Indigenous Peoples’ Movements


Indigenous peoples’ movements emerged according to what Santos (2003,
238) calls the sociology of emergences, which aims “to identify and enlarge
the signs of possible future experiences” that are actively ignored by
hegemonic knowledge and rationality. As the sociology of absences explains
why indigenous peoples’ experiences, knowledges, and realities have been
largely non-existent in the past, the sociology of emergences illustrates how
these experiences, knowledges, and realities are now emerging as counter-
113
hegemonic forces against Western knowledge and rationality. The rise of these
peoples’ movements is a response to the expansion of globalization’s frontiers
into their territories (Rodríguez-Garavito and Arenas 2005, 242). According to
César Rodríguez-Garavito and Luis Carlos Arenas (ibid.), indigenous groups’
struggles against global economic forces have been shaped by three related
core demands: self-determination, land rights, and cultural survival. Their
movements are repudiating the Westernized mapping of the world as a single
economic entity and resisting the erasures of the past and assimilations of the
present.
As the frontiers of globalization expand, indigenous peoples and their
demands are becoming more visible. Anthony Giddens (2000, 31) argues that
globalization is the reason for the revival of local cultural identities in different
parts of the world. Instead of facilitating cultural assimilation, globalization
is intensifying cultural attitudes and reinforcing differences. Indigenous
peoples in Latin America are resisting global economic forces and demanding
autonomy and recognition of their collective rights to self-determination on
their territories. The peasant identity is losing its political traction and being
gradually supplanted by political organization around indigenous identity
(Jung 2008, 147). This is a result of governments’ failed recolonization and
assimilation policies. Indigenous peoples’ resistance movements rest upon
“the recapturing of their self-concepts and their cultural roots to re/create
spaces of consciousness, possibility, and presence through the re/construction
and mobilization of indigenous discourses, identities, and claims in a variety
of social, legal and political arenas” (Feldman 2002, 34). The most prominent
example of success is the new Bolivian constitution, which was approved in a
constitutional referendum in 2009. It seeks to end the oppression of indigenous
communities which has been going on for centuries. The constitution grants
36 previously marginalized groups rights to territory, language, and their own
community justice systems and declares coca a part of the nation’s heritage.
Upon signing the new constitution, Bolivian President Evo Morales said: “This
is the second independence, the true liberation of Bolivia” (Al Jazeera 2009).
Latin American indigenous peoples’ movements have gained
prominence because of globalization. The dependence of worldwide
economic growth on a continuous resource supply causes natural resources
to become scarcer. Exploration for new resources includes surveying
unexplored and still-pristine lands, many of which belong to indigenous
peoples. Consequently, indigenous peoples, governments, and multinational
corporations are clashing in what Jerry Mander (2005, 4) alternatively calls
“resource wars,” “worldview wars,” or “‘paradigm wars’ . . . deeply based in
opposite understandings of how human beings should live on the earth.” In
Latin America, the globalization of the region’s economies has provoked active
resistance from peasant populations and indigenous communities who see
their survival being threatened by the economic, political, and cultural effects
of neoliberal globalization (Harris 2002, 142). For Roberto Perez, president of
the U’wa governing council and de facto leader of the U’wa people, neoliberal
policies introduced in the 1980s and 1990s were Western ways of thinking and
114
a politic of the government and multinational corporations that was imposed
on the U’wa on their own territories. The resources that have been exploited
have benefited a few groups that hold economic power (Cox 2002). Indigenous
peoples in Latin America have emerged from their shared experiences of
marginalization to combat the forces of neoliberal globalization (Niezen
2003, 9). Their movements are often vigorous and effective. The Zapatistas in
Mexico, the Confederation of Indigenous Nationalities of Ecuador, and the
Aymara in Bolivia are among the most active opponents of neoliberal reforms
and their consequences (Korten 1995, 295).
These movements involve ongoing engagement strategies to create new
relations with broader publics and institutions and new practices. Dorothy
Hodgson (2002, 1040) argues that the formation of visible and effective
movements has been facilitated by an array of transnational connections.
Coalitions between indigenous peoples and non-governmental organizations
(NGOs) have enabled the international promotion of indigenous peoples’
demands for self-determination.1 At the same time, human rights, legal
developments, and peace commissions have played a significant role in the
consolidation of these peoples’ rights. Notably, improvements in ICTs have
allowed indigenous peoples to mobilize beyond the local level and build
strong sub-national, national, regional, and international alliances with
other indigenous and non-indigenous groups. Using ICTs, these peoples are
establishing and maintaining international connections that strengthen their
political voice locally, nationally, and internationally. Alliances are becoming
increasingly important in achieving recognition of indigenous peoples’ rights
at both the national and international levels.
Until recently, most indigenous peoples had no legal protection against
multinational corporations that enter their traditional territories to gain access
to resources. Over the past two decades, international organizations, especially
the United Nations (UN) and International Labour Organization (ILO), have
become gradually more interested in protecting indigenous peoples’ rights.
One of the main outcomes of this interest was the inclusion of Article 14 in
ILO Convention No. 169, which obligates signatory countries to recognize
indigenous peoples’ property rights (Silva 2011, 2). Colombia’s indigenous
peoples have been very successful in protesting against local governments and
multinational corporations by utilizing Article 14 (Ulloa 2005, 47).
More and more, indigenous peoples are shifting their focus to the
international arena, striving to be involved at the highest level possible.
International law now accepts that these peoples enjoy collective rights to
ownership and control of their territories, to exercise their customary laws, and
to represent themselves through their own representative institutions. In this
context, indigenous peoples’ movements have become a form of empowerment
that allows groups to freely establish relations with international agencies as
equal, autonomous social agents that have control over their territories and
resources (Ulloa 2003).
One of indigenous peoples’ main demands is the preservation of their
ability to make all decisions about their ancestral lands. Their goals are to
115
defend their traditional territories and, in many cases, the historical beliefs
and customs associated with their ways of living. They are effectively seeking
to retain their autonomy. Autonomy refers to the capacity of individuals and
groups to shape the conditions under which they live. Regarding groups,
autonomy usually means something closer to the Greek roots autos (self) and
nomos (law)—the capacity to give oneself laws (Blaser, Feit, and McRae 2008).
As indigenous peoples demand autonomy and respect for local forms of
governance, they challenge the historical racist and stereotypical representation
of the “Native” as backwards and primitive. These peoples’ movements
have embraced indigenous epistemologies when challenging Western ideals
and beliefs (Yashar 1998, 23). The concerns of contemporary movements
extend beyond the material concern for land as a productive resource. Land
is central to the definition of self and crucial for the survival of indigenous
identities. The potential and real loss of land affects indigenous peoples’
autonomy and viability as well as their histories, cultures, and spiritual lives.
When non-indigenous people assume that indigenous peoples’ demands for
land primarily reflect economic or political interests and secondarily reflect
spiritual and emotional concerns, they fail to recognize the application of
Western epistemologies that indigenous peoples’ movements try to resist
(Blaser, Feit, and McRae 2008). These movements are effectively resisting
global economic forces by challenging Western epistemologies, demanding
respect, and claiming autonomy over their lands and lives. Santos’s sociology
of emergences explains the emergence of indigenous peoples’ movements as
a counter-hegemonic force opposing neoliberal globalization. One thriving
group is the U’wa, who for more than two decades have asserted their claims
for ownership and control over their territories.

The Case of the U’wa People


The U’wa, a name that means “people who think, people who know how
to speak,” are a community of approximately 8,000 indigenous people who
live in the forests of northeastern Colombia in the departments of Arauca,
Boyacá, Santander, and North Santander (Rodríguez-Garavito and Arenas
2005; Mander and Tauli-Corpuz 2003; Niezen 2003). The original territories
of the U’wa, once a tribe of 20,000, stretched from southern Venezuela into
northeastern Colombia. The U’wa have no written language and their culture
is preserved through songs. Their existence throughout the centuries has
depended on their ancestral lands, resources, and religious practices, all of
which are inextricably intertwined elements of their culture (Rodríguez-
Garavito and Arenas 2005, 245). Their religion dictates that they maintain
harmony among all the layers of creation: earth, water, oil, mountains, and
sky (ibid.). The U’wa believe that they are the sole guardians of the forests
and species on their traditional territories. In fact, they prohibit human access,
including their own, in some areas. Many outsiders marvel at the ability of the
U’wa to sustain themselves without scarring their lands.
Having survived periods of invasion, conquest, and colonization,
116
the U’wa are now again struggling against incursions and subsequent
militarization of their territories related to oil exploration and drilling
(ibid., 243). While oil installations attract armed conflict between guerillas
and Colombian government forces, the main concern of the U’wa is that oil
exploration on their territories will lead to environmental disasters and the
demise of their culture, which will threaten the existence of the tribe as a
cohesive group (Ulloa 2005, 52). One cultural belief of the U’wa is that Mother
Earth, which has sustained them for centuries, is sacred. They believe that Earth
is a living organism and, just as blood runs through the human body to keep it
alive, oil is Earth’s blood that keeps her alive. Their myths of origin tell that oil
must not be extracted since the extraction of oil will only result in greediness,
disorder, and illness, and subsequently the destruction of the environment
and humankind. For the U’wa, “oil is the blood of Mother Earth . . . [T]o take
the oil is, for [them], worse than killing your own mother. If you kill the Earth,
then no one will live” (ibid., 53). They understand that if oil exploration is
allowed on their lands, the balance of their entire world will be disturbed. As
such, the value of economic projects does not exceed the value of humankind
and planet Earth. They believe that pumping oil will lead to deforestation and
oil spills, as well as ecological degradation, which accompanies the laying of
roads in virgin forests. For these reasons, the U’wa oppose oil exploration on
their territories (Rodríguez-Garavito and Arenas 2005, 250). They informed
the Colombian government of the significance of oil in their culture and the
ecological consequences that they expect oil exploration to bring to their
lands. Regardless, the Colombian government granted Occidental Petroleum
Corporation (Oxy) a license in 1992 to drill for oil on U’wa territories.
To defend their property rights, the U’wa turned to the Constitutional
Court of Colombia, which guards the integrity and supremacy of the
constitution and rules on the constitutionality of laws, amendments to the
constitution, and international treaties. They claimed that a royal warrant
granted by the Spanish Crown to the Tuneba Nation, ancestors of the U’wa
people, in 1802 ratified and delimited the jurisdiction of their territories
and gave them the absolute right to all soil and subsoil on their territories
in present-day Arauca, Boyacá, Casanare, Santander, North Santander, and a
part of southwestern Venezuela. These rights were ratified in Colombian Law
153 of 1887 and Article 332 of the 1991 constitution. In 1997 the Constitutional
Court ruled in favour of the U’wa, invoking the 1991 constitution and ILO
Convention No. 169. The court concluded that indigenous collective rights
stand on a par with individual human rights (ibid., 252). However, the more
powerful Council of State of Colombia, the highest court of administrative law,
overthrew the Constitutional Court’s ruling. The council focused on national
law rather than constitutional or international law on indigenous rights. It
found that the Colombian government was not legally obligated to consult
indigenous communities before granting licenses for oil drilling. Informing
the affected groups about extraction plans and eliciting feedback, as the
government had done, satisfied the standards set by national law, according
to the council (ibid.).
117
The U’wa were baffled that both the Constitutional Court and Council
of State had focused on their rights to participate in the consultation process
rather than on the substance of their opposition to oil drilling on principled, as
opposed to procedural, grounds, which they considered to be non-negotiable
(ibid.). The decisions demonstrated that neither the court nor the council
understood the opposition of the U’wa to the drilling of oil. In this case, the
views of the U’wa were not taken into account in the decision-making process
for granting licenses for oil drilling, effectively making their epistemologies
non-existent, according to Santos’s theory of absences.
Nevertheless, the U’wa have continued to denounce oil exploration on
their traditional territories at the national and international levels. The first
U’wa protest against Oxy was launched in March 1993 with a non-violent
campaign involving rallies (ibid., 257). The rallies did not affect the Colombian
government’s stance or stop Oxy’s oil exploration, however. The U’wa then
called three general peasant strikes, which saw approximately 5,000 people
from 48 indigenous groups join together to support their cause (Ulloa 2005,
47). To press the Colombian government to revoke Oxy’s drilling license, the
mobilization effort involved road blockades, which brought the local economy
to a halt, and hunger strikes by indigenous members of Colombia’s Congress
during legislative periods (ibid., 53). The opposition of the U’wa was so strong
that their protest strategy included a pact among themselves to commit mass
suicide2 by jumping off a cliff if Oxy’s exploration plans were not halted
(Rodríguez-Garavito and Arenas 2005; Tebtebba Foundation and International
Forum on Globalization 2005; Ulloa 2005; Niezen 2003). For the U’wa, suicide
is preferable to the desecration of their ancestral lands. In the words of Berito
Kuwaru’wa, an influential U’wa leader who played an instrumental role in an
international campaign to stop oil drilling: “We would rather die, protecting
everything that we hold sacred, than lose everything that makes us U’wa”
(Ulloa 2005, 47). The threat of mass suicide has made the U’wa a symbol of
worldwide resistance to neoliberal globalization by indigenous peoples
(Rodríguez-Garavito and Arenas 2005, 251).
U’wa leaders assert that their people want to continue their way of life
on their own territories. Such a view does not apply only in situations such as
incursions and oil exploration—it is also being adapted as the foundation of
a different development model that responds to environmental crises caused
by resource extraction. The U’wa are just one indigenous group among many
that wants to preserve the planet for future generations. In accordance with
Santos’s sociology of emergences, such signs of possible future experiences
ignored by the current global economic model are beginning to emerge as
alternatives to the current hegemonic system.
What is more, the U’wa have earned the support of many NGOs such as
Rainforest Action Network, Amazon Defense Coalition, and Oilwatch, which
have helped them campaign against Oxy. The case of the U’wa people has
been prominently featured at several events, in particular the protests against
the International Monetary Fund and World Bank in Washington, DC, in 2000,
the 2004 Social Forum of the Americas held in Quito, and the annual World
118
Social Forum (ibid., 255). The U’wa movement is evidently growing through
strategies of engagement with broader publics and institutions, giving rise to
new relations with supporters and new practices. The extensive and speedy
capabilities of ICTs have allowed the movement to go global. For instance,
the U’wa and their supporters have initiated negative publicity campaigns
through mass media and protests in front of Oxy’s headquarters in Los
Angeles, which turned the Colombian project into a public relations nightmare
for the company. The actions of the U’wa and their supporters forced Oxy to
leave the traditional territories of the U’wa in 2002 and return its oil concession
to the Colombian government (Tebtebba Foundation and International Forum
on Globalization 2005, 164). Nonetheless, Ecopetrol, a Colombian state-owned
enterprise, started drilling oil on U’wa lands in 2003, forcing the U’wa people
to again resist (ibid.). Their resistance continues until today.
The U’wa want to retain control over their traditional territories and
ensure cultural survival. As Perez asserts: “[W]hat we’re saying is respect our
territory” (Semple 2002). The U’wa are demanding not only respect for their
rights, as stipulated in the 1991 constitution and ILO Convention No. 169,
but their autonomy. In response to the decision by the Council of State, the
U’wa have gone to the Inter-American Commission on Human Rights of the
Organization of American States (OAS) to present their grievances. At the time
of writing, the case is still in process.

Conclusion
The U’wa people’s actions against Oxy and the Colombian government
illustrate that resistance against multinational corporations and national
governments is possible. Their relative success is a result of the combination
of grassroots mobilization at the local level with national and international
support, and the simultaneous pursuit of political and legal strategies both
nationally and internationally. In many instances, actions by Latin American
indigenous peoples are being legitimized throughout the region. The U’wa
movement has been effective insofar as it has managed to: (1) bring the issue
of indigenous rights vis-à-vis resource extraction in Colombia to the fore; (2)
influence discourses on indigenous cultural significance; and (3) change target
actors’ policies (Rodríguez-Garavito and Arenas 2005, 261). However, the key
issue is control, whether over land, knowledge, the past, the present, or the
future.
Through resistance, indigenous peoples vindicate their right to exist
and remain distinct from the dominant societies in which they live. The U’wa
resist the Colombian government, which remains committed to the neoliberal
model and characterized by exclusions and inequalities. Throughout Latin
America, indigenous peoples’ resistance movements and ways of life will
continue to demonstrate that there exist contemporary economic, political, and
social alternatives to the commodification of all resources (Harry 2005, 76). The
U’wa have interpreted appropriate and often necessary modes of economic
behaviour through songs, myths, and beliefs, which affirm and reinforce their
119
relationship with the Earth. The U’wa cosmogony goes beyond its locality—it
is part of the reframing of the relations between society and nature imposed by
the Western world. The slogan of the World Social Forum is “Another world is
possible.” To achieve another world, this world needs to imagine both “other
worlds” and “worlds otherwise”; that is, “worlds that are more just and
sustainable and, at the same time, worlds that are defined through principles
other than those of Eurocentric modernity” (Escobar 2004, 220). Resistance to
neoliberal globalization is not just an ecological and political necessity, but a
cultural necessity as well.
Latin American governments are encountering resistance from their
indigenous populations, who are demanding recognition of their collective
rights to self-determination on their territories. State recognition of these
populations’ rights to land and resources is one approach to rebalancing the
distribution of property rights and implementing certain self-government
forms of territorial jurisdiction that retain or restore indigenous peoples’ control
over their traditional territories. It is crucial that indigenous peoples’ rights,
as enshrined in national laws and international agreements, are implemented
and not merely paid lip service. In this regard, signatory countries of ILO
Convention No. 1693 and the UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous
Peoples4 must fulfill their obligations outlined in these documents. It is likely
that Latin American governments will only fully embrace their obligations if
they are pressured to do so by their own populations, other governments, and
international actors such as NGOs. Therefore, mutual co-operation between
indigenous peoples around the world and international organizations, such as
the UN, ILO, OAS, and specialized NGOs, and integrated capacities enabled
by ICTs are needed to help shape global public opinion, which can support
indigenous peoples in realizing their aspirations.
120
Notes
1. NGOs such as Amazon Watch, Oxfam International, and Cultural Survival
have been strong supporters of Latin American indigenous peoples.
2. Some U’wa communities committed mass suicide several centuries earlier
to avoid being enslaved by Spanish conquistadors.
3. Fourteen out of the 22 signatory countries to ILO Convention No. 169 are
from Latin America.
4. Bolivia was the first country to approve the United Nations Declaration on
the Rights of Indigenous Peoples.

Acknowledgements
The author would like to thank Dr. Mario Blaser for his support and
guidance, the editors and blind reviewers of the Paterson Review, as well as
the expert reviewers for their comments and suggestions which made this
article much more robust.

References
Al Jazeera. 2009. “Bolivia Enacts New Constitution.” Al Jazeera, February 7.
http://www.aljazeera.com/news/americas/2009/02/2009271736487938
18.html
Beauclerk, John, and Jeremy Narby, with Janet Townsend. 1988. Indigenous
Peoples: A Field Guide for Development. Oxford: Oxfam.
Blaser, Mario, Harvey A. Feit, and Glenn McRae, eds. 2008. In Way of
Development: Indigenous Peoples, Life Projects and Globalization. London:
Zed Books.
Burger, Julian. 1987. Report From the Frontier: The State of the World’s
Indigenous Peoples. London: Zed Books.
Cooney, Paul. 2006. “The Decline of Neoliberalism and the Role of Social
Movements in Latin America.” Paper presented at the X Jornadas de
Economía Crítica, ¿Alternativas al capitalismo?, Barcelona, Spain,
March 23–25.
Cox, Karen. 2002. “Questions Gerry Adams Could Have Asked the US
Congress about the ‘Andean Regional Initiative’.” The Blanket: A
Journal of Protest and Dissent, May 4. http://indiamond6.ulib.iupui.
edu:81/questionsga.html.
Dirlik, Arif. 2006. “Globalization as the End and the Beginning of History:
The Contradictory Implications of a New Paradigm.” Working Paper,
Duke University, Durham, NC.
Escobar, Arturo. 2004. “Beyond the Third World: Imperial Globality, Global
Coloniality and Anti-Globalization Social Movements.” Third World
Quarterly 25 (1): 207–30.
Feldman, Alice. 2002. “Making Space at the Nations’ Table: Mapping the
Transformative Geographies of the International Indigenous Peoples’
Movement.” Social Movement Studies 1 (1): 31–46.
121
Giddens, Anthony. 2000. Runaway World: How Globalization is Reshaping Our
Lives. New York: Routledge.
Harris, Richard L. 2002. “Resistance and Alternatives to Globalization in
Latin America and the Caribbean.” Latin American Perspectives 20 (6):
136–51.
Harry, Debra. 2005. “High-Tech Invasion: Biocolonialism.” In Paradigm Wars:
Indigenous Peoples’ Resistance to Globalization, edited by Terry Mander
and Victoria Tauli-Corpuz, 71–76. San Francisco: Sierra Club Books.
Hodgson, Dorothy L. 2002. “Introduction: Comparative Perspective on the
Indigenous Rights Movement in Africa and the Americas.” American
Anthropologist 104 (4): 1037–49.
Jung, Courtney. 2008. The Moral Force of Indigenous Politics: Critical Liberalism
and the Zapatistas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Korten, David. 1995. When Corporations Rule the World. San Francisco:
Berrett-Koehler.
Mander, Jerry. 2005. “Introduction: Globalization and the Assault on
Indigenous Resources.” In Paradigm Wars: Indigenous Peoples’
Resistance to Globalization, edited by Terry Mander and Victoria Tauli-
Corpuz, 3–10. San Francisco: Sierra Club Books.
Niezen, Ronald. 2003. The Origins of Indigenism: Human Rights and the Politics
of Identity. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Reinsborough, Patrick. 2002. “Victory for the U’wa.” Earth First! Journal.
http://www.earthfirstjournal.org/article.php?id=130.
Rodríguez-Garavito, César A., and Luis Carlos Arenas. 2005. “Indigenous
Rights, Transnational Activism, and Legal Mobilization: The Struggle
of the U’wa People in Colombia.” In Law and Globalization from Below:
Towards a Cosmopolitan Legality, edited by Boaventura de Sousa Santos
and César A. Rodríguez-Garavito, 241–66. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Santos, Boaventura de Sousa. 2003. “The World Social Forum: Toward a
Counter-Hegemonic Globalization (Part I and II).” In World Social
Forum: Challenging Empires, edited by Jai Sen, Anita Anand, Arturo
Escobar, and Peter Waterman, 235–45. New Delhi: Viveka Foundation.
Scholte, Jan Aart. 2000. Globalization: A Critical Introduction. New York: St.
Martin’s Press.
Seabrook, Jeremy. 2004. “Localizing Cultures.” Korea Herald, January 13.
http://www.globalpolicy.org/globaliz/cultural/2004/0113jeremyseabr
ook.htm.
Semple, Kirk. 2002. “The U’was’ Last Stand: Colombian Indians vs.
Occidental Petroleum.” U.S. News & World Report, February 6. http://
www.usnews.com/usnews/news/articles/000214/archive_032984.htm.
Silva, Diego. 2011. “Going Beyond Recognition: Building an Effective and
Sustainable Property Rights Systems for Indigenous Territories.”
International Affairs Review XX (1): 1–20.
Tebtebba Foundation and International Forum on Globalization. 2005.
“Briefing Reports.” In Paradigm Wars: Indigenous Peoples’ Resistance
122
to Globalization, edited by Jerry Mander and Victoria Tauli-Corpuz,
163–77. San Francisco: Sierra Club Books.
Ulloa, Astrid. 2003. “The Ecological Native: Indigenous Peoples’ Movements
and Eco-Governmentality in Colombia.” Paper presented at the 2003
meeting of the Latin American Studies Association, Dallas, Texas,
March 27–29.
———. 2005. The Ecological Native: Indigenous People’s Movements and Eco
Governmentality in Colombia. New York: Routledge.
Veltmeyer, Henry. 2005. “Development and Globalization as Imperialism.”
Canadian Journal of Development Studies 26 (1): 89–106.
Williamson, John. 2006. “After the Washington Consensus: Latin American
Growth and Sustainable Development.” Keynote speech at the
Seminar on Latin American Financing and the Role of Development
Banks organized by the IDB, BDMG, and ALIDE, Belo Horizonte,
Brazil, March 30–31.
Yashar, Deborah J. 1998. “Contesting Citizenship: Indigenous Movements
and Democracy in Latin America.” Comparative Politics 31 (1): 23–42.
Zibechi, Raul. 2010. Dispersing Power: Social Movements as Anti-State Forces.
Translated by Ramor Ryan. Oakland: AK Press.
123
Paterson Review of International Affairs (2012) 12: 123–143.

The Quiet Tsunami: The Ecological,


Economic, Social, and Political
Consequences of Ocean Acidification
Natassia Ciuriak
School of Public Policy and Administration, Carleton University

A large portion of the carbon dioxide emitted into the atmosphere


is absorbed by the world’s oceans. They become more acidic as they
absorb the gas. This has far-reaching implications for the oceanic
food web, biodiversity, and the global economy, particularly fishing
and ecotourism industries in developing countries. This article
briefly outlines the scientific evidence of ocean acidification and the
implications of anthropogenic carbon emissions for marine ecosystems.
It then assesses the economic, social, and political ramifications of
ocean acidification and suggests a new strategy for the promotion of
climate change policy. The “quiet tsunami” of oceanic climate change
necessitates a policy shift away from the business-as-usual approach to
reducing carbon emissions. The high stakes involved in this looming
crisis may prompt unwilling governments to act in order to ensure food
security and protect key economic markets around the world.

Introduction
Marine food resources have supported human civilizations from time
immemorial. However, humanity’s path to economic development over the
past century has created a newly emerging threat to oceanic health. Humans
have been dramatically increasing their emissions of carbon dioxide (CO2)
and other greenhouse gases into the atmosphere as population, industrial
activity, and international trade and travel have grown. Emissions, which
increase the atmospheric concentration of CO2, continue unabated, driven in
good measure by rising income levels and related energy-intensive privileges
in some of the world’s most populous countries, notably China and India.
This reinforces the ongoing problem of global warming, which raises the
temperature of ocean waters, the sea level (by melting continental glaciers),
and, importantly for this discussion, the acidity of oceans. In fact, up to half
of the total amount of CO2 released because of human activities over the past
two centuries has been absorbed by oceans (Royal Society 2005, 5).
A rapid increase in the absorption of CO2 lowers the pH level of
seawater—this is a phenomenon commonly known as ocean acidification—
and decreases carbonate-ion concentration (Zeebe and Wolf-Gladrow 2001).
124
Of course, oceans are neither homogeneous nor static. The pH level of seawater
varies with pressure and temperature, and thus is influenced by depth and
latitude. Polar waters differ from temperate waters, coastal regions differ
from open oceans, and different regions of oceans are affected differently
by particular patterns of water circulation. For example, the pH level can be
affected by horizontal flows such as the Gulf Stream, vertical interchanges
in which surface waters sink in some places and nutrient rich waters upwell
from the depths in others, and the influx of alkaline river waters. There are
also diurnal, seasonal, and multi-year cycles. Over sufficiently long periods of
time, measured in thousands of years, the equilibrium pH level of seawater is
restored by kinetic, chemical, and biological processes (Caldeira et al. 2007).
The impact of CO2 absorption on key parts of the oceanic food web is
well established. As Richard Feely et al. (2008, 1490) explain: “The reaction
of CO2 with seawater reduces the availability of carbonate ions that are
necessary for calcium carbonate (CaCO3) skeleton and shell formation for
marine organisms such as corals, marine plankton, and shellfish.” Once
formed, calcium carbonate dissolves if seawater is not sufficiently saturated
with carbonate ions (CO32-). Since calcium carbonate is more soluble at lower
temperatures and at higher pressures, there is a saturation horizon below
which calcium carbonate dissolves. Marine organisms that produce calcium
carbonate, referred to as calcifiers, inhabit waters above the saturation
horizon, the depth of which varies from place to place. Increased absorption
of CO2 by oceans thus both reduces the availability of the building blocks
used by coral, plankton, shellfish, and other calcifiers and modifies the depth
and temperature of the water at which these organisms can exist.
A large and fast change to the chemistry of oceans caused by
anthropogenic carbon emissions threatens important oceanic ecosystems.
Damage to plankton, which underpins the oceanic food web, and coral
reefs, which house much of the planet’s marine biodiversity, will have
repercussions throughout the entire marine ecosystem. This is described by
the Secretariat of the Convention on Biological Diversity (2009, 49): “Many
calcifying species are located at the bottom or middle of global ocean food
webs, therefore loss of shelled organisms to ocean acidification will alter
predator–prey relationships and the effects will be transmitted throughout the
ecosystem [emphasis added].”
Recognition that global warming is not detrimental everywhere in
the world (UNFCCC 2011) has served to weaken national and international
political responses to climate change, but there are no similar offsetting benefits
when it comes to ocean acidification. Moreover, unlike with global warming,
there is no debate about the anthropogenic cause of ocean acidification.1
Ocean acidification provides a unique opportunity for people
who advocate for action on climate change to reinforce their demands
on governments to take action. It is a direct and incontrovertible result of
anthropogenic carbon emissions and will affect fishing and ecotourism
industries. Accordingly, an emphasis on the major observable effects of
climate change on the world’s oceans, collectively described as the “quiet
125
tsunami” (NRDC 2009, 1), can result in political action on climate change
mitigation. To give but one example, concerns about the ramifications of
ocean acidification on the Great Barrier Reef helped tilt the balance of votes in
Australia toward the implementation of a carbon tax.2
The Government of Canada has thus far avoided action that would
allow it to meet emissions reduction targets under the Kyoto Protocol, from
which it withdrew in December 2011 citing costs and probable disruption of
certain economic sectors (Delacourt 2010). All the while the government has
ignored the cost of inaction (see McLaughlin 2011). This article demonstrates
that while action on climate change may be perceived as costly, inaction will
be costlier in the long run. It argues that there is a definite need for immediate
action, since national and global problems related to climate change will only
increase in number and severity should climate change and ocean acidification
be allowed to continue unabated.

Literature Review
Research on ocean acidification is in its relative infancy. In 2009, 62 per cent of
research papers on ocean acidification had been published since 2004 (Hood
et al. 2009, 7). The 2005 report on ocean acidification by the Royal Society
developed by a nine-member working group, which drew on submissions
from 33 professionals in the field, provided a comprehensive review of
the then-extant literature. It serves as a baseline assessment of the state of
knowledge on the causes and effects of ocean acidification as well as marine
organism and ecosystem responses and adaptation to elevated levels of
acidity. The Royal Society (2005, 39–41) reached eight main conclusions:

• Oceans are absorbing the CO2 that is released into the atmosphere by
human activities and this is causing chemical changes which make
seawater more acidic.
• These changes in ocean chemistry will impact marine organisms and
ecosystems.
• Oceans play a very important role in the global carbon cycle and
Earth’s climate system.
• The socio-economic consequences of ocean acidification could be
substantial, given the effects on coral reefs and fisheries.
• The scale of future changes to the chemistry and acidity of oceans
can only be reduced by preventing the accumulation of CO2 in the
atmosphere.
• Unless global emissions of CO2 are reduced by twice their 2005 levels
by the year 2100, the Southern Ocean will become under-saturated
for aragonite, which is required by some organisms to make calcium
carbonate skeletons and shells.
• The magnitude of ocean acidification can be predicted with a high
level of confidence. Assessments of its impacts, particularly on marine
organisms, are much less certain and require additional research efforts.
126
• Ocean acidification is a powerful reason, in addition to climate
change, to reduce global CO2 emissions.

In 2009, the Secretariat of the Convention on Biological Diversity


provided additional grounds for concern. It (2009, 9) confirmed that ocean
acidification is a result of anthropogenic CO2 emissions and that many of
its effects on marine ecosystems will be variable and complex. Although
evidence found that a few species, such as some phytoplankton, fungi, and
bacteria, may experience certain benefits, the Secretariat (ibid.) warned that
most ecosystems in acidified seawater are less diverse and missing those
species that form their skeletons and shells from calcium carbonate. Further,
it documented various sub-lethal effects of exposure to low pH on various
organisms’ developmental and adult phases. These effects vary depending on
a species’ genetics, pre-existing capabilities to adapt to changing conditions,
and environmental factors.3 Importantly, the Secretariat (ibid., 5) outlined the
following:

By 2100, 70% of cold-water corals, key refuges and feeding grounds


for commercial fish species, will be exposed to corrosive waters.
Furthermore, given current emission rates, it is predicted that the
surface waters of the highly productive Arctic Ocean will become under-
saturated with respect to essential carbonate minerals by the year 2032,
and the Southern Ocean by 2050, with disruptions to large components
of the marine food web.

The Secretariat (ibid., 9) concluded that acidification is “irreversible on


timescales of at least tens of thousands of years, and substantial damage to
ocean ecosystems can only be avoided by urgent and rapid reductions in
global emissions of CO2.”
The amount of CO2 that will be released by the end of the century
under a business-as-usual scenario will be large and extremely rapid in the
geological time scale. Data from Antarctic ice cores show that the concentration
of CO2 in the atmosphere over the past 650,000 years varied between a low
of 180 parts per million (ppm) during cold glacial periods to a high of 300
ppm during warm inter-glacial periods (IPCC 2007, 465). By 2010, the mean
concentration of atmospheric CO2 at sea level was measured to be 389.78 parts
per million by volume (ppmv) (NOAA 2011b). Current CO2 concentration is
in the range last recorded during the Pliocene (circa five to three million years
ago), a period in which the global temperature was substantially warmer and
sea levels were much higher (Pagani et al. 2010). The amount of CO2 that
will be released during this century will likely be greater than any amount
recorded since the Palaeocene-Eocene Thermal Maximum (PETM) some 55
million years ago (Dickens, Castillo, and Walker 1997). That event caused
widespread dissolution of seafloor carbonates (Zachos et al. 2005) and a mass
extermination of seafloor (“benthic”) species (Ridgwell and Schmidt 2010).
Notably, the buildup of CO2 during the PETM was much more gradual than
127
the present buildup (Kump, Bralower, and Ridgwell 2009).
John Veron (2008) shows that the five mass extinction events which
Earth has experienced so far were each associated with “reef gaps” in the
geological record—extended periods during which there is no evidence
of living reefs. These periods were linked to changes in ocean chemistry
associated with atmospheric CO2 levels. Veron (ibid., 459) argues that “The
prospect of ocean acidification is potentially the most serious of all predicted
outcomes of anthropogenic carbon dioxide increase . . . [and] has the potential
to trigger a sixth mass extinction event.” Similarly, an extensive literature
review conducted by Scott Doney et al. (2009, 184) concluded that “[a]
cidification impacts on processes so fundamental to the overall structure and
function of marine ecosystems that any significant changes could have far-
reaching consequences for the oceans of the future and the millions of people
that depend on its [sic] food and other resources for their livelihoods.”4
Comparing the PETM to the current buildup, Andy Ridgwell and Daniela
Schmidt (2010, 5) observe as follows:

We infer a future rate of surface-ocean acidification and environmental


pressure on marine calcifiers unprecedented in the past 65 [million
years], and one that challenges the potential for surface-ocean plankton
to adapt. For benthic organisms, rapid and extreme undersaturation
of the deep ocean would make their situation precarious, and the
occurrence of widespread extinction of these organisms during the
PETM greenhouse warming and acidification event raises the possibility
of similar extinction in the future.

Economic and Social Impacts of Ocean Acidification


Research on the economic impact of ocean acidification remains limited.
Attempts at overall economic assessments of climate change either ignore this
phenomenon (Tol 2002a; 2002b) or give it only a passing mention without
incorporating its costs into the analysis (Stern 2006; Nordhaus 2008; Tol 2009).
Accordingly, drawing attention to the economic impacts of ocean acidification
is crucial when informing public opinion and, by extension, public policy.
The fishing industry is a small but significant component of the global
economy. The total contribution of commercial capture fisheries, including
marine and inland harvest and post-harvest subsectors, to global gross
domestic product (GDP) was estimated at approximately US$274 billion in
2007 (World Bank, FAO, and WorldFish Center 2010), of which about 90 per
cent can be attributed to marine fisheries, based on the value share of the
capture. This figure is small in the context of a global economy valued at
approximately US$62 trillion (IMF 2010), but it is not negligible. Aquaculture
is the fastest growing animal food-producing sector and currently accounts
for almost half of total food fish supply; approximately one-third of
aquaculture production is marine-based (FAO 2011). While studies of ocean
acidification have mainly focused on natural marine ecosystems, the issue
128
has registered on the aquaculture industry’s radar. In 2010, a brief session on
ocean acidification was held at the triennial meeting of the World Aquaculture
Society together with the U.S. National Shellfisheries Association.
The overall economic impact of ocean acidification on marine fisheries
and aquaculture has not yet been systematically evaluated. Studies of specific
types of marine organisms such as shellfish, on which aquaculture depends,
demonstrate that the costs are substantial (Talmage and Gobler 2009; Narita,
Rehdanz, and Tol 2011). Relative to the risks posed by climate change,
however, the impact on any specific type of fishery is small in dollar value,
commensurate with the share of fisheries in global GDP. For instance, the
cost to shellfish production in 2100 would be about US$100 billion, which
represents up to 1.5 per cent of the total expected damage caused by climate
change and around 0.025 per cent of global GDP (ibid., 14).
Specific economic impacts matter in politics. On average, the United
States annually derives US$4 billion of primary value from commercial harvests
from American waters and at-sea processing (NOAA 2011a). Approximately
24 per cent of this figure comes from harvesting fish that depend directly on
calcifiers (Cooley and Doney 2009). Aquaculture, which also depends heavily
on calcifiers, accounted for over US$1.2 billion in additional income in 2007.
The National Oceanic and Atmospheric Administration calculated that one
million jobs are associated with the American commercial fishing industry,
which accounts for about US$32 billion in income annually (NOAA 2011a).
Ocean acidification will negatively affect these figures and may have tangible
political ramifications.
Impacts will certainly be felt in recreational fishing and marine tourism.
While commercial fishing, including international trade, in the United States
was valued at US$70 billion in 2009 (ibid.), recreational fishing contributed
US$50 billion in sales impacts, US$23 billion in value-added impacts, and
supported 327,000 jobs (National Marine Fisheries Service 2011, 8). Marine
tourism has become one of the fastest-growing areas of the world’s tourism
industry (Hall 2001, 602). Australia’s Great Barrier Reef receives roughly two
million visits each year and generates about US$5.7 billion in tourism and
fishing revenue, which sustains 53,800 full-time jobs (McCook et al. 2010).
Tourism around the Hawaiian coral reefs accounts for about US$364 million
annually in value-added economic activity, 84 per cent of which is generated
from snorkelling and diving on reefs. Further added value from property
accounts for US$40 million each year, generated by rising property values
near healthy reefs (Royal Society 2005, 33).
The effects of ocean acidification on these industries could inform potent
arguments that may prove to convince reluctant governments to act on climate
change. For example, the Royal Society concluded that even under modest
emissions scenarios, which predict an atmospheric concentration of 600 ppmv
of CO2 by 2100, climate change is predicted to cost the economy around the
Great Barrier Reef a minimum of US$2.6 billion over 19 years to 2020 (ibid.).
Under higher emissions scenarios with an atmospheric CO2 concentration of
800 ppmv, losses will rise to over US$14.6 billion (ibid.). More recent estimates
129
place the net present value of the Great Barrier Reef at US$51.5 billion and
the cost of serious degradation of the reef system at US$39.2 billion, of which
US$15.8 billion represents intrinsic value (Oxford Economics 2009).
Although these figures may seem small relative to the value of the
global economy and costs thought to be associated with a shift from fossil fuels
to renewable energies, they belie the importance of fishing and ecotourism
to certain regions. Narrow sectoral impacts can have disproportionately
large influences on national policies. For instance, Canada and Spain almost
went to war over illegal overfishing on the Grand Banks in 1995 (Schaefer
1995). Furthermore, the roots of piracy in Somalia can be traced to concerns
about fishing rights. As Patrick Lennox (2008, 8) writes: “[Somalian pirates]
were acting at first to protect their territorial waters from illegal fishing and
dumping by foreigners, which became progressively significant as it became
more and more evident to outsiders that Somalia was not capable of patrolling
its exclusive economic zone.” Although these two examples are unrelated to
ocean acidification, they highlight the value of the fishing industry to those
that rely on it and the lengths that governments and individuals are willing
to go in order to protect resources.
Ocean acidification, unlike illegal trawling or disputes over fishing
rights, will affect every country that trades fish or fishery products because
no waters will be exempt from this phenomenon, though the distribution of
effects will by no means be even. Importantly, the countries with the greatest
interest in marine fisheries include leading developed countries, such as
the United States, the European Union, and Japan, and major developing
countries, such as India and China, the latter of which accounts for about 16
per cent of total catch—by far the largest share (European Commission 2010,
16). The health of the fishing industry thus impacts most, if not all, countries
with a coastline and threatens local economic activity and food security.

Challenges Faced by Developing Countries


The problem of ocean acidification has implications for global equity. Seafood
makes up more than 20 per cent of consumed animal protein for 2.6 billion
people worldwide and over 30 per cent in the developing world (Gupta
2006, 4). Coral reefs provide habitat for 25 per cent of total catch, increasing
food security for one billion people in Asia alone (CDNN 2009). Developing
countries provided approximately half of the total export value of trade in
seafood products in 2006, with 80 per cent of all imports going to developed
countries. Throughout the developing world, the fishing industry directly
employs about 150 million people (Hauge, Cleeland, and Wilson 2009, 2).
In addition, fishing is a particularly important source of support for
many households at the subsistence level. A Vietnamese case study showed
that when subsistence fishing was taken into account, total marine capture
was about 58 per cent higher compared to official statistics (which do not
take into account subsistence fishing) (World Bank, FAO, and WorldFish
Center 2010, 43). The study found that in 10 provinces adjacent to the Mekong
130
Delta more than eight million people relied directly on the capture of fish
and aquatic animals to meet their nutritional needs. Disruption or collapse
of the fishing industry would thus put considerable strains on social support
networks and intensify urbanization pressures.
Southeast Asia and the Caribbean depend greatly on oceans for
nutrition and incomes and are located near some of the most vulnerable
waters in the world. The Philippines provides an illustrative case study of
the impact of deteriorating coral reefs on developing countries, since the
country is found in one of the world’s most prolific coral-producing, though
most acidic, areas. The Coral Triangle covers 1.6 billion acres of Southeast
Asia and is the planet’s most biologically diverse region in terms of marine
biota (Hoegh-Guldberg et al. 2009, 5). Coral reefs are important to the Filipino
people for nutritional and economic reasons, among others. Reefs provide
habitat for fish species upon which the Filipino population depends for 50 per
cent of its animal protein intake (White, Vogt, and Arin 2000, 598). These reefs
provide livelihoods for over one million small-scale fishermen and contribute
almost US$1 billion annually to the Filipino economy (ibid.). It is estimated
that reef fish account for 20 per cent of total catch in the country (ibid., 599). A
loss of fisheries-related incomes and employment would significantly stress
national organizations and international bodies concerned with humanitarian
needs, such as the United Nations World Food Programme. Furthermore,
there would be a huge, albeit immeasurable, loss in the intrinsic value of
a unique culture, a way of life, and some of the world’s largest and most
beautiful coral reefs.
Coral reefs are also crucial for the ecotourism industry, which encourages
sustainable practices in local host economies while providing governments
with additional tourism-derived tax revenue. Ecotourism has been shown to
address certain dimensions of poverty and complement conservation efforts
(Ministry of Population and the Environment of Nepal 2004, 209). Estimates
suggest that ecotourism associated with coral reefs generates US$300,800/
km2 per year in revenue for the Filipino government (White, Vogt, and Arin
2000, 600). With a total reef area of 26,000 km2, the Philippines could lose an
important source of revenue because of ocean acidification.
Coral reefs are worth conserving because of the tangible nutritional and
economic benefits that coastal communities derive from them as well as their
intrinsic value. These fragile systems are under a variety of anthropogenic
stresses, including dangerous fishing practices, effluent runoff, and most
recently ocean acidification. Additional stresses hinder ecosystems’ abilities
to recover and remain productive. The reefs have been deteriorating over the
past 30 years. In 2001, the United Nations Environment Programme reported
that 97 per cent of Filipino reefs were under threat (Spalding, Ravilious, and
Green 2001). By 2007, Reef Check, an international organization that assesses
the health of reefs in 82 countries, stated that only 5 per cent of the Philippines’
coral reefs were doing well, with the rest being damaged, diseased, or dead
(Agriculture Business Week 2008).
The case study of the Philippines is just the tip of the iceberg. Coral
131
reefs around the world are deteriorating because of anthropogenic stresses.
Losses in economic value, among other things, are a main result. For example,
Lauretta Burke et al. (2011, 78) found that the projected degradation of
Caribbean reefs will result in relatively large annual economic losses: by 2015,
reef-associated fisheries will lose between US$95 million and US$140 million
in net revenues while ecotourism will suffer losses between US$100 million
and US$300 million. Southeast Asia as a whole is extremely vulnerable to
reef loss and consequent economic losses (ibid., 73). It bears repeating that
ocean acidification causes much damage to coral reefs by corroding them
and, due to the reduction in the availability of calcium carbonate, preventing
new structural growth.

Global Equity and Climate Change


Global equity is a central aspect of the international climate change debate.
While developed countries’ carbon-intensive development is responsible
for much of the climate change to date, developing countries are left to
suffer many of the consequences with relatively little adaptive capacity. It
is true that the contemporary carbon-based development of some populous
developing countries is contributing to this problem, but as South African
Minister of Environmental Affairs and Tourism Marthinus van Schalkwyk
(2009) said: “[W]e cannot wish away historical responsibility for the problem.
The fact of the matter is that the carbon space is finite and 70% of the ‘safe’
carbon space has already been used up, largely by industrialized countries.”
Most of the responsibility to act therefore lies with developed countries. They
have the capacity and technologies to adapt to a warming planet and the duty
to help developing countries adapt. Not only is this the right path to take
environmentally, but economically there are benefits to the proliferation of
clean-energy technologies.
The phenomenon of ocean acidification raises the stakes for action on
climate change. The choice is not one of comfort and convenience but rather one
of survival because “[t]he harm is against humans, it is largely other-inflicted,
and it is not life-style-, but life-threatening” (Müller 2002, 2). Damage done by
ocean acidification will threaten the food security and incomes of billions of
people. Many of those people live in developing countries that do not have
the organizational, technological, or financial capabilities to handle food
distribution and economic dislocation. Stresses will further slow development
in key parts of the world, namely Southeast Asia and the Caribbean.

Ocean Acidification and Climate Change Policy


There is a disconnect between polluters and pollution victims when it comes
to the issue of global equity in the context of a changing climate. Developed
countries first acknowledged their obligation to provide financial support for
developing countries’ climate change mitigation and adaption efforts in the
1992 United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC)
132
(Demerse 2009, 1). Their sense of obligation is informed by two principles:
(1) the polluter pays principle, which dictates that the polluter should bear
the financial burden of repairing damage caused by pollution and preventing
further pollution; and (2) common but differentiated responsibility, which
refers to the globally shared responsibility to protect shared resources, with the
caveat that responsibility is different depending on a country’s contribution
to an environmental problem and its capacity to address that problem (ibid.,
5). Governments and firms tend to offer economic explanations for their
adoption of a wait-and-see approach to climate change, often arguing that
climate change mitigation is simply too expensive. Such arguments are
baseless and hypocritical. Ocean acidification may prove to be the missing
puzzle piece that enables local, national, and international climate change
advocates to promote change in climate change policy-making.
The costs of ocean acidification have largely been ignored. North
America in particular has been unwilling to change its business-as-usual
approach. The United States has rejected internationally coordinated climate
change policies, arguing that any deal that does not include large emitters such
as China is not fair and the economic impact on Americans is unacceptable. In
2006, Canadian Prime Minister Stephen Harper emphasized industry worries
that meeting emissions reduction targets would cost too much (Suzuki and
Taylor 2009, 95–96) and has since pulled out of the Kyoto Protocol to avoid
heavy penalties for his country’s failure to act. However, as Ken Thompson
(2010) argues, the cost argument hardly stands since unnecessarily high
military budgets could be reworked to make more money available for
spending to tackle climate change. Nicholas Stern (2006, xvii) demonstrates
that inaction will raise the costs of adaptation and annual revenues of up to
US$2.5 trillion can be generated by taking a low-carbon path.
The international movement for global co-operative action on climate
change has also been hindered by denialism by conservative political parties,
think tanks, and media corporations often funded to some degree by fossil
fuel-related corporations (Suzuki and Taylor 2009; Dunlap and McCright
2010; Hoggan and Littlemore 2009; Monbiot 2006; Gutstein 2009). Among
major political parties in developed countries, the Republican Party in the
United States and the Harper Conservatives now stand practically alone in
their refusal to address the problem of climate change. Anti-science and anti-
intellectual trends are unfortunately gaining ground in the Republican Party,
which, as Elisabeth Rosenthal (2011) argues, “has managed to turn skepticism
about man-made global warming into a requirement for electability.” The
Harper Conservatives may not deny science, but their policy is the same: little,
if any, action to reduce emissions. The United States and Canada have both
pledged to reduce their emissions by 17 per cent from 2005 levels by 2020, an
increase of 3 per cent from 1990 levels. Comparatively, the European Union
has pledged a 20 per cent reduction from 1990 levels by 2020. Developing
countries’ pledges cover a wide range: China aims to reduce its emissions
by about 7 per cent from 1990 levels, India is set to increase emissions by 30
per cent from 1990 levels, and Brazil, being the role model, pledged to reduce
133
emissions by 36 per cent from 1990 levels (Climate Action Tracker 2011).
The international community continues to meet periodically as the
Conference of the Parties (COP) to the UNFCCC. The 15th COP, which took
place in 2009 in Copenhagen, did not live up to expectations that it would
produce a successor agreement to the Kyoto Protocol. Countries agreed to
the weak Copenhagen Accord which encourages signatories of the UNFCCC
“to cap the global temperature rise by committing to significant emission
reductions and to raise funds to help the developing world address climate
change” (European Environment Agency 2010). The accord recognizes that
climate change is “one of the greatest challenges of our time” and something
must be done, but it does not require countries to abide by reporting
mechanisms or binding targets for 2020 or 2050 (UNFCCC 2011). Oxfam
International (2009, 9) indicates that, “[the accord] bundles the adaptation
needs of the world’s poorest people together with calls for compensation
. . . for oil-producing countries that claim they will lose revenue when the
world shifts away from fossil fuels.” Global equity concerns played a large
role in Copenhagen. Some developing countries refused to sign on to the
accord, which would require poor and vulnerable developing countries to
follow international procedures in order to gain financial support for their
mitigation efforts, a process that has proven to be difficult for these low-
capacity countries (Chandani 2010, 222).
A year later, the 16th COP in Cancún was under pressure to lay the
groundwork for binding targets for all countries, including the United States,
which many countries insisted must be brought into an agreement (Pew
Center on Global Climate Change 2010, 2). The meeting was also expected
to develop a multilateral financing mechanism to channel hundreds of
billions of dollars to developing countries to help them mitigate emissions
and adapt to the effects of climate change (Snegaroff and Cuenca 2010). The
meeting resulted in the Cancún Agreements, a deal which does not obligate
governments to take new steps, though provided a foundation for a deal with
binding targets to be reached at the next meeting.
In 2011, signatories of the UNFCCC met in Durban for the 17th COP,
which resulted in the Durban Platform outlining a course of action that
would see the development of a new treaty which covers all major emitters.
In addition to extending the Kyoto Protocol’s first commitment period, the
parties “explicitly recognised the global gap between countries’ existing
emissions reduction pledges out to 2020, and the global goal of limiting
average temperature increases to below 2 degrees [Celsius] above pre-
industrial levels” (The Carbon Report 2011). The Durban Platform stated that
a new treaty must be finalized by 2015 and come into force in 2020.
Despite countries’ acknowledgment that there is a need to shift
toward low-carbon societies, a timely agreement that significantly and
rapidly curbs emissions is unlikely because fossil fuel-related interests have
substantial influence on political decisions in key countries. Global fossil fuel
subsidies in 2008 amounted to $557 billion (IEA 2010, 1) and continue to be
high. For instance, the Pembina Institute estimated that the Government of
134
Canada provides CAD$2 billion per year in financial support to the fossil
fuel industry (Demerse 2010). Politicians in North America tend not to cut
support to this industry since fossil fuel-related corporations have a history
of funding political parties that pander to their interests (Gutstein 2009;
McQuaig 2004). This reduces the probability that countries will act to address
ocean acidification.
The fact that ocean acidification is an observable direct result of CO2
emissions is fortunate because that may be important in motivating governments
to act. The U.S. government passed the Federal Ocean Acidification Research
And Monitoring Act of 2009 to develop research and monitoring capabilities
within the National Oceanic and Atmospheric Administration (Buck and
Folger 2009). Fisheries and Oceans Canada is examining the issue, though
no specific policy actions have been taken (Fisheries and Oceans Canada
2011). The Oslo and Paris (OSPAR) Commission, administrator of the OSPAR
Convention for the Protection of the Marine Environment of the North-East
Atlantic, addresses fisheries issues for the European Union and lists ocean
acidification as a concern (OSPAR Commission 2011). Ocean acidification is
evidently under consideration by key governments, but action appears to be
restricted to research and discussion.
The lack of consensus and concerted global action indicates that
advocacy is necessary. A driver for action on climate change is co-operation by
multiple stakeholders to counter industrial lobbies. The Advocacy Coalition
Framework argues that stakeholders want to convert their convictions into
policy and will seek allies and form advocacy coalitions to do so (Weible
2006, 99). A number of stakeholders that have been or will soon be affected
by ocean acidification have been identified. First, there are activists and
educators—environmentalists, conservationists, and marine scientists—who
are committed to public education on ocean acidification. Second, there are
direct economic stakeholders, such as capture fisheries, aquaculturists, and
the marine ecotourism industry. Third, there are myriad stakeholders in the
alternative energy industry, who are keen to secure government subsidies
and tax exemptions to help develop economies of scale for their technologies.
Fourth, there are those who have a desire to maintain oceanic biodiversity for
its intrinsic beauty and interest, including snorkelers, divers, scientists, and
members of the general public. Finally, there are certain governments that are
confronted with sectoral or regional pressures because of ocean acidification,
such as those which depend on fisheries for nutrition, incomes, and economic
growth. Many stakeholders are willing to advocate on this issue, whether it
be for financial, humanitarian, or symbolic reasons.
The Advocacy Coalition Framework identifies two conditions that
facilitate policy change: “changes in beliefs of a dominant coalition or changes
in available resources and venues [that] are brought about by external shocks,
policy-oriented learning, or hurting stalemate” (Weible 2006, 101). Given
the far-reaching consequences of climate change and ocean acidification,
policy change driven by external shocks, such as widespread coral death and
fisheries collapse, is not desirable. The focus must be on influencing the beliefs
135
of the dominant coalition, currently formed by reluctant governments and
the general public. Although research on and high-level acknowledgment
of ocean acidification have increased attention to the problem, the need for
immediate action has yet to be accepted by key countries. The salience of the
issue must be elevated in the minds of the public with education campaigns
through the media and at the national level.
Advocacy coalitions and educational efforts are in nascent stages. An
international network of research and environmental stakeholders has already
been formed and is active in policy advocacy. Two symposia on oceans in a high-
CO2 world, organized by the Scientific Committee on Ocean Research, United
Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization, and International
Geosphere-Biosphere Programme have been held since 2004 and a third is set
to take place in September 2012 in California. Ocean acidification has been
raised as a major issue by the United Nations Environment Programme, which
cites it as a threat to food security (UNEP 2010), and briefs aimed at policy-
makers have been issued. The issue of ocean acidification was also raised at
the 16th COP, where the point was made that targets for limiting atmospheric
CO2 concentrations are dangerously in excess of the amount that causes oceanic
damage (Harrould-Kolieb 2010). Although the issue is relatively new on the
international scene, action evidently must not be delayed.
Education campaigns will not be effective until governments
eliminate subsidies and tax exemptions for fossil fuel-related corporations.
In particular, Canada should remove subsidies to corporations that operate
in Alberta’s tar sands, since oil production is responsible for a significant
increase in Canada’s greenhouse gas emissions (Environment Canada 2011,
19–20). Subsidies should instead be provided to clean and renewable energy
companies to ensure that inexpensive alternative energy options exist. Funds
can also be put toward protecting coastlines and reducing or eliminating
harmful fishing practices. Such actions would send an important message
to Canadian citizens and corporations that the government is taking climate
change seriously.

Conclusion
After completing the Millennium Ecosystem Assessment, 1,360 leading
experts in a variety of scientific fields concluded in 2005 that “over the past 50
years, humans have changed ecosystems more rapidly and extensively than
in any comparable period of time in human history . . . . This has resulted
in a substantial and largely irreversible loss in the diversity of life on Earth”
(Hoggan and Littlemore 2009, 11). Ocean acidification is just one problem
caused by climate change, but it is a problem that a policy of adaptation will
not sufficiently address. Addressing it requires direct confrontation with CO2
emissions. In addition to the threat that ocean acidification poses to the global
biosphere, oceanic biodiversity, and humans’ food security, the potential of
the phenomenon to inspire action by governments should make it an integral
part of efforts to address climate change more generally.
136
Notes
1. Some observers argue that oceanic ecosystems have the capacity to cope
with future climate change. See, for example, Maynard, Baird, and Pratchett
(2008) and a response by Hoegh-Guldberg (2009). Hendriks, Duarte, and
Álvarez (2010) argue that biological processes allow marine organisms to
handle pH changes. See Dupont, Dorey, and Thorndyke (2010) for a response.
2. The Australian Parliament voted 74-72 in favour. Prior to the vote, the
government had received a report that documented damage to the Great
Barrier Reef by uncontrolled CO2 emissions.
3. Many effects of lower pH on marine biota have been documented in the
literature. These include stunted growth (Bechmann et al. 2011), weakened
reproductive performance (Havenhand et al. 2008; Kurihara 2008), and
weakened immune system responses (Bibby et al. 2008). Hofmann et al.
(2010) identify impacts of ocean acidification on photosynthesis, respiration,
acid-base regulation, aspects of behaviour, and tolerance of other stressors.
Kroeker et al. (2010) conclude that “[o]cean acidification is a pervasive
stressor that could affect many marine organisms and cause profound
ecological shifts . . . [T]he biological effects of ocean acidification are generally
large and negative, but the variation in sensitivity amongst organisms has
important implications for ecosystem responses.” Albright (2011) finds that
ocean acidification has “the potential to impact multiple life history stages of
corals, including critical processes independent of calcification.” Examining
the effects of ocean acidification on early life history of invertebrates, Dupont
and Thorndyke (2009, 3122) conclude that “many species and ecosystems
will experience profound modifications with severe socio-economic
consequences.” Compounding the effects of ocean acidification are various
pressures such as pollution and exploitation of resources (Secretariat of the
Convention on Biological Diversity 2009, 53).
4. Other studies also conclude that there exists a threat of massive disruption
to oceanic ecosystems. See Dupont, Dorey, and Thorndyke (2010), Barnard
and Grekin (2010), Hofmann et al. (2010), Beman et al. (2011), and Veron
(2011).

References
Agriculture Business Week. 2008. “Philippines’ Coral Reefs on the Verge of
Extinction.” Agribusiness Week, July 12. http://www.agribusinessweek.
com/philippines-coral-reefs-on-the-verge-of-extinction.
Albright, Rebecca. 2011. “Reviewing the Effects of Ocean Acidification on
Sexual Reproduction and Early Life History Stages of Reef-Building
Corals.” Journal of Marine Biology 2011. http://downloads.hindawi.
com/journals/jmb/2011/473615.pdf.
Barnard, Nicola, and Jacqueline Grekin. 2010. “Issue Paper No. 7: Ocean
Acidification.” In Biodiversity and Climate Change Series, edited by
Tim Christophersen, Jacqueline Grekin, and Balakrishna Pisupati.
137
Convention on Biological Diversity and the United Nations
Environmental Programme. http://www.cbd.int/doc/publications/
unep-cbd-issue-papers/unep-cbd-issue-papers-07-en.pdf.
Bechmann, Reneé K., Ingrid C. Taban, Stig Westerlund, Brit F. Godal, Maj
Arnberg, Sjur Vingen, Anna Ingvarsdottir, and Thierry Baussant.
2011. “Effects of Ocean Acidification on Early Life Stages of Shrimp
(Pandalus borealis) and Mussel (Mytilus edulis).” Journal of Toxicology
and Environmental Health 74 (7-9): 424–38.
Beman, J. Michael, Cheryl-Emiliane Chow, Andrew L. King, Yuanyuan
Feng, Jed A. Fuhrman, Andreas Andersson, Nicholas R. Bates, Brian
N. Popp, and David A. Hutchins. 2011. “Global Declines in Oceanic
Nitrification Rates as a Consequence of Ocean Acidification.”
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of
America 108 (1): 208–13.
Bibby, Ruth, Steve Widdicombe, Helen Parry, John Spicer, and Richard Pipe.
2008. “Effects of Ocean Acidification on the Immune Response of the
Blue Mussel Mytilus edulis.” Aquatic Biology 2: 67–74.
Buck, Eugene H. and Peter Folger. 2009. “Ocean Acidification.”
Congressional Research Service Report to Congress, April 24. http://
docs.lib.noaa.gov/noaa_documents/NOAA_related_docs/CRS_
reports/R40143.pdf.
Burke, Lauretta, Kathleen Reytar, Mark Spalding, and Allison Perry. 2011.
Reefs at Risk: Revisited. Washington, DC: World Resources Institute.
Caldeira, Ken, David Archer, James P. Barry, Richard G. J. Bellerby, Peter
G. Brewer, Long Cao, Andrew G. Dickson, et al. 2007. “Comment on
‘Modern-Age Buildup of CO2 and its Effects on Seawater Acidity and
Salinity’ by Hugo A. Loáiciga.” Geophysical Research Letters 34 (18):
L18608.
CDNN (Cyber Diver News Network). 2009. “Coastal Development, Human
Population Increase Killing Coral Reefs.” January 9. http://www.cdnn.
info/news/eco/e090109.html.
Chandani, Achala. 2010. “Expectations, Reality, and Future: A Negotiator’s
Reflections on COP 15.” Climate Law 1: 207–25.
Climate Action Tracker. 2011. “Climate Action Tracker.” Accessed December
29, 2011. http://www.climateactiontracker.org.
Cooley, Sarah R., and Scott C. Doney. 2009. “Ocean Acidification’s Impact
on Fisheries and Societies: A U.S. Perspective.” Current: The Journal of
Marine Education 25 (1): 15–19.
Delacourt, Susan. 2010. “Climate Bill, Commons Crushed in One Blow.”
Toronto Star, November 17. http://www.thestar.com/news/sciencetech/
environment/article/892053.
Demerse, Clare. 2009. Our Fair Share: Canada’s Role in Supporting Global
Climate Solutions. Drayton Valley: Pembina Institute.
———. 2010. “Leaked Government Document Says Canada Should End
Fossil Fuel Subsidies.” Pembina Institute, May 26. http://www.
pembina.org/blog/339.
138
Dickens, Gerald R., Maria M. Castillo, and James C. G. Walker. 1997. “A
Blast of Gas in the Latest Paleocene: Simulating First-Order Effects
of Massive Dissociation of Oceanic Methane Hydrate.” Geology 25:
259–62.
Diringer, Elliot. 2010. “Sixteenth Session of“A Blast of Gas in the Latest
Paleocene: Simulating First-Order Effects of Massive Dissociation
of Oceanic Methane Hydrate.” Geology 25 the Conference of the
Parties to the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate
Change and Sixth Session of the Meeting of the Parties to the Kyoto
Protocol.” Pew Center for Global Climate Change, December. http://
www.pewclimate.org/docUploads/cancun-climate-conference-cop16-
summary.pdf.
Doney, Scott C., Victoria J. Fabry, Richard A. Feely, and Joan A. Kleypas.
2009. “Ocean Acidification: The Other CO2 Problem.” Annual Review of
Marine Science 1: 169–92.
Dunlap, Riley E., and Aaron M. McCright. 2010. “Climate Change Denial:
Sources, Actors and Strategies.” In Routledge Handbook of Climate
Change and Society, edited by Constance Lever-Tracy, 240–60. New
York: Routledge.
Dupont, S., and M. C. Thorndyke. 2009. “Impact of CO2-Driven Ocean
Acidification on Invertebrates Early Life-History – What We Know,
What We Need to Know and What We Can Do.” Biogeosciences
Discussions 6: 3109–31.
Dupont, Sam, Nathan Dorey, and Michael Thorndyke. 2010. “What Meta-
analysis Can Tell Us about Vulnerability of Marine Biodiversity to
Ocean Acidification?” Estuarine, Coastal and Shelf Science 89: 182–85.
Environment Canada. 2011. Canada’s Emissions Trends. Ottawa: Public Works
and Government Services of Canada.
European Commission. 2010. Facts and Figures on the Common Fisheries Policy.
Luxembourg: Publication Office of the European Union.
European Environment Agency. 2010. “COP15: Outcomes and the Way
Forward.” European Environment Agency, January 20. http://www.
eea.europa.eu/highlights/cop15-outcomes-and-the-way-forward.
FAO (Food and Agriculture Organization). 2011. The State of World Fisheries
and Aquaculture 2010. Rome: Food and Agriculture Organization.
Feely, Richard A., Christopher L. Sabine, J. Martin Hernandez-Ayon, Debby
Ianson, and Burke Hales. 2008. “Evidence for Upwelling of Corrosive
‘Acidified’ Water onto the Continental Shelf.” Science 320 (5882):
1490–92.
Fisheries and Oceans Canada. 2011. “Ocean Acidification.” March 7. http://
www.dfo-mpo.gc.ca/science/oceanography-oceanographie/impacts/
acidification-eng.html.
Gupta, M.V. 2006. “Challenges in Sustaining and Increasing Fish Production
to Combat Hunger and Poverty in Asia.” NAGA, WorldFish Center
Quarterly 29 (1-2): 4–10.
Gutstein, Donald. 2009. Not a Conspiracy Theory. Toronto: Key Porter Books.
139
Hall, C. Michael. 2001. “Trends in Ocean and Coastal Tourism: The End of
the Last Frontier?” Ocean & Coastal Management 44 (9-10): 601–18.
Harrould-Kolieb, Ellycia. 2010. “COP16: Targeting Ocean Acidification.”
OCEANA: The Beacon (blog), December 9. http://na.oceana.org/en/
blog/2010/12/cop16-targeting-ocean-acidification.
Hauge, Kjellrun Hiis, Belinda Cleeland, and Douglas Clyde Wilson. 2009.
Fisheries Depletion and Collapse. Geneva: International Risk Governance
Council.
Havenhand, Jon N., Fenina-Raphaela Buttler, Michael C. Thorndyke, and Jane
E. Williamson. 2008. “Near-Future Levels of Ocean Acidification Reduce
Fertilization Success in a Sea Urchin.” Current Biology 18 (15): 651–52.
Hendriks, Iris E., Carlos M. Duarte, and Marta Álvarez. 2010. “Vulnerability
of Marine Biodiversity to Ocean Acidification: A Meta-analysis.”
Estuarine, Coastal and Shelf Science 86 (2): 157–64.
Hoegh-Guldberg, Ove. 2009. “Climate Change and Coral Reefs: Trojan
Horse or False Prophecy? A Response to Maynard et al. (2008).” Coral
Reefs 28: 569–575.
Hoegh-Guldberg, Ove, Hans Hoegth-Guldberg, J. E. N. Veron, Alison Green,
Ed Gomez, Melanie King, Janice Lough, et al. 2009. The Coral Triangle
and Climate Change: Ecosystems, People and at Risk. Brisbane: World
Wildlife Fund.
Hofmann, Gretchen E., James P. Barry, Peter J. Edmunds, Ruth D. Gates,
David A. Hutchins, Terrie Klinger, and Mary A. Sewell. 2010. “The
Effect of Ocean Acidification on Calcifying Organisms in Marine
Ecosystems: An Organism to Ecosystem Perspective.” Annual Review
of Ecology, Evolution, and Systematics 41: 127–47.
Hoggan, James, and Richard Littlemore. 2009. Climate Cover-Up: The Crusade
to Deny Global Warming. Vancouver: Greystone Books.
Hood, Maria, Wendy Broadgate, Ed Urban, and Owen Gaffney. 2009. Ocean
Acidification: A Summary for Policymakers from the Second Symposium
on the Ocean in a High-CO2 World. Sweden: Second Symposium on
the Ocean in a High-CO2 World. http://www.ocean-acidification.net/
OAdocs/SPM-lorezv2.pdf.
IEA (International Energy Agency). 2010. “Energy Subsidies: Getting the
Prices Right.” Office of the Chief Economist, June 7. http://www.iea.
org/files/energy_subsidies.pdf.
IMF (International Monetary Fund). 2010. “World Economic Outlook
Database.” http://www.imf.org/external/pubs/ft/weo/2010/02/
weodata/index.aspx.
IPCC (Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change). 2007. “Ocean
Acidification Due to Increasing Atmospheric Carbon Dioxide.” In
Contribution of Working Group I to the Fourth Assessment Report of the
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, 2007, edited by S. Solomon,
D. Qin, M. Manning, Z. Chen, M. Marquis, K.B. Averyt, M. Tignor,
and H.L. Miller. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://
www.ipcc.ch/publications_and_data/ar4/wg1/en/ch10s10-4-2.html.
140
Kroeker, Kristy J., Rebecca L. Kordas, Ryan N. Crim, and Gerald G. Singh.
2010. “Meta-analysis Reveals Negative Yet Variable Effects of Ocean
Acidification on Marine Organisms.” Ecology Letters 13 (11): 1419–34.
Kump, Lee R., Timothy J. Bralower, and Andy Ridgwell. 2009. “Ocean
Acidification in Deep Time.” Oceanography 22 (4): 94–107.
Kurihara, Haruko. 2008. “Effects of CO2-Driven Ocean Acidification on the
Early Developmental Stages of Invertebrates.” Marine Ecology Progress
Series 373: 275–84.
Lennox, Patrick. 2008. Contemporary Piracy off the Horn of Africa. Calgary:
Canadian Defence and Foreign Affairs Institute.
Maynard, Jeffrey A., Andrew H. Baird, and Morgan S. Pratchett. 2008.
“Revisiting the Cassandra Syndrome: The Changing Climate of Coral
Reef Research.” Coral Reefs 27 (4): 745–49.
McCook, Laurence J., Tony Ayling, Mike Chappo, J. Howard Choat,
Richard D. Evans, Debora M. De Freitas, Michelle Heupel, et
al. 2010. “Adaptive Management of the Great Barrier Reef: A
Globally Significant Demonstration of the Benefits of Networks of
Marine Reserves.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
of the United States of America 107: 18278–85. http://www.pnas.org/
content/107/43/18278.full.pdf+html.
McLaughlin, David. 2011. “Message from the President and CEO.” In
Paying the Price: The Economic Impacts of Climate Change for Canada, by
the National Round Table on the Environment and the Economy, 5.
Ottawa: National Round Table on the Environment and the Economy.
McQuaig, Linda. 2006. War, Big Oil and the Fight for the Planet: It’s the Crude,
Dude. Toronto: Anchor Canada.
Ministry of Population and the Environment. 2004. “Ecotourism and Poverty
Alleviation: Contribution of Tourism in Developing Countries.” In
State of the Environment 2004. Nepal: Ministry of Population and the
Environment of Nepal.
Monbiot, George. 2006. Heat. Toronto: Doubleday Canada.
Müller, Benito. 2002. Equity in Climate Change: The Great Divide. Oxford:
Oxford Institute for Energy Studies.
Narita, Daiju, Katrin Rehdanz, and Richard S.J. Tol. 2011. “Economic
Costs of Ocean Acidification: A Look into the Impacts on Shellfish
Production.” ESRI Working Paper No. 391, Economic and Social
Research Institute, Dublin. http://www.esri.ie/UserFiles/publications/
WP391/WP391.pdf.
National Marine Fisheries Service. 2011. Fisheries Economics of the United States
2009. Maryland: U.S. Department of Commerce. http://www.st.nmfs.
noaa.gov/st5/publication/econ/2009/FEUS%202009%20ALL.pdf.
NOAA (National Oceanic and Atmospheric Administration). 2011a.
“Commercial Fishing - A Cultural Tradition.” http://stateofthecoast.
noaa.gov/com_fishing/welcome.html.
———. 2011b. “Mauna Loa CO2 Annual Mean Data.” ftp://ftp.cmdl.noaa.
gov/ccg/co2/trends/co2_annmean_mlo.txt.
141
Nordhaus, William. 2008. A Question of Balance: Weighing the Options on
Global Warming Policies. New Haven: Yale University Press.
NRDC (National Resources Defense Council). 2009. Ocean Acidification:
The Other CO2 Problem. New York: National Resources Defense
Council. http://www.nrdc.org/oceans/acidification/files/NRDC-
OceanAcidFSWeb.pdf.
OSPAR (Oslo and Paris) Commission. 2011. “Climate Change.” http://www.
ospar.org/content/content.asp?menu=00230307000000_000000_000000.
Oxfam International. 2009. Climate Shame: Get Back to the Table. Oxfam
Briefing Note, December 21. http://www.oxfam.org/sites/www.oxfam.
org/files/briefing-note-climate-shame-get-back-to-the-table.pdf.
Oxford Economics. 2009. Valuing the Effects of Great Barrier Reef Bleaching.
Australia: Great Barrier Reef Foundation.
Pagani, Mark, Zhonghui Liu, Jonathan LaRiviere, and Ana Christina Ravelo.
2010. “High Earth-System Climate Sensitivity Determined from
Pliocene Carbon Dioxide Concentrations.” Nature Geoscience 3: 27–30.
Ridgwell, Andy, and Daniela N. Schmidt. 2010. “Past Constraints on
the Vulnerability of Marine Calcifiers to Massive Carbon Dioxide
Release.” Nature Geoscience 3: 196–200.
Rosenthal, Elisabeth. 2011. “Where Did Global Warming Go?” New
York Times, October 15. http://www.nytimes.com/2011/10/16/
sunday-review/whatever-happened-to-global-warming.html?_
r=2&pagewanted=all.
Royal Society. 2005. Ocean Acidification due to Increasing Atmospheric Carbon
Dioxide. Policy document 12/05. June. http://royalsociety.org/
uploadedFiles/Royal_Society_Content/policy/publications/2005/9634.pdf.
Schaefer, Andrew. 1996. “1995 Canada-Spain Fishing Dispute (The Turbot
War).” Georgetown International Environmental Law Review VIII (3):
437–49.
Secretariat of the Convention on Biological Diversity. 2009. Scientific
Synthesis of the Impacts of Ocean Acidification on Marine Biodiversity.
CBD Technical Series No. 46. Montreal: Secretariat of the Convention
on Biological Diversity. http://coralreef.noaa.gov/education/oa/
resources/cbd_ts46_oceanacidification-web.pdf.
Snegaroff, Claire, and Anna Cuenca. 2010. “Cancun Climate Talks
Enter Final Stretch.” Agence France-Presse, December 15. http://
www.thejakartaglobe.com/afp/cancun-climate-talks-enter-final-
stretch/410173.
Spalding, Mark D., Corinna Ravilious, and Edmund P. Green. 2001. The
World Atlas of Coral Reefs. Cambridge: United Nations Environment
Programme World Conservation Monitoring Centre.
Stern, Nicholas. 2006. The Economics of Climate Change: The Stern Review.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Suzuki, David, and Dave Robert Taylor. 2009. The Big Picture: Reflections
on Science, Humanity, and a Quickly Changing Planet. Vancouver:
Greystone Books.
142
Talmage, Stephanie C., and Christopher J. Gobler. 2009. “The Effects of
Elevated Carbon Dioxide Concentrations on the Metamorphosis, Size,
and Survival of Larval Hard Clams (Mercenaria mercenaria), Bay
Scallops (Argopecten irradians), and Eastern Oysters (Crassostrea
virginica).” Limnology and Oceanography 54 (6): 2072–80.
The Carbon Report. 2011. “What is COP 17?” http://www.thecarbonreport.
com/what-is-cop-17.
Thompson, Ken. 2010. Do We Need Pandas? The Uncomfortable Truth about
Biodiversity. London: Green Books.
Tol, Richard S.J. 2002a. “New Estimates of the Damage Costs of Climate
Change, Part I: Benchmark Estimates.” Environmental and Resource
Economics 21 (1): 47–73.
———. 2002b. “New Estimates of the Damage Costs of Climate Change, Part
II: Dynamic Estimates.” Environmental and Resource Economics 21 (2):
135–60.
———. 2009. An Analysis of Mitigation as a Response to Climate Change.
Frederiksberg: Copenhagen Consensus Center. http://fixtheclimate.
com/uploads/tx_templavoila/AP_Mitigation_Tol_v_3.0.pdf.
UNEP (United Nations Environment Programme). 2010. UNEP Emerging
Issues: Environmental Consequences of Ocean Acidification: A Threat to
Food Security. Nairobi: United Nations Environment Programme.
http://www.unep.org/dewa/pdf/Environmental_Consequences_of_
Ocean_Acidification.pdf.
UNFCCC (United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change).
2011. “Climate Change Information Sheet 10: Agriculture and Food
Security.” http://unfccc.int/essential_background/background_
publications_htmlpdf/climate_change_information_kit/items/288.php.
Van Schalkwyk, Marthinus. 2009. “Marthinus Van Schalkwyk Addresses
High Level Climate Change Seminar in Washington.” Climate Action
Partnership, January 30. http://www.cap.org.za/view.asp?ItemID=32&
tname=tblComponent1&oname=&flt=&pg=front.
Veron, John E. N. 2008. “Mass Extinctions and Ocean Acidification:
Biological Constraints on Geological Dilemmas.” Coral Reefs 27:
459–72.
———. 2011. “Ocean Acidification and Coral Reefs: An Emerging Big
Picture.” Diversity 3 (2): 262–74.
Weible, Christopher M. 2006. “An Advocacy Coalition Framework
Approach to Stakeholder Analysis: Understanding the Political
Context of California Marine Protected Area Policy.” Journal of Public
Administration Research and Theory 17 (1): 95–117.
White, Alan T., Helge P. Vogt, and Tijen Arin. 2000. “Philippine Coral Reefs
under Threat: The Economic Losses Caused by Reef Destruction.”
Marine Pollution Bulletin 40 (7): 598–605.
World Bank, FAO (Food and Agriculture Organization), and WorldFish
Center. 2010. The Hidden Harvests: The Global Contribution of Capture
Fisheries. Washington, DC: World Bank. http://siteresources.
143
worldbank.org/EXTARD/Resources/336681-1224775570533/
TheHiddenHarvestsConferenceEdition.pdf.
Zachos, James C., Ursula Röhl, Stephen A. Schellenberg, Appy Sluijs,
David A. Hodell, Daniel C. Kelly, Ellen Thomas, et al. 2005. “Rapid
Acidification of the Ocean During the Paleocene-Eocene Thermal
Maximum.” Science 308 (5728): 1611–15.
Zeebe, Richard E., and Dieter A. Wolf-Gladrow. 2001. CO2 in Seawater:
Equilibrium, Kinetics, Isotopes. New York: Elsevier.
145
Paterson Review of International Affairs (2012) 12: 145–162.

Climate Change, Migration, and Megacities:


Addressing the Dual Stresses of Mass
Urbanization and Climate Vulnerability
Miles DePaul
Balsillie School of International Affairs, Wilfrid Laurier University

This article assesses the dual stresses that climate change and
climate-induced migration are imposing on megacities in developing
and emerging market countries. While cities in these countries are
experiencing unprecedented urbanization, impacts of climate change
such as desertification, flooding, and sea level rise will likely further
increase urbanization and put additional pressure on physical and
social infrastructure. Cities are not impervious to the impacts of
climate change and as populations grow, these stresses will become
more pronounced, especially if infrastructure and regulations remain
underdeveloped. This article draws on two cases, Bangladesh and
India, to illustrate the forces that are causing involuntary mobility
from rural to urban areas and the consequent stresses that megacities
like Mumbai will experience. It concludes with recommendations to
develop comprehensive climate adaptation policies in order to limit
the impacts of short- and long-term climate change on cities and the
economic cost of such investments in the future, and to seek a normative
shift on the issue of climate-induced migration to ensure that those
victimized by anthropogenic and natural climate change are met with a
compassionate, coordinated global regime.

Introduction
As evidence on the implications of a changing climate builds, migration is
becoming a salient consequence of unabated greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions
and poor climate risk adaptation. The scientific consensus is that warming
of the climate system is “unequivocal” (IPCC 2007)—a term not freely
used in the scientific community. With an increase in global temperatures
and climatic variability, there is a higher risk of an increase in migration-
inducing events, such as droughts, desertification, flooding, soil erosion,
and transmission of airborne diseases, and other societal and ecological
incidents. Megacities, defined as metropolitan areas with a total population
in excess of 10 million people (Rana 2011, 240), are becoming focal points for
climate change impacts and mass urbanization that in turn result in growing
vulnerability to environmental and social change. The intersection of climate
146
change impacts and mass urbanization creates dual stresses on megacities:
the stress of mass urbanization hinders the ability of megacities to adapt to
the stress of climate change. This creates a negative feedback loop whereby
climate change adaptation becomes progressively more difficult because of
inadequate housing, infrastructure, resource supplies, and social services.
There are prominent examples of the severe impacts of climate change,
particularly in developing and emerging market countries where poor health
is often exacerbated. The World Health Organization (2008, 2) reported that
a warmer and more volatile climate is expected to increase the already high
instances of annual deaths related to natural disasters (60,000), urban air
pollution (800,000), diarrhea (1.8 million), and malnutrition (3.5 million). The
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC), the leading international
body for the assessment of climate change established by the United Nations
Environment Programme and the World Meteorological Organization in
1988, indicates that there is “high confidence” in the scientific community that
anthropogenic climate change is contributing to sea level rise and consequent
high-risk scenarios for coastal cities without proper infrastructure (IPCC
2007, 7). Megacities such as Dhaka, Bangladesh, and Calcutta, India, typically
rank among the most vulnerable coastal cities (WWF 2009, 2). Furthermore,
as Priyanka Anand and Kallidaikurichi Seetharam (2011, 28) suggest, “when
we consider that currently 13 out of the largest 20 megacities in the world are
coastal cities, the grave situation facing urban populations around the world
becomes poignantly apparent.” Climate change is undoubtedly a global
problem, one that becomes more challenging over time as it continues and
more people move to cities.
While estimates vary, a conservative estimate is that annual migration
to urban centres because of environmental change currently totals
approximately 50 million people (Warner 2010, 697). Reasonable estimates
by the International Organization for Migration suggest that the annual
migration total could reach 200 million by 2050 (ibid.). If meaningful global
action on climate change is not taken by 2020, there is a high likelihood that
Earth will experience a series of tipping points, or irreversible events whereby
the required mitigation becomes nearly impossible, causing significant yet
unpredictable impacts on human mobility patterns. Nick Mabey (2009, 2)
assesses that “these ‘worst-case scenarios’ are not low probability, but largely
inevitable under current momentum of economic behaviour. As atmospheric
concentrations [of carbon dioxide] increase, there is little uncertainty over
whether extreme impacts will occur, only when they will happen.” Migration
will likely become a necessary survival option for individuals in an increasing
number of vulnerable regions.
Most affected by climate impacts and climate-induced migration are
highly vulnerable cities, notably megacities in developing and, to a lesser
degree, emerging market countries where the physical, social, and regulatory
infrastructure is typically insufficient to address these emergent stresses.
As of 2007, more people live in cities than in rural areas for the first time in
history, while more and more cities are growing past the population mark of
147
10 million (Bhagat and Mohanty 2009, 7). Meanwhile, cities are increasingly
vulnerable to climate impacts because of “coastal location, exposure to the
urban heat-island effect, high levels of outdoor and indoor pollution, high
population density, and poor sanitation” (Campbell-Lendrum and Corvalan
2007, 1). These concurring trends have resulted in unprecedented pressure on
megacities.
Research on the intersection of climate change and migration and their
combined impact on megacities is still in its infancy and hence insufficient
in the face of critical policy questions on the subjects of mitigating climate
change and building resilience to impacts. Scholars, such as Alex de Sherbinin,
Andrew Schiller, and Alex Pulsipher (2007), Diarmid Campbell-Lendrum
and Carlos Corvalan (2007), Mobarak Khan, Alexander Kramer, and Luise
Prufer-Kramer (2011), and Hilary Bambrick et al. (2011) assess the health and
social impacts of climate change on cities and megacities, broadly concluding
that climate change should be seen as a significant issue for cities and
policies at all levels of government need to be designed to reflect this. These
studies fall short of mentioning the added stresses that mass urbanization
could impose on cities. Scholars such as Imtiaz Ahmed (2009), Cecelia Tacoli
(2009), and Nicola Ranger et al. (2011) look at migration patterns and climate-
induced urbanization in developing and emerging market countries. Their
studies suggest that physical and social infrastructure currently cannot cope
with mass urbanization. These scholars neglect to consider the stresses that
climate change will impose on overpopulated regions. Only Susana Adamo
(2010) considers the interrelation of migration, climate change, and cities,
though she investigates theoretical implications rather than evaluating
specific national and regional policies. Institutions, like the United Nations
Population Fund, conduct extensive research on trends in population,
climate change, and urban density (see, for instance, Dodman 2009), but the
connection to migration is seldom made.
In order to assess the coinciding effects of climate change and climate-
induced migration on megacities, this article will first outline a typology of
climate migrants and refugees by considering the impacts of climate change
as multipliers to current push factors of migration. It will then analyze the
stresses that climate change imposes on megacities, particularly the dual
stresses of mass urbanization and increasing climate vulnerability. It will
then utilize a case-specific analysis of the interconnectedness of developing
and emerging market countries to illustrate the forces that drive involuntary
international and intranational mobility from rural to urban settings, and the
subsequent stresses megacities experience and will continue to experience in
upcoming decades. The case of Bangladesh is examined because the country
is especially vulnerable to climate change and Bangladeshis have a history of
migration to safer regions in Bangladesh and neighbouring India. Climate-
induced migration within India demonstrates the physical, economic,
ecological, and cultural shocks that megacities such as Mumbai will likely
experience in the future. Case methodology shows how climate-induced
migration has many facets, both international and intranational, and suggests
148
that major urban centres are disproportionately impacted. This article
concludes by arguing that there is a need to move past the stifled debate
on the inclusion of climate migrants in the international migration regime
and acknowledge that climate change is having real impacts on migration
patterns and, in turn, the capabilities of megacities to accommodate influxes
of people. Two policy recommendations are proposed. First, the development
of local policies, predominantly related to adaptation projects and mitigation
initiatives, is necessary to build resilience to climate change. Second, a
normative shift on the issue of climate-induced migration is needed to ensure
that those victimized by anthropogenic and natural climate change are met
with a compassionate, coordinated global regime rather than strict national
immigration policies, like those currently employed in India.

Climate Refugees as Victims: A Typology


Maggie Ibrahim (2005, 171) cautions against the use of the term “threat” when
discussing migration because doing so “lays the foundation for an increasingly
interventionist style of international relations . . . By shrouding migrants within
a context of threat and insecurity, a dichotomy forms between host states (us)
and migrants (them).” This line of thinking is likely what influenced Lester
Brown, founder of the Worldwatch Institute and Earth Policy Institute, to
introduce the term “environmental refugee” into the international migration
lexicon, a term which puts the onus on states to be compassionate to victims of
environmental volatility (Brown 1977, 1). The terms “environmental refugee”
and “climate refugee” are often met with reservations from agencies such as
the Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees (UNHCR),
which prefers the term “environmentally displaced persons” because of the
historical and legal weight that the term “refugee” holds in the international
system (Biermann and Boas 2010, 66). But the refusal to be flexible with the
term “refugee” in order to account for current and predicted future migration
forces is the refusal to acknowledge a changing global dynamic.
Climate change creates three parallel categories of push factors that
induce migration and there are three corresponding conceptions of migrants:
traditional migrants, traditional refugees, and climate refugees. First, sudden-
onset climate-related disasters such as floods and hurricanes are push factors
that are already resulting in forced migration from disaster areas. Many scholars
argue that individuals who are temporarily or permanently forced off of their
land “because of a marked environmental disruption” should be considered
“climate refugees” (Warner 2010, 694). Such disasters are identifiable fear-and-
consequence-driven push factors. Whereas the 1967 Refugee Protocol relating
to the Status of Refugees focused on “fear from persecution” for reasons of
“race, nationality, religion, membership in a particular social group, or political
opinion” (ibid.), modern conceptions of fear, and thus of refugees, include fear
of otherwise unavoidable natural forces. Fear in both cases is rooted in the
desire for survival and security from threats—predominantly political threats
in the former case and natural threats in the latter. The definition of “refugee”
149
needs to remain clear so as to maintain the effectiveness of the Refugee Protocol.
Yet, the definition, as well as the review process, also needs to be flexible in
order to adapt to ever-changing threats. A definition that equates “fear from
persecution” with the very real fear from climate-related natural disasters
would create new migration norms and simultaneously advance the urgency
of mitigating climate change risks.
Second, slow-onset climate impacts such as soil erosion and
desertification are push factors which magnify current “interacting physical
and social variables, including agricultural and economic decline that
ultimately force people from their homelands” (Homer-Dixon 1991, 1).
These indirect, aggregated phenomena are largely unaccounted for by states,
hence individuals on the move tend to be classified as migrants rather than
refugees. Climate refugees’ claims—for example, the lack of employment
opportunities and unacceptable socio-economic conditions—are often similar
if not identical to traditional migrants’ claims. Individuals are eventually
forced to migrate because of exogenous threats to housing and sustenance;
moving is often a decision of last resort. The distinction between traditional
migrants and climate refugees helps to understand the contemporary factors
influencing migration, particularly as climate-induced migration becomes
a more prominent issue. Embedding climate-induced migration within
traditional migration definitions eliminates the nuance that is required to
better address causes and effects, and thus limits the potential for effective
solutions.
A third climate-related push factor category marries the first two
categories above: slow-onset climate impacts and sudden forced migration. A
changing climate’s impact on agricultural production and natural resources
will lead to what Thomas Homer-Dixon (1991, 1) calls “acute national
and international conflict.” He (ibid.) explains that “countries may fight
over dwindling supplies of water and the effects of upstream pollution. In
developing countries, a sharp drop in food crop production could lead to
internal strife across urban-rural and nomadic-sedentary cleavages. If
environmental degradation makes food supplies increasingly tight, exporters
may be tempted to use food as a weapon.” This third category remains
under-researched. There is some disconnection between climate and conflict
models. These predictions indicate that in the event of mass migration, states
must avoid costly and irresponsible militarization and instead implement
more rational and compassionate policies. Conflict in populous regions like
Southeast Asia and sub-Saharan Africa would likely lead to forced migration
and individuals forced from their lands would be classified as traditional
refugees according to UNHCR.
Given these three categories, one of the fundamental challenges for
the current international migration regime is to reconcile the likely trend of
climate-related migration with the global shift to stricter border controls and
immigration policies in light of the perceived threats of terrorism and illegal
immigration. The international community is approaching a crossroads
where a country’s national immigration policies will determine many of its
150
future development and security outcomes. As Tacoli (2009, 515) argues, “[p]
olicies that support and accommodate mobility and migration are important
for adaptation and the achievement of broader development goals. However,
in most cases migration is still seen by many governments and international
agency staff as disruptive and requiring control and restrictive measures.” In
short, there is a need to reconceptualize strict national immigration policies
in the face of climate-induced migration and this need has larger social and
developmental justifications.
Having outlined push factors, a typology of migrants, and the need
for flexible definition of “refugee,” this article now turns to how the dual
stresses of mass urbanization and increasing climate vulnerability are putting
previously unseen stresses on cities around the world. It will investigate how
appropriate evidence-based policy-making on climate change mitigation and
adaptation will help limit instances of the aforementioned push factors.

The Dual Stresses of Climate Change on Cities


Large cities are experiencing both mass urbanization and increasing
vulnerability to climate change impacts, dual stresses that are unique to the 21st
century. These stresses are putting pressure on the abilities of cities, primarily
megacities in developing and emerging market countries, to provide basic
services and support for their populations. Accelerated population growth
in cities means that local governments must deal with residence overflow,
diminished sanitation, high transit demand, and other social and welfare
pressures. At the same time, cities are increasingly vulnerable to climate
impacts such as floods and heat waves, which can exacerbate these varying
pressures. Ranger et al. (2011, 140) argue that “many of the world’s cities are
hotspots of risk from extreme weather events and levels of risks in many cities
are likely to grow due to a combination of population growth and development
and rising intensities of extreme weather events.” If the dual stresses, which
cities will continue to experience, are not fully acknowledged and properly
addressed, all levels of government and international governance structures
will put populations and basic physical and social infrastructure at undue
risk. As mass urbanization continues, climate refugees will be leaving one
vulnerable zone for another.
By comparing the contemporary reality that more people live in cities
than rural areas to the fact that only 13 per cent of the world’s population lived
in cities during the early 20th century, it is evident that mass urbanization
will impose societal, economic, and cultural pressures on urban centres, since
there is currently less space and fewer resources to be shared or distributed
(Bhagat and Mohanty 2009, 6). Pressures include new burdens on transit
infrastructure, increased competition for jobs, and reduced provision of
social services. Instances of xenophobia may increase because some people
might make a connection between migration and deteriorating conditions.
Furthermore, over 900 million people—more than 70 per cent of urban
populations in developing countries—currently live in slum-like conditions,
151
with this number expected to increase to two billion over the next 30 years
(Little and Cocklin 2009, 77). Slum-like conditions are characterized by “low
incomes, poor housing and provision of basic services, and no effective
regulation of pollution or ecosystem degradation” (Campbell-Lendrum and
Corvalan 2007, 111). While some studies suggest that urbanization can be a
“positive force in overall poverty reduction” (Ravallion, Chen, and Sangraula
2007, 5), this is only possible if urbanization is met with robust social and
physical urban infrastructure. Masud Rana (2011, 243) suggests that
“urbanization and rapid urban change may be a negative sign of development
provided the urban problems arise due to improper management and
unplanned growth.” Given the poor infrastructure conditions in a number of
impoverished regions, like Bangladesh, climate-induced migration will likely
lead to unplanned growth in megacities and management of this growth will
probably be inadequate. If natural disasters, land degradation, or conflict
result in sudden mass movements of people, megacities may experience the
“urbanization of poverty,” which would send shocks through societies and
the global economy as prospects for equitable economic growth deteriorate.
While it would be wrong to generalize that these claims apply to all of the
world’s 26 megacities, the policy issues at hand could certainly become
salient in megacities like São Paolo, New York City, and London, where
mass urbanization and climate change are already major concerns for local
governments.
As cities begin to grapple with the prospects of increased urbanization,
they are becoming increasingly vulnerable to the impacts of climate change.
As Adamo (2010, 162) points out, “a large proportion of urban expansion is
taking place in areas exposed to environmental hazards, [for example] low
lying plains, coastal zones, stepped slopes and drylands.” Notably, while
coastal zones represent only 2 per cent of total land in the world, they are
inhabited by 14 per cent of the world’s overall population and 23 per cent of
its urban population (ibid.). Inherent vulnerabilities like proximity to coasts
and low river deltas are exacerbated by lax building codes, poor sanitation
and waste policies, and the lack of resilience systems such as dams and dykes
(de Sherbinin, Schiller, and Pulsipher 2007, 45–47). De Sherbinin, Schiller,
and Pulsipher (ibid., 41) best explain this mix of stress and vulnerability:
different pressures across scales come together in various sequences to create
unique “stress bundles” that affect local systems. Significant consequences
can result when stresses emanating from the environment coalesce with those
arising from society. The concurrence of stresses synergistically enlarges the
vulnerability of a system and risks then emerge from multiple sources and at
different scales.
The dual stresses of mass urbanization and increasing vulnerability to
climate impacts create stress bundles. To illustrate the consequences of these
dual stresses for megacities, the next section will examine two complementary
cases. One is a case of international migration from Bangladesh to India and
the other is a case of intranational migration from rural regions in southern
India to Mumbai.
152
Dual Cases: Bangladesh and India
This section analyzes historical trends in and future projections for Bangladesh,
a developing country, and India, an emerging market country. The instances of
the dual stresses and their consequences in these two cases are examples of a
global problem. Many countries in Africa and South America are experiencing
similar challenges. For example, ActionAid (2006, 2) looks closely at the impact
of climate change on six African cities while frequently commenting on the
added pressure that urbanization puts on flood resistance and public safety.
Adamo (2010, 163) discusses an example in northeastern Brazil where “regional
rural-urban migration and urban growth have also been related to the negative
effects of droughts in agriculture, while growing populations in cities generate
a concentrated demand for water that surpasses local availability.” The dual
stresses are evidently not unique to specific cities and regions, especially when
trends and future prospects are considered.
In choosing cases to exemplify aforementioned statistics and
arguments, this article needed to select a region that has recently dealt with
mass urbanization and climate-related pressures so as to offer a historical
perspective that is instructive in indicating likely future occurrences in other
regions. The criteria used to select a case were: (1) presence of a megacity,
defined as a metropolitan area with a population in excess of 10 million; (2)
proximity to common climate risk zones such as coasts, deserts, and low-
lying plains; and (3) historical trends of migration between neighbouring
countries. The cases of Bangladesh and India were ultimately selected
because of the presence of Mumbai, a coastal city that has been experiencing
mass urbanization. This trend suggests that a migration channel exists; there
is a history of migration between Bangladesh and India typically due to
economic push factors. These factors will likely be exacerbated by climate
change. The cases also satisfy the criterion of vulnerability given proximity
to coasts and deserts, characteristics that are quite common among the
world’s 26 megacities. It is important to note that specific conclusions drawn
from these cases, including exact climate risks, numbers of expected climate
refugees, and overall risks, cannot be applied to other megacities. However,
the resulting policy recommendations, which are transferable, should be
applied globally.
According to the IPCC (2007, 7–22), the main climate change impacts in
the India–Bangladesh region are increased frequency of droughts and floods
negatively affecting local production, sea level rise exposing coasts to risks
such as coastal erosion, and glacier melt in the Himalayas with more flooding
and rock avalanches. The convergence of these impacts would likely lead to
consequences for migration patterns and, subsequently, substantial pressures
on societies in the region. Following discussions of historical trends, this
section outlines the potential impacts that climate change will have on
migration by first looking at international migration from rural Bangladesh
to urban India and then at internal migration from rural to urban India.
153
International migration from Bangladesh to India

Migration from Bangladesh to India has historically been a prominent issue


because of the persistent economic inequality and related differences in social
well-being between the two countries. The impending impacts of climate
change, particularly in southern Bangladesh, are expected to aggravate
tensions on the highly sensitive India–Bangladesh border. Bangladesh is
one of the countries most vulnerable to climate change because of exposure
to climate-related natural disasters, agriculture dependency, and its
government’s inability to adapt (Maplecroft 2010). Expected impacts include
poor soil, water, and air quality and natural disasters such as floods, droughts,
and tropical storms (Poncelet et al. 2010, 212). According to Maplecroft (2010),
a British global risks analysis company, the Southeast Asian region and in
particular India and Bangladesh are most vulnerable to climate change, and
in fact are already experiencing elevated risks: “Throughout 2010, changes
in weather patterns have resulted in a series of devastating natural disasters,
especially in South Asia, where heavy floods in Pakistan affected more than
20 million people (over 10% of the total population) and killed more than
1,700 people. There is growing evidence climate change is increasing the
intensity and frequency of climatic events.”
Migration patterns will be especially affected by sea level rise and
riverbank erosion, which are already contributing to “impoverishment and
marginalization of rural families due to the loss of productive agricultural
lands” (Poncelet et al. 2010, 213). Some scholars predict that environmental
calamities in Bangladesh will primarily result in internal migration from
rural to urban areas (ibid.), while others predict that in the medium to long
term, more precarious scenarios will result in migration to its most affluent
neighbour, India (Ahmed 2009, 297). A key observation is that “even a meter
rise in sea level would inundate half of Bangladesh’s riceland, forcing the
relocation of easily 40 million people. In a densely populated country . . .
internal relocation would not be easy” (ibid.). Bangladesh’s population
has in fact increased from 144 million at the time of Ahmed’s 2009 study to
roughly 158 million (CIA World Factbook 2011). Notably, Richard Black,
Dominic Kniveton, and Kerestin Schmidt-Verkerk (2011, 445) argue that,
given the economic inequality between Bangladesh and India, “it is likely
that a significant proportion of any growth in migration that might result
from rural impoverishment associated with the negative impacts of climate
change could be seen in international migration to India; indeed, such cross-
border migration is already arguably the largest bilateral migration flow in
the world, larger even than flows from Mexico to the United States.” Climate
change is catalyzing additional international migration, which is straining
relations between the countries. An estimated 20 million Bangladeshis
are living illegally in India, a situation that has become “a major source of
tension between the two countries” and has generated “a host of destabilising
political, social, economic, ethnic, and communal tensions in many states and
union territories of [India]” (Alam 2003, 423). Climate-related pressures in
154
Bangladesh may put India–Bangladesh relations under even greater strain
in the coming decades. As such, India is pursuing stricter border security
policies, which include the construction of a three-metre-tall barbed-wire
fence along nearly the entire India–Bangladesh border (Ahmed 2009, 303).
India has so far fenced over 4,000 kilometres of the border and constructed
roads and floodlights to prevent illegal migration (Jones 2009, 293).
India’s strict border security policies, coupled with the Bangladeshi
government’s consistent denial of “any illegal movement of people from
Bangladesh to India,” are producing “stateless persons” in this region
(Ahmed 2009, 302). Ahmed (ibid.) explains that “in the midst of governmental
politicking, with the Bangladesh government disowning the environmental
refugees as ‘citizens’ of the country and the Indian government calling them
‘illegal migrants’ and taking measures to push them out of India, the victims
of environmental disruptions, including (mal)development, end up losing
protection from both countries.” That is, these victims lose protection of their
basic rights and face the constant threat of deportation and abuse from local
police and residents.
In addition to political and often cultural exile, these migrants tend to
be relegated to live in slum-like conditions. Alice Poncelet et al. (2010, 216)
discuss the vicious cycle for climate refugees as it pertains to India:

Many slums where migrants had settled have been destroyed by


the government, because they were illegal. The government is not
implementing any resettlement or rehabilitation plans, but has closed
down several slums. In such situations, people move from one slum
to the other. At first, these people are determined not to move back to
their original places, unless there are possibilities to earn a decent living.
However, people are tired of moving all the time without achieving
any improvement in quality of life, so when they are faced with this
additional and unexpected difficulty (closing of the slums), some
migrants chose to return to their place of origin.

The individuals least responsible for climate change—the poor and vulnerable
in developing and emerging market countries—are most affected by the
consequences of a changing climate. Without a substantive mix of adaptation
policies and more-open borders in contexts of forced migration, climate
change could result in further impoverishment of the poor, exacerbated
stresses on megacities, and violent conflict.

Internal migration in India and its impact on Mumbai

Climate-induced international migration will likely be problematic, but


research on the link between climate change and migration indicates that
internal migration, or retreatment, is going to be the most significant aspect
of climate-induced migration in all regions of the world. In India, climate-
related desertification in the south is catalyzing migration to many of the
155
country’s megacities, including Delhi, Kolkata, and Mumbai. One study on
desertification and land degradation in India concluded that a 105.5 mega-
hectare area of the country, or 37 per cent of the country’s total geographic
area, is undergoing processes of land degradation and of this, the area
undergoing desertification is 81.4 mega hectares (Ajai et al. 2009, 1478).
Much of this land is agricultural land in the rural south. The implications
for global food security aside, desertification is reducing job opportunities
and catalyzing mass migration from the rural south to India’s urban centre
(Leighton 2006, 48).
Mumbai is an exemplary case of climate-induced mass urbanization and
the consequent urbanization of poverty. India’s most populous city, Mumbai
has a population of approximately 12.5 million residents; its population has
increased by one-quarter in the past 20 years (India Online Pages 2011). Much
of this population growth is a result of internal migration from the south and
international migration from neighbouring countries. These trends are and
will continue to be amplified by a changing climate.
Climate change has exacerbated Mumbai’s many geographical and
infrastructural vulnerabilities. The climate-related July 2005 monsoon
flooding that killed more than 1,000 people demonstrated how vulnerable
Mumbai really is. Flat topography, low river deltas, poor drainage systems,
and lax building codes make the city particularly vulnerable to climate-
related pressures (de Sherbinin, Schiller, and Pulsipher 2007, 49). Mass
urbanization is a problem on top of these vulnerabilities. According to the
Munich Re Foundation (2007), those who died were disproportionately
people living in slum settlements, with leading causes of death being
drowning, wall collapse, and various diseases. Since over half of Mumbai’s
population lives in “squatter communities,” characterized by single-storey
buildings made of salvaged materials and suffering from poor sanitation
and restricted access to water, vulnerabilities are only compounded (de
Sherbinin, Schiller, and Pulsipher 2007, 49–50). This creates stress bundles.
For instance, poorly designed and maintained buildings are damaged by
extreme weather events. Local governments, which prioritize urgent capacity
concerns like transportation provision, have limited abilities to improve
disaster preparedness because of increased pressure on their resources. Local
economies slow as more and more individuals become impoverished and
are forced into slums. Policy at all levels of government has thus far been
ineffective in the face of compounded vulnerabilities and stress bundles.
Local governments’ underdeveloped adaptation strategies, alongside the
federal government’s restrictive immigration policies and the international
community’s general disregard for climate-induced migration, are resulting
in worsening living conditions. De Sherbinin, Schiller, and Pulsipher (ibid.,
50) argue that “the challenges posed by climate change, especially flooding
and sub-surface shifting in landfill areas, are unlikely to be met effectively.”
As instances of climate-related pressures increase, life in Indian
megacities will continue to be distinguished by vulnerability and poverty,
and urbanization will likely continue unabated. The convergence of the
156
Indian federal government’s lax climate change mitigation policies, its
attitude toward Bangladeshi migrants, and local governments’ ineffectual
adaptation strategies make these trends highly likely. Desertification will
force many Bangladeshis to seek refuge in India. As desertification continues
and water scarcity becomes a reality in India’s south, extreme weather
patterns, especially flooding, will worsen already precarious socio-economic
conditions in Mumbai. India and its major cities will become increasingly
vulnerable.

Finding Solutions
The fundamental solution is for all countries to pursue rigorous climate change
mitigation policies, given that there is an “unequivocal” scientific consensus
that “[m]ost of the observed increase in global average temperatures since the
mid-20th century is very likely due to the observed increase in anthropogenic
GHG concentrations” (IPCC 2007, 5) and that the stresses and vulnerabilities
outlined above are respectively climate-related and exacerbated by climate
change. Developed countries and countries that benefit disproportionately
from oil and coal industries must accept more responsibility for reducing
emissions since they are responsible for the majority of emissions currently
in the atmosphere. There are many policy options to choose from. Climate
change can be addressed through emissions pricing (introducing a carbon
tax), emissions caps (establishing a cap-and-trade system), voluntary
emissions reduction targets and incentives for industry, and research funding
for and development of new emission-reducing technologies.
Coordinating a global response to climate change has to date been
difficult because of obstruction by key countries, particularly the United
States and China, which results in lowest-common-denominator agreements.
Leading up to the 15th Conference of the Parties to the United Nations (UN)
Framework Convention on Climate Change in Copenhagen in 2009, the
international climate regime was seen as “digging itself into ever deeper holes
of rancorous relationships, stagnating issues, and stifled debates” (Depledge
2006, 1). The most recent meeting held in Durban, the 17th Conference of the
Parties, produced an agreement that delayed the finalization of a successor
treaty to the Kyoto Protocol until 2015 and stated that the new treaty would
come into effect in 2020. Reform of the international climate regime has been
proposed countless times since its conception in 1992. Trade sanctions and
financial penalties, among other compliance mechanisms, have been discussed.
The political backlash against such proposals has significantly tempered
expectations on reforming the regime, not to mention the persistent tensions
between developed and developing countries over the responsibility to reduce
emissions. John Drexhage (2008, 1) argues that “to address the multi-faceted
climate challenge we face, governance efforts must evolve beyond the current
global regime-building model and . . . environmental and development policies
must become much better integrated.” Global fora are not the only means of
addressing climate change. Matthew Hoffman (2011, 5) suggests that “the
157
center of gravity in the global response to climate change is shifting from
the multilateral treaty-making process to the diverse activities found beyond
the negotiating halls . . . . in cities, provinces and states, citizen groups, and
corporations.” It is impossible to remove state actors from the equation, but
Hoffman makes an important point: since climate impacts are local, securing
local-led and community-owned solutions is a promising way forward.
Since meaningful state action has not been taken at recent UN meetings,
grassroots movements promoting mitigation and adaptation strategies must
continue to be mobilized worldwide. These movements should promote
investment in transportation, renewable energy, and infrastructure and
engage individuals, corporations, and not-for-profit organizations. For local
and municipal governments, climate change is becoming a real risk factor and
policy priority. The C40 Cities Climate Leadership Group, a network of the
world’s megacities committed to addressing climate change, has emerged to
reduce emissions and climate risks. Local action plans can be much more fluid
and collaborative, whereas national and international plans have historically
been slow-moving and competitive. If national governments do not reconsider
their policy stances, the well-being of cities and prospects for sustainable
economic and social development are at risk. Governments could help scale
up local initiatives through funding and strategic support for transformative
ideas and by opening up the regulatory environment to better mobilize
capital for impactful work. For example, social and environmental finance
could make a difference by funding local solutions to global challenges, but
regulatory provisions, such as lending rules, stall action.
Even if all countries reduced GHG emissions to zero tomorrow, the
impact humankind has already had on natural systems will continue causing
detrimental climate change. As such, resilience policies must be pursued in
all countries, particularly those with megacities. The three characteristics of
resilience are: (1) the amount of disturbance a society can absorb and “still
remain within the state of the domain of attraction;” (2) the degree to which
the society is capable of self-organization or adjustment; and (3) the degree
to which the society can build and increase the capacity for learning and
adaptation (Prasad et al. 2009, 32). Policies include early warning systems,
contingency plans, and relief measures. Notably, Singapore has increased
the ground level in all reclamation programs and the City of London has
redesigned the Thames Barrier flood control system to factor in likely sea
level rise due to climate change (ibid., 30). In the pursuit of climate resilience
in Mumbai, the Tata Energy Research Institute, an Indian environmental non-
governmental organization, conducted a study which concluded that “US$24-
million invested in protection against sea-level rise would reduce the economic
impact by US$33-billion dollars” (de Sherbinin, Schiller, and Pulsipher 2007,
49). There are uncertainties about what the exact climate impacts on cities
and particularly megacities will be, hence scholars such as Bambrick et al.
(2011, 71) call for a focus on improving health and quality of life “no matter
what climate impacts eventuate” as a more appropriate means of adapting
to change. Policy goals include: reducing air pollution contributing to smog,
158
which will only worsen respiratory conditions as temperatures increase;
leveraging community engagement and local solutions to improve early
warning systems; and ensuring that adequate health care and preventative
measures are available in the event of flooding, resource scarcity, and heat
waves (ibid., 72–75). This focus necessitates providing public health clinics
for respiratory illnesses, establishing adequate building codes in high-risk
regions, and integrating health and well-being into municipal transit policies.
In the cities of many developing and emerging market countries, inadequate
resilience strategies and poor physical and social infrastructure mean that
migration remains the most attractive option.
The prevalence of migration as a means of adapting in the short
term suggests that there is a need for a normative shift in the international
understanding of and global response to climate-related mobility. Tacoli
(2009, 515) argues that “what is needed urgently is a radical change in
perceptions of migration, and a better understanding of the role that local
and national institutions need to play in making mobility be seen as part
of the solution rather than the problem.” Most immigration policies try to
“influence the volume, direction and types of population movement,” hence
there is a need to reconceptualize the focus of immigration policies in order to
“accommodate changes in migration patterns that result from environmental
degradation, economic growth or crisis” (ibid., 523).
A normative shift would mean change at the India–Bangladesh
border—it would mean moving away from strict border security, which
treats climate refugees as threats, toward developing policies that treat them
as victims of an inherently global problem. This perspective would change the
international understanding of what is threatening. The events that induce
forced migration, like climate change and conflict, would be seen as the real
threats. Kim Rygiel (2010, 5) argues that “the increased implementation of
border controls on the part of governing authorities has enabled the greater
segregation (and differential treatment) of ‘legitimate’ mobilities such as
leisure and business, from ‘illegitimate’ mobilities such as terrorism and illegal
immigration.” In order to move beyond the “us” and “them” dichotomy and
redefine what is threatening, the root challenges facing the international
migration regime must be addressed. Rygiel (ibid., 14–15) highlights an
emerging politics of resistance, which involves, for example, the No One is
Illegal and No Border movements, which are challenging the securitization of
citizenship. Dispelling the notion of the securitized and legalized individual
whose rights can be withheld and to whom resources can be denied, which
had significant momentum prior to the modern era in border enforcement
that linked low security to the risk of terrorist attacks, would lead to changes
in border controls in climate-sensitive regions such as the India–Bangladesh
border. An example of effective policy would be to divert the abundant
resources spent on keeping people out, like on fences, guards, and biometric
technologies, toward increasing the resilience of megacities so that they
have the capacity to provide for victims of climate change and avoid the
perpetuation of slum-like conditions.
159
Conclusion
With global temperatures and climatic variability increasing, and a
corresponding higher risk of an increase in migration-inducing events, 40
million Bangladeshis could be forced to find refuge in nearby safer regions.
Historical trends and empirical research suggest that the densely populated
cities of India are not only the preferred option, but often the only option for
climate refugees. Major cities in Africa, South America, and Asia are similarly
vulnerable to many of the climate change impacts discussed above. Stress
bundles may emerge to put pressure on governments and perpetuate poverty.
Rigorous climate change mitigation and adaptation policies are needed
to avoid such scenarios all around the world. Likewise, a normative shift is
needed, particularly in climate-sensitive regions and security discourse, to
redefine what is threatening. The cases of Bangladesh and India indicate that
the real threat is climate change, not migrants. Without addressing the causes
and effects of climate change, what many people perceive as threats from
migration will never be resolved.
The problem at hand is undoubtedly global and so systemic change is
necessary. The potential implications of mass migration increase the urgency
of the situation—all countries may be faced with the consequences of climate-
induced migration. Given the prioritization of immigration issues in North
America, Europe, and increasingly Southeast Asia, ignoring the empirical
evidence suggesting that mass migration is a very likely consequence of
climate change would be incompetent policy-making.
The policy recommendations in this article are only the tip of the
iceberg and only an initial step in the right direction. Much research is still
needed on policy on climate-induced migration to megacities and much
more attention is needed from all levels of government. Specifically, there
are gaps in knowledge when it comes to understanding the impacts that
climate-induced mass migration will have on local economies, food security,
education services, and cultures. A better understanding of the potential
impacts on each of these areas could lead to even greater urgency on the issue
of climate change mitigation and adaptation.
160
Acknowledgements
Thanks to Dr. Kim Rygiel for inspiring this research, and challenging my
assumptions.

References
ActionAid. 2006. Climate Change, Urban Flooding and the Rights of the Urban
Poor in Africa: Key Findings from Six African Cities. London: ActionAid
International.
Adamo, Susana. 2010. “Environmental Migration and Cities in the Context
of Global Environmental Change.” Current Opinions in Environmental
Sustainability 2 (3): 161–65.
Ahmed, Imtiaz. 2009. “Environmental Refugees and Environmental Distress
Migration as a Security Challenge for India and Bangladesh.” In
Facing Global Environmental Change: Environmental, Human, Energy,
Food, Health and Water Security Concepts, edited by Hans Günter
Brauch, Úrsula Oswald Spring, John Grin, Czeslaw Mesjasz, Patricia
Kameri-Mbote, Navnita Chadha Behera, Béchir Chourou, and Heinz
Krummenacher, 295–308. Berlin: Springer.
Ajai, A. S. Arya, P. S. Dhinwa, S. K. Pathan, and K. Ganesh Raj. 2009.
“Desertification/Land Degradation Status Mapping in India.” Current
Science 97 (10): 1478–83.
Alam, Sarfaraz. 2003. “Environmentally Induced Migration from Bangladesh
to India.” Strategic Analysis 27 (3): 422–28.
Anand, Priyanka, and Kallidaikurichi Seetharam. 2011. “Climate Change
and Living Cities: Global Problems with Local Solution.” In Climate
Change and Sustainable Urban Development in Africa and Asia, edited by
Belinda Yuen and Asfaw Kumssa, 21–35. New York: Springer.
Bambrick, Hilary Jane, Anthony Guy Capon, Guy Bruce Barnett, R. Matthew
Beaty, and Anthony John Burton. 2011. “Climate Change and Health
in the Urban Environment: Adaptation Opportunities in Australian
Cities.” Asia-Pacific Journal of Public Health 23 (2): 67–79.
Bhagat, R. B., and Soumya Mohanty. 2009. “Emerging Patterns of
Urbanization and the Contribution of Migration in Urban Growth in
India.” Asian Population Studies 6 (1): 5–20.
Biermann, Frank, and Ingrid Boas. 2010. “Preparing for a Warmer World:
Towards a Global Governance System to Protect Climate Refugees.”
Global Environmental Politics 10 (1): 60–88.
Black, Richard, Dominic Kniveton, and Kerestin Schmidt-Verkerk. 2011.
“Migration and Climate Change: Towards an Integrated Assessment
of Sensitivity.” Environment and Planning A 43 (1): 431–50.
Brown, Lester. 1977. “Redefining National Security.” World Watch Institute: 1.
Campbell-Lendrum, Diarmid, and Carlos Corvalan. 2007. “Climate Change
and Developing Country Cities: Implications for Environmental
Health and Equity.” Journal of Urban Health 84 (1): 109–17.
161
CIA World Factbook. 2012. “South Asia – Bangladesh.” https://www.cia.
gov/library/publications/the-world-factbook/geos/bg.html.
Depledge, Joanna. 2006. “The Opposite of Learning: Ossification in the
Climate Change Regime.” Global Environmental Politics 6 (1): 1–22.
de Sherbinin, Alex, Andrew Schiller, and Alex Pulsipher. 2007. “The
Vulnerabilities of Global Cities to Climate Hazards.” Environment and
Urbanization 19 (1): 39–64.
Dodman, David. 2009. “Urban Density and Climate Change.” April 2. http://
www.unfpa.org/webdav/site/global/users/schensul/public/CCPD/
papers/Dodman%20Paper.pdf.
Drexhage, John. 2008. “Climate Change and Global Governance: Which Way
Ahead.” IISD Global Environmental Governance Briefing Paper No. 2,
International Institute for Sustainable Development, Winnipeg.
Hoffman, Matthew J. 2011. Climate Governance at the Crossroads: Experimenting
with a Global Response after Kyoto. New York: Oxford University Press.
Homer-Dixon, Thomas. 1991. “On the Threshold: Environmental Changes as
Causes of Acute Conflict.” International Security 16 (2): 1–4.
Ibrahim, Maggie. 2005. “The Securitization of Migration: A Racial
Discourse.” International Migration 43 (5): 171.
India Online Pages. 2011. “Mumbai’s Population.” Accessed August 2011.
http://www.indiaonlinepages.com/population/mumbai-population.
html.
IPCC (Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change). 2007. “Climate Change
2007: Synthesis Report; Summary for Policymakers.” http://www.ipcc.
ch/pdf/assessment-report/ar4/syr/ar4_syr_spm.pdf.
Jones, Reese. 2009. “Geopolitical Boundary Narratives, the Global War on
Terror and Border Fencing in India.” Transactions of the Institute of
British Geographers 34 (3): 290–304.
Khan, Md. Mobarak Hossain, Alexander Kramer, and Luise Prufer-Kramer.
2011. “Climate Change and Infectious Disease in Megacities of the
Indian Subcontinent: A Literature Review.” In Health in Megacities and
Urban Areas, edited by Alexander Krämer, Mobarak Hossain Khan,
and Frauke Kraas, 135–152. New York: Springer.
Leighton, Michelle. 2006. “Desertification and Migration.” In Governing
Global Desertification: Linking Environmental Degradation, Poverty, and
Participation, edited by Pierre Marc Johnson, Karel Mayrand, and
Marc Paquin, 43–58. Burtlington: Ashgate.
Little, Laura, and Chris Cocklin. 2009. “The Vulnerability of Urban Slum
Dwellers to Global Environmental Change.” In Global Environmental
Change and Human Security, edited by Richard A. Matthew, Jon
Barnett, Bryan MacDonald, and Karen L. O’Brien, 77–96. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Mabey, Nick. 2009. “What Does the Security Community Need from a
Global Climate Regime.” E3G Briefing, November. http://www.e3g.
org/images/uploads/E3G_What_does_the_Security_Community_
need_from_a_Global_Climate_Regime.pdf.
162
Maplecroft. 2010. “Big Economies of the Future - Bangladesh, India,
Philippines, Vietnam and Pakistan - Most at Risk from Climate
Change.” October 21. http://maplecroft.com/about/news/ccvi.html.
Munich Re Foundation. 2007. “Vulnerability in Megacities: A Case Study
of Events in Mumbai and Paris.” http://www.munichre-foundation.
org/NR/rdonlyres/5A2170A5-FED4-47AE-B2C7-A2C6A9055B39/0/
PosterWolfMumbaiandParis.pdf.
Poncelet, Alice, François Gemenne, Marco Martiniello, and Hassan Bousetta.
2010. “A Country Made for Disasters: Environmental Vulnerability
and Forced Migration in Bangladesh.” In Environment, Forced
Migration and Social Vulnerability, edited by Tamer Afifi and Jill Jäger,
211–22. Berlin: Springer.
Prasad, Neeraj, Federica Ranghieri, Fatima Shah, Zoe Trohanis, Earl Kessler,
and Ravi Sinha. 2009. Climate Resilient Cities: A Primer on Reducing
Vulnerabilities to Disasters. Washington, DC: World Bank.
Rana, Masud P. 2011. “Urbanization and Sustainability: Challenges and
Strategies for Sustainable Urban Development in Bangladesh.”
Environment, Development, and Sustainability 13 (1): 237–56.
Ranger, Nicola, Stéphane Hallegatte, Sumana Bhattacharya, Murhty Bachu,
Satya Priya, K. Dhore, Farhat Rafique, et al. 2011. “An Assessment of
the Potential Impact of Climate Change on Flood Risk in Mumbai.”
Climatic Change 104 (1): 139–67.
Ravallion, Martin, Shaohua Chen, and Prem Sangraula. 2007. “New
Evidence on the Urbanisation of Global Poverty.” World Bank Policy
Research Working Paper No. 4199, World Bank, Washington, DC.
Rygiel, Kim. 2010. Globalizing Citizenship. Vancouver: UBC Press.
Tacoli, Cecelia. 2009. “Crisis or Adaptation? Migration and Climate Change
in a Context of High Mobility.” Environment and Urbanization 21 (2):
513–25.
Warner, K., M. Hamza, A. Oliver-Smith, F. Renaud, and A. Julca. 2010.
“Climate Change, Environmental Degradation and Migration.”
Natural Hazards 55 (3): 689–715.
World Health Organization. 2008. Protecting Health from Climate Change:
World Health Day 2008. Geneva: World Health Organization.
WWF (World Wildlife Fund). 2009. Mega-Stress for Mega-Cities: A Climate
Vulnerability Ranking of Major Coastal Cities in Asia. Gland: WWF
International.
Very special thanks to our sponsors

You might also like