A Lacanian Supplementation To Love in L'Immanence Des Vérités (8803)
A Lacanian Supplementation To Love in L'Immanence Des Vérités (8803)
Abstract
In L’Immanence des vérités, Alain Badiou re-writes the Platonic allegory of the cave. As the
book’s structure reveals, Badiou’s central claim is that truths are absolute, for they are
constituted by the dialectic between finitude and infinity, the consequence of which lies in the
creation of the œuvre. Although love is often affected by individual difference, family,
money, and social norms, philosophy calls for a rupture with these instances of finitude,
awakening us to the truth that love is open to the possibility of infinity embodied by
contingent encounter, amorous declaration, and the faithful construction of the Two. Badiou
calls for subjectivization of this possibility, in the form of the amorous œuvre, through and
beyond the Lacanian impasse of the sexual non-relationship. This article supplements
Badiouian love with Lacanian psychoanalysis by developing five points. First, the binary
framework “Lacanian finitude vs Badiouian infinity” can be misleading. Second, Badiou
himself regards the unconscious and the analytic discourse as inscribed by the dialectic
between finitude and infinity. Third, Lacan allows us to recognize that the œuvre and the
waste are not opposed, but rather supplementary to each other. Fourth, for both Lacan and
Badiou, love constitutes the interlacing of the non-relationship and the Two. Fifth, the
Badiouian amorous absolute must sustain a moderate attitude toward the real of the absolute
as the fusional One and thus, is intertwined with the Lacanian absolute as the sexual
relationship. Based on these points, this article elaborates such concepts as the amorous labor,
the dialectic between œuvre and waste, and the artisan of love.
In L’Immanence des vérités, Badiou rewrites Plato’s allegory of the cave. He starts with an
analysis and critique of finitude, moves onto an exploration of the kingdom of infinity, and
concludes by elaborating on the theory of the œuvre, the finite form of truth that is open to
infinity. The book’s itinerary can thus be summed up as “finitude – infinity – œuvre.” If
Being and Event focused on the universality of truths (the generic multiplicity that is
indiscernible to the knowledge of the situation) and Logics of Worlds supplements Being and
Event by articulating the particularity of truths (the incorporation of the consequences of the
inexistent in a specific world), L’Immanence des vérités clarifies the absoluteness of truths.
Truths are absolute, in that the dialectic between finitude and infinity leads to the creation of
the œuvre endowed with an index of absoluteness. It is possible to address love as truth in
terms of this itinerary. Human animal’s love is often constituted by the apparatuses of
2
finitude, such as sexuality, capital, convention, identity, and death. Philosophy, however, calls
for a rupture with finitude and encourages us to turn to infinity. More specifically, philosophy
affirms the contingent encounter outside of the pre-existing law, the declaration
difference, and the metaphysical happiness originating from the amorous process itself. To
support this affirmation, Badiou appropriates mathematical theory of large cardinals to show
the immanent possibility of infinity against the power of finitude. A key point here is the
distinction between the constructible (finitude) and the generic (infinity). If the former refers
to what is definable by the dominant language, the latter refers to what is elusive to and
subtracted from the defining power of the dominant language. Transposing this distinction
onto the domain of love, we can state that if family, ideology, social norms constitute finitude
(l’amour à la Gödel), evental encounter, amorous declaration, and the construction of the
constituents of finitude, it is always possible to support and subjectivize the amorous infinity.
However, there is a point of the impossible, regarding which the amorous infinity should be
moderate and temperate. It is the mortal passion of becoming the One, which constitutes a
deviant approach to the amorous absoluteness. Love can persist only insofar as it does not
yield to the temptation of the fusional One. After exploring the amorous infinity and its limit
point, one descends to the territory of finitude. One is no longer faced with love as the waste
(déchet) that is passively stuck onto finitude, but with love as the œuvre (œuvre) that is
actively interlocked with infinity, despite its finite form, and dynamically expandable based
on its subjective elaboration. For Badiou, who supplements Lacan, the amorous œuvre
consists of faithfully constructing the Two, while coming to terms with the impasse of the
sexual non-relationship. The amorous œuvre shows that love is not merely universal
1
Badiou (2018a, p. 264).
3
absolute; this is to say that it creates the amorous Two like a complete cardinal, which means
that the amorous world subjectively constructed by lovers is as powerful as or more powerful
than the existing objective world. Here, love reveals itself not as a transient feeling, but as an
absolute index, inscribing the figure of humanity within the trans-human truth.
Certainly, this vision of love often provokes a strong backlash. Let us introduce one line of
critique. Badiou presents the principle of maximality as a core axiom of the approach to
infinity.2 This principle stipulates that any intelligible entity exists, insofar as its existence can
be inferred without any contradiction from the axioms concerning the entity in question.
Here, some may argue that Badiouian love is derived from the philosophico-mathematical
thesis that presupposes equivalence between being and thinking. For such an opponent, love
as truth is nothing but a construct of thought, belonging to a theoretical fiction suturing love
to mathematics. Other detractors, however, may argue that love as truth is a consequence of a
decision suturing love to politics. For instance, Badiou notes that there is a political
implication of the axiom of choice, in that this axiom allows for a representation beyond the
emphasize reliable entitlement, the axiom of choice presents illegal and supra-legal
entitlement. In fact, the axiom of choice fits into Badiou’s critique of online dating systems
and family systems, both of which demand that love be based on a calculable property and a
predetermined guarantee. For this opponent, however, Badiou is transforming the communist
political subject into the amorous subject, radically emancipated from the contemporary
capitalist, technocratic, familial regime. In sum, these two critiques regard Badiouian love as
2
Badiou (2014, p. 11).
3
Badiou (2014, p. 20).
4
These are external critiques of Badiou’s system, but there can be an internal critique as well.
According to such a critique, Badiou treats finitude too lightly. After all, to use the Spinozian
terms, finite modes exist alongside infinite modes. To use the set theoretical terms, there are
not only infinite sets, but also finite sets; Badiou, on this view, never takes finite modes and
finite sets seriously. Badiou’s likely retort is that his vision is hardly lopsided toward infinity
and that the œuvre actually embodies a dialectical relation between infinity and finitude. In
fact, Badiou points out that the total rupture with finitude amounts to an ultra-leftist chimera. 4
The œuvre does not require a global separation from finitude, but rather a local rupture with
finitude. This viewpoint is already present in the Theory of the Subject where Badiou notes
that while an exclusive focus on force (e.g., Deleuze’s chaos) belongs to the ultra-leftist
deviation, an exclusive focus on place (e.g., Lévi-Strauss’s structure) belongs to the ultra-
rightist deviation.5 This opponent nevertheless insists that Badiou’s approach may be
conceived of as infinity-centrism, calling our attention to the facticity of finitude with which
one should cope, and not the ideology of finitude by which one is enslaved. Given that the
œuvre of love, “apart from the familial state, seem doomed to sporadic moments of ecstasy,” 6
the opponent may also affirm, like Blanchot, that ecstasy as an instance of disaster is “not
absolute but disorients the absolute.”7 Love constitutes our existential drama not only with
happiness but with disaster, and disaster does not simply subordinate us to nihilism, but rather
disorients the absolute. While love evokes the possibility of participating in infinity despite
our finite existence, love also testifies ruthlessly to the impossibility of ignoring finitude. In
L’Immanence des vérités, Badiou argues that, while the size of the world amounts to an
4
Badiou (2018a, p. 266).
5
Badiou (2009b, p. 207).
6
Badiou (2018a, p. 560).
7
Vinciguerra (2014, p. 164).
5
inaccessible cardinal, the size of the amorous œuvre amounts to a complete cardinal that is
superior to an inaccessible cardinal and subsumes it from above. According to this opponent,
however, we cannot state that love overwhelmed by the world, which fails to create a
complete cardinal, is not genuine love, implying that love as truth addresses only a partial and
narrow spectrum of love. In sum, this critique asserts that Badiou too easily dismisses the
For our part, leaving aside the conditions in which these critiques are justifiable, let us briefly
recall Badiou’s response to Peter Hallward, who criticized Badiou’s presentation of abstract
thinking that reduces empirical multiplicities to formal multiplicities. 8 One may consider a
similar kind of critique of love that can be found in L’Immanence des vérités: “What does
love have anything to do with the theory of large cardinal?” Here, we may expect Badiou to
(sic); I am perfectly aware of the paradoxical violence of the statements I uphold.” 9 Here, it is
notable that, at the end of this response is a full presentation of the core thesis of
from ordinary and mundane life, and it is only through awakening that we live as Immortals
(Aristotle) or, consider the absolute with us all along (Hegel). Moreover, an awakening is
absolutely convinced that the duty of philosophy is to break with the dogma of finitude and
awaken from the slumber of finitude. In this respect, no external critique can dampen the
critique can discourage the philosopher’s courage to fight against the mastery of finitude.
This article argues that a more reasonable engagement with Badiou consists neither of
8
Badiou (2004, p. 232).
9
Badiou (2004, p. 237).
10
Badiou (2004, p. 237).
6
external nor internal critiques, but rather of a subtle supplementation to Badiou. To produce
this supplementation, this article uses the same material used by Badiou to present love as
Let us construct this supplementation in five points. The first point concerns finitude and
infinity. In Conditions, Badiou points out the essential finitude of the Lacanian subject, for
through the conjunction of the preceding numbers of 0 and 1. 12 Here, a Lacanian may argue
that the Lacanian feminine subject is not essentially finite. While the phallic function, which
affects all speaking beings, corresponds to finitude, feminine jouissance, which goes beyond
finitude and the sexual non-relationship, even between finitude and feminine jouissance,
based on Lacan’s following remark: “Its finitude [the finitude of the drives] is related to the
such.”13 Although it is unclear how the equivalence between finitude and feminine jouissance
can be derived from this passage, the connection between finitude and the impossibility of the
sexual non-relationship is made clearly here. But things change, as Lacan develops the
feminine “not-all” in Seminar XX. A woman is not-all because of “a jouissance that, with
respect to everything that can be used in the function of Φx, is in the realm of the infinite.” 14
Here, the infinity of feminine jouissance, which goes beyond the phallic finitude or the
finitude of the drives, is affirmed. For Badiou, however, this is unsatisfactory, for the infinity
of feminine jouissance is, at best, the infinity of inaccessibility. Feminine infinity is not
11
Regarding the necessity and significance of this supplementary approach, see e.g. Bryant (2007).
12
Badiou (2004, p. 225).
13
Badiou (2004, p. 226).
14
Lacan (1998, p. 103).
7
the same sense that we do not know how God transcends human imperfection, even as we do
know that God transcends human imperfection. Meanwhile, Lacan, in Seminar XVI, states
that the hysteric poses the infinite point of jouissance as absolute. 15 However, the hysterical
infinity comes even closer to finitude, for the hysteric aims not at satisfaction, but at
infinity is a negative infinity. Because of this negative aspect of the Lacanian infinity, Badiou
would confirm that the Lacanian infinity is pre-Cantorian. Meanwhile, Lacan, in Seminar
XXI, connects the not-all with the Cantorian Aleph-naught. 16 However, whether Lacan is pre-
Cantorian or Cantorian, Aleph-naught (e.g., the cardinality of the set of the natural numbers)
is not sufficiently infinite for Badiou. For Badiou, in L’Immanence des vérités, describes the
kingdom of infinity as a hierarchical structure in which there are four types of infinity:
parts, and infinity as proximity to the absolute. These correspond roughly to inaccessible
cardinal, compact cardinal, Ramsey cardinal, and complete cardinal. All of these are absent
from Lacan’s engagement with infinity. Moreover, Badiou points out a correlation between
Lacan’s insufficient engagement with infinity, his political skepticism, and his rational
pessimism.
“It is moreover a regrettable error of Lacan in Seminar ... or Worse to let people
believe that the infinities higher than ω are only fictions. By doing so, he paid in
pure theory the price of his political skepticism, and more generally of rational
It is indeed true that the analytic work attempts to transform neurotic miseries into common
15
Lacan (2006, p. 335).
16
Lacan (1973, the lesson of 19 February 1974).
17
Badiou (2018a, p. 323).
8
unhappiness through the activation of the unconscious. However, this article argues that the
schema “Lacanian finitude (or inaccessible infinity) vs Badiouian infinity” can be misleading,
especially when we consider Badiou’s discussion of the unconscious and the analytic
the unconscious. On the one hand, he argues that the unconscious is subject to finitude.
Consider the following remark: “The fundamental ontological hypothesis of any oppressive
system, whatever it is (including, for example, the unconscious of an individual), asserts the
unlimited sovereignty of finitude, which amounts to affirming that all that is, all multiplicity,
is constructible.”19 On the other hand, he supports the infinity of the unconscious when he
suggests that we immanentize the Cartesian idea of God. Twisting the Lacanian formula a bit,
Badiou states that “God is the unconscious itself.” 20 That is to say, the conscious
representation does not know the divine infinity, and yet, the unconscious knows it very well.
God as the unconscious is “the latent, immanent infinite resource, of which we have only
signs at the conscious level.”21 Moreover, Badiou maps his notion of the event onto the
subjectively inscribed, first, in the unconscious,” 22 and the operation of the subject of truth
lies in elaborating the unknown consequences of this inscription. Badiou also accepts that, if
repression corresponds to the apparatus of finitude in psychoanalysis, the analytic work lies
in stripping away repression, through the activation of the unconscious as the immanent
infinity. In this respect, the unconscious is not merely finitude-based, but actually touches on
18
For a detailed explanation of this framework and its discursive context, see Price (2015, pp. 162–164).
19
Badiou (2018a, p. 268).
20
Badiou (2018a, p. 188).
21
Badiou (2018a, p. 188).
22
Badiou (2018a, p. 188).
9
infinity. In fact, Badiou’s ambivalent and contradictory remarks on the unconscious hardly
contradiction as such. On the one hand, if an analysand’s unconscious does not oppressively
push him/her to the deadlock of finitude, we cannot ever make sense of why the analysand
uses the analytic work to explore an outside chance. On the other hand, however, if the
unconscious does not contain an immanent infinity, we cannot ever make sense of how the
analytic work can lead to the practical effect of subjective change. Here, let us recall Lacan’s
In a 2018 conference after the publication of L’Immanence des vérités, Badiou actually
adopts a similar attitude towards psychoanalysis. 24 He first states that, for Lacan, infinity is a
figure of feminine desire, and that this feminine infinity belongs to a classical discourse
originating from the Greek tragedy. Then, he states that the relation between finitude and
infinity is analogous to the relation between the symptom and the unconscious. The analytic
work mobilizes and redeploys the unconscious as infinity to destabilize and reconstruct the
symptom as finitude. Insofar as the unconscious is the reservoir of the subjective infinity, the
analytic work moves from the symptom as the finite unconscious formation to the underlying
structure causing the symptom, supporting the potential plasticity of the unconscious. During
this process, analysis encounters the real gap that resists any causal explanation or structural
logic, which Lacan calls the object a. Through this encounter, the subject experiences his/her
constitutive division and explores an occasion for a new subjectivization. In this respect,
draw a more nuanced conclusion. Despite their theoretical and practical differences, Lacan
23
Lacan (2006b, p. 520).
24
Badiou (2018b, n. p.).
10
and Badiou agree on the following point: The unconscious is an interlacing of finitude and
infinity, and the analytic work aims at subjectivization based on the infinity of the
This leads us to the third point. How then is the analytic “work” similar to and different from
the Badiouian “œuvre”? This requires attention, for one possible translation of “œuvre” is
“work.” Let us first consider how Lacan addresses work (travail) and waste (déchet). For
Lacan, work is a product of the master discourse. Work is something that the master as the
agent commands the slave as the other to accomplish. After all, is it not a master who
declares “time to work”? Work is also a product of the capitalist discourse focusing on social
utility and calculable performance. Thus, the subject is haunted by the following superegoic
voice: “Only those who work are allowed to enjoy,” or “work hard, then you will be able to
enjoy someday.” However, work does not belong exclusively to the master discourse. Work is
concerned with the analytic discourse as well. In Seminar XVI, Lacan states that
psychoanalytic experience allows us to introduce the analogy between truth and work. “In the
analytic discourse, the work of the truth is rather obvious, because it is painful.” 25 The
analytic discourse is not only about the articulated knowledge of the unconscious that the
subject does not know yet repeats, but about the not-all sayable truth, namely, gaps in
Moving onto waste, Lacanian waste is very different from Badiouian waste. In Seminar XV,
Lacan states that waste is compatible with the analytic act. 26 This is because the analyst serves
as the abject object that captures the analysand’s uninterpretable jouissance, thereby
mirroring the subjective real of the analysand. The waste implies that the analyst is not really
an analyst, except for his physical presence, but rather a semblant, namely, an instrument
25
Lacan (2006a, pp. 199–200).
26
Lacan (1967, the lesson of 6th December 1967).
11
the analyst is positioned at the point of idealization (I) or the subject-supposed to know about
the analysand’s unconscious. As analysis progresses, however, the analyst’s status falls into
the waste-object a, whose functional necessity consists only of encouraging the analysand to
face his/her subjective real and find a way to live with his/her opaque jouissance through a
proper symbolization. Here, let us map the idea of civilization as sewer (égout) in Seminar
XXI onto obsessional neurosis.27 The obsessional neurotic loves consciously, but hates
unconsciously. That is to say, he is too civilized and is therefore obliged to love his neighbor
and repress hate. Such ambivalence generates a variety of ritual symptoms for the
discontent in civilization, with his symptom being the stupidity of truth or the truth of
stupidity. As Denise Lachaud writes, “Who better than the obsessional could state loudly
what every speaking being repressed: in the beginning was hatred?” 28 The analyst as the
sewer of civilization can help him articulate his hatred, and this function of the sewer can
lead the obsessional to love in a new way. Here, let us refer to Lacan’s remark in Seminar
XX, frequently quoted by Badiou. “It is love that approaches being as such in the
encounter.”29 But Lacan immediately adds that, in love, at stake are beings who do not meet
each other, beings who are affected by the sexual non-relationship; he finally concludes that
love gives way to hatred. Love as the approach to being and hatred as the missed encounter
with being are interlocked. Therefore, the axiom that love is hainamoration (the nexus of hate
Finally, let us refer to the text “The pleasure and the fundamental rule (Le plaisir et la règle
27
Lacan (1973, the lesson of 9th April 1974).
28
Lachaud (1995, p. 320).
29
Lacan (1998, p. 145).
30
Lacan (1974, the lesson of 15th April 1975).
12
fondamentale)” in which Lacan relates the analytic work to the work of art (œuvre d’art).31
Lacan first specifies that the function of the pleasure principle lies in regulating the stimulus
as minimally as possible. In fact, insofar as the pleasure principle is interlocked with the
reality principle, it is no more than a conservative apparatus that distinguishes between the
normal and the abnormal, the average and the exceptional. However, the pleasure principle is
ultimately dislocated and disoriented by a paradoxical pleasure. In other words, it falls into
the trap of jouissance. Furthermore, psychoanalysis addresses the symptom as the particular
reach his/her singularity, name, and destiny. Lacan compares this singularity to a work of art.
Here, the analytic work leads the analysand to reconcile with his/her singular destiny after
working through his/her particular symptoms. However, Lacan concludes that this is not the
analyst’s intention. “It [our intention] is not at all to lead someone to make a name for
through the good hole of what is offered to him as singular.” 32 Sometimes, analysis has a
chance of turning the analysand’s singularity into a work of art. But the fundamental goal is
to incite him/her to go through the hole of such a work of art, no matter how painstakingly
Having considered all of this, the Lacanian work-waste-work of art has an interesting impact
on the conceptual configuration of the Badiouian œuvre-waste. For Lacan, the work can
signify both the product of the master’s commandment and the analytic work of the truth, and
waste has a clinically significant value. Moreover, although the work of art is regarded as a
singular destiny beyond particular symptoms, the core of the analytic work consists of
passing through the hole of the work. For Badiou, while the œuvre is the finite form of the
31
Lacan (1978).
32
Lacan (1978, p. 24).
13
active effect of infinity, the waste is the finite remainder of the passive consequence of
infinity. But the Lacanian triad “work-waste-work of art” is not simply incomplete or
imperfect, in light of the Badiouian œuvre. Still less do they belong to Badiouian waste.
Rather, the Lacanian triad blurs the philosophical distinction between œuvre and waste,
although for Badiou this distinction is as absolute as the Platonic distinction between truth
and opinion. Lacan points to the ambivalence of work, clarifies the positive and indispensable
value that waste contains, and articulates the importance of the hole of the work. Put simply,
it suggests the possibility of the interlacing of the œuvre and the waste. In fact, in
“Making work with regard to finitude, ontological here, political for Marx,
interrupting the work and being satisfied with a few possible acts. But acts are
nothing if they are not works too. We must therefore continue to clear in order to
make, and this is why any work takes with it, like a building site does, the
obscure and indistinguishable pile of waste that it must have stirred up.”33
The categorical distinction between œuvre and waste can be mitigated. After all, creating the
œuvre and clearing the waste are coexistent. To make a satisfactory œuvre, one should
process the waste skillfully. One may note that, sometimes, the pile of waste turns into the
œuvre through artistic elaboration. Refer to the project Plastikophobia, made by Benjamin
Von Wong, Joshua Goh, Laura François, and hundreds of volunteers. Constructing a large-
scale installation piece made of 18,000 plastic cups collected from restaurants in Singapore,
the project evokes the extent to which disposable items affect the environment. Although the
title of the project contains the pathological symptom, its visible effect is so powerful that it
33
Badiou (2018, p. 462).
14
promote awareness of the truth that humanity is not the master of the globe. Let us also note
that, as this project transforms piles of plastic cups into a crystal cave, it fits well into
Badiou’s critical message to the contemporary art world, which is that art is not a blatant
exposure of death, violence, sex, and body, but rather a creation of a new form. In sum, the
œuvre and waste do not stand in a relationship of binary opposition, but one of mutual
supplementation.
How then does the supplementary relationship between the œuvre and waste actually appear
in the domain of love? This questions leads us to the fourth point about the Lacanian sexual
non-relationship and the Badiouian Two. For Badiou, love that does not transform the sexual
or work through the impasse of the sexual non-relationship remains a waste. Only love that
comes to terms with the sexual impasse and constructs the faithful Two can become an
œuvre. More specifically, Badiou brings up two kinds of elements in love. On the one hand,
at the stage of contingent encounter, love is affected by the object-cause of desire μ, which
reduces the beloved’s total being to a partial object. While this object clearly explains the
evental aspect of love, it is not sufficient for Badiouian love. Badiou argues for “a concept of
love that is less miraculous and more hard work, namely, a construction of eternity within
time, of the experience of the Two, point by point.”34 When the charm of μ is no longer
constructed during the amorous process and subtracted from the sexual positions of both Man
and Woman. This implies that lovers, in their engagement with t, appeal to neither Man nor
Woman, but to Humanity, which can be summoned from the perspective of the Two. Love is
an index of the absolute, because it attests to Humanity as touched upon by the Two. In sum,
34
Badiou (2012, p. 80).
15
if μ is on the side of the sexual impasse, despite its evental power, then t illustrates the
properly amorous aspect, which is the construction of the Two beyond the sexual.
Interestingly, we can observe that Lacan, in his own way, also considers both the non-
relationship and the Two in different places. On the one hand, Lacan sticks to his axiom that
there is no such thing as the sexual relationship. Even the analytic discourse cannot overcome
the impasse of the sexual non-relationship. On the contrary, the analytic discourse prefers to
support and preserve the impasse. “Not that one could ever expect from it [the new discourse
that is analysis] the relation that I’m referring to, namely that it is the absence [of the relation]
that gives the speaker access to the real.”35 While the absence of the sexual relationship
amounts to the real of the speaking being, one cannot expect that the analytic discourse
authorizes the sexual relationship. But Lacan states in “The Third” that the singularity of the
analytic discourse consists of making a bond of two. “Socially speaking, psychoanalysis has a
consistency different from that of other discourses: it is a bond of two [un lien à deux]. It is in
this respect that it occupies the place of the lack of the sexual relation.” 36 Therefore, although
Lacan does not authorize the relation [rapport] of two, he affirms the bond [lien] of two. And
this bond, between the analyst and the analysand, does not amount to an overcoming of the
sexual non-relationship. Rather, the bond of two and the non-relationship are superimposed.
To use the Badiouian term, the bond of two arrives as an event in a supernumerary and
supplementary way, where the sexual non-relationship is lacking. Moreover, just as the
Badiouian scene of the Two does not pre-exist, but is constructed through the gradual
exploration of properly amorous and a-sexual fragments, the Lacanian bond of two does not
pre-exist, but is slowly established by the enduring symbolization of the subjective real. In
this respect, the framework in which Lacan focuses on the real of the non-relationship, while
Badiou focuses on the truth of the two is misleading. Rather, both Lacan and Badiou, albeit in
35
Lacan (2001, p. 506).
36
Lacan (2019, p. 87).
16
different terms, recognize the troublesome situation that love confronts with the sexual
impasse, and both point out the necessity of devising a consistent endeavor to find a way in
that troublesome situation, instead of being discouraged and frustrated by it. To state that
Badiou is easily sublating the sexual impasse though the amorous truth is as much a
simplification as stating that Lacan is pessimistically stuck in the sexual impasse due to his
skepticism of the possibility of the advent of the Two. Rather, it is important to note that the
Badiouian limping march in love implies that, without the impact of the non-relationship,
love would never actually be limping and that the Lacanian consistency of the analytic
discourse lies in the formation of the bond of two against the backdrop of the non-
relationship. In sum, love constitutes an interlacing of the non-relationship and the Two.
Finally, let us address the problem of the absolute in Lacan and Badiou. In his intellectual
itinerary, Lacan brings up different kinds of the absolute. In Écrits, he regards death as the
absolute master of human being37 and states that a woman “represents the absolute Other in
the phallocentric dialectic.”38 In Seminar XI, he brings up the absolute point of transference,
at which the analysand’s desire is projected onto the analyst as the subject-supposed-to
know.39 As mentioned above, he states in Seminar XVI that the hysteric poses her jouissance
as absolute. For our part, let us suggest another kind of the Lacanian absolute via the hole of
the work of art mentioned above. Doubtless, this hole is the hole of the sexual non-
relationship. Although the analysand succeeds in creating his/her singular destiny, like an
encouraged to encounter the hole of a work of art. The fundamental intention of the analyst is
not concerned about the analysand’s creation of a work of art but about the analysand’s
37
Lacan (2006b, p. 289).
38
Lacan (2006b, p. 616).
39
Lacan (1981, p. 253).
17
psychoanalytic experience of going through the hole. This implies that the hole is an ultimate
endpoint. Moreover, the hole is also a structural deadlock. In Seminar XVIII, Lacan observes
that the sexual non-relationship figures as the central void in the structure of the neurotic’s
discourse.40 The sexual non-relationship is a topological and irreducible void that cannot be
filled up with any social, legal, or discursive relationship. In this respect, the sexual non-
relationship constitutes one of the figures of the Lacanian absolute. For Lacan, the absolute is
a hole or void. The absoluteness of love then would not lie in feeling eternity and attaining
harmony, but in facing the hole and enduring the void. The absoluteness of love is inseparable
Although Badiou would certainly reject such an amorous absoluteness, the situation is not so
simple. In L’Immanence des vérités, Badiou defines the absolute substance V as the place in
which all set-theoretically multiple-beings can be thought. What is notable here is the
ambivalence of V. On the one hand, V is open because it has a hierarchical structure that
begins with the empty set and moves interminably upward to the complete cardinal and
beyond. Now, for Badiou, love can be evoked as both the empty set (the multiple-of-nothing
as the indeterminate name) and the infinite multiplicities of large cardinals. “The power of the
multiple and its empty ‘heart’ can also be summoned through the systematic play, carried to
infinity, of pure difference (love).”41 Insofar as every multiplicity, including the empty set, can
be summoned through love, we can state that love is pervasively embedded within the ever-
ascending movement from the empty set to the complete cardinal and above. However, as
Kunen’s theorem proves, there is a limit to the ascending movement, which implies that the
succession is impossible, and this constitutes “the real of the absolute.” 42 However, one may
40
Lacan (2007b, p. 166).
41
Badiou (2004, p. 234).
42
Badiou (2018a, p. 681).
18
be tempted to ignore the real of the absolute and to attain the ultimate cardinal that entertains
a privileged relationship with the absolute. In technical terms, this can occur when one
terms, one commits such a deviating practice by appealing to the internal movement of the
substance, rather than dialectically touching the substance through the mediation of the
attribute. In love, this temptation emerges as the desire to attain the One.
longer have to deal with the gap, the difference, the separation between the
withdrawal or defect. The ambition, basically, to be in V, the one that goes from
V to V.43
Note that the absolute referent itself and the place of absolutization of truths are distinct.
Truths can and must be absolutized, not by means of the substance V, but by the attribute M
as the internal model of V. Moreover, the gap between V and M must be maintained
rigorously. Applying this to love, love can survive and persist only when it continues struggle
with the gap between the desiring One and the ever-precarious Two, rather than leaning
toward the desiring One, which ultimately aims for the ecstatic One. Just as absolute power
In this respect, while the absoluteness of love can be summoned through the void and infinity,
the real of the absoluteness of love should be handled carefully. The absoluteness of love lies
not only in applying the power of the Two to the ascending movement in the kingdom of
infinity, but also in facing the real of the ascending movement and staying alert to the
overwhelming temptation to be the One. Here, let us note that Badiou regards V as both the
43
Badiou (2018a, p. 481).
19
is philosophically imperative to stay true to the amorous absoluteness, those who treat the
great Vacuum poorly are sucked into and devoured by it. The scene of the Two can be
constructed only insofar as lovers avoid falling into the One as the great Vacuum. For Lacan’s
part, in Seminar XX, he articulates the One of the sexual relationship, which is distinct from
the One of pure difference.45 In Seminar XXV, he remarks that the sexual relationship is
equivalent to the empty set.46 Integrating and recasting these two remarks slightly allows one
to assert that the sexual relationship does not merely amount to the empty set, but to the
Vacuum that can dominate the subject through the fatal temptation of becoming the One.
Thus emerges another Lacanian absolute, the absolute of the Vacuum of the sexual
relationship, which works in concert with the previous Lacanian absolute, that of the hole of
the sexual non-relationship. In clinical terms, if the sexual non-relationship may trigger
various neurotic symptoms, the sexual relationship may reduce the unsatisfactory lack of love
to the ravaging excess of jouissance. If the sexual relationship is fully operative at the level of
the traumatic real outside the mediation of fantasy, lovers in the sexual relationship who face
its invasive jouissance may get bogged down in the black hole of the Vacuum. Here, love
leads to the total nullification of subjectivity, as in Nagisa Oshima’s film In the Realm of the
Senses, where the woman cuts off the penis of her beloved, an act that prompts Lacan to
comment that the woman’s fantasy actually consists of killing him rather than castrating him 47
and, arguably, of dying with him to achieve absolute eroticism. In sum, the sexual
relationship is a significant form of the absolute that the absoluteness of the amorous truth
should devise a way of handling, and the Badiouian amorous absolute should learn to resist
yielding to the temptation of the Vacuum of the catastrophic sexual relationship. Thus, the
44
Badiou (2018a, p. 40).
45
Lacan (1998a, pp. 7/47).
46
Lacan (1977, the lesson of 15th November 1977).
47
Lacan (2017, p. 107).
20
3 Amorous Labor, Dialectic between Œuvre and Waste, and Artisan of Love
Let us summarize our five points. First, the framework “Lacanian finitude vs Badiouian
infinity” can be misleading. Second, for Badiou himself, the unconscious and the analytic
discourse are inscribed by the dialectic between finitude and infinity. Third, Lacan allows us
to recognize that the œuvre and the waste do not stand in opposition, but rather supplement
each other. Fourth, for both Lacan and Badiou, love constitutes the interlacing of the non-
relationship and the Two. Fifth, the Badiouian amorous absolute must stay moderate toward
the real of the absolute as the fusional One and thus, cannot be conceived as separate from the
Lacanian absolute as the sexual relationship. What then is a term capable of epitomizing all
of these points? This article argues that it is an amorous labor. For Badiou, love is a labor,
vérités allows us to recognize that love is a labor in a more concrete and comprehensive way.
knowledge and yet moves towards the truth, because it is a work that deals with waste as the
passive remainder of infinity and creates the œuvre as the active effect of infinity, because it
is a practice that struggles with the limit of the sexual non-relationship and launches into the
singular Two, and because it is a force that connects the void and the multiple with infinity
without falling prey to the temptation posed by the sexual relationship of the One as the
Vacuum. In fact, an amorous labor implies the following point experienced by every lover: all
of the anguish and happiness proper to love comes from and consists of the amorous labor
itself. Love contains anguish, because it requires a constant struggle with the infinite
difference of the unconscious structure of each individual, and yet, it remains a happy labor
48
Badiou (2018a, p. 622).
21
because it allows us to touch upon the unprecedented infinity that can be produced by the
expansion of the pure difference of the Two. For this reason, an amorous labor can become a
labor of love. An amorous labor is both a stammering act that works through the real and a
This idea of an amorous labor provokes a new approach to the problem of the amorous
absolute and the amorous agent. Concerning the amorous absolute, it does not exclusively
belong to the œuvre. For Badiou, the concept of the index (index) serves as a criterion that
distinguishes between the œuvre and the waste. It is the index that saves the œuvre from
being stuck onto finitude, makes the œuvre irreducible to the archive, and leads the œuvre
into touching upon the absolute.49 However, as discussed above, the distinction between the
œuvre and the waste can be blurred, rendering it impossible to specify the amorous absolute
cannot be specified by the operation of the index. In fact, the amorous absolute lies in
something that is not directly articulated by, but can be drawn from, Badiou’s discussion; this
is the dialectic between the œuvre and the waste, the consequence of which is an amorous
labor. Badiou argues for the creation of the œuvre through the specifically oriented dialectic
between finitude and infinity. Love, however, goes so far as to affirm the practice of labor
through the immanently untotalizable dialectic between œuvre and waste, the space of which
can be conceived of as the interstitial zone of the super-absolute. While the amorous œuvre is
indexed by the absolute, love remains irreducible to and untamable by the absolute. Just as
the theory of large cardinals shows that a super-compact cardinal can subsume a compact
cardinal, due to its reflexivity, love opens up the zone of super-absolute beyond the truths
indexed by the absolute, due to its protean character. Let us add the observation that, if a
super-compact cardinal relativizes and subsumes a compact cardinal due to its superior
degree in the kingdom of infinity, the amorous super-absolute embraces the amorous absolute
49
Badiou (2018a, pp. 521–527).
22
In love, what is at stake is not simply that the absolute is with us all along (Badiou with
Hegel), but that the lover makes him/herself committed to a unique labor. This labor actually
fits well into the etymology of absolute (absolutus). Absoluteness means being freed. While
signify that love is different from freedom, it is the amorous labor that evokes and proves that
the lover is radically freed. A lover, however, is freed in an enigmatic way, without being able
to identify or discern from what he or she is freed. A lover is freed without being freed from
anything, because a lover is committed to a strange labor, from which one can neither be
freed (labor constitutes love itself) nor bound to (while there are conjugal obligations, nothing
essentially binds us to the amorous labor). A lover is not merely indexed by the absolute truth,
but is so absolutely freed that he/she cannot be contained or restricted by the absolute. What
kind of an agent, then, is a lover? In Seminar IX, Lacan specifies that there is no such thing as
the subject of love, but rather only the victim of love. 50 This is because love constitutes a
wound caused by the Vacuum of the sexual relationship. For Badiou’s part, he articulates the
subject of love, which turns the sexuality of the human animal into the material of the trans-
human truth. This occurs because love constitutes a singular infinity that is heterogeneous to
the finitude of the sexual. However, the amorous super-absolute calls for neither the victim of
love nor the subject of love, but rather the artisan of love. Only the artisan of love knows how
to devote him/herself to the masterpiece (chef d’œuvre), while finding a way to recycle the
misfired and fragmentary waste. And this artisan’s elaborate workmanship does not appear
only rarely in a fine museum, but frequently in our daily lives; yet, it is never totally
manifested and transparent, for the amorous labor is both an intimate phenomenon and an
opaque mystery.
50
Lacan (1961, the lesson of 21st February 1962).
23
The common implication of the amorous labor, the dialectic between the œuvre and the
waste, and the artisan of love is the need to articulate the interlacing of Lacan and Badiou in
our practice and thinking about love. While Badiou’s philosophical project focuses on the
critique of finitude and the affirmation of infinity, this article argues that one must return to
the experience of the artisan of love from the perspective of the interlacing of Lacan and
Badiou, and not simply from an empiricist or phenomenological perspective. Let us recall
Fichte’s description of love as “a desire for something altogether unknown, the existence of
which is disclosed solely by the need of it, by a discomfort, and by a void that is in search of
whatever will fill it, but that remains unaware of whence fulfillment may come.”51 The love
sense that it is non-objective movement heading toward infinity. At the same time, it is
Lacanian, in the sense that it is related to desire and disclosed by discomfort and void. If this
Bacanian approach to love seems too idealist, it is possible to conceive of a more sensible
─upper lack, with the punt, bathed off the bank, then pushed out into the stream
and drifted. She lay stretched out on the floorboards with her hands under her
head and her eyes closed. Sun blazing down, bit of a breeze, water nice and
lively. I noticed a scratch on her thigh and asked her how she came by it. Picking
gooseberries, she said. I said again I thought it was hopeless and no good going
on and she agreed, without opening her eyes. [Pause.] I asked her to look at me
and after a few moments─[pause]─after a few moments she did, but the eyes just
slits, because of the glare. I bent over her to get them in the shadows and they
opened. [Pause. Low.] Let me in. [Pause.] We drifted in among the flags and
51
Rougemont (1983, p. 220).
24
stuck. The way they went down, sighing, before the stem! [Pause.] I lay down
across her with my face in her breasts and my hand on her. We lay there without
moving. But under us all moved, and moved us, gently, up and down, and from
side to side.52
This passage narrates the scene of love that Krapp encountered again, while listening to the
tape recording of his life episodes. Badiou proposes two different readings of this passage.
According to one reading, what is at stake is the immanence of the Other inscribed in the
subject’s memory and the possibility of awakening. 53 Despite Krapp’s old age, the trace of the
Other still intrudes on his isolation, and evokes the evental possibility of the other life that
differs from the present lonely life. According to the alternative reading, the passage
describes “the multiple of the absolute moment, the one in which love, even when in the
statement of its end, suggests the infinite of the sensible.” 54 At the very moment that lovers
agree on the idea that their love is hopeless, lovers lay there, unmoving, but are moved by all
that moves under them. As a literary reconfiguration of the Aristotelian unmoved mover or
the Badiouian substance V, the passage shows lovers engaged in a movement without
movement. Even at its hopeless point of crisis and limit, love allows for a paradoxical spatio-
For our part, it is important to note that Beckett presents the Bacanian figure of love, namely,
love in its structural limit and its absolute trace. We can illustrate this point by
contextualizing Krapp’s last speech within the structure of the play. Krapp finally states:
“Perhaps my best years are gone. When there was a chance of happiness. But I wouldn’t want
them back. Not with the fire in me now. No, I wouldn’t want them back.” 55 One may claim
that, while Krapp is now indulged in his perverse practice of listening to his recordings, the
52
Beckett (1984, p. 55).
53
Badiou (2003a, pp. 70–71).
54
Badiou (2008, p. 278).
55
Beckett (1984, p. 58).
25
amorous scene in question may belong to one of Krapp’s best years, when he had a chance of
happiness. A brief re-encounter with this scene, however, is so strong that it infiltrates
Krapp’s solitude, kindling fire in him. This absolute trace of love, which eventally causes the
resurrection of the amorous fire, serves as the Spinozian-Badiouian index of truth. Truth is
the index of both itself and the false (verum index sui et falsi). It is not the case that Krapp
was previously in love and now exists in solitude. Rather, Krapp’s past and present are
marked indelibly by the amorous scene and can be re-marked by it in an unpredictable way.
Therefore, love in its absolute trace is already enough for him, so “he would not want them
back.” At the same time, let us note that, despite his random and impatient manipulation,
Krapp repeatedly runs into the recording of this amorous scene over the course of the play.
The scene thus amounts to the Lacanian real, as that which always returns to the same place.
Krapp will have remained irresistibly attached to and haunted by the amorous scene in a
symptomatic way. Here, love is discovered and re-discovered only through its loss. As in the
Freudian-Lacanian aim of drive, he will have circumnavigated the hole of the de-naturalized
drive beyond the satisfaction of biological need, extracting his jouissance from the amorous
mis-encounter without knowing what he is involved in. The amorous scene thus constitutes a
structural limit to his subjectivity. This time, exhausted by the demonic repetition of the loss
Seminar XXII, Lacan declares: “And that is why love is precious, eh!, rarely realized, as
everyone knows, only lasting for a time and all the same made up of the fact that it is
essentially this breaking down of the wall where one can only give yourself a bump on the
forehead, in short, that is at stake.” 56 For Lacan, the preciousness, rarity, and transience of
love are correlative with the fact that love is an attempt to breach its own impasse, which
56
Lacan (1974, the lesson of 21st January 1975).
26
never authorizes an easy way through. Any attempt to surmount the lovewall (amur) results
in an insurmountable bump. Here, love appears as an impassable impasse. For Badiou, what
matters is not breaking down the wall (fracturer le mur), but jumping over the wall (faire le
mur) of relativism, nihilism, and skepticism. To create the œuvre of love, one should not rely
on existing norms to bypass the wall, nor tolerate being imprisoned behind the wall. Love can
touch upon its proper infinity beyond the power of finitude. Of course, this love is not devoid
of a risk or obstacle. But it contains a sort of surplus, undisturbed by and invulnerable to the
impasse. This surplus is borne of turning the stumbling block of the sexual into a stepping-
stone of the amorous. Love preserves its index of the absolute, despite a bump on the
forehead. Here, love appears as an impassible pass. We thus reach the following formulation,
from the perspective of the interlacing of Lacan and Badiou: Love resides between an
To conclude, L’Immanence des vérités shows that love is an itinerary of the absolute that
passes through the dialectic between finitude and infinity. As Badiou is not only
supplemented by but also interlaced with Lacan, however, we have been inspired to move
beyond love as theorized in L’Immanence des vérités. Here, it is possible to witness love
glimmering at the gap between the œuvre and the waste, the Two and the non-relationship,
the truth and the hole, the absolute and the Vacuum. There is no eros of integration, but rather
an errancy of interstice. It is also possible to envision the artisan of love, who stands
obliquely between the victim of love and the subject of love, practicing the amorous labor,
holding dear the misfired waste of love, and constructing the infinite subjective world.
Moreover, every lover can hear this artisan, who sometimes tires, but never gives up on the
laborious work, voice wishfully, “Let love become an integral absolution for the super-
absolute interstice.”
27
References
Badiou, Alain. 2001. Ethics: An Essay on the Understanding of Evil. Trans. Peter Hallward.
London: Verso.
Badiou, Alain. 2003a. On Beckett. Eds. Alberto Toscano and Nina Power. Manchester:
Clinamen.
Badiou, Alain. 2003b. The Scene of Two. Trans. Barbara P. Fulks. Lacanian Ink 21: 42–55.
Badiou, Alain. 2004. Some Replies to a Demanding Friend. Trans. Alberto Toscano. In Think
Again: Alain Badiou and the Future of Philosophy. London: Continuum.
Badiou, Alain. 2008. Conditions. Trans. Steven Corcoran. New York: Continuum.
Badiou, Alain. 2009a. Logics of Worlds. Trans. Alberto Toscano. London: Continuum.
Badiou, Alain. 2009b. Theory of the Subject. Trans. Bruno Bosteels. New York: Continuum.
Badiou, Alain. 2012. In Praise of Love. Trans. Peter Bush. London: Serpent’s Tail.
Badiou, Alain. 2013. Lacan: L’antiphilosophie 3, 1994–1995. Paris: Fayard.
Badiou, Alain. 2014. Toward a New Thinking of the Absolute. Crisis & Critique, Special
Issue: 11–21.
Badiou, Alain. 2015. Métaphysique du bonheur réel. Paris: PUF.
Badiou, Alain. 2017. The True Life. Trans. Susan Spitzer. Cambridge: Polity.
Badiou, Alain. 2018a. L’Immanence des vérités, Paris: Fayard.
Badiou, Alain. 2018b. Citéphilo Conference. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=6-
sFK0ThZMM
Beckett, Samuel. 1984. Krapp’s Last Tape. In Samuel Beckett: The Collected Shorter Plays.
New York: Grove Press.
Bryant, Levy. 2007. Symptomal Knots and Evental Ruptures: Žižek, Badiou and Discerning
the Indiscernible. In International Journal of Žižek Studies 1(2): n.p.
Lacan, Jacques. 1961. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book IX: Identification, 1961–1962.
Unpublished translation by Cormac Gallagher.
Lacan, Jacques. 1966. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book XIV: The Logic of Fantasy, 1966–
1967. Unpublished translation by Cormac Gallagher.
Lacan, Jacques. 1967. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book XV: The Psychoanalytic Act,
1967–1968. Unpublished translation by Cormac Gallagher.
Lacan, Jacques. 1973. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book XXI: Les non-Dupes Errent,
1973–1974. Unpublished translation by Cormac Gallagher.
Lacan, Jacques. 1974. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book XXII: RSI, 1974–1975.
Unpublished translation by Cormac Gallagher.
Lacan, Jacques. 1977. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book XXV: The Moment to Conclude,
1977–1978. Unpublished translation by Cormac Gallagher.
Lacan, Jacques. 1978. Le plaisir et la règle fondamentale: Intervention à la suite de l’exposé
d’André Albert. In Lettres de l’École Freudienne 24: 22–24.
Lacan, Jacques. 1981. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book XI: The Four Fundamental
Concepts of Psychoanalysis. Trans. A. Sheridan. New York: W.W.Norton.
Lacan, Jacques. 1998. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book XX: On Feminine Sexuality, the
Limits of Love and Knowledge, 1972–1973. Trans. Bruce Fink. New York:
W.W.Norton & Co.
Lacan, Jacques. 2001. Autres écrits. Ed. Jacques-Alain Miller. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.
Lacan, Jacques. 2006a. Le Séminaire XVI: D’un autre à l’Autre, 1968–1969. Ed. Jacques-
Alain Miller. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.
28
Lacan, Jacques. 2006b. Écrits: The First Complete Edition in English. Trans. Bruce Fink.
New York: W.W.Norton & Co.
Lacan, Jacques. 2007a. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book XVII: The Other Side of
Psychoanalysis, 1969–1970. Trans. Russell Grigg. New York: W.W.Norton & Co.
Lacan, Jacques. 2007b. Le Séminaire XVIII: D’un discours qui ne serait pas du semblant,
1970–1971. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.
Lacan, Jacques. 2017. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book XXIII: The Sinthome, 1975–1976.
Trans. Adrian Price. Cambridge: Polity.
Lacan, Jacques. 2018. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book XIX: ...or Worse, 1971–1972.
Trans. Adrian Price. Cambridge: Polity.
Lacan, Jacques. 2019. The Third. In The Lacanian Review 7: Get Real. Paris: New Lacanian
School.
Lachaud, Denise. 1995. L’enfer du devoir: Le discours de l’obsessionnel. Paris: Denoël.
Park, Youngjin. 2018. On Love: Between Lacan and Badiou. University of Toronto,
PhD dissertation. TSpace, tspace.library.utoronto.ca/handle/1807/89811.
Price, Adrian R. 2015. “I START OFF FROM THE LIMIT,” On the first lesson of Seminar
XX, Encore. Lacunae 11: 131–164.
Rougemont, Denis de. 1983. Love in the Western World. Trans. Montgomery Belgion.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Vinciguerra, Rose-Paule. 2014. Femmes lacaniennes. Paris: Éditions Michèle.