Reconciliation and Justice After Genocide
Reconciliation and Justice After Genocide
Journal
December 2010
Recommended Citation
Parent, Geneviève (2010) "Reconciliation and Justice after Genocide: A Theoretical Exploration," Genocide
Studies and Prevention: An International Journal: Vol. 5: Iss. 3: Article 5.
Available at: https://digitalcommons.usf.edu/gsp/vol5/iss3/5
This Articles is brought to you for free and open access by the Open Access Journals at Digital Commons @
University of South Florida. It has been accepted for inclusion in Genocide Studies and Prevention: An International
Journal by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ University of South Florida. For more information, please
contact [email protected].
Reconciliation and Justice after
Genocide: A Theoretical Exploration
Geneviève Parent
Laurentian University
Genocide Studies and Prevention 5, 3 (December 2010): 277–292. 6 2010 Genocide Studies
Geneviève Parent, ‘‘Reconciliation and Justice after Genocide: A Theoretical Exploration,’’
success and durability of the reconciliation process. It will also examine the conflic-
tual nature and dynamics of reconciliation so as to underline how reconciliation can
be influenced by the form of justice privileged in transitional periods. To ignore these
aspects is to seriously jeopardize the medium and long-term prospects of reconcilia-
tion processes.
Post-conflict Reconciliation
How can reconciliation be possible? It is very difficult. I cannot reconcile with the
person who killed members of my family. He cannot bring them back, he cannot erase
the pain . . . Nothing of them (family members) is left. It is as if they never existed.1
278
Reconciliation and Justice after Genocide
279
Genocide Studies and Prevention 5:3 December 2010
between government and the rebel group(s), implies adopting and implementing
better policies, building ‘‘liberal’’ institutions, and changing the attitudes and
behaviors of those in power.18 Within this framework, internally displaced persons
are often marginalized, although many have warned that they must be considered
because they can greatly exacerbate problems and obstruct reconciliation.19 Since
transitional countries have little resources, the need is to target problems efficiently
in order to determine at which level reconciliation programs should be aimed and
work best.20
The question of the relevant level of reconciliation largely depends on ‘‘who is
looking at it.’’ In academia for instance, political scientists tend to put more emphasis
on the state,21 whereas social psychologists tend to focus on individuals and increas-
ingly on social groups.22 Although some put forward a multilevel approach,23 it is
far from a predominant approach to the problem of reconciliation. In practice, the
importance of the psychological dimension of reconciliation is much more explicit at
the local and social/community levels (e.g., local initiatives, NGOs, etc.), while it
tends to be ignored, dismissed, and/or minimized by national and international
peacebuilders (e.g., international courts, state/nation-building efforts, etc.). Attention
should be paid to this issue because reconciliation is almost always working at
all levels simultaneously, but not necessarily harmoniously. Hence, differences in
purposes or objectives are reflected in the respective levels, contradicting or working
against each other. It is important to have a global perspective on reconciliation
where all levels are considered. The variety of different understandings of reconcilia-
tion must bring scholars and stakeholders from different fields and perspectives
together—examining the affinities and tensions—in order to bridge the division and
have a holistic and inclusive approach to reconciliation. This diversity should be an
opportunity to engage into dialogue with others—all parts of a whole—to challenge
one’s own understanding or to explore new understandings rather than to divide
each into camps of like-minded individuals in order to strengthen one’s own view-
points. Otherwise, efforts at one or more level(s) could work against other level(s).
Processes of reconciliation will or will not foster sustainable peace, but they will
transform individuals, communities, groups, and their interrelationships.
To be effective, the reconciliation process must proceed bottom-up and top-down
simultaneously. Indeed, individuals are the fundamental elements of society and
widespread trauma throughout the population negatively affects all possible levels
of reconciliation.24 Most importantly, while the physical and mental health of
individuals is crucial for national reconciliation, national reconciliation has no imme-
diate, automatic, or necessary effect upon individual well-being.25 A government can
promote individual reconciliation through ‘‘genuine commitment’’ and ‘‘conciliatory
acts’’ done in public, which are accompanied by other initiatives such as funding
direct assistance to survivors or supporting public education. In short, citizens have
to believe that the government is genuinely seeking reconciliation. In the context of a
divided society, the importance of the psychological dimension—extreme traumatiza-
tion of the citizens—is substantiated by a number of defining features. For instance,
a divided society is characterized by the geographic proximity of the antagonistic
parties (often living as neighbors); by the perpetuation of conflicts across genera-
tions; by the lines of conflicts that are drawn from regional, religious, and/or ethnic
affiliations where one group oppressed the other; and by direct violence infliction.26
The experience of civil war is thus very different from the experience of interstate
war because it often questions and challenges the very nature and/or raison d’être of
the society at (civil) war.
280
Reconciliation and Justice after Genocide
281
Genocide Studies and Prevention 5:3 December 2010
Rwanda
Three levels of transitional justice can be been identified in Rwanda: the Inter-
national Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR), the formal criminal trials at the
national level, and the gacaca courts at the local level.38 After the genocide, the
government of Rwanda and the international community put much emphasis on
holding perpetrators accountable. Fighting impunity was at the core of the Rwandan
government’s policies, in conjunction with other measures to promote national
reconciliation.
In the context of a post-conflict divided society, within the retributive form of
justice framework, the concepts of victim and perpetrator tend to be conceived in
282
Reconciliation and Justice after Genocide
283
Genocide Studies and Prevention 5:3 December 2010
While in Rwanda silence remains on the alleged RPF war crimes, the number of
Hutu suspected of being génocidaires keeps on increasing.46 Gacaca played an impor-
tant role in the staggering increased number of accused génocidaires.47 It appears to
encourage an ‘‘exclusive’’ form of justice rather than an ‘‘inclusive’’ form where all
parties recognize their deeds and the others’ sufferings, even if they are of different
nature and degree. In fact, increasing literature indicates that the gacaca courts
seem to be skewed against Hutu. For instance, the Rwandan ambassador to Belgium
indicated that the number of suspected génocidaires was close to two million, which
approximated the number of Hutu male in that period.48 As Mamdani wrote,
Every time I visited post-genocide Rwanda, I would ask responsible state officials . . .
how many ordinary civilians they thought had participated in the genocide. Every
time the answer was in the millions. Even more troubling, the estimate grew with
each visit.49
284
Reconciliation and Justice after Genocide
Vidal suggests that the ban on public references to ethnic identity facilitates the link
between Hutu and génocidaire since it leads all to forget that Hutu are not all guilty
and that some were in fact courageous and/or victimized.54 Also, it has been much
more difficult to remember and recognize that many Hutu suffered and are suffering
since the word Hutu is publicly banned. Hintjens explains that the ‘‘victims’’ in
Rwanda—whether they were in exile or in Rwanda—are connected by ‘‘a common
persecution and their victimizers, as a whole, are to blame’’ for it.55 The dichotomy
Tutsi/Hutu is very palpable and perpetuating. The Tutsi constitute an ‘‘us’’; the
Hutu represent the ‘‘other.’’ Twa remain invisible/non-existent. Dichotomous iden-
tities are implicitly intertwined with the victim/perpetrator dualism, making both
dichotomies mutually reinforcing. Both dichotomies have been enforced by Rwandan
political programs and initiatives such as the imposition of an official one-sided and
exclusive memory.
The question of historical memory, both individual and collective, is crucial to
the victim’s psychological rehabilitation, and thus to the reconciliation process. And
yet each commemoration does not recognize explicitly the massacred Hutu, thus
reinforcing the Hutu’s collective guilt. Buckley-Zistel contends that each commemo-
ration appears to further create negative emotions and negative cognitive percep-
tions for both Tutsi and Hutu.56 For Tutsi, being reminded of the genocide through
commemoration on a daily basis can only feed his/her trauma symptoms, fears, and
negative feelings and perceptions toward the ‘‘other.’’ Moreover, the impoverished
conditions of many Tutsi survivors make matters worse as they claim that the
government largely ignores their call for compensation, increasing further their
post-conflict difficulties. A number of studies indicate that these material conditions
encourage the use of violence in order to remedy the miserable survival conditions.57
For Hutu, being identified as accomplices or suspected génocidaires, receiving no
acknowledgment for their sufferings and/or good deeds, and being marginalized
and stigmatized (often worsening their material conditions) in addition to their
post-conflict and post-genocide trauma symptoms (even if they are different than
the Tutsi’s) produces increasing resentment toward Tutsi. In these conditions where
psychological dispositions toward thinking in dualisms are reinforced, the potential
to resort to violence against the ‘‘other’’ appears to be increasingly likely.
Burkley-Zistel sustains that there is a ‘‘pretended’’ peace in Rwanda that is
supported by fear and pragmatism. In terms of pragmatism, the author explains
that living in an environment where ‘‘all depend on all,’’ means that ‘‘survival and
prosperity require collaboration.’’ 58 The gap between ‘‘us victims’’ and ‘‘them perpe-
trators’’ seems to have been continually and silently widened. Hence, this imposed
top-down ‘‘ethnic identity unity’’ and ‘‘consensus’’ do little to promote constructive
relationships between Tutsi and Hutu. These national initiatives conflict with any
form of psychological healing of individuals and communities. As each Rwandan
has to suppress his/her own suffering while trying to survive, openness toward the
‘‘other’’ has become unlikely.
This is basic psychology. Survey studies conducted in Northern Ireland indicate
that feelings of victimization of one’s party and competitive victimhood with the
adversary are negatively related to reconciliation.59 On the other hand, empathy
and perceptions of common identity with the antagonist was positively related to
reconciliation: ‘‘a full understanding of intergroup conflict requires changing the
relationships between the adversaries (e.g., to greater trust and constructive
cooperation) and attending to their psychological needs and feelings (e.g., needs for
justice and equality, feelings of victimization or guilt).’’ 60
285
Genocide Studies and Prevention 5:3 December 2010
286
Reconciliation and Justice after Genocide
objective is aimed toward the victims’ needs and interests because restorative
justice prioritizes the victim’s restoration rather than the perpetrator’s punishment.
Without leaving the harmful and illegitimate deeds unpunished, restorative justice
restores, so to speak, the perpetrator’s humanity; he/she can become a functioning
and contributing member of the community again.
Focused on the harms done and their redress, restorative justice promotes the
separation between the perpetrator’s actions and identity. This approach lays the
ground for a different perception of the other’s behavior than inherent ‘‘evilness.’’ A
dialogue on the possibilities of change is more likely. In short, acknowledgment and
willingness to seek repairs can be a starting point for a broader reconsideration of
relationships among individuals, groups, communities, and societies.
It was argued previously that the distinction between victim and perpetrator are
muddied in the context of war,67 especially in the context of a genocide.68 Indeed,
genocide implies that whole communities are displaced or destroyed, neighbors turn
against neighbors via forced complicity or inbred distrust. The theoretical static
victim and perpetrator identities do not reflect the fluid and changing sets of identi-
ties of each individual. Of particular importance in this regard, the ethnic group
often determines who is constructed as a victim or as a perpetrator, as seen above
in the case of Rwanda. A restorative approach to justice allows more fluidity and
flexibility in the victim/perpetrator identification since its responses to harmful or
criminal behavior seeks, first, to repair the harm done (to individual, community,
society), and, second, to address the reactions and the needs of the parties involved,
and then to reintegrate the ‘‘author of the harmful or criminal deeds’’ and the
‘‘victim’’ into the community and society. In short, restorative justice emphasizes
the intersubjective relationships and their complexity, especially in post-conflict
settings. While restorative justice is not as easily implemented as the retributive
form, it seems necessary to facilitate the (re)humanization of both parties. It
promotes much needed intergroup contacts in order to (re)build wider social relation-
ships within a deeply divided society.
287
Genocide Studies and Prevention 5:3 December 2010
occur. Officially and overtly identified as victim or perpetrator, each antagonist sees
their view of the ‘‘other’’ confirmed or strengthened.
There may be no more official Tutsi and Hutu identities, but the victim/
perpetrator-génocidaires identities could be more powerful than the former in per-
petuating the violence. The intensified negative emotions and cognitions, fear, dire
survival conditions, and so on, all constitute potential contributors to violence and
even genocide. The psychological and intersubjective dimensions of the traumatized
are clearly ignored in the reconciliation process, thus jeopardizing its prospects. Unless
all levels of reconciliation are considered in an inclusive and holistic way, fear, silence,
suppressed anger, hate, denial, among other things, will continue to prevail and to
work against reconciliation efforts at all levels. Projects and policies of reconciliation
and justice will bring durable peace only if they acknowledge and deal with the
intersubjective and psychological complexity of post-conflict environments.
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank Bruno Charbonneau and two anonymous reviewers for their
comments and advice in writing this article.
Notes
1. Interview, victim of Rwanda’s genocide, September 2009.
2. Yaacov Bar-Siman-Tov, ‘‘Dialectics between Stable Peace and Reconciliation,’’ in From
Conflict Resolution to Reconciliation, ed. Yaacov Bar-Siman-Tov (New York: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 2004).
3. See Harvey M. Weinstein and E. Stover, ‘‘Introduction: Conflict, Justice and Reclama-
tion,’’ in My Neighbor, My Enemy: Justice and Community in the Aftermath of Mass
Atrocity, ed. Eric Stover and Harvey M. Weinstein (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2004); Erin Daly and Jeremy Sarkin, Reconciliation in Divided Societies: Finding
Common Ground (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2007); Phil Clark,
‘‘Establishing a Conceptual Framework: Six Key Transitional Justice Themes,’’ in
After Genocide: Transitional Justice, Post-Conflict Reconstruction and Reconciliation
in Rwanda and Beyond, ed. Phil Clark and Zachary D. Kaufman (New York: Columbia
University Press, 2009).
4. Daly and Sarkin, Reconciliation in Divided Societies.
5. Clark and Kaufman, ‘‘After Genocide,’’ in After Genocide, ed. Clark and Kaufman.
6. For instance, see William J. Long and Peter Brecke, War and Reconciliation: Reason and
Emotion in Conflict Resolution (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2003).
7. Ervin Staub, ‘‘Reconciliation after Genocide, Mass Killing, or Intractable Conflict: Under-
standing the Roots of Violence, Psychological Recovery and Steps toward a General
Theory,’’ Political Psychology 27, no. 6 (2006): 867–94; Chris Cunneen, ‘‘Exploring the
Relationship between Reparations, the Gross Violation of Human Rights, and Restorative
Justice,’’ in Handbook of Restorative Justice: A Global Perspective, ed. Dennis Sullivan
and Larry Tifft (New York: Routledge, 2008); Emma Hutchison and Roland Bleiker,
‘‘Emotional Reconciliation: Reconstituting Identity and Community after Trauma,’’
European Journal of Social Theory 11, no. 3 (2008): 385–403; Solomon N. Gasana, ‘‘Con-
fronting Conflict and Poverty through Trauma Healing: Integrating Peace-Building and
Development Processes in Rwanda,’’ in After Genocide, ed. Clark and Kaufman; John
Steward, ‘‘Only Healing Heals: Concepts and Methods of Psycho-Social Healing in Post-
Genocide Rwanda,’’ in After Genocide, ed. Clark and Kaufman.
8. Daly and Sarkin, Reconciliation in Divided Societies, 183.
9. Marc H. Ross, ‘‘Ritual and the Politics of Reconciliation,’’ in From Conflict Resolution to
Reconciliation, ed. Yaacov Bar-Siman-Tov (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004),
200.
288
Reconciliation and Justice after Genocide
10. Daly and Sarkin, Reconciliation in Divided Societies; Karen Brounéus, ‘‘Analyzing Recon-
ciliation: A Structured Method for Measuring National Reconciliation Initiatives,’’ Peace
and Conflict: Journal of Peace Psychology 14, no. 3 (2008): 291–313; Clark and Kafuman,
‘‘After Genocide’’; Brandon Hamber and Grainne Kelly, ‘‘Beyond Coexistence: Towards a
Working Definition of Reconciliation,’’ in Reconciliation(s): Transitional Justice in Post-
conflict Societies, ed. Joanna R. Quinn (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2009).
11. See Karen Brounéus, Reconciliation: Theory and Practice for Development Cooperation
(Sweden: The Swedish International Development Cooperation Agency, 2003), 294;
Staub, ‘‘Reconciliation after Genocide, Mass Killing, or Intractable Conflict’’; Cheril de la
Rey, ‘‘Reconciliation in Divided Societies,’’ in Peace, Conflict and Violence, ed. Daniel J.
Christie, Richard V. Wagner, and Deborah D. Winter (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice
Hall, 2001); Louis Kriesberg, ‘‘Coexistence and Reconciliation of Communal Conflicts,’’ in
The Handbook of Interethnic Coexistence, ed. Eugene Weiner, Alan B. Slifka, and Lan B.
Slifka (New York: Continuum, 1998); John P. Lederach, Building Peace: Sustainable
Reconciliation in Divided Societies (Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace
Press, 1997); Joanna R. Quinn, ‘‘Introduction,’’ in Reconciliation(s), ed. Quinn.
12. Staub, ‘‘Reconciliation after Genocide, Mass Killing, or Intractable Conflict,’’ 868.
13. Daly and Sarkin, Reconciliation in Divided Societies.
14. Charles Villa-Vincencio, ‘‘Transitional Justice, Restoration, and Prosecution,’’ in Handbook
of Restorative Justice, ed. Sullivan and Tifft; Brandon Hamber, Transforming Societies
after Political Violence: Truth, Reconciliation, and Mental Health (New York: Springer,
2009).
15. For instance, Lederach, Building Peace; Ervin Staub, ‘‘Genocide and Mass Killing:
Origins, Prevention, Healing and Reconciliation,’’ Political Psychology 21, no. 2 (2000):
367–82; Ervin Staub, ‘‘Preventing Violence and Generating Humane Values: Healing
and Reconciliation in Rwanda,’’ International Review of the Red Cross, December, no.
852 (2003): 791–806; Long and Brecke, War and Reconciliation; Herbert C. Kelman,
‘‘Reconciliation as Identity Change: A Social-Psychological Perspective,’’ in From Conflict
Resolution to Reconciliation, ed. Bar-Siman-Tov; Ifat Maoz, ‘‘Social-Cognitive Mechanism
in Reconciliation,’’ in From Conflict Resolution to Reconciliation, ed. Bar-Siman-Tov; Judy
Barsalou, ‘‘Trauma and Transitional Justice in Divided Societies,’’ Special Report no. 135
(Washington, DC: The United States Institute of Peace, 2005); Ervin Staub, Laurie A.
Pearlman, and Rezarta Bilali, ‘‘Psychological Recovery, Reconciliation and the Pre-
vention of New Violence: An Approach and Its Uses in Rwanda,’’ in Peacebuilding in
Traumatized Societies, ed. Barry Hart (Lanham: University Press of America, 2008);
Herbert C. Kelman, ‘‘Reconciliation from a Social-Psychological Perspective,’’ in The
Social Psychology of Intergroup Reconciliation, ed. Arie Nadler, Thomas E. Malloy, and
Jeffrey D. Fisher (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008); Gasana, ‘‘Confronting
Conflict and Poverty through Trauma Healing’’; Steward, ‘‘Only Healing Heals.’’
16. Ronnie D. Lipschutz, ‘‘Beyond the Neoliberal Peace: From Conflict Resolution to Social
Reconciliation,’’ Social Justice: A Journal of Crime, Conflict and World Order 25, no. 4
(1998): 5–19.
17. Hutchison and Bleiker, ‘‘Emotional Reconciliation.’’
18. Karen Brounéus, ‘‘Analyzing Reconciliation: A Structured Method for Measuring
National Reconciliation Initiatives,’’ Peace and Conflict: Journal of Peace Psychology 14,
no. 3 (2008): 291–313.
19. Luc Huyse, ‘‘The Process of Reconciliation,’’ in Reconciliation after Violent Conflict: A
Handbook, ed. David Bloomfield, Teresa Barnes, and Luc Huyse (Stockholm: Inter-
national Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance, 2003).
20. Daly and Sarkin, Reconciliation in Divided Societies.
21. For instance, Michael Krepon and Amit Sevak, Crisis Intervention, Confidence Building
and Reconciliation in South Asia (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1995); Cynthia J. Arnson,
Comparative Peace Processes in Latin America (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
289
Genocide Studies and Prevention 5:3 December 2010
1999); Mark R. Amstutz, ‘‘Is Reconciliation Possible after Genocide: The Case of
Rwanda,’’ Journal of Church and State 48, (2006): 541–65.
22. For instance, Nadler and Shnabel, ‘‘Instrumental and Socioemotional Paths to Inter-
group Reconciliation and the Needs-Based Model of Socioemotional Reconciliation’’;
Walter G. Stephan, ‘‘The Road to Reconciliation,’’ in The Social Psychology of Intergroup
Reconciliation, ed. Nadler, Malloy, and Fisher.
23. Lederach, Building Peace.
24. See Daniel Bar-Tal and Gemma H. Bennink, ‘‘The Nature of Reconciliation as an
Outcome and as a Process,’’ in From Conflict Resolution to Reconciliation, ed. Yaacov
Bar-Siman-Tov (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004); Yael Danieli, ‘‘Essential Ele-
ments of Healing after Massive Trauma: Complex Needs Voiced by Victims/Survivors,’’
in Handbook of Restorative Justice, ed. Sullivan and Tifft.
25. Daly and Sarkin, Reconciliation in Divided Societies.
26. See de la Rey, ‘‘Reconciliation in Divided Societies’’; John P. Lederach, ‘‘Beyond Violence:
Building Sustainable Peace,’’ in Beyond Violence, ed. Arthur Williamson (Belfast: Com-
munity Relations Council, 1995).
27. Hamber, Transforming Societies after Political Violence.
28. Nadler and Shnabel, ‘‘Instrumental and Socioemotional Paths to Intergroup Reconcilia-
tion and the Needs-Based Model of Socioemotional Reconciliation,’’ 44.
29. Clark, ‘‘Establishing a Conceptual Framework: Six Key Transitional Justice Themes.’’
30. See Harvey M. Weinstein and Eric Stover, ‘‘Introduction: Conflict, Justice and Reclama-
tion,’’ in My Neighbor, My Enemy: Justice and Community in the Aftermath of Mass
Atrocity, ed. Eric Stover and Harvey M. Weinstein (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2004).
31. Carrie Gustafson, ‘‘International Criminal Courts: Some Dissident Views on the Con-
tinuation of War by Penal Means,’’ Houston Journal of International Law 21, no. 1
(1998): 51–84.
32. Huyse, ‘‘The Process of Reconciliation,’’ 97.
33. Rama Mani, Beyond Retribution: Seeking Justice in the Shadows of War (Boston: Polity
Press, 2002); Suren Pillay, ‘‘Conclusion,’’ in Peace versus Justice? The Dilemma of
Transitional Justice in Africa, ed. Chandra L. Sriram and Suren Pillay (New Zealand:
University of KwaZulu-Natal Press, 2009).
34. Kingsley C. Moghalu, ‘‘Reconciling Fractured Societies: An African Perspective on
the Role of Judicial Prosecutions,’’ in From Sovereign Impunity to International Account-
ability: The Search of Justice in a World of States, ed. Ramesh C. Thakur and Peter
Malcontent (Tokyo: United Nations Press, 2004), 216.
35. Laurel E. Fletcher, Harvey M. Weinstein, and Jamie Rowen, ‘‘Context, Timing and the
Dynamics of Transitional Justice: A Historical Perspective,’’ Human Rights Quarterly 31
(2009): 163–220.
36. Andrew Ashworth, ‘‘Some Doubts about Restorative Justice,’’ Criminal Law Forum 4,
no. 2 (1993): 284.
37. Joanna Shapland, ‘‘The Victim, the Criminal Justice System and Compensation,’’ British
Journal of Criminology 24 (1984): 131–49; Robert Elias, The Politics of Victimization:
Victims, Victimology and Human Rights (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986);
Leslie Sebba, Third Parties: Victims and the Criminal Justice System (Columbus: Ohio
State University Press, 1986); Brian Williams, Working with Victims of Crime: Policies,
Politics and Practice (London: Jessica Kingsley Publishers, 1999); Jo Goodey, Victims
and Victimology: Research, Policy and Practice, (Harlow: Pearson Education Limited,
2005); William G. Doerner and Steve P. Lab, Victimology, 5th ed. (Cincinnati: Lexis
Nexis, 2008).
38. For more details on each initiative, see William A. Schabas, ‘‘Post-Genocide Justice
in Rwanda: A Spectrum of Options’’; Bert Ingelaere, ‘‘The Gacaca Courts in Rwanda,’’ in
Traditional Justice and Reconciliation after Violent Conflict: Learning from African
Experiences, ed. Luc Huyse and Mark Salter (Stockholm: International Institute for
290
Reconciliation and Justice after Genocide
291
Genocide Studies and Prevention 5:3 December 2010
60. Arie Nadler, Thomas E. Malloy, and Jeffrey D. Fisher, ‘‘Intergroup Reconciliation:
Dimensions and Themes,’’ in The Social Psychology of Intergroup Reconciliation, ed.
Nadler, Malloy, and Fisher, 4.
61. International Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance, Reconciliation after
Violent Conflict: Policy Summary (Stockholm: International Institute for Democracy and
Electoral Assistance, 2003), 5.
62. For an overview, see Ernesto Kiza, Corene Rathgeber, and Holger-C. Rohne, Victims of
War—An Empirical Study on War Victimization and Victim’s Attitudes towards Address-
ing Atrocities (Hamburg, Germany: Hamburger Institut für Socialforshung, 2002).
63. Holger-C. Rohne, ‘‘Opportunities and Limits for Applying Restorative Justice in the
Context of the Israeli-Palestinian Conflict,’’ in Restoring Justice after Large-Scale Violent
Conflicts, ed. Ivo Aertsen, Jana Arsovska, Holger C. Rohne, Marta Valinas, and Kris
Vanspauwen (London: Willan Publishing, 2008).
64. Felicia Pratto and Demis E. Glasford, ‘‘How Needs Can Motivate Intergroup Recon-
ciliation in the Face of Intergroup Conflict,’’ in The Social Psychology of Intergroup
Reconciliation, ed. Nadler, Malloy, and Fisher, 132.
65. Mary Achilles and Howard Zehr, ‘‘Restorative Justice for Crime Victims: The Promise
and the Challenge,’’ in Gordon Bazemore and Mara Schiff, Restorative Community
Justice: Repairing Harm and Transforming Communities (Cincinnati: Anderson Publish-
ing, 2002), 88–91.
66. Charles Villa-Vicencio, ‘‘Transitional Justice, Restoration, and Prosecution,’’ in Handbook
of Restorative Justice, ed. Dennis Sullivan and Larry Tifft (New York: Routledge, 2008),
393.
67. Uwe Ewald, ‘‘Victimization in the Context of War—Some Aspects of a Macro-Victimological
Research Project,’’ European Journal of Crime, Criminal Law and Criminal Justice 10,
nos. 2–3 (2002): 90–97.
68. Naomi Roth-Arriaza, ‘‘Reparations in the Aftermath of Repression and Mass Violence’’ in
My Neighbor, My Enemy, ed. Stover and Weinstein.
292