1st_amendment_outline_2024_spring
1st_amendment_outline_2024_spring
AMENDMENT
COURSE OUTLINE
Professor Kevin Francis O’Neill
Law 680—Section 61
Spring Semester 2024
Cleveland State University College of Law
NOTE TO STUDENTS:
Throughout this Outline, new developments in the case law appear in red font.
* * *
1
TABLE OF CONTENTS
PAGE SECTION TOPIC
003 I Introduction to Freedom of Expression
003 I(A) The Text: Implications of the Wording of the Speech Clause
005 I(B) Theory: Philosophical Justifications for Protecting Speech
007 I(C) Historical Development of Speech Protections
020 II Content-Based Restrictions on Speech
020 II(A) Speech That “Causes” Unlawful Conduct: Brandenburg
050 II(B) Speech That Provokes a Hostile Audience Reaction
061 II(C) Classified Information: Gag Orders on Press Coverage
069 III Overbreadth, Vagueness, and Prior Restraint
069 III(A) Overbreadth
076 III(B) Vagueness
078 III(C) Prior Restraint
087 IV “Low” Value Speech
090 IV(A) Defamatory Statements
102 IV(B) Threats
108 IV(C) Commercial Advertising
112 IV(D) Obscenity and Child Pornography
122 IV(E) Reluctance to Create New Categories of Unprotected Speech
126 IV(F) Lewd/Profane/Indecent Speech (Including “Secondary Effects”)
143 IV(G) Hate Speech
155 V Time, Place, and Manner Restrictions: Doctrinal Introduction
169 V(A) General Principles of Time/Place/Manner Regulation
172 V(B) The Public Forum: Doctrinal Introduction
179 V(B)(1) The Public Forum: Streets and Parks
184 V(B)(2) The Public Forum: Other Publicly Owned Property
193 V(B)(3) Unequal Access and the Problem of Content Neutrality
206 V(B)(4) Government Speech
213 V(B)(5) Government-Funded Speech
219 V(C) Symbolic Conduct
225 V(D) Political Solicitation, Contribution, and Expenditure
226 VI Additional Problems
226 VI(A) The Speech Rights of Students
239 VI(B) The Speech Rights of Public Employees
245 VI(C) Compelled Affirmation, Expression, and Association
254 VI(D) Compelled Disclosure of Expression, Belief, and Association
260 VII Introduction to the Religion Clauses
271 VIII The Establishment Clause
285 IX The Free Exercise Clause
301 X The Press Clause
309 XI Freedom of Association
2
313 Appendix Police Power to Disperse and Arrest Demonstrators
* * *
* * *
I.
INTRODUCTION TO
FREEDOM OF EXPRESSION
3
a. The First Amendment—in fact, the whole Bill of
Rights—is an express restraint on the powers of
government.
4
e. Though free expression is accorded great weight in
many contexts, it is never regarded as an absolute.
5
c. a self-fulfillment rationale, which holds that
expressive freedom is a necessary aspect of
individual dignity, autonomy, and self-realization.
a. Underlying authorities:
6
Supreme Court’s hostility to content-based
regulation [Cantwell].
7
rationale offers only meager support for protecting
art and literature.
8
e. Thus, in tracing the growth of expressive freedom, I
will focus here on the regulation of seditious speech
—in an accelerated tour of history from the advent of
the printing press to the present day.
9
ENGLISH LAW 337-38 (London, Methuen 1937); 2 SIR
JAMES FITZJAMES STEPHEN, A HISTORY OF THE CRIMINAL
LAW OF ENGLAND 299-300 (London, MacMillan 1883).
10
4. But starting with the reign of Henry VIII and
continuing late into the 17th century, the
definition of treason was extended (both by
statute and judicial decree) to embrace mere
utterances critical of the government. SIEBERT
at 265-68; IRVING BRANT, THE BILL OF RIGHTS 26-
27 (1965); 4 REEVES at 273-74; Philip
Hamburger, The Devel-opment of the Law of
Seditious Libel and the Control of the Press, 37
STANFORD L. REV. 661, 666-67 (1985).
11
1. In addition to constructive treason, the English
government employed a second method in
controlling the spread of dangerous ideas: the
licensing of the press. HENTOFF at 58-60;
SIEBERT at 41-87, 141-46, 186-91; BRANT at 98-
100; Hamburger at 671-91, 714-17.
12
unwieldy, ineffective, and conducive to bribery.
Id. at 263; Hamburger at 714-717.
13
4. After 1689, concomitant prosecutions were
carried out by Parliament itself, as both the
Lords and the Commons vigorously pursued any
publication critical of their actions. LEVY at 14.
14
12. At the crown’s behest, 2 STEPHEN at 311-13,
Chief Justice Scroggs (in 1680) established that
juries in seditious libel prosecutions were
permitted to decide only one issue: whether the
defendant had actually published the remark.
The King v. Harris, 7 Cobbett’s State Trials
925, 929-30 (K.B. 1680) (Scroggs, L.C.J.).
15
LIVINGSTON RUTHERFURD, JOHN PETER ZENGER, HIS
PRESS, HIS TRIAL (Chelsea House 1981) (1904).
f. The Zenger trial was the last of its kind under the
royal judges; on the Revolution’s eve, grand juries
thwarted such prosecutions by refusing to indict.
LEVY at 17.
16
h. Even after the Revolution, seditious libel remained a
powerful tool for suppressing dissent—but now it
was used by the States to punish loyalist expression.
FORREST MCDONALD, NOVUS ORDO SECLORUM: THE
INTELLECTUAL ORIGINS OF THE CONSTITUTION 45-46
(1985); LEVY at 173-85.
17
supported the Sedition Act and favored a
Blackstonian view of press freedom. SMITH at 152-
55; ORIGINAL INTENT at 219; RON CHERNOW,
ALEXANDER HAMILTON 572 (2004); David A. Anderson,
The Origins of the Press Clause, 30 UCLA L. REV.
455, 517 (1983); JOHN E. O’CONNOR, WILLIAM
PATERSON: LAWYER AND STATESMAN 182 (1979).
18
under the leadership of President John Adams, the
Federalist Party “designed” the Sedition Act “to
attack and eliminate the political opposition”—
namely, the Republican Party of Thomas Jefferson
and James Madison. Id. at 360. Spearheaded by
Secretary of State Timothy Pickering, the Adams
administration launched 51 prosecutions under the
Sedition Act, most of them aimed at silencing and
punishing Republican newspaper editors who had
criticized President Adams and his administration.
Id. at 361.
19
(4) It was not until 1925 that the First Amendment
was deemed to reach the States—through the
conduit of the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due
Process Clause. Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S.
652, 666 (1925).
20
a. Throughout the 20th century, government officials
sought to punish such provocative sentiments as:
21
e. Thus, the Court has ruled that Julian Bond could not
be denied a seat in the Georgia House of
Representatives for expressing “sympathy with, and
support [for] the men in this country who are
unwilling to respond to the military draft” (Bond v.
Floyd, 385 U.S. 116, 120 (1966));
* * *
II.
CONTENT-BASED RESTRICTIONS ON SPEECH:
DANGEROUS IDEAS AND INFORMATION
22
b. Because the most vocal of the war critics were
socialists, anarchists, labor radicals, and recent
immigrants, the public saw free speech as a cloak for
everything “un-American.” WALKER at 12.
23
(4) McKinley’s assassin, an anarchist, used his
dying speech to declare: “I killed the President
because he was an enemy of the good people—
of the working people. I’m not sorry for my
crime.” FREDERICK DRIMMER, UNTIL YOU ARE
DEAD: THE BOOK OF EXECUTIONS IN AMERICA 194-
95 (1990).
24
(8) With diagrams and detailed instructions, Most
explained how to prepare gunpowder; concoct,
store, and administer poisons; handle guns,
knives, detonating gas, and dynamite; and wrap
and dispatch his own original invention, the
letter bomb. TRAUTMANN at 100.
25
as various forms of mass activity, such as
picket lines, parades, demonstrations, and
soapbox speeches on downtown street corners
in which Wobblies would express their radical
ideology in deliberately provocative language.
Id. at 1056, 1065.
26
was not until 1920, with the ratification of the
19th Amendment, that women finally received
the vote.)
27
(24) Sanger and her husband were indicted and
prosecuted under the Comstock Act—
28
89; FLYNN at 278. The government tried to
discourage this picketing by arresting and
jailing the suffragists, who received 30-day and
60-day sentences; their leaders were locked up
for seven months. WALTON at 193. Looking back
over that two-year span of protest, “some 2,000
women had picketed, 500 had been arrested,
and 168 served jail time.” WALTON at 234.
29
206-07; SOLOMON at 29-30; RICHARD DRINNON, REBEL
IN PARADISE 186-89, 194-95, 221-22 (1961); MARIAN J.
MORTON, EMMA GOLDMAN AND THE AMERICAN LEFT:
NOWHERE AT HOME 85-86 (1992).
30
sentence for giving an anti-war speech. FONER at
177.
31
(1) In Shaffer, the Ninth Circuit upheld the
Espionage Act conviction of a defendant who
had mailed a book, THE FINISHED MYSTERY, that
contained certain “treasonable, disloyal, and
seditious utterances” in opposition to U.S.
involvement in World War I. 255 F. at 886.
32
(2) Far more speech-protective than “bad
tendency” was the “express incitement” test
propounded by Learned Hand in Masses
(granting an injunction forbidding the
Postmaster from blocking the mailing of the
August 1917 issue of The Masses, a
revolutionary journal critical of the war).
33
involvement in World War I, mailed anti-war
and anti-draft leaflets to draft-age men.
Through its adoption in Schenck, the “clear
and present danger” test effectively replaced
“bad tendency” and “express incitement” as the
prevailing standard for deciding illegal
advocacy cases.
34
3. Many scholars believe that Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes,
Jr. underwent a transformation in his thinking about free
speech during the summer of 1919. The same man who
sent Eugene Debs to prison in the spring took a very
different position in the autumn, urging protection even
for “opinions that we loathe and believe to be fraught with
death.” Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630 (1919)
(Holmes, J., dissenting). What happened to Holmes? It
appears that his views on free speech were reformulated
in the summer of 1919 through interactions with Learned
Hand, Zechariah Chafee, and Harold Laski. See THOMAS
HEALY, THE GREAT DISSENT: HOW OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES
CHANGED HIS MIND—AND CHANGED THE HISTORY OF FREE
SPEECH IN AMERICA 201, 343 (2013).
35
“[W]hen men have realized that time has upset
many fighting faiths, they may come to [see]
that the ultimate good desired is better
reached by free trade in ideas—that the best
test of truth is the power of the thought to get
itself accepted in the competition of the
market, and that truth is the only ground upon
which their wishes safely can be carried out.
That at any rate is the theory of our
Constitution.”
36
Americans, who saw law and order collapsing.
WALKER at 42. In 1919 alone there were 3,600 strikes
in the United States involving more than four million
workers. JAFFE at 3. The American press reacted
hysterically to the strikes, ascribing them to
Communist orchestration. MURRAY at 64-65.
37
criticized the government. MURRAY at 193-94; JAFFE
at 176-77; WALKER at 42.
38
the slightest suspicion of a Russian heritage or
leftist political outlook. PRESTON at 220-21; WALKER
at 44; JAFFE at 188-89; MURRAY at 213. The
Washington Post expressed its approval: “There is no
time to waste on hair-splitting over infringement of
liberty.” WALKER at 44.
c. Gitlow’s Significance:
39
“It is said that this manifesto was more than a
theory, that it was an incitement. Every idea is
an incitement. It offers itself for belief and if
believed it is acted on unless some other belief
outweighs it or some failure of energy stifles
the movement at its birth. The only difference
between the expression of an opinion and an
incitement in the narrower sense is the
speaker’s enthusiasm for the result. Eloquence
may set fire to reason. But whatever may be
thought of the redundant discourse before us it
had no chance of starting a present
conflagration. If in the long run the beliefs
expressed in proletarian dictatorship are
destined to be accepted by the dominant forces
of the community, the only meaning of free
speech is that they should be given their
chance and have their way.”
40
a. Unanimously sustaining the California Criminal
Syndicalism Act conviction of a woman who merely
attended the conven-tion of, and sought to help
organize, a new political party: the California branch
of the Communist Labor Party.
41
dissent, and he cautioned that widespread
suppression of speech can destabilize society
(id. at 375):
42
(1) Refusing to criminalize mere membership in an
organization, the Industrial Workers of the
World (IWW), whose ultimate goal was the
revolt of the working class.
43
(2) Reversing the criminal syndicalism conviction
of a defendant who had merely assisted in the
conduct of a public meeting, held under the
auspices of the Communist Party, to support a
longshoremen’s strike.
44
discretion of a jury, is an unwarranted invasion
of the right of freedom of speech.” 301 U.S. at
261.
9. McCarthyism (1950-1954)
45
internal security emergency in case of invasion,
declaration of war, or domestic insurrection, after
which the attorney general could detain any person
for whom there was “reasonable ground to believe
that such person probably will engage in, or
probably will conspire with others to engage in, acts
of espionage or sabotage.” This section was
sponsored by liberal senators Hubert Humphrey and
Estes Kefauver, who were anxious to prove their anti-
Communist credentials. Id. at 198.
46
states, the federal government, and many local
governments. Most resembled the 1947 Taft-Hartley
Act, which required labor union officials to swear, “I
am not a member of the Communist Party or
affiliated with such party,” and “I do not believe in,
and I am not a member of nor do I support any
organization that believes in or teaches the
overthrow of the United States government by force
or by any illegal or unconstitutional methods.”
WALKER at 188.
47
the propitious occasion appeared.” 341 U.S. at 497.
On these facts, the Holmes-Brandeis test would
never support a conviction, because there is no
suggestion of an imminent revolt.
48
i. Douglas, in dissent, observes that a conviction for
teaching the techniques of sabotage and
assassination might be appro-priate, but the record
here has no such evidence. Defendants merely
taught Marxist-Leninist doctrine—from books that
lawfully remain on American library shelves. How,
then, can we criminalize the use of those books?
49
would bar the Supreme Court from hearing appeals
in all cases involving congressional investigating
committees, the federal loyalty program, state anti-
subversive laws, and the acts of state courts, school
boards, and bar admission controversies involving
alleged subversives. Id. at 243.
50
(2) The defendant urges her audience to accept the
principle that commission of unlawful acts may
be moral or necessary to achieve political goals
(e.g., Schenck, Noto).
51
(2) and is LIKELY to incite or produce
52
b. When applying the LIKELY-to-incite prong, bear this
in mind: If the speaker is asking her listeners to do
something so complex or dangerous that they will
not likely undertake it without additional
information, special tools, or further persuasion,
then Brandenburg’s LIKELY-to-incite prong is
probably not satisfied.
15. Rice v. Paladin Enterprises, 128 F.3d 233 (4th Cir. 1997)
a. Background
b. Questions
c. Outcome
53
(2) “[T]his book,” held the court, “constitutes the
archetypal example of speech which, because it
methodically and comprehensively prepares
and steels its audience to specific criminal
conduct through exhaustively detailed
instructions on the planning, commission, and
conceal-ment of criminal conduct, finds no
preserve in the First Amendment.” 128 F.3d at
256.
54
(a) Hess v. Indiana, 414 U.S. 105, 107 (1973)
(“We’ll take the fucking street later!”);
and
http://thehomegunsmith.com/hitman.shtml
* * *
55
venomous speech to an auditorium packed with 800
supporters, id. at 3, while outside, straining against
a cordon of police, “‘a surging, howling mob’” of one
thousand people “‘hurl[ed] epithets at those who
would enter and tried to tear their clothes off,’” id.
at 16.
56
a. Setting aside breach-of-the-peace conviction of
defendant, a Jehovah’s Witness, who, in the course of
his sidewalk proselytizing, incensed passers-by in
playing a phonograph record that expressed
virulently anti-Catholic sentiments.
57
5. Feiner v. New York, 340 U.S. 315 (1951)
58
hardihood to suggest that the principle of freedom
of speech sanctions incitement to riot.”).
59
the crowd do not justify silencing a controversial
speaker. Id. at 320. And because one member of the
crowd specifically threatened to haul the speaker off
the platform. Id. at 330-31 (Douglas, J., dissenting).
But right after acknowledging that “the ordinary
murmurings ... of a hostile audience” do not justify
“the suppression of unpopular views,” the majority
opinion stresses that “we are not faced here with
such a situation.” Id. at 320-21. What situation are
we faced with? The majority opinion replies that
police are not “powerless to prevent a breach of the
peace” when “as here the speaker passes the bounds
of argument or persuasion and undertakes
incitement to riot.” Id. at 321 (emphasis added).
Thus, a close reading of the opinion suggests that
the majority itself regarded Feiner as an incitement
case, not a hostile audience case.
60
“would allow persons to be punished merely for peacefully
expressing unpopular views.” 379 U.S. at 551.
61
(3) Opposing racial segregation.
62
law. This is completely different from the hostile
audience situation, in which the speaker’s
controversial message so inflames the audience that
they want to attack HER.
63
produce a clear and present danger of a serious
substantive evil that rises far above public
inconvenience, annoyance, or unrest.”
64
b. Bible Believers v. Wayne County, 805 F.3d 228 (6th
Cir. 2015) (en banc) (hostile audience case in which
self-described Christian evangelists insulted large
groups of Muslims at an Arab culture festival,
proclaiming Mohammed a false prophet and child
molester, and asserting that Muslims will be damned
to hell if they fail to repent by rejecting Islam—this
message triggered an angry reaction by large
numbers of Muslim adolescents, who hurled eggs,
plastic bottles, and other debris at the evangelists
until law enforcement officers, who did little to
protect the evangelists, forced them to leave under
threat of arrest) (court holds that the officers
effectuated a heckler’s veto by compelling the
evangelists to leave; moreover, held the court, the
officers failed to satisfy their duty to protect the
evangelists from the lawless behavior of the rioters—
the First Amendment does not allow the government
to silence an unpopular speaker as a convenient
alternative to quelling a hostile audience).
65
the lawless behavior of the rioting individuals.” Id. at
252.
66
b. Note the increasingly marginal role that the
“fighting words” doctrine has played in First
Amendment jurisprudence.
13. Skokie
67
a. Snyder v. Phelps is a TORT suit. What is a tort suit
doing in the midst of these hostile audience
prosecutions? Your authors introduce the case as
follows: “Suppose the Nazis had just marched in
Skokie. Could individual residents who were shocked
and outraged by their conduct have sued them for
damages for the intentional infliction of emotional
distress? Consider Snyder.”
68
f. Chief Justice Roberts concluded his majority opinion
by observing: “Speech is powerful. It can stir people
to action, move them to tears of both joy and sorrow,
and—as it did here—inflict great pain. On the facts
before us, we cannot react to that pain by punishing
the speaker. As a Nation we have chosen a different
course—to protect even hurtful speech on public
issues to ensure that we do not stifle public debate.
That choice requires that we shield Westboro from
tort liability for its picketing in this case.” Id. at
1220.
* * *
C. Classified Information
69
coverage gag orders issued to ensure a fair
trial. 427 U.S. at 572-73. A fourth Justice
(White) expressed “grave doubt” whether such
a prior restraint would ever be justified. Id. at
570.
70
Amendment that delaying the proceedings
long enough to read all 47 volumes would
only compound the constitutional
violation;
71
(4) What propositions ARE clear from this case, if
any?
(5) Did the Court play fast and loose with national
security?
72
(c) But this has been the law since 1931 in
Near v. Minnesota, 283 U.S. 697 (1931),
where the Court observed that no one
“would question but that the government
might prevent ... the publication of the
sailing dates of transports or the number
and location of troops.” Id. at 716.
73
information as historical facts—facts that
were deeply unflatter-ing to the Executive
Branch because they showed the great
extent to which our leaders lied to the
American people and kept them in the
dark about the conduct of the war.
74
against the government could “involve human
life itself and on such an awesome scale.” 467
F. Supp. at 995.
75
unconstitutional because they are content
based. Id. at 797.
76
verdict, then no gag order may issue.” Id. at
798.
* * *
III.
OVERBREADTH, VAGUENESS,
AND PRIOR RESTRAINT
A. Overbreadth
77
b. City of Houston v. Hill, 482 U.S. 451 (1987) (striking
down—as facially overbroad—an ordinance
prohibiting speech that “in any manner” interrupts a
police officer in performing his duties; the ordinance
was so broadly worded that it was violated every day
and effectively gave police unfettered discretion to
arrest individuals for words or conduct that merely
annoyed or offended them).
78
used overbreadth analysis when confronted with a
content-neutral time, place, and manner regulation
that it might have invalidated just as readily under
the narrow tailoring requirement of intermediate
scrutiny.
79
(4) If you see a fact pattern like Reno or Gooding—
where the government has imposed a content-
based restriction whose focus is not confined to
unprotected speech but also reaches protected
expression—go ahead and apply the
overbreadth doctrine. This is the situation
where the overbreadth doctrine is most clearly
applicable.
80
d. is limited by the requirement of “substantial”
overbreadth.
7. Facial Challenges
81
b. The Supreme Court “has altered its traditional rules
of standing to permit—in the First Amendment area
—‘attacks on overly broad statutes with no
requirement that the person making the attack
demonstrate that his own [speech] could not be
[punished if the] statute [were] drawn with the
requisite narrow specificity.’ Litigants, therefore, are
permitted to challenge a statute not because their
own rights of free expression are violated, but
because of a judicial prediction or assumption that
the statute’s very existence may cause others not
before the court to refrain from constitutionally
protected speech or expression.” Broadrick v.
Oklahoma, 413 U.S. 601, 612 (1973) (quoting
Dombrowski v. Pfister, 380 U.S. 479, 486 (1965)).
82
permissible to punish this defendant under an
appropriately narrow statute.
9. “Narrowing” Constructions
83
U.S. at 884, but state legislation should be narrowed
by the courts of that state, Gooding v. Wilson, 405
U.S. 518, 520 (1972); Erznoznik v. City of Jackson-
ville, 422 U.S. 205, 216 (1975).
84
rejected an overbreadth challenge to a statute that
prohibited persons from knowingly promoting a
sexual performance by a child under the age of 16.
B. Vagueness
85
18 U.S.C. § 2339A(b), that imposed a ten-year jail
sentence for knowingly providing material support—
including any “training”—to a foreign terrorist
organization.
86
When this case was decided, the American public was
sharply divided on the question of how the flag should be
treated. On college campuses, in an attitude growing out
of the Vietnam War protests, students displayed the flag
in a gesture of mock patriotism or sewed it onto their
clothing—sometimes upside down or on the seat of their
pants. Other segments of society believed that display on
a flagpole was the only proper use of the flag.
87
basis, with the attendant dangers of arbitrary and
discriminatory application.
C. Prior Restraint
3. Speech-Restrictive Injunctions
88
(4) Under the “collateral bar” rule, speech-
restrictive injunctions must be obeyed even if
they are unconstitutional.
89
any “malicious, scandalous, or defamatory”
material; the paper had been sharply critical of
the Minneapolis police chief, accusing him of
corruption).
90
e. Speech-restrictive injunctions must not be issued ex
parte, and their restraints must be limited to the
narrowest possible scope:
91
(2) By engaging in expressive activity in defiance of
such an injunction, a speaker places herself in
contempt of court—and, under the collateral
bar rule, the injunction’s unconstitutionality is
no defense to the contempt citation. Randy
Barnett, The Puzzle of Prior Restraint, 29 STAN.
L. REV. 539, 553 (1977).
92
(2) the time frame within which the licensor must
grant or deny the permit.
93
(e) Hague v. CIO, 307 U.S. 496 (1939)
(unfettered discretion) (permit for public
meetings and demonstrations).
94
(6) Closely akin to these “unfettered discretion”
cases are those in which the permit scheme
allows licensing officials to consider either the
controversial nature of a speaker’s message or
its potential for inspiring a hostile response.
95
f. Failing to place limits on the time frame within
which the licensor must grant or deny the permit
96
LAND USE, AND THE FIRST AMENDMENT 291,
335-36 & n.269 (Brian J. Connolly ed.,
2017).
97
(a) Content-neutral permit schemes
governing expressive use of a public
forum are STILL unconstitutional if they
vest the licensing official with
UNFETTERED DISCRETION to grant or
deny the permit (Thomas, 534 U.S. at
323); and
* * *
IV.
CONTENT-BASED RESTRICTIONS:
“LOW” VALUE SPEECH
98
2. These “low-level” categories of speech are denied full
First Amendment protection because, in the words of
Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568, 571-72
(1942), they are “no essential part of any exposition of
ideas,” and are of only “slight social value as a step to
truth.”
b. Obscenity;
c. Child Pornography;
e. True Threats.
a. Defamatory Statements;
99
C. But before applying strict scrutiny, you should always check to
see if the regulated speech falls into one of the “low-level”
categories of expression:
1. must be content-neutral;
100
1. Defamatory Statements
2. True Threats
3. Commercial Advertising
4. Obscenity
5. Child Pornography
6. The Lewd/Profane/Indecent
* * *
IV(A).
DEFAMATORY STATEMENTS
(False Statements of Fact)
NOTE TO STUDENTS:
In this section of my Outline, you will often see the word “libel.”
The term “libel” refers to a defamatory statement that is published
in PRINT. The term “slander” refers to a defamatory statement that
is purely ORAL.
101
5. That case, New York Times v. Sullivan, reversed a
$500,000 libel award to a Southern official who, following
a clash with civil rights demonstrators, identified certain
factual inaccuracies in an advertisement they published in
the New York Times recounting the event.
102
to desegregate the Montgomery, Alabama bus lines.
TAYLOR BRANCH, PARTING THE WATERS 185 (1988). As
president of the Southern Christian Leadership
Conference, he quickly rose to the forefront of the
nonviolent struggle for black civil rights in the South.
103
officials brought a NUMBER of libel suits that were
designed to intimidate and punish the national news
media. Mary Rose Papandrea, The Story of New York
Times Co. v. Sullivan, in FIRST AMENDMENT STORIES 229,
229 (Richard W. Garnett & Andrew Koppelman eds.,
2012).
7. These suits targeted the New York Times, CBS News, and
the Associated Press for their coverage of governmental
efforts to suppress the civil rights movement. SAMANTHA
BARBAS, ACTUAL MALICE: CIVIL RIGHTS AND THE FREEDOM OF
THE PRESS IN NEW YORK TIMES V. SULLIVAN 2 (2023). In
filing these lawsuits, Southern segregationists were trying
to inflict financial ruin upon the Northern press. BARBAS
at 86.
104
3. What pushed the Supreme Court to create this extra layer
of protection? It was the EASE with which plaintiffs could
win these cases under state libel laws. How easy was it?
Let’s take a look...
f. Only three issues were left for the jury to decide (id.
at 262):
(3) And if the jury answered yes to (1) and (2), how
much money should be awarded to the plaintiff
as damages?
105
1. The “Times Malice” standard now extends not only to
public officials but also to public figures. Curtis
Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U.S. 130, 164 (1967).
106
drawn into a particular public controversy and thereby
becomes a public figure for a limited range of issues. In
either case, such persons assume special prominence in
the resolution of public questions.”
107
defamation suits by private figure plaintiffs. SMOLLA &
NIMMER ON FREEDOM OF SPEECH § 23:4 at n.37 (March 2021
Update).
108
b. Second, by voluntarily thrusting themselves into the
public spotlight, public officials and public figures
have invited closer scrutiny by the media, thereby
“expos[ing] themselves to increased risk of injury
from defamatory falsehood[s].” Gertz, 418 U.S. at
345.
109
far-right magazine who warned his readers that
Gertz was part of a nationwide Communist
conspiracy to discredit local law enforcement
agencies. The publisher accused Gertz of framing,
and orchestrating false testimony against, a Chicago
policeman named Nuccio who was convicted of
second-degree murder in the shooting death of a
youth named Nelson. Id. at 325-26. The Supreme
Court held that Gertz was neither an all-purpose nor
a limited-purpose public figure. Id. at 351-52. Even
though Gertz had built a distinguished legal career—
success-fully challenging the obscenity ban on Henry
Miller’s novel Tropic of Cancer, overturning the
death sentence imposed on Jack Ruby for killing
President John F. Kennedy’s assassin, and publishing
several books on legal subjects, RANDY E. BARNETT &
HOWARD E. KATZ, CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS 602 (2013)
—Gertz was not an all-purpose public figure because
“he had achieved no general fame or notoriety in the
community” and “[n]one of the prospective jurors
called at the trial had ever heard of [him].” 418 U.S.
at 351-52. Though Gertz agreed to represent the
Nelson family in civil litigation against Officer
Nuccio, id. at 325, he was not a limited-purpose
public figure because he “took no part” in Nuccio’s
criminal prosecution and “he never discussed either
the criminal or [the] civil litigation with the press,”
id. at 352. Accordingly, Gertz “did not thrust himself
into the vortex of this public issue, nor did he
engage the public’s attention in an attempt to
influence its outcome.” Id. Based on this analysis,
the Court concluded that Gertz was a private figure.
Id.
110
Time magazine for alleged inaccuracies in its
coverage of the divorce trial. Even though the wife
was married to “the scion of one of America’s
wealthiest industrial families,” id. at 450, and even
though she held several press conferences during
the divorce proceedings, id. at 454-55 n.3, the
Supreme Court ruled that she was a private figure,
not a public figure, id. at 455. In arriving at this
conclusion, the Court observed: “[E]ven though the
marital difficulties of extremely wealthy individuals
may be of interest to some portion of the reading
public,” the “[d]issolution of a marriage through
judicial proceedings is not the sort of ‘public
controversy’ referred to in Gertz.” Id. at 454. The
Court also rejected the notion that the plaintiff had
voluntarily thrust herself into the public spotlight—
in order to obtain a divorce, the plaintiff had no
choice but to appear in court. Id. at 454.
111
countered that Hutchinson was now a nationally-
known figure; but the Court replied that Hutchin-son
had grown famous only because of the Golden Fleece
Award: “[T]hose charged with defamation cannot, by
their own conduct, create their own defense by
making the claimant a public figure.” Id. at 134-35
(emphasis added). Hutchinson had not thrust
himself or his views into the public spotlight;
instead, he had been lifted out of obscurity by the
very same statements he was challenging as
defamatory. Id. at 135.
112
repeater will not be liable unless he is at fault in stating a
falsehood and may not be at fault if he reasonably relied
upon the original publication. DOBBS at 1123.
113
observed that the Stolen Valor Act “targets falsity and
nothing more.” Id. at 2545.
* * *
IV(B).
THREATS
114
standard that inquires whether it is reasonable to
interpret the statement as expressing an intent to
harm the victim. This is a fact-sensitive inquiry that
examines not only the words employed but the
context in which they were communicated.
115
being prosecuted for threatening President Lyndon Baines
Johnson. The defendant was arrested at an anti-war rally
for telling a crowd of demonstrators: “If they ever make
me carry a rifle, the first man I want to get in my sights is
L.B.J.” He was convicted under a federal statute that
criminalizes any threat to kill or injure the President.
Though the Court deemed this statute constitutional “on
its face,” it held that the defendant’s remark was the sort
of “political hyperbole” that did not constitute a “true
threat.” Id. at 708. Accordingly, it could not be deemed to
fall within the statute’s reach and could not be punished
under the First Amendment.
10. United States v. Kelner, 534 F.2d 1020 (2d Cir. 1976) is an
influential true threats decision. In Kelner, the Second
Circuit upheld the criminal threats conviction of a Jewish
Defense League activist who proclaimed on television that
he and his colleagues were preparing to kill Yasser Arafat,
who was then present in New York City for a speech to the
United Nations; the defendant stressed that “[e]verything
116
[has been] planned in detail,” and that the operation was
already in motion. 534 F.2d at 1021. The court held that
these facts fell within the unprotected boundaries of the
true threats category.
117
of death or bodily injury. VA. CODE ANN. § 18.2-423.2(B).
The Virginia Supreme Court upheld a criminal convic-tion
under this statute in a case where the defendant, in an
effort to intimidate his African-American neighbors,
displayed a noose in a tree in his front yard from which he
hung a black, life-sized mannequin. Turner v. Virginia,
809 S.E.2d 679 (Va. 2018).
118
reproduc-tive health services.” 18 U.S.C. §
248(a)(1) & (c)(1)(A).
119
not be deemed an unprotected threat, id. at
1019.
(4) There are two reasons, says the panel, for this
distinction:
120
public rally, rather than directly to his targets.”
244 F.3d at 1019.
* * *
IV(C).
COMMERCIAL ADVERTISING
(“Commercial Speech”)
121
speech categories. Valentine v. Chrestensen, 316 U.S. 52
(1942).
122
in fact alleviate them to a material degree.” Greater
New Orleans, 527 U.S. at 188.
C. Note that the Central Hudson test affords LESS protection for
commercial speech than that enjoyed by political speech.
Notwithstanding Virginia State Board of Pharmacy v. Virginia
Citizens Consumer Council, 425 U.S. 748 (1976), the Court has
recognized that commercial advertising holds only a
“subordinate position” on the scale of First Amendment values.
D. But over the last 30 years, the Court has shown a willingness to
read the Central Hudson test more strictly, thus affording
MORE protection for commercial speech than previously. See,
e.g.,
123
intermediate scrutiny of Central Hudson. Justice Breyer
(in dissent) accuses him of doing so. Though he does
briefly invoke Central Hudson and other commercial
speech precedents, id. at 2667-68, Justice Kennedy
asserts that the challenged statute imposes both a
speaker-based and a content-based burden on protected
expression, making it appropriate to apply “heightened
scrutiny,” id. at 2667. Part of the problem in identifying
the correct test is that the restricted speech in Sorrell is
not clearly advertising, and advertising has always resided
at the core of the commercial speech doctrine. This may
explain why Justice Kennedy states that “there is no need
to determine whether all speech hampered by [the
statute] is commercial, as our cases have used that term.”
Id. at 2667. In the end, he says, “the outcome [here] is the
same whether a special commercial speech inquiry or a
stricter form of judicial scrutiny is applied.” Id. at 2667.
b. 44 Liquormart (prices).
124
people in the dark for what the govern-ment perceives to
be their own good.” 517 U.S. at 503 (emphasis added).
F. The Supreme Court has never been entirely satisfied with the
Central Hudson test, and a number of Justices have expressed
an inclination to abandon it. But they are so widely divided on
how to approach commercial advertising that we shouldn’t
expect a new test anytime soon.
* * *
IV(D).
OBSCENITY
Much of the material contained in this lecture is derived from
125
BOB WOODWARD & SCOTT ARMSTRONG, THE BRETHREN: INSIDE THE
SUPREME COURT 231-46, 294-306 (1979) (2005 paperback edition).
B. Where did this convoluted test come from? To find out, let’s go
back in time—to 1971 and the Supreme Court chambers of
Justice Byron White.
126
5. White’s test for obscenity: No erect penises, and no oral,
anal, or vaginal penetration.
127
3. But in Roth’s wake, lower courts kept banning material
that Brennan thought was clearly NOT obscene.
128
3. Brennan and Burger circulated competing opinions,
trying to sway the three undecided Justices.
129
softball question, tying the necessary flexibility to the jury
system.
130
found them repulsive. As the father of three daughters, he
found it impossible to justify any First Amendment
protection for such expression. Thus, it was inevitable
that he would side with Chief Justice Burger.
10. When Powell declared his intention to vote with the Chief
Justice, poor Harry Blackmun was left in the center of a 4-
to-4 tie (just as he had been only a few months earlier in
Roe v. Wade).
13. Blackmun held out on this change and Burger, after twice
rejecting it, finally relented. Miller v. California was born.
15. Note that the first and second prongs are reflective of a
local standard, but the third prong is a national standard.
16. Note also the influence of White and Blackmun, the two
swing votes.
131
Justices, to be graphically specific about which hard-
core sex acts pornographers would have to avoid.
I. Aftermath
132
1. Within the vast spectrum of sexually explicit material,
only the narrow subsets of obscenity (discussed in this
section) and child pornography (discussed in the next
section) may be criminalized.
133
7. Though the private possession of obscene material is
protected from prosecution, Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U.S.
557, 565 (1969), the public exhibition of such material—
even in a theater open only to consenting adults—is not,
Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, 413 U.S. 49, 57 (1973).
* * *
CHILD PORNOGRAPHY
2. But unlike Miller, a trier of fact need not find that the
material appeals to the prurient interest of the average
person; and
1. Background
134
a. Advances in computer imaging technology have
enabled child pornographers to create computer-
generated child porn—i.e., pornographic materials
that depict children engaging in sexually explicit
activity without using real children to create the
materials. 35 U. SAN FRANCISCO L. REV. 109, 111
(2000).
135
(2) Protecting children from “sexual exploitation
provide[s] a compelling governmental interest”
in proscribing both real and virtual child porn.
3. The Outcome:
136
Ashcroft v. Free Speech Coalition, 535 U.S. 234
(2002).
* * *
IV(E).
THE COURT’S RELUCTANCE TO CREATE NEW
CATEGORIES OF UNPROTECTED SPEECH
A. In 2010 and 2011, the Supreme Court handed down two
decisions that reveal a deep unwillingness to recognize any
additional categories of unprotected speech. Let’s take a close
look at those two decisions.
137
Court’s refusal to uphold the statute shows that the
Justices are reluctant to recognize new categories of
unprotected speech.
138
9. The Chief Justice went on to suggest that speech will be
deemed categorically unprotected only if it has so been
treated by long-standing historical tradition: “Our
decisions ... cannot be taken as establishing a
freewheeling authority to declare new categories of
speech outside the scope of the First Amendment. Maybe
there are some categories of speech that have been
historically unprotected, but have not yet been specifically
identified or discussed as such in our case law. But if so,
there is no evidence that ‘depictions of animal cruelty’ is
among them. We need not foreclose the future
recognition of such additional categories to reject the
Government’s highly manipulable balancing test as a
means of identifying them.” Id. at 1586.
139
“without persuasive evidence that a novel restriction on
content is part of a long (if heretofore unrecognized)
tradition of proscription.” Id. at 2734.
* * *
140
IV(F).
THE LEWD/PROFANE/INDECENT
A. Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15 (1971)
141
(1) These factors—captive audience, bombardment
of sensibilities, intrusion upon the privacy of an
unwitting “audience”—later prove important in
the Supreme Court’s treatment of the
Lewd/Profane/Indecent.
142
such freedom will ultimately produce a more
capable citizenry and more perfect polity and in
the belief that no other approach would
comport with the premise of individual dignity
and choice upon which our political system
rests.”
143
1. The City’s “Traffic Safety” Justification
144
(3) This is precisely what the City attempted here,
singling out films containing nudity for special
prohibition.
145
especially vulnerable to content-based restrictions
on indecent speech.
146
c. The laudable goal of protecting children, he asserts,
does not mean reducing the adult population to
receiving only what is fit for kids.
147
E. Iancu v. Brunetti, 139 S. Ct. 2294 (2019)
148
5. In justifying this divergent treatment, the Court has
stressed two aspects of broadcasting:
149
4. This “affirmative steps” factor would loom large in Reno v.
ACLU, helping to distinguish the medium of cyberspace
from the medium of broadcasting.
150
d. Finally, and again in sharp contrast to the broadcast
medium, “[c]ommunications over the Internet do not
‘invade’ an individual’s home or appear on one’s
computer screen unbidden.” 521 U.S. at 869
(quoting the district court’s findings of fact, 929 F.
Supp. at 844). This theme evokes the “affirmative
steps” idea from Sable—the notion that, in
cyberspace, one goes actively searching for material
rather than being passively bombarded by it, that
“[u]sers seldom encounter content ‘by accident,’”
Reno, 521 U.S. at 869.
151
(5) Thus, the Act’s inevitable effect would be to
reduce the level of discourse on the Internet
from that suitable for adults to that suitable
only for children:
152
“plausible, less restrictive alterna-tives to COPA”—
namely, blocking and filtering software.
153
3. The secondary effects doctrine has been applied to a wide
range of laws governing adult entertainment
establishments. These include zoning laws and laws
restricting window displays, hours of operation, and the
interaction between performers and customers.
154
values that frequently accompany adult theaters, not
the sexually explicit content of the films they exhibit,
id. at 48, the ordinance “is completely consistent
with our definition of ‘content-neutral’ speech
regulations as those that ‘are justified without
reference to the content of the regulated speech,’”
id. at 48-49 (emphasis added) (quoting Virginia
Pharmacy Board v. Virginia Citizens Consumer
Council, Inc., 425 U.S. 748, 771 (1976)).
155
b. The ordinance was not underinclusive for failing to
embrace massage parlors and other adult
businesses. The City was free to address adult
businesses one step at a time. Id. at 52-53.
See Z.J. Gifts v. City of Aurora, 136 F.3d 683, 687 (10th
Cir. 1998) (dissimilarity between adult businesses
examined in secondary effects study on which city relied
and adult businesses the city sought to regulate did not
affect the ordinance’s content-neutrality for First
Amendment purposes).
The Court held that the city could justify this ban by using
studies that focused on single-use, not multiple-use,
buildings. City of Los Angeles v. Alameda Books, Inc., 535
U.S. 425 (2002).
156
7. Alameda Books is interesting for the candor that Justice
Kennedy uses to describe the secondary effects doctrine.
Writing separately (in an opinion that concurred in the
judgment), Kennedy asserted that “[this ordinance] is
content-based and we should call [it] so,” adding that
Renton’s effort to describe such ordinances as content-
neutral “was something of a fiction.” 535 U.S. at 448.
157
establishments—NOT any broad power to regulate
public morality—justified the application of its public
indecency statute to the dancers in the Kitty Kat
Lounge. 501 U.S. at 582.
158
preamble invoked the secondary effects
doctrine by citing “a recent increase in nude
live entertainment within [our] City [that]
adversely impacts the … public health, safety,
and welfare by providing an atmosphere
conducive to violence, sexual harassment,
public intoxication, prostitution, the spread of
sexually transmitted diseases, and other
deleterious effects.” 529 U.S. at 290.
159
b. Cable TV: United States v. Playboy Entertainment
Group, Inc., 529 U.S. 803 (2000) (using strict
scrutiny to strike down a federal statute banning
“signal bleed” of sexual images because such images
can be fully blocked upon request by individual cable
subscribers); id. at 804 (“There is a key difference
between cable television and the broadcasting
media, which is the point on which this case turns:
Cable systems have the capacity to block unwanted
channels on a household-by-household basis.”).
* * *
IV(G).
160
HATE SPEECH
161
9. Just because the governmental power we recognize here is
susceptible to abuse is no reason for withholding it from
Illinois.
1. Is Beauharnais dead?
162
4. Or, even if it doesn’t fit neatly into the narrow definition
of fighting words, why can’t hate speech form a new
category of “low-level” expression, consistent with the
language in Chaplinsky, 315 U.S. at 572 (“no essential
part of any exposition of ideas,” and of only “slight social
value as a step to truth”)?
1. The Justifications:
2. The Implications:
163
(2) Professor Mari Matsuda concedes as much, but
asserts nevertheless that racist speech is so
harmful, so dangerous, so historically
untenable that we may safely treat it as sui
generis—and thus properly outside the realm of
protected discourse. Matsuda, Public Response
to Racist Speech: Considering the Victim’s
Story, 87 MICH. L. REV. 2320 (1989).
164
building into it either a balancing test or a
categorical ban on racist speech. But reliance on the
Equal Protection Clause raises questions about what
other speech would be included; e.g., sexist speech,
homophobic speech, etc.
D. By the mid 1990s, when the smoke had cleared, the battle to
vest government with greater power to punish hate speech—
and to punish pornography as a species of hate speech—had
been lost.
2. What happened?
165
a. Courts refused to expand the fighting words doctrine
and refused to create new categories of unprotected
expression to which hate speech and pornography
might have been relegated.
166
since, in both instances, the government was singling out
particular bigoted viewpoints for special punishment.
167
“the great censor and director of which thoughts are good
for us.” Id. at 330.
* * *
168
categories of speech that are unworthy of full First
Amendment protection because they are (315 U.S. at
572):
169
d. Even the advocacy of imminent lawless action (“Let’s
blow up the R.I.T.A. Office right now!”), which might
be regarded as an idea or opinion, is best regarded
as akin to fighting words:
170
speech and will add them only in accordance with
long-standing historical tradition.
171
3. The key question raised by the movement for punishing
hate speech is this:
172
8. In other words, these were the very conditions that
spawned the Holmes/Brandeis approach to free speech—
the approach that still prevails today.
11. Surely we can draw a line between hateful speech and the
viewpoints I’ve just listed.
* * *
V.
173
TIME, PLACE, AND MANNER RESTRICTIONS:
LIMITATIONS ON THE MEANS OF
COMMUNICATION
AND THE PROBLEM OF CONTENT-NEUTRALITY
DOCTRINAL INTRODUCTION
174
b. the standards for gauging content neutrality.
175
(3) What is the difference between CONTENT
discrimina-tion and VIEWPOINT
discrimination? A CONTENT-based restriction
singles out a particular topic or subject for
regulation. A VIEWPOINT-based restriction
ventures within a given topic or subject,
singling out a particular idea or opinion for
disfavored treatment.
176
(8) Matal v. Tam, 137 S. Ct. 1744 (2017) (striking
down, as viewpoint based, the Lanham Act’s
ban on registering trademarks that “disparage”
any “person[], living or dead”) (ruling in favor
of trademark registration for “The Slants,” an
Asian-American rock band); Iancu v. Brunetti,
139 S. Ct. 2294 (2019) (striking down, as
viewpoint based, the Lanham Act’s ban on
registering any “immoral[] or scandalous”
trademarks) (ruling in favor of trademark
registration for “FUCT” as the brand name of a
clothing line); id. at 2300 (by prohibiting the
registration of “scandalous” trademarks, the
Lanham Act “allows registration of marks when
their messages accord with, but not when their
messages defy, society’s sense of decency and
propriety”); id. at 2301 (“[A] law disfavoring
‘ideas that offend’ discriminates based on
viewpoint, in violation of the First
Amendment.”).
177
based upon one particular sentence in
Ward: “[T]he requirement of narrow
tailoring is satisfied ‘so long as
the...regulation promotes a substantial
government interest that would be
achieved less effectively absent the
regulation.’” 491 U.S. at 799 (quoting
United States v. Albertini, 472 U.S. 675,
689 (1985)).
178
ordinance would violate the narrow
tailoring requirement by banning parades
anywhere within the city’s central
business district on all workdays—because
it would allow parades only when the
downtown streets are bereft of onlookers.
Sixteenth of September Planning
Committee, Inc. v. City and County of
Denver, 474 F. Supp. 1333 (D. Colo.
1979).
179
tailoring requirement prevents the
government from too readily sacrificing
speech for efficiency,” id. at 2534-35
(internal quotation marks and citations
omitted).
180
the govern-ment to impose a total ban on
stepping into the street and approaching
the occupants of motor vehicles stopped
at traffic lights to solicit money or sell
newspapers? The pre-McCullen decision
upholds the ordinance with no hesitation;
the parties actually stipulated that the law
was narrowly tailored. The Contributor v.
City of Brentwood, 726 F.3d 861 (6th Cir.
2013). The post-McCullen decision strikes
the law down for lack of narrow tailoring.
Reynolds v. Middleton, 779 F.3d 222 (4th
Cir. 2015).
181
its asserted interest without burdening
substan-tially more speech than
necessary).
182
her message. Million Youth March, Inc. v.
Safir, 18 F. Supp. 2d 334, 347-48 (S.D.N.Y.
1998); accord Nationalist Movement v.
City of Boston, 12 F. Supp. 2d 182, 191-93
(D. Mass. 1998).
183
white neighborhood, its previous foray
there having been curtailed when
bystanders pelted the procession with
rocks, bricks, and explosive devices, city
officials violated the First Amendment in
denying the organizers a permit for a
second march through the same neighbor-
hood, proposing instead an alternate
route through an all-black neighborhood);
id. at 673-74 (since the whole point of
plaintiffs’ march was to publicize and
protest a pattern of violence against
blacks attempting to reside in or travel
through the specified neighborhood, the
city’s proposal for an alternate route—
taking plaintiffs away from that
neighborhood and away from their
intended audience—was constitutionally
inadequate as an alternative channel of
communication).
184
c. Mosley does not exemplify the only way that a speech
restriction can violate the content neutrality
requirement. Even if the regulation does not, as in
Mosley, expressly discriminate on the basis of
subject matter, it can run afoul of the content
neutrality requirement if the circumstances
surrounding its enactment reveal a governmental
intent to favor or punish particular messages. Town
of Gilbert, 135 S. Ct. at 2227.
185
neutral justification, the court held that the
regulation could not be deemed content based.
186
b. Second, where the government serves as a content-
conscious gatekeeper, selectively blocking access to
a forum based on the speaker’s intended message—
as, for example, in Mahoney v. Babbitt, 105 F.3d
1452 (D.C. Cir. 1997), where the National Park
Service sought to prevent anti-abortion protesters
from displaying banners along the route of President
Clinton’s inaugural parade.
187
c. barring early-morning or late-evening
demonstrations; and
188
most demonstrations and parades during the Vietnam era
were conducted by those opposing the war.
*****
V(A).
GENERAL PRINCIPLES
189
hesitate to peer behind the asserted governmental
justifica-tion, where it found an illegitimate
regulatory purpose, id. at 147: “[Because] the
dangers of distribution can so easily be controlled by
traditional legal methods, [the challenged
ordinance] can serve no purpose but that forbidden
by the Constitution, the naked restriction of the
dissemination of ideas.”
190
(2) And Brennan was unwilling to uphold such a
restriction based on the flimsy record that San
Diego had established in support of its twin
justifications: traffic safety and aesthetics.
191
b. The court observed: “Just like the political signage
banned from residential property in City of Ladue,
handheld signs are inexpensive, they are easy to
create and customize, and they can reach a wide
variety of listeners. ... The rich tradition of political
lawn signs perhaps is surpassed only by America’s
history of marches and rallies dotted with handheld
signs and placards of every imaginable description
and covering every conceivable political message.”
38 F.4th at 951.
192
c. The notion, best expressed in Kovacs, that
government has a freer hand in restricting the time,
place, and manner of expression than its content.
*****
V(B).
SPEECH ON PUBLIC PROPERTY:
THE PUBLIC FORUM
*****
DOCTRINAL INTRODUCTION
193
c. Traditional public forums are places that “by long
tradition or by government fiat have been devoted to
assembly and debate.” Perry Education Association
v. Perry Local Educators’ Association, 460 U.S. 37,
45 (1983). They are largely confined to public
squares, streets, parks, and sidewalks.
194
restrictions. To survive judicial review, such
restrictions must satisfy intermediate scrutiny—they
must be “‘justified without reference to the content
of the regulated speech,’” must be “‘narrowly
tailored to serve a significant government interest,’”
and must “‘leave open ample alternative channels
for communicati[ng] the information.’” Ward v. Rock
Against Racism, 491 U.S. 781, 791 (1989) (quoting
Clark v. Community for Creative Non-Violence, 468
U.S. 288, 293 (1984)).
195
reasonableness test. Perry, 460 U.S. at 46. In a non-
public forum, it is permissible for the government to
prohibit all protest activities. Thus, the First
Amendment afforded no defense to anti-war
protesters who occupied a nonpublic forum (a
corridor in a federal office building) to read aloud
the names of fallen soldiers. United States v. Sroka,
307 F. Supp. 400 (E.D. Wis. 1969).
196
public discourse.” Krishna Conscious-ness, 505 U.S.
at 680 (citations and internal quotation marks
omitted). Absent these intentional, affirmative steps
by the government, the property in question will be
deemed a nonpublic forum.
197
r. Here is an important point to remember about
designated and limited public forums. After opening
such a forum, there is no requirement that the
government keep it open indefinitely. Perry, 460 U.S.
at 45-46 & n.7. But there is very little case law
governing the closure of a designated or limited
public forum. It appears that the government may
close such a forum whenever it wants to, with no
offense to the First Amendment, and its motive for
closing the forum is irrelevant. Sons of Confederate
Veterans v. City of Lexington, 722 F.3d 224, 231-32
(4th Cir. 2013). When a designated or limited public
forum is closed, it reverts back to the status of a
nonpublic forum. Id. at 231.
198
Pageant is a nonpublic forum because the Park
Service has never treated it as “a forum for all
expression on the subject of Christmas or for
all displays on that subject,” and because the
Park Service “carefully selects only a few
displays and does not routinely accept displays
from those who tender them”); id. at 533
(holding that in a nonpublic forum, the
government may deny access to any prospective
speaker, so long as its decision is “reasonable
and viewpoint neutral”). The court here
narrowly defined the “relevant forum” as the
Pageant (i.e., the event), not the Ellipse (i.e.,
the public park on which the event was staged)
—and concluded that, since the Pageant was a
nonpublic forum, the Park Service was free to
select only “traditional” Christmas displays for
inclusion in the event. Since the Ellipse is
unquestionably a traditional public forum,
identifying the Pageant as the “relevant forum”
enabled the court to conclude that a public
forum had been converted into a nonpublic
forum.
199
nonpublic-forum island in the traditional-
public-forum sea of the statehouse grounds:
“To allow the government to limit traditional
public forum property and thereby create
within it a nonpublic forum would destroy the
entire concept of a public forum.”).
*****
V(B)(1).
THE PUBLIC FORUM:
STREETS AND PARKS
c. But all that changed with Hague v. CIO, 307 U.S. 496
(1939).
200
(2) police harassment of union picketers;
201
i. Schneider, decided only eight months after Hague,
made clear the Court’s commitment to opening
public forums for speech purposes, even over
asserted governmental interests in preventing
littering or public inconvenience.
202
prohibited only “focused” picketing conducted
solely in front of a single, targeted home.
203
struck down, for lack of narrow tailoring, a
Massachusetts statute that imposed a 35-foot buffer
zone at abortion clinics.
204
permissible if it is directly linked to, and serves to
defray, the administrative expenses incurred by the
government in regulating the speaker’s expressive
activity. Kevin Francis O’Neill, Disentangling the
Law of Public Protest, 45 LOYOLA L. REV. 411, 467-68
(1999).
205
*****
V(B)(2).
THE PUBLIC FORUM:
OTHER PUBLICLY OWNED PROPERTY
206
suggests, of the need for access to a
unique forum.
207
look not only to the property’s free speech
“compatibility,” but also to the government’s “policy
and practice” vis-à-vis the property. Id. at 802-03.
208
alternative channels of communication
immediately outside the fairgrounds (satisfying
Prong #3).
209
individuals engaged in postal business.” The case is
significant for three features:
210
Moreover, they can’t be deemed public forums
because their principal purpose is not to
promote the free exchange of ideas. Thus,
Rehnquist substantially narrows the concept of
the traditional public forum by transforming
Hague’s DESCRIPTIONS of streets and parks
into PREREQUISITES that must be satisfied in
order to qualify for traditional public forum
status.
211
that serves as the crossroads of the
community, not to promote hair-
splitting distinctions about various
sorts of public spaces.
212
from her Facebook page after he posted a comment
on her page alleging corruption in the county
government. As chair of the county board of
supervisors, Ms. Randall created what she called
“the Chair’s Facebook Page,” where she welcomed
comments from constituents: “I really want to hear
from ANY [county] citizen on ANY issue[], request,
criticism, complement[,] or just your thoughts.” Id.
at 673 (emphasis in original). The Fourth Circuit
held that “the interactive component of the Chair’s
Facebook Page constituted a public forum, and
Randall engaged in unconstitutional viewpoint
discrimination when she banned [the offending
constituent] from that forum.” Id. at 688.
Unfortunately, the court did not decide whether the
Chair’s Facebook Page constituted a traditional,
designated, or limited public forum—because the
viewpoint discrimination that occurred here is
prohibited in all forums. Id. at 687.
213
governance and executive outreach.” Id. at 235-
36.
214
selectively blocking a liberal advocacy group from
their respective Twitter pages).
215
Amendment restrains only governmental restrictions
on speech.
*****
V(B)(3).
THE PUBLIC FORUM:
UNEQUAL ACCESS AND THE
PROBLEM OF CONTENT NEUTRALITY
216
d. When directed at speech in a traditional public
forum, such content-conscious gate-keeping will be
analyzed under strict scrutiny—and, 99 percent of
the time, will be deemed to violate the First
Amendment.
217
f. In restricting access to NON-public forums, only
viewpoint-based discrimination is forbidden. Perry,
460 U.S. at 46.
218
affords ready access for LABOR speech
(Mosley)?
219
discrimination in denying access to a
“nonpublic” forum).
220
displays as SPONSORED BY, ERECTED BY the
government.
221
(3) Rejecting an Establishment Clause basis for
permitting or requiring the government to
discriminate against religious expression in
public forums.
222
viewpoints. Religion may be a vast area of
inquiry, but it also provides, as it did here, a
specific premise, a perspective, a standpoint
from which a variety of subjects may be
discussed and considered. The prohibited
perspective, not the subject matter, resulted in
the [University’s denial of the subsidy].”)
(emphasis added)).
223
(1) Upholding city’s refusal to accept any political
advertising for placement in or upon the city’s
rapid transit vehicles. Holding that advertising
spaces in or upon the city’s transit vehicles do
NOT constitute a public forum, the Court rules
that the city’s decision to preclude all political
advertising—by advancing the reasonable
governmental objectives of minimizing
“chances of abuse, the appearance of
favoritism, and the risk of imposing upon a
captive audience,” id. at 304—did not offend
the First Amendment.
224
government will not be free to prefer some
political ads over others. See, e.g., American
Freedom Defense Initiative v. SMART, 698 F.3d
885 (6th Cir. 2012) (state-run transit authority
did not violate the First Amendment when it
rejected plaintiff’s effort to place an anti-
Muslim advertisement on the sides of the
authority’s buses; the authority’s consistent
policy of refusing all political and ideological
ads meant that the advertising spaces on its
buses were a NON-public forum as in Lehman,
and not a designated public forum); New York
Magazine v. Metro-politan Transportation
Authority, 136 F.3d 123 (2d Cir. 1998) (where
transit authority had accepted not only
commercial but also political advertising on its
buses, the advertising space constituted a
DESIGNATED public forum—thus, transit
authority violated First Amend-ment in
rejecting an ad critical of the mayor); White
Coat Waste Project v. Greater Richmond
Transit Co., 35 F.4th 179, 196-203 (4th Cir.
2022) (transit authority, invoking its ban on all
“political” advertising on its buses, rejected an
ad that opposed taxpayer-funded animal
experimenta-tion; court holds that the transit
authority’s ban failed to satisfy the
reasonableness requirement for speech
restrictions in a nonpublic forum, because the
ban was enforced in a confusing and
inconsistent manner—sometimes narrowly
confined to criticism of govern-ment, other
times broad enough to bar public advocacy
statements calling for a boycott of McDonald’s
or the National Football League; in so holding,
the court invokes Minnesota Voters Alliance v.
Mansky, 138 S. Ct. 1876 (2018) for the
proposition that, “to be reasonable, nonpublic-
forum speech restrictions must be ‘capable of
reasoned application,’” 35 F.4th at 199
(quoting Mansky, 138 S. Ct. at 1892)).
225
constituted a NON-public forum, so that granting
access to exclusive bargaining representative of
teachers union (and denying access to rival union)
did not violate the rival union’s First Amendment
rights.
226
restrictions “can be based on subject matter
and speaker identity so long as the distinctions
drawn are reasonable in light of the purpose
served by the forum and are viewpoint neutral.”
473 U.S. at 806.
227
speech activities taking place on the
premises; instead, such a forum is created
by an intentional and affirmative
dedication of the property by the
government for certain expressive
purposes. Id. at 730.
228
views but, instead, because “the voters lacked
interest in his candidacy,” the station did not
violate the First Amendment by excluding him
from the debate. Id. at 683.
229
“By recognizing the distinction [between
‘general’ and ‘selective’ access], we encourage
the government to open its property to some
expressive activity in cases where, if faced with
an all-or-nothing choice, it might not open the
property at all. That this distinction turns on
governmental intent does not render it
unprotective of speech. Rather, it reflects the
reality that, with the exception of traditional
public fora, the government retains the choice
of whether to designate its property as a forum
for specified classes of speakers.”
230
CLS argued that under this requirement it would be
forced to admit avowed atheists and “unrepentant
homosexual[s]” into its organization. Id. at 2980.
But student organizations are free to exist without
RSO status; RSOs merely receive certain benefits and
subsidies that are not given to student groups that
discriminate in conferring membership. When the
University refused to grant RSO status to CLS, citing
CLS’s intention to discriminate on the basis of
religion and sexual orientation, CLS filed suit,
alleging that its First Amend-ment rights had been
violated. In a 5-4 decision, the Supreme Court ruled
against CLS, holding that RSO status is a “limited”
public forum, and that the University’s restrictions
on access to that forum were reasonable and
viewpoint neutral.
*****
V(B)(4).
GOVERNMENT SPEECH
231
a. In Summum, Justice Alito framed the issue as
follows: “This case presents the question whether
the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment
entitles a private group to insist that a municipality
permit it to place a permanent monument in a city
park in which other donated monuments were
previously erected. The Court of Appeals held that
the municipality was required to accept the
monument because a public park is a traditional
public forum.” Id. at 1129.
232
f. When it comes to privately funded or donated
monuments, governmental entities are selective, id.
at 1133; they exercise considerable care in choosing
such monuments because the public parks they
adorn “play an important role in defining the
identity that a city projects to its residents and to
the outside world,” id. at 1133-34.
233
6. Matal v. Tam, 137 S. Ct. 1744 (2017), is not really a
government speech case; it’s a viewpoint discrimination
case. But it did slam the door on expanding the
government speech doctrine to encompass federal
trademark registration. So Matal is significant for
establishing some LIMITS on the government speech
doctrine.
234
dangerous misuse. If private speech could be
passed off as government speech by simply
affixing a government seal of approval,
government could silence or muffle the
expression of disfavored viewpoints. For this
reason, we must exercise great caution before
extending our government-speech precedents.”
Id. at 1758.
(4) Then Alito has some fun with the idea that the
government is speaking here: “[I]f trademarks
represent government speech, what does the
Government have in mind when it advises
Americans to ‘make.believe’ (Sony), ‘Think
different’ (Apple), ‘Just do it’ (Nike), or ‘Have it
your way’ (Burger King)? Was the Government
warning about a coming disaster when it
registered the mark ‘EndTime Ministries’?” Id.
at 1759.
235
plates were government speech. But in Walker,
he was writing in DISSENT—and that raises the
question whether Matal and Walker can be
reconciled.
c. FACTS:
236
(3) But the City does not always use the third
flagpole to fly its own flag. Upon request and
after approval, the City allows private parties to
stage a “flag-raising event” with a flag of their
own choosing.
237
(1) Here is Alito’s key point: IN A GOVERNMENT
SPEECH CASE, THE ESSENTIAL QUESTION IS
WHETHER THE GOVERNMENT IS SPEAKING
INSTEAD OF REGULATING PRIVATE
EXPRESSION. Any test that strays from this
focus is a distraction and a disservice.
238
(5) Here is the three-factor test advanced by
Justice Breyer in his majority opinion. To
determine whether it is confronted with
government speech, a court must consider:
“the history of the expression at issue; the
public’s likely perception as to who (the
government or a private person) is speaking;
and the extent to which the government has
actively shaped or controlled the expression.”
Id. at 1589-90.
239
*****
V(B)(5).
GOVERNMENT-FUNDED SPEECH
1. Government-Funded Expression
240
same time funding an alternative program
which seeks to deal with the problem in
another way”).
241
works by two controversial artists—the
homoerotic photographs of Robert Mapple-
thorpe and the “Piss Christ” of Andres Serrano
—had been federally subsidized.
242
American sensibilities. Id. at 606-07 (Souter, J.,
dissenting).
243
arguments against federal provisions and
Supremacy Clause argu-ments against state
provisions. 531 U.S. at 544.
244
(2) “The relevant distinction that has emerged
from our cases,” wrote Chief Justice Roberts,
“is between conditions that define the limits of
the government spending program—those that
specify the activities Congress wants to
subsidize—and conditions that seek to leverage
funding to regulate speech outside the
contours of the program itself.” 133 S. Ct. at
2328.
245
(8) The Chief Justice concluded: “The Policy
Requirement compels as a condition of federal
funding the affirma-tion of a belief that by its
nature cannot be confined within the scope of
the Government program. In so doing, it
violates the First Amendment and cannot be
sustained.” Id. at 2332.
*****
V(C).
SYMBOLIC CONDUCT
C. Symbolic Conduct
246
with a view toward influencing others to adopt his
anti-draft, anti-war beliefs.
247
(1) if it is within the constitutional power of the
government;
248
intent of its framers was purely and simply to put a
stop to this particular form of antiwar protest, which
they deemed extraordinarily contemptible and
vicious—even treasonous—at a time when American
troops were engaged in combat. … On the basis of
this legislative history, it is not open to doubt that
the attitude of defiance manifested in the draft-card
burnings was what represented the threat seen by
Congress, and that the infuriating offensiveness of
this mode of dissent was what drove Congress to
prohibit it.”
249
that is in reality a facade for viewpoint-based
discrimination.”
250
punish the wearing of an American military uniform
in a theatrical production critical of the war in
Vietnam).
251
distinguished O’Brien on the grounds that THIS
statute was DIRECTLY related to expression).
* * *
V(D).
252
POLITICAL SOLICITATION,
CONTRIBUTION, AND EXPENDITURE
253
b. Congress cannot bar corporations from making
them, even if the corporation is spending the money
to disseminate a partisan political message; and
* * *
VI.
ADDITIONAL PROBLEMS
A. The Speech Rights of Students
254
of prisoners and military personnel because those topics
are virtually ignored in your casebook, STONE SEIDMAN.
But I have given you the governing law on those topics in
my Speech Clause Overview.
2. Schools:
255
the realm of off-campus Internet
communications. Mahanoy Area School District
v. B.L., 141 S. Ct. 2038, 2047-48 (2021). (I
discuss Mahanoy below, in the section on OFF-
campus expression by students.)
256
the speech restriction will be upheld if it is
“reasonably related to legitimate pedagogical
concerns.” Hazelwood School District v.
Kuhlmeier, 484 U.S. 260, 272-73 (1988)
(upholding a high school principal’s decision to
remove two articles from the student news-
paper—a story describing three students’
experiences with pregnancy, and a story
discussing the impact of divorce on students at
the school). NOTE: This category is limited to
student speech that appears in a publication or
setting that may be reasonably perceived to
bear the school’s stamp of approval.
257
expressed her frustration on Snapchat:
“Fuck school fuck softball fuck cheer fuck
everything.” Id. at 2043. These words
were accompanied by a photo of B.L. with
her middle finger raised.
258
B.L.’s punishment violated the First
Amendment.
259
Instead of propounding a comprehensive First
Amend-ment rule to govern all regulatory
restrictions on off-campus speech, Justice
Breyer identified three basic principles to be
applied in such cases. Id. at 2046. And these
principles all counsel AGAINST giving school
administrators the same “leeway” they enjoy
when regulating ON-campus speech. Id. at
2046. Here are the three principles:
260
(a) In his concurring opinion, Justice Alito
deftly summarized the key points to be
gleaned from Justice Breyer’s decision.
261
location outside the school. She did not
identify the school in her posts or target
any member of the school com-munity
with vulgar or abusive language. B.L. also
transmitted her speech through a
personal cellphone, to an audience
consisting of her private circle of
Snapchat friends. These features of her
speech, while risking transmission to the
school itself, nonetheless...diminish the
school’s interest in punishing B.L.’s
utterance.” Id. at 2047.
262
within the classroom, then within the
bounds of a school-sponsored
extracurricular activity”? Id. at 2047.
Justice Breyer replied that the record was
bereft of any facts even approaching
Tinker’s substantial disruption standard:
“Rather, the record shows that discussion
of the matter took, at most, 5 to 10
minutes of an Algebra class ‘for just a
couple of days’ and that some members of
the cheerleading team were ‘upset’ about
the content of B.L.’s Snapchats. But when
one of B.L.’s coaches was asked directly if
she had ‘any reason to think that this
particular incident would disrupt class or
school activities other than the fact that
kids kept asking ... about it,’ she
responded simply, ‘No.’ ... The alleged
disturbance here does not meet Tinker’s
demanding standard.” Id. at 2047-48
(citations omitted).
263
cheerleading coach, and put out
‘negativity ... that could impact students
in the school.’ The freedom of students to
speak off-campus would not be worth
much if it gave way in the face of such
relatively minor complaints.” Id. at 2058
(Alito, J., concurring) (footnotes omitted).
264
expression by public school students. Left undisturbed are a number
of influential LOWER COURT decisions that deal with this question.
These lower court cases may be grouped into three distinct
categories, based on the content of what the student said: (1) threats
of violence directed at the school community; (2) hurtful remarks or
bullying directed at other students at the school; and (3) criticism or
mockery directed at teachers or administrators at the school. (In his
Mahanoy concurrence, Justice Alito singled out these categories
while reviewing the lower court decisions. Id. at 2056-57.) The lower
courts themselves (except for the Chen decision discussed
immediately above) have not yet recognized these categories; but in
Mahanoy’s wake, they may begin to do so—particularly because
Justice Breyer’s majority opinion identified threats and bullying as
two situations in which schools may have a legitimate regulatory
interest in OFF-campus speech. Id. at 2045. Here, then, is my own
summary of some key lower court decisions, divided into the three
categories set forth above.
(1) THREATS
Bell v. Itawamba County School Board, 799 F.3d 379 (5th Cir. 2015)
(en banc) (plaintiff high school student wrote and performed a rap
music video bitterly attacking two coaches at the school, accusing
them of improper sexual contact with female students; the song is
pervasively profane, accusing both coaches of “fucking with” the
students, and accusing one coach of being a “dirty ass nigga” who
salivates while “looking down girls’ shirts”; he warns the coaches
that he’s going to shoot them—“betta watch your back ... going to
get a pistol down your mouth”; the student posted his video on both
Facebook and YouTube, admitting that his intended audience was
the entire school community); id. at 396 (holding that “Tinker
governs our analysis ... when a student intentionally directs at the
school community speech reasonably understood by school officials
to threaten, harass, and intimidate a teacher, even when such speech
originated, and was disseminated, off-campus without the use of
school resources.”); id. at 400 (concluding that the threatening
nature of plaintiff’s video gave the school board a reasonable basis
to forecast a substantial disruption).
265
VanderMolen,” that singled out the student’s English teacher; even
though a police investigator and a school psychologist both
concluded that the communication was intended as a joke, and even
though it took two or three weeks before anyone at school even
learned about it, Mr. VanderMolen asked and was allowed to stop
teaching the student’s class; a hearing officer concluded that even
though the communication took place outside of school, it disrupted
school operations by requiring special attention from school
officials, who had to replace the threatened teacher and interview
pupils during class time); id. at 39-40 (in finding the requisite nexus
between the school and the student’s expression, the Second Circuit
adopted a relaxed standard, requiring only that it must have been
reasonably foreseeable that the student’s out-of-school
communication would come to the attention of school authorities
and foreseeably create a risk of substantial disruption).
(2) BULLYING
266
campus. Third, and most surprising to me, the court finds a lack of
disruption, even on a factual record that features an utterly
distraught victim and extensive efforts by school officials to deal
with the on-campus impact of plaintiff’s video.
J.S. v. Blue Mountain School District, 650 F.3d 915 (3d Cir. 2011)
(en banc) (holding that school district violated eighth grader’s First
Amendment rights when it suspended her for creating a MySpace
parody profile of her principal—in which the principal describes
himself as a “hairy, expressionless, sex addict” with a small penis
whose interests include “fucking in my office” and “hitting on
students and their parents”—where the student created the parody
on a weekend on her home computer, and where her parody neither
caused a substantial disruption in school nor gave school officials a
reasonable basis to forecast such a disruption). This en banc
decision by the Third Circuit is significant in three respects. First, it
stresses that school officials have no authority to punish students for
off-campus use of profane language; punishment may be imposed
only for student speech that creates a substantial on-campus
disruption. Id. at 932-33. Second, off-campus speech is not
converted into on-campus speech merely because another student,
obeying a direct request from the principal, prints out a hard copy of
the speech and brings it to school. Id. at 933. Third, and perhaps
most important, the court offers extended guidance on the
circumstances that must exist before school officials may punish a
student based on their reasonable forecast of disruption. Id. at 928-
31. Contrasting the emotional turmoil of the Vietnam protest in
Tinker with the juvenile prank at issue here, and observing that the
Tinker majority found no facts in the record justifying a disruption
forecast in that case, the Third Circuit concluded that no basis for
such a forecast existed here. Citing facts in the record to support
this conclusion, the Third Circuit observed that the student created
the profile as a joke; she took steps to make it “private” so that
access was limited to her friends; and the profile was so sophomoric
and nonsensical that nobody could, or did, take it seriously.
Layshock v. Hermitage School District, 650 F.3d 205 (3d Cir. 2011)
(en banc) (holding that school district violated high school student’s
First Amendment rights when it suspended him for creating a
MySpace parody profile of his high school principal—in which the
principal describes himself as a “big steroid freak” who recently
stole a “big keg,” smoked a “big blunt,” and was “too drunk to
remember” his birthday—where the student created the parody at
267
his grandmother’s house using his grandmother’s computer during
non-school hours, and where the district court found that the parody
did not produce a substantial disruption at school). The Third
Circuit, sitting en banc, here affirms the district court’s decision,
which distinguished Morse and Bethel because “[Morse] does not
permit school officials unfettered latitude to censor student speech
under the rubric of ‘interference with the educational mission,’” and
Bethel does not apply to off-campus speech. 496 F. Supp. 2d 587,
599-600 (W.D. Pa. 2007). The primary significance of the Third
Circuit’s decision is its refusal to find a sufficient nexus between off-
campus Internet speech and the school environment—a nexus that
would allow school officials to punish the speech in question—where
the student obtained a photograph of the principal by copying it
from the school’s website and where, on at least one occasion, the
student displayed his parody on campus using a school computer.
J.S. v. Bethlehem Area School District, 807 A.2d 847 (Pa. 2002)
(upholding the expulsion of an eighth-grade student based on the
content of his Internet homepage) (with bitter, sophomoric humor,
the student’s homepage featured a multi-media attack on his algebra
teacher and the principal of his school; using text, animation,
graphics, and sound clips, the website ridiculed the principal as
sexually promiscuous, and tarred the algebra teacher as a “bitch”
and a tyrant; it mockingly depicted her as a witch and as Hitler,
offered satirical reasons why she should “die,” and repeated 136
times the statement, “Fuck you, Mrs. Fulmer”); id. at 865 (the
court’s decision is significant for holding that the student’s website,
which was created at home, became “on-campus” speech for First
Amendment purposes when he accessed it at school and showed it to
a classmate).
ANALYSIS
These Internet speech cases pose the same difficult question that
Mahanoy sought to address: Under what circumstances can school
officials punish a student for her OFF-CAMPUS expression, posted
on the Internet with her own cell phone or computer? The answer
seems to hinge upon (1) whether the off-campus speech creates a
powerful ON-CAMPUS impact, and (2) whether the student speaker
WANTED to reach the whole school community, not merely a small
circle of friends.
268
Wisniewski, respectively). But this difference might be explained by
the stark differences between what the students SAID in these cases.
The Third Circuit cases merely involved student MOCKERY of school
officials, while Bell and Wisniewski both involved student THREATS
to kill or injure school officials. In a post-Columbine world in which
students have massacred their classmates and teachers, it is
understandable why a judge might be more sensitive to threats of
violence, showing greater deference to school administrators in their
handling of such threats.
* * *
269
e. In Pickering, a public schoolteacher had been fired
for a letter he’d published in a local newspaper
criticizing the school board’s spending of tax
revenues and questioning its purported need for new
revenues.
270
her contempt for the policies of President Ronald
Reagan.
271
misrepresentations, amounting to perjury by the
police officer who testified. Ceballos relayed his
findings to his supervisors in a “disposition
memorandum” of the sort normally used for these
investigations. In that memorandum, he
recommended that the prosecutor’s office should
dismiss the criminal charges because of the police
officer’s misrepresentations. Ceballos claimed that
his super-visors retaliated against him for his
statements in the memorandum, demoting him,
denying him promotion, and reassigning him to a
different office and different job duties. The
Supreme Court ruled against Ceballos, holding that
the statements contained in his memorandum were
job-duty speech, not citizen speech.
272
In Lane, a public employee at a community
college was fired by the college president after
testifying truthfully in court about fraudulent
conduct by a former colleague at the college.
The Supreme Court ruled that Garcetti did not
bar the employee’s speech retaliation claim,
holding that the First Amendment protects a
public employee who provides truthful sworn
testimony, compelled by subpoena, outside the
scope of his ordinary job duties. It was
undisputed that plaintiff’s ordinary job duties
did not include testifying in court proceedings.
273
never form the basis for a First
Amendment retaliation claim. Such a
rule would place public em-ployees
who witness corruption in an im-
possible position, torn between the
obliga-tion to testify truthfully and
the desire to avoid retaliation and
keep their jobs.”
274
Amendment purposes, and the Constitution does not
insulate their communications from employer
discipline.” 547 U.S. at 421.
275
624 (1943), where the Supreme Court struck down a
mandatory flag salute and pledge of allegiance law
directed at all children within the West Virginia public
schools.
276
First Amendment right to avoid becoming the
courier for such message.” Id. at 715.
277
b. Compelling the inclusion of this group effectively
altered the expressive content of the organizers’
parade—a type of com-pelled speech that violates the
First Amendment.
278
heavily dependent on federal funding that the Solomon
Amendment effectively operated as a mechanism for
compelled speech. Chief Justice Roberts, writing for the
Court, observed that the Solomon Amendment does not
compel the communication of any specific content,
making it distinguishable from compelled speech cases
like Barnette and Wooley.
279
cake to celebrate a same-sex marriage—that
conveyed a message he personally rejected.
280
(2) Analyzing the COMPELLED Speech Issue.
Justice Thomas argued that enforcing the anti-
discrimination law against the baker in this
case compelled him to convey a message that
he did not wish to convey: “Here ... Colorado
would not be punishing [the baker] if he
refused to create any custom wedding cakes; it
is punishing him because he refuses to create
custom wedding cakes that express approval of
same-sex marriage.” Id. at 1746 (Thomas, J.,
concurring in part and concurring in the
judgment) (emphasis added).
281
(5) “She will not produce content that ‘contradicts
biblical truth’ regardless of who orders it.”
282
facilities (that provide women with assistance
involving pregnancy or family planning) to tell those
women where they might obtain help, including
financial help, with comprehensive family planning
services, prenatal care, and abortion.” 138 S. Ct. at
2379 (Breyer, J., dissenting).
283
govern our disposition of this case.” Id. at 2383
(Breyer, J., dissenting).
284
explaining medical assistance for childbirth,
potential child support, and adoption services.
138 S. Ct. at 2384 (Breyer, J., dissent-ing).
285
riders”) paying for the union’s collective bargaining
representation; but they did not have to pay for, and the
union would have to raise funds separately to support,
political activities and endorsements engaged in by the
union. [Janus holds that non-union public employees
cannot be compelled to pay the union anything, even for
collective bargaining representation.]
286
freedom of association—since revealing a member’s
identity exposes him to the threat of reprisal. 357
U.S. at 462.
287
c. “Even the Federalist Papers, written in favor of the
adoption of our Constitution, were published under
fictitious names.” Id. at 65.
288
specifically, the identity of the donor and the dollar
amount conveyed.
289
c. In Brown, the Socialist Workers Party balked at
complying with an Ohio campaign finance law that
required every candidate for political office to
identify each contributor and each recipient of a
disbursement of campaign funds. Id. at 89-90.
290
compelled disclosures will subject those identified to
“threats, harassment, or reprisals.” Id. at 88. And
this protec-tion from compelled disclosure applies
not only to campaign contributors but also to the
recipients of campaign disburse-ments. Id. at 98.
291
political speech, we apply ‘exacting’ scrutiny, and we
uphold the restriction only if it is narrowly tailored to
serve an overriding state interest.” McIntyre v. Ohio
Elections Commission, 514 U.S. 334, 347 (1995)
(emphasis added). The current Court, at least, regards
“exacting” scrutiny as falling short of strict scrutiny. This
is apparent from Justice Thomas’s dissent in Doe v. Reed,
where he argued that the Court should have applied full-
blown strict scrutiny, not the lesser standard it employed,
130 S. Ct. at 2839 (Thomas, J., dissenting), and from the
Chief Justice’s majority opinion, where he acknowledged
using a standard that fell short of the strict scrutiny
urged by Thomas, id. at 2820 n.2.
* * *
VII.
INTRODUCTION TO THE RELIGION CLAUSES
A. In the text of the First Amendment, the Speech and Press
Clauses are preceded by the two Religion Clauses (the
Establishment and Free Exercise Clauses):
292
Congress shall make no law
respecting an establishment of
religion, or prohibiting the free
exercise thereof ....
293
c. may not foster an excessive governmental
entanglement with religion (the ENTANGLEMENT
prong).
294
5. Kennedy: Expressly Overruling Lemon
295
Clause in Shurtleff v. City of Boston, 142 S. Ct.
1583 (2022).
6. American Legion
296
(2) The Court did not overrule Lemon. But it
strongly encouraged lower courts to abandon
Lemon in favor of an approach that gives great
deference to well-established customs,
practices, and monuments.
297
the statehouse grounds in Austin, Texas, which
had existed for 40 years without inspiring any
complaint).
7. Recommended Analysis
298
c. As for Category #2 (religious symbols or writings
adorning government property), this is where
American Legion will have an immediate and
dramatic impact. In American Legion’s wake, courts
will very likely REJECT an Establishment Clause
challenge to the presence of religious symbols or
writings in any official seals, mottos, monuments, or
displays that have longstanding historical or
traditional roots. What about NEW religious
monuments, seals, etc.? In American Legion, only
two Justices (Gorsuch and Thomas) argued that the
presumption of constitutionality should extend to
ALL religious monuments, seals, etc., both old and
new. It remains to be seen how the lower courts will
distinguish between old and new.
299
category, Covid-19 public health regulations that
limit RELIGIOUS gatherings may be no more
restrictive than limits on access to beauty parlors,
fitness centers, and other secular activities—e.g.,
Roman Catholic Diocese of Brooklyn v. Cuomo, 141
S. Ct. 63 (2020) (applying strict scrutiny because
New York limited gatherings by religious
congregations more aggressively than it limited
access to many secular activities).
300
c. Unclear from these cases—but highly unlikely—is
whether a bad faith or willfully punitive deprivation
of religious freedom would survive the relaxed
scrutiny of a “reasonableness” test. If a plaintiff
could prove that a state actor had such a motive, it
would certainly seem that his Free Exercise claim
would be successful.
301
all schoolchildren, including those attending private
religious schools.
302
2. In Rosenberger v. Rectors & Visitors of the University of
Virginia, 515 U.S. 819 (1995), where the Court held that a
student religious journal was entitled to the same subsidy
from student activity funds that the University furnishes
to secular student journals, Justice Souter (dissenting)
and Justice Thomas (concurring) advanced competing
views of James Madison’s famous Memorial and
Remonstrance.
303
5. Various Themes by Which the Religion Clauses Might Be
Construed
* * *
VIII.
THE ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE
304
A. Arguments Favoring a BROAD Interpretation of the
Establishment Clause (i.e., favoring a strict separation between
church and state):
305
3. Congress early on appointed a Chaplain and paid him with
public funds.
306
prevailing religion, as indicated by his opinion for the
Court in Lee v. Weisman, which struck down a policy that
authorized prayer at public school graduation ceremonies.
307
d. This is because the Religion Clauses “mean that
religious beliefs and religious expression are too
precious to be either proscribed or prescribed by the
State. The design of the Consti-tution is that
preservation and transmission of religious beliefs
and worship is a responsibility and a choice
committed to the private sphere....[T]he central
meaning of the Religion Clauses ...is that all creeds
must be tolerated and none favored.” 505 U.S. at
589.
308
1. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668 (1984)
309
a. In Allegheny, a majority of Justices adopted
O’Connor’s “no endorsement” analysis as a general
guide in Establishment Clause cases.
310
“endorsement” test. And Kennedy writes the
majority opinion in Town of Greece. By abrogating
Allegheny, Kennedy was paving the way for the death
of Lemon and the endorsement test.
311
Kennedy writing a 3-vote plurality (joined by Roberts
and Alito) and Thomas writing a 2-vote concurrence
in the judgment (joined by Scalia). This split is
prompted by differing views of a “coercion” test that
would replace the old “endorsement” test.
312
judge was present during the prayer, able to observe
who remained and who departed the courtroom. In a
decision that completely ignores the Town of Greece
distinction between legislative and courtroom
prayers, id. at 964 (Jolly, J., concurring in part and
dissenting in part), the Fifth Circuit holds that this
program does not violate the Establishment Clause.
313
immediate protest, in marked contrast to the Ten
Commandments display in Van Orden v. Perry [see
immediately below], which existed for 40 years without
triggering any complaint).
314
1. Mueller v. Allen, 463 U.S. 388 (1983): Upholding, 5-4, a
state tax deduction for expenses incurred for “tuition,
textbooks, and transportation” for elementary and
secondary schoolchildren, regardless of whether they
attended public or nonpublic schools.
315
(1) This Powell quote neatly sums up the view of
the Establishment Clause that is currently held
by the Court’s right wing.
316
surfaces again as the Court rejects a challenge to a
statute that authorized the payment of public funds to
blind persons for vocational rehabilitation services where
the recipient planned to use the funds to pay tuition at a
Christian college.
317
from conducting such classes on the premises of
parochial schools.
318
reading instruction and counseling at
nonpublic schools); and
319
h. Though Justice O’Connor may not have liked it, the
deferential Thomas approach to aid cases likely
commands majority support among the current
Justices.
320
* * *
IX.
THE FREE EXERCISE CLAUSE
A. Overview
321
2. Bear in mind that Free Exercise claims are greatly
weakened if advanced by the denizens of certain
“restricted environments”—soldiers and prisoners.
322
thereby crossed the line into an Establishment
Clause violation.
323
closing law case) and holds that unemployment
compensation cannot be denied to a woman fired by her
employer for refusing to work on her church’s sabbath,
Saturday.
6. But the Court refused to apply that test in one of its most
significant Free Exercise cases: Employment Division v.
Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990).
324
7. In Smith (per Justice Scalia), the Court applied rational
basis review in rejecting the Free Exercise claims of two
Native Americans who were denied unemployment
benefits after being fired from their jobs for partaking in
the sacramental use of peyote—part of a religious ritual in
the Native American Church.
325
who use the drug for other reasons. They assert, in
other words, that [the Free Exercise Clause bars the
government from] requiring any individual to
observe a generally applicable law that requires (or
forbids) the performance of an act that his religious
belief forbids (or requires).” Id. at 878.
d. This goes too far, says Scalia: “We have never held
that an individual’s religious beliefs excuse him from
compliance with an otherwise valid law prohibiting
conduct that the State is free to regulate.” Id. at
878-79.
326
acknowledged an eventual willingness to jettison
Smith once a workable substitute can be developed.
327
a. In the wake of Smith, Free Exercise claims will be
analyzed under rational basis review if directed at a
law of general applicability that in some way burdens
the plaintiff’s religious practices. Generally
speaking, strict scrutiny is triggered only when the
government purposefully interferes with a religious
belief or practice—e.g., Church of the Lukumi
Babalu Aye v. City of Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520, 533
(1993). But there are two additional situations in
which strict scrutiny will be used in analyzing a Free
Exercise claim—(1) when dealing with so-called
“hybrid” claims; and (2) when confronted with
exemption systems that ignore religion.
b. “Hybrid” Claims
328
(4) BUT: Some Circuits have expressed doubt
whether the hybrid rights exception exists at
all, calling it dictum at best. Parents for Privacy
v. Barr, 949 F.3d 1210, 1238 (9th Cir. 2020);
Leebaert v. Harrington, 332 F.3d 134, 143 (2d
Cir. 2003).
329
dispute between the City and one of its long-
standing foster care agencies: Catholic Social
Services (“CSS”), an agency affiliated with the
Roman Catholic Archdiocese. The City stopped
referring children to CSS upon discovering that
the agency, due to its religious beliefs about
marriage, would not certify same-sex couples to
be foster parents. Id. at 1874. CSS filed suit
when the City balked at renewing their contract
unless CSS pledged to certify same-sex couples.
Id. at 1874.
330
(8) The Chief Justice concluded: “The creation of a
system of exceptions under the contract
undermines the City’s contention that its non-
discrimination policies can brook no
departures. The City offers no compelling
reason why it has a particular interest in
denying an exception to CSS while making
them available to others.” 141 S. Ct. at 1882
(citations omitted).
331
religious exercise? What forms of scrutiny
should apply? And if the answer is strict
scrutiny, would pre-Smith cases rejecting free
exercise challenges to garden-variety laws
come out the same way?” Id. at 1883 (citations
omitted).
332
brought a Free Exercise challenge to the red and
orange occupancy limits on attendance at religious
services. They argued that these occupancy limits
imposed greater obstacles to religious worship than
to comparable secular activities.
333
13. Masterpiece Cakeshop v. Colorado Civil Rights
Commission, 138 S. Ct. 1719 (2018): This case presented
a compelled speech issue and a religious freedom issue.
The Court ducked both issues—but they are worth
discussing, because lawsuits with fact patterns like this
one are percolating in the lower courts. I discussed the
compelled speech issue in section VI(C) of this Outline.
We’ll confront the religious freedom issue right here.
334
The Supreme Court never squarely addressed either
of these issues.
335
likely handing the baker a defeat and triggering a
rebellion by Alito, Gorsuch, and Thomas. Those
Justices want a vigorous Free Exercise Clause; they
want to eliminate the possibility of rational basis
review; and they are now calling loudly for Smith to
be buried. See Fulton v. City of Philadel-phia, 141 S.
Ct. 1868 (2021), where Justices Alito, Gorsuch, and
Thomas urged that Smith be overruled.
* * *
336
Trinity Lutheran Church v. Comer, 137 S. Ct. 2012 (2017);
and Espinoza v. Montana Department of Revenue, 140 S.
Ct. 2246 (2020). Let’s address them in the sequence in
which they were decided.
337
4. Carson v. Makin, 142 S. Ct. 1987 (2022): Applying strict
scrutiny under the Free Exercise Clause, the Court struck
down a Maine tuition assistance program that expressly
disqualified religious schools. Writing for a 6-3 majority,
Chief Justice Roberts observed: “The State pays tuition for
certain students at private schools—so long as the schools
are not religious. That is discrimination against religion.”
Id. at 1998. This holding does not mean that Maine MUST
fund religious education: “A State ‘need not subsidize
private education. But once a State decides to do so, it
cannot disqualify some private schools solely because they
are religious.’” Id. at 2000 (quoting Espinoza, 140 S. Ct. at
2261).
338
be an easy case because taxing religious publications
might well violate the Free Exercise Clause.
* * *
X.
THE PRESS CLAUSE
339
A. A “Preferred” Status for the Press?
340
2. But the following cases show that:
341
f. And Branzburg kept his promise: he published these
stories without revealing the identities of his
subjects.
342
Amendment privilege protecting them from
compelled disclosure of their confiden-tial sources—
a privilege that survived the 5-to-4 Branzburg
decision due to Powell’s concurrence.
343
Amendment, the First Amendment affords the news media
no special protection from search and seizure.
344
f. Notwithstanding the Act, Zurcher still shows that the
Press Clause affords the news media no greater
protection from search and seizure than that enjoyed
by the public generally.
345
c. Thus, the First Amendment confers upon the public
a broad “right to know” about governmental
proceedings: “[T]he First Amendment goes beyond
protection of the press and the self-expression of
individuals to prohibit government from limiting the
stock of information from which members of the
public may draw. Free speech carries with it some
freedom to listen. In a variety of contexts, this Court
has referred to a First Amendment right to receive
information and ideas.” Id. at 575-76 (citations and
internal quotation marks omitted).
346
proceedings, the Supreme Court has examined “two
complementary considera-tions,” Press-Enterprise II,
478 U.S. at 8:
347
down a special tax on paper and ink employed in the
publishing of periodicals.
* * *
XI.
FREEDOM OF ASSOCIATION
A. Introduction
348
B. An Organization’s Freedom from Compelled Disclosure of Its
Members
349
Party or any group that advocated overthrowing the
government by force or violence).
350
2. Barring Gays from the Boy Scouts: Boy Scouts of America
v. Dale, 530 U.S. 640 (2000) (trumping an anti-
discrimination statute with the freedom from government-
compelled association, the Supreme Court holds that a
law prohibiting the Boy Scouts from excluding gays
effectively violates the First Amendment right of
expressive association because, as found by the Court, id.
at 661, opposition to homosexuality is part of “the
organization’s expressive message”).
* * *
351
APPENDIX
Police Power To Disperse
And Arrest Demonstrators
NOTE TO STUDENTS:
You will not be tested on these materials, but they may be
of interest given the huge upsurge in public protest after
the police killing of George Floyd.
A. Introduction
352
2. The governing law in this area has been developed
through a combination of First Amendment and Fourth
Amendment principles.
353
sufficiently frequent that police have adopted a practice of
‘permitting’ them to use a specific corridor of city streets.
This waiver of the permit requirement is informal; it
seems to consist just in not telling the demonstrators that
they need a permit.” Vodak, 639 F.3d at 741 (emphasis in
original).
354
to disperse. Carr v. District of Columbia, 587 F.3d 401,
409-10 (D.C. Cir. 2009).
355
reasonable opportunity to comply with that order.” 434
F.3d at 575.
END
356