We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 29
Political Theory: Middle Ages
Origins of Religious -Political Thought
Medieval Thought • “Medieval” refers to Europe Medieval philosophy includes the “pre-scholastic”, “scholastic” and “late scholastic” periods. • “Scholasticism” refers to the intellectual culture characteristic of the medieval schools. • 12th century schooling became a flourishing industry in Paris, Bologna and many other places. By the early 13th century the masters of the schools in some places had formed corporations generally called universities. University • A university was a guild (i.e. trade association) of masters or students in a town. The university was not itself a teaching institution: teaching was done in the masters' schools (or later in colleges). • Schools of higher education had existed among the Greeks, Jews and Muslims, but a trade association of teachers or scholars was a new idea. • Like the ancient schools, the medieval schools taught by means of textbooks: Aristotle in the Arts faculty, Averroes and Avicenna in medicine, the Bible and in theology. • By medieval political philosophy we understand the medieval writings on politics that are similar to the modern writings we classify as political philosophy. • Medieval authors were usually academics writing to be read by university-educated readers, they drew upon ideas explored in the schools and they wrote in an academic way. Some wrote commentaries on Aristotle's Politics and academic “disputed questions” related to topics of political philosophy. • Many of the Fathers were influenced by the Platonism and Stoicism that every educated person became acquainted with in the ancient world. • Augustine was particularly influenced by Platonism, in the version modern scholars call “Neo-Platonism”, i.e., the philosophy of Plotinus. • The Church Fathers passed down to the middle ages the idea that certain key social institutions were not part of God's original plan for mankind, namely the institutions of coercive government, slavery and property. • The idea found in Seneca and other ancient Stoics of a Golden Age had a parallel in Christian thinking, namely the age of innocence in the Garden of Eden, from which mankind were expelled because of the sin of Adam and Eve (the “Fall”). Early Middle Age Europe
• Emperor Theodosius adopted Christianity as a state religion for
the Roman Empire.
• Empire was under attack by the foreign invasions (Germanic
tribes, Visigoths and Vandals)and there was internal class struggles.
• The economic political and military unity of Roman Empire came
to an end.
• Hopes and survival of the Roman Empire was dependent on the
new religion: Christianity City of God and City of Evil • The work of Augustine's most likely to be known to modern students of political thought is The City of God. St. Augustine • The common opinion on coercive government and slavery was expressed by Augustine. God “did not intend that …[man] should have lordship over any but irrational creatures: not man over man, but man over the beasts. Hence, the first just men were established as shepherds of flocks, rather than as kings of men” (City of God, XIX.15, p. 942). • Two cities, the city of God and the earthly city, are distinguished by two loves, love of God and (misdirected) love of self, and by two destinies, heaven and hell. Augustine's most famous contribution to theology was the doctrine of predestination. • God has decreed from all eternity that to some he will give the grace needed to attain eternal salvation, while the rest of mankind (the majority) will go to eternal damnation. • Salvation requires the grace of “final perseverance”, i.e. the grace of being in friendship with God at the moment of death. • Some who live well for most of their lives may fall away at the very end. Thus we cannot tell for sure who is predestined to salvation. Since the city of God consists of those predestined to salvation, we cannot be sure of its membership. • The city of God is not identical with the Church, since not all members of the Church will be saved. The earthly city is not identical with any particular state, since some members of a state may be predestined to salvation. A particular state may include citizens of both cities. • As a Platonist Augustine thought in terms of a hierarchy of levels of reality, in which lower levels imitate or reflect the higher levels. • Augustine's is not a philosophy of “black and white”, of stark opposition between the forces of light and the forces of darkness—this was the Manichean philosophy, to which Augustine at one time subscribed, until the reading of certain works of the Platonists had led him to reject it. According to Augustine there is no absolute evil. • Anything evil must be to some extent good, or it could not exist at all. Its evil consists in disorder or misdirection, in its failing to attain all the goodness appropriate to it. “The peace of all things lies in the tranquillity of order, and order is the disposition of equal and unequal things in such a way as to give to each its proper place” (City of God, p. 938). • There are many orderings and sub-orderings, and there are therefore different kinds or levels of peace, and (for beings capable of moral choice) different kinds or levels of virtue, justice and happiness • Augustine offers to prove that by Cicero's definition, the Romans never had a republic. • “I shall attempt to show that no such commonwealth ever existed, because true justice was never present in it” (p. 80), since the Romans did not obey the true God. • As Augustine says, “There was, of course, according to a more practicable definition, a commonwealth of a sort”, It is only by narrow definition that it can be said that non-Christians cannot form a commonwealth. • Motivated by love of honour, the Romans were able to live together in an approximation to peace, justice and happiness, though not in “true” peace, justice and happiness. Justice in some measure is essential to anything that deserves to be called a commonwealth. • Among medieval Christians there were at least three views of the goods and evils of government: 1)Government may be, and should be, rule by the ideal Christian ruler, whom the Protestants later called “the godly prince”; such a ruler would lead his people in obedience to God. 2)Government may be simply a wicked tyranny, an expression of the “earthly city”. 3)Government exists to organise the cooperation of “men of good will” i.e., citizens of the two cities united by an interest in earthly peace and other earthly goods valued by both Christians and others. Such a limited view of the goals of government is found in Marsilius and Ockham. • All three views could find support in The City of God. St. Aquinas On natural law and other kinds of law Thomas again follows not Aristotle but the tradition of civil and canon law going back to the Roman Stoics He distinguishes divine law (eternal and positive) from human law, and among human laws he distinguishes natural law from the law of nations and civil law. Law is concerned with direction to the common good, which belongs to the whole people . All positive human law must be in accordance with natural law, though its prescriptions will depend upon choice and circumstances (for example, natural law prescribes that we must not kill, but human positive law makes additional rules to prevent killing, rules that may depend on arbitrary choice. Natural law is in effect morality, and according to Thomas the human mind, reflecting on and analysing human experience, can see the truth of various fundamental moral principles, which are thus “self-evident”, not in need of proof, and too fundamental to be capable of proof . On property, Thomas follows the view of the Stoics and the Fathers that property exists by human positive law. Natural law permits us to use things but property goes beyond power to use: it includes a power to exclude others from use, and this power is conferred by human positive law Property rights give way to extreme need, so in time of extreme need using another's property without permission is not theft The best form of government, according to Thomas, is a mixed government combining elements of democracy, aristocracy and kingship This is reminiscent of Aristotle's preference for mixed government over either democracy or oligarchy, but in fact many ancient writers, including Cicero, advocated mixed government. On the duty to obey government, Thomas does not adopt the position that many others found in the New Testament, that disobedience is never justified. According to Thomas Aquinas, though there is a general duty to obey the law and the government, an unjust law is not a law For Thomas Aquinas, as for Aristotle, doing moral philosophy is thinking as generally as possible about what I should choose to do (and not to do), considering my whole life as a field of opportunity (or misuse of opportunity). Thinking as general as this concerns not merely my own opportunities, but the kinds of good things that any human being can do and achieve, or be deprived of.
(Fathers of The Church Patristic Series 49) by Lactantius (Author), McDonald O.P., Sr. Mary Francis (Translator) - The Divine Institutes, Books I-VII-The Catholic University of Ameri