Western Political Philosphers
Western Political Philosphers
Introduction:
Machiavelli, born in Florence, Italy, in 1469,
stands as a pivotal figure of the Renaissance,
evoking both admiration and criticism. As a
champion of civic republicanism, his ideas
have significantly shaped the thoughts of
subsequent thinkers. Antonio
Gramsci commends Machiavelli for
distinguishing politics from ethics,
emphasizing his pragmatic approach to
governance over abstract philosophical ideals.
His contributions heralded a new intellectual
era, leading Maxey to designate him as
the “First Modern Political Thinker.”
The Renaissance was marked by various
forces that disrupted the concept of a unified
Christian order. Economic growth fostered
commerce and urbanization, while innovations
like the printing press revolutionized
communication. This period also saw a
transition from barter to monetary systems,
alongside groundbreaking scientific and
geographical discoveries. The rise of
centralized states with distinct national
languages, a renewed respect for scientific
inquiry, and demographic shifts contributed to
the formation of a secular order.
Universities emerged, challenging the Church’s
educational monopoly and promoting literacy
and the revival of the human
spirit. Individualism and humanism flourished
as central themes. Jacob Burckhardt noted
that the essence of the Renaissance lay in the
“new man,” who pursued glory and self-
realization over religious asceticism. Harold
Laski remarked on this remarkable
transformation, stating that the essence of the
Renaissance is found in Machiavelli’s writings.
Machiavelli depicted the evolving nature of
the state by understanding the complexities of
statecraft, where decisions were influenced by
political realities rather than religious doctrines
or idealized concepts of governance. He is
recognized as the father of political realism,
prioritizing the practical aspects of politics.
Table of Contents
1. Introduction:
2. Influences on Machiavelli
3. Important Works of Machiavelli
4. Methodology of Machiavelli
5. Political Ideas of Machiavelli
6. On Human Nature/Universal Egoism
7. On Morality
8. On Religion
Influences on Machiavelli
“Machiavelli was the child of his times” –
Dunning
“The whole of Renaissance is in Machiavelli.” –
Laski
“Machiavelli was narrowly dated and narrowly
located.” – Sabine
Machiavelli: Child of his
time
Niccolò Machiavelli, born in Florence in 1469 to
a wealthy family, was well-educated for a
political career. He rose quickly in government
and gained diplomatic experience through
missions abroad. However, in 1513, political
turmoil in the Florentine Republic led to his
downfall, including a year in prison. After being
released, Machiavelli was forced to retire from
politics.
During this time, he wrote influential works,
most notably The Prince and Discourses on
the First Ten Books of Titus Livy. His
writings reflected a pragmatic approach to
politics, often
advocating for the use of ruthless tactics if
necessary. Machiavelli believed that political
leaders were often driven by self-interest rather
than public good, influenced by the chaotic
state of Italy, which was divided into five
regions and plagued by foreign domination.
The Catholic Church’s desire to maintain
power further hindered Italy’s unification.
Inspired by the idea of a unified Italy under a
strong monarchy, similar to France and Spain,
Machiavelli’s thoughts marked a transition from
medieval to modern political
theory. Machiavelli, according to Dunning,
“stood on the borderline between the
Middle Ages and the Modern Ages.
Let’s discuss some key developments
influenced his thought
Renaissance
The Renaissance, known as the rebirth of
logic and civilizational values, revitalized the
spirit of inquiry and humanism, which found
expression in Machiavelli’s ideas. At its core
was the emergence of a new individual
driven by self-interest, seeking glory and
fame. This modern individual became the
focus of Machiavelli’s philosophy. Concurrently,
the notion of a modern state, powerful and
pervasive, developed, shaping Machiavelli’s
understanding of statecraft.
Reformation
The Reformation, marked by the separation of
the public and private spheres in religion,
led to the rise of secularism and
the separation of church and state. These
developments significantly influenced
Machiavelli’s political thought, earning him the
title of the Father of European Secularism.
Breakdown of Feudalism
While the old feudal order crumbled, the
emergence of the territorial nation-state as a
sovereign entity was still in its infancy.
Machiavelli’s preference for common people
over nobility reflected the changing times.
Rise of Nation-State
Machiavelli was deeply concerned with Italy’s
need to become a strong nation-state, making
Italian unification a primary objective. His
dream was to see a united, regenerated, and
glorious Italy, requiring the defense and
preservation of the state and its people.
Machiavelli’s emphasis on the spirit of his
times is evident in his advocacy for a national
army.
Rise of Capitalism
Machiavelli’s portrayal of human nature
as self-centered, materialistic, and
possessive mirrors the psychology of the
emerging bourgeois class.
Important Works of
Machiavelli
17. Art of war (1521) – It is a classic on theory of
war and Military in the west. It explains the
relation between war and politics in
Machiavelli’s political thought.
18. History of Florence (1525) – It talks about
‘Prince’ is one of
the best books written on statecraft (Art of
Politics). He is compared to Chanakya in this
regard. Machiavelli in Prince gives advice to
the Prince (ruler) about ruling the states in a
realist manner.
Methodology of Machiavelli
Machiavelli was deeply influenced
by Aristotle, valuing historical methods over
church teachings. He dismissed religious
doctrines, believing human nature and its
problems remain constant across time. Thus,
he focused on real political situations rather
than abstract constitutional theories. His
analysis was rooted in the conditions of his
own era, making him a keen observer and
realist.
According to Sabine, Machiavelli used history
to support conclusions he reached
independently, and Dunning described his
work as emphasizing the “art of government”
rather than a theory of the state. While
narrower in scope than Aristotle, Machiavelli’s
insights into political dynamics reveal strengths
and weaknesses in situations, offering practical
judgments on policy limitations and event
forecasts.
His pragmatic views, such as “might is
right” and “the end justifies the
means,” suggest that he prioritized outcomes
over methods. Often considered the Father of
Political Realism, he embraced a cyclical
view of history, emphasizing psychology and
historical patterns. The Prince focuses on
state security, while The Discourses delves
into liberty.
Political Ideas of Machiavelli
On Human Nature/Universal
Egoism
Machiavelli’s political philosophy, alongside his
concept of “moral indifference,” is “Universal
Egoism.” He rejected the idea of inherent
goodness in human nature, arguing that
all individuals are fundamentally selfish and
driven by egoism. For Machiavelli, fear is a
more powerful motivator than love, with the
desire for security being the primary concern of
human behavior. Human nature is aggressive
and acquisitive; people strive to keep what they
have and seek more, leading to constant
competition due to the scarcity of resources.
To maintain security, a ruler must embody fear.
A prince who is feared understands how to
relate to his subjects and ensures their safety.
Machiavelli noted that individuals often
misjudge their hopes and desires, suggesting
that balancing opposing interests is essential
for a stable society.
During Machiavelli’s time, Italy was rife with
corruption, violence, and inequality. He
believed that the establishment of an absolute
monarchy with despotic powers was necessary
to restore order. He emphasized that rulers
must understand human nature, which remains
consistent throughout history, noting traits like
selfishness and ingratitude. He famously
remarked that “people could forget a father’s
loss but not the loss of their
property. Consequently, he concluded that
individuals prioritize their self-interest,
supporting a ruler only as long as their own
interests are met, highlighting the need for
rulers to remain attentive to their subjects’
needs.
On Morality
Machiavelli is renowned for his assertion that in
politics, ends justify means. He firmly
separated religion and politics, as well as
ethics and politics, establishing the autonomy
of politics from these moral frameworks. He
argued that political actions should be
evaluated based on political standards rather
than religious or ethical ones. What may be
considered ethnically or religiously wrong can
be politically correct in Machiavelli’s view.
To illustrate this, Machiavelli introduced the
concept of “Dual Morality”. According to this
concept, the morality of a prince differs from
that of a common person. While an ordinary
individual may be willing to sacrifice their life
for their principles, a prince cannot afford to
sacrifice the nation-state for personal
principles. Here Machiavelli gave the idea
of “Flexible Disposition”, which states that
Prince must act as per demand of fate and
circumstances. The morality of a prince, as
defined by Machiavelli, revolves around
ensuring the security and preservation of the
nation and its people.
“There is nothing like ethics for Prince. He is
everything”. – The originality of
Machiavelli written by Berlin.
On Religion
Machiavelli did not hold a stance against
religion itself but rather took issue with the
institutionalized Church of his time. He saw
the Church as a corrupt entity and attributed
Italy’s lack of unification partly to its influence.
Consequently, he advocated for a separation
between the Church and the state, aiming to
prevent the Church from guiding governmental
affairs.
Machiavelli’s approach to religion was
utilitarian in nature. He advised princes
to utilize religion in the interest of the
nation. He viewed religion as a disciplinary
force that could assist rulers in governing their
people effectively. Machiavelli even
recommended that a prince should maintain a
public appearance of religiosity, even if the
prince personally lacked faith. He believed
that people preferred their rulers to be
religious.
On State and Its Preservation
Machiavelli regarded the state as the highest
authority to which subjects should
wholeheartedly submit. He believed that the
prosperity of the subjects was the yardstick for
evaluating the success or failure of a state. In
his view, a successful state was one ruled by a
single leader, favoring monarchy over
aristocracy. He emphasized the importance of
a reliable army composed of native troops
instead of relying on foreign soldiers.
While Machiavelli considered a republican
state as the best form of government in
theory, he acknowledged that the prevailing
conditions of his time favored a monarchical
government. He firmly asserted the secular
nature of the state, subordinating the Church to
the authority of the state.
Machiavelli viewed politics from the ruler’s
perspective, prioritizing state preservation over
constitutional excellence. He examined
government mechanisms that strengthen the
state and identified errors leading to downfall.
As Sabine noted, “The purpose of politics is
to preserve and increase political
power,” with success being the main criterion
for judgment.
Advice on the Amount of
Power
Machiavelli famously declared, “It is better for
the Prince to
be feared than loved”. He advocated that a
prince should skillfully employ both hard power
and soft power. While he acknowledged the
value of soft power in generating goodwill, he
argued that goodwill alone was insufficient to
ensure compliance, as human beings were
inherently selfish and ungrateful. Machiavelli
believed that people acted in their own self-
interest, so a policy of love and goodwill was
not adequate.
The prince, in Machiavelli’s view, should exploit
the weaknesses of human nature. Force
should not be the first resort but should be
applied when absolutely necessary. When the
prince decided to use force, it should be
employed decisively to completely crush the
opponent and leave no room for revenge.
Machiavelli recognized the potency of the
desire for revenge in humans and believed that
it could override rational self-interest, driving
individuals to take actions even against their
own wellbeing.
Machiavelli on Prince
Machiavelli offers clear guidance on the
attributes a prince should possess. He
famously advises that a prince must embody
both the cunning of a fox and the bravery of
a lion. To elucidate these qualities further:
21. Cleverness – Like a fox, a prince should be
Introduction
Thomas Hobbes, born on April 5, 1588, in
England, is a key figure in Western political
thought, particularly known for his views on
human nature, political authority, and the need
for an all-powerful sovereign. He was famously
called the “Monster of Malmesbury” due to
widespread criticism for atheism and impiety.
Both Parliamentarians and Royalists disliked
him, as his ideas challenged popular
representation and the Divine Right of Kings.
Hobbes’ philosophical status wasn’t fully
appreciated until the 19th century, when his
ideas influenced English utilitarians and French
Encyclopaedists. His philosophy combined
mechanical
materialism, radical individualism, and
psychological egoism. Sir Frederick
Pollock remarked that utilitarianism adapted
Hobbes’ ideas, especially from his Leviathan.
By the mid-20th century, Hobbes was
recognized as a leading English political
philosopher, with Michael Oakeshott
calling Leviathan a masterpiece.
Hobbes developed the absolutist theory
of sovereignty and contributed to the positivist
theory of law. Though often seen as
authoritarian, scholars like Gauthier found
connections between Hobbes’ ideas and
modern liberalism. His philosophy also
influenced Marxist thought, with Karl
Marx noting, “Hobbes was the father of us
all.” Today, his ideas remain influential in
political, ethical, and legal discussions.
Table of Contents
23. Introduction
24. Early Life of Thomas Hobbes
Hobbes
33. Rights and Duties by Thomas Hobbes
34. The Church and the State in Hobbes’ Political
Thought
35. Political Obligation in Hobbes’s Philosophy
Philosophy
37. Comments on Thomas Hobbes
39. Conclusion
to body
and matter.
45. De Homine (1658): Further elaborated on his
nature
were intertwined, both stemming from divine
commands.
Thus, Hobbes grounded political obligation in
morality, providing a solid foundation for the
sovereign’s authority. Hobbes’s theory of
political obligation ultimately strengthened the
position of the sovereign, reinforcing the need
for an absolute authority in maintaining societal
order.
Women and the Gender
Question in Hobbes’s
Philosophy
In his exploration of human nature and society,
Hobbes also delved into the role of women and
gender dynamics. He held that in the state of
nature, women who gave birth held a unique
position as both mothers and authorities over
their children. Their authority derived from the
act of protection and nurturing that childbirth
necessitated.
However, as societies evolved into civil
societies, Hobbes observed a shift in the status
of women. They became subordinated and
were denied the right to participate in the
political process. Despite being an advocate for
human equality in principle, Hobbes did not
grant equal authority to both men and women.
He defended the prevailing patriarchal
structure by granting fathers exclusive
jurisdiction within the family unit. Hobbes’s
belief that males possessed greater wisdom
and courage led him to endorse this patriarchal
system further. Even in the broader context of
the commonwealth, Hobbes assigned
succession solely to male children, citing their
natural fitness to rule.
Hobbes’s stance on gender equality remained
complex. While he acknowledged the idea of
gender equality, he did
not overtly challenge or oppose the prevailing
patriarchy of his time.
Comments on Thomas
Hobbes
57. ‘The leviathan is the greatest perhaps the sole
master of Political Philosophy written in English
Language’ – Oakeshott
58. ‘Hobbes was the first one to lay down the
Ebinstien
61. ‘Hobbesian state of nature is classical example
law’.
65. ‘Force and Fraud are in War the two cardinal
virtues’.
66. ‘In the State of Nature, Profit is the measure of
right’.
67. ‘No arts; no letters; no society; and which is
than anarchy
Conclusion
In conclusion, Thomas Hobbes made
significant contributions to political philosophy
by constructing a systematic theory
encompassing absolute sovereignty, the laws
of nature, human nature, and political
obligation. His philosophy emphasized the
necessity of a sovereign authority to prevent
perpetual war and conflict. Hobbes considered
self-preservation a fundamental law of nature
and believed that the state’s primary role was
to ensure peace, order, and security, in
contrast to Aristotle’s concept of the state as a
granter of a good life.
Hobbes’s political thought was a response to
the changing conditions of 17th-century
England, addressing political conflicts, the
demand for religious virtue, and economic
restructuring. He began with the notion of
natural rights but ultimately constrained them
within a viable civil society. While he restricted
the natural liberty of individuals, he did not
endorse the idea of individuals having the right
to curtail the authority of the state. Hobbes’s
philosophical legacy continues to shape our
understanding of politics and society, shedding
light on both enduring and evolving aspects of
his ideas.
WESTERN POLITICAL THOUGHTFATHER
OF LIBERALISMJOHN LOCKE'S POLITICAL
PHILOSOPHY
John Locke: The
Philosopher of Individual
Rights and Enlightenment
Thinker
21 September 2023
John Locke was an influential Enlightenment
philosopher known for his ideas on empiricism
and natural rights, asserting that individuals
have inherent rights to life, liberty, and property,
which greatly influenced modern political
thought.
John Locke (1632 – 17040
Introduction
John Locke, a prominent figure of the
Enlightenment, was born on August 29, 1632,
in Wrington, England. Renowned as both a
philosopher and physician, Locke is often
referred to as the ‘Father of Liberalism’ due
to his significant impact on Enlightenment
thought, particularly through his advocacy for
the Social Contract Theory, government by
consent, human freedom, and the role of
reason in society. He argued that a
society practicing intellectual and religious
toleration was ideal for stability, earning him
the title of the ‘father of the Enlightenment.’
Locke’s pivotal contribution lies in justifying
the Glorious Revolution of 1688, which
transitioned England from an absolute
monarchy to a constitutional one. His writings
provided essential philosophical foundations
for this significant historical moment. Recent
scholarship on Locke has revealed a wealth of
new material, especially from the Lovelace
collection, enhancing our understanding of his
life and thought.
However, contemporary interpretations of
Locke’s political theory have become
increasingly divergent. Some view him through
a lens of Hobbism, emphasizing an egoistic
and utilitarian ethics, while others argue for a
deontological perspective, presenting him as a
classical natural law thinker. There are further
characterizations of Locke as a “prince of
individualists,” while others depict him as a
collectivist akin to Rousseau.
The complexity of Locke’s philosophy is
evident in the various interpretations, from
Martin Seliger’s “liberal constitutionalism” to
Macpherson’s reading of it as a theory of
“capitalist appropriation.” Each interpretation
has merit, but attempts to fit Locke into rigid
philosophical categories often distort his rich
and multifaceted ideas. This complexity
creates a challenging comparison with
contemporaries like Hobbes, illustrating the
difficulties faced by those analyzing his work.
As noted by J.W.W. Watkins, it is essential to
recognize Locke’s unique contributions while
acknowledging the diverse and sometimes
conflicting interpretations of his
philosophy.
Table of Contents
70. Introduction
71. Major Works by John Locke
Locke
74. State of Nature by John Locke
Individual Rights
79. Political Obligation: Obedience Grounded in
Political Philosophy
81. Differences between Hobbes and Locke on
Natural Rights
82. Famous Quotes by John Locke
83. Conclusion
quality for
others.
89. Property rights extend only to what individuals
By:Politicalsciencesolution.Com
Date:
22 September 2023
Jean-Jacques Rousseau was an 18th-century
French philosopher known for his ideas on
social contract theory and the belief in the
innate goodness of humans, while also
advocating for a more egalitarian society.
Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712- 1778)
Introduction
Born on June 28, 1712, in the picturesque city
of Geneva, Jean-Jacques Rousseau emerged
as a pivotal figure during the Enlightenment
era, leaving an indelible mark on the
intellectual landscape of his time. Often
referred to as the intellectual Father of the
French Revolution, Rousseau was a
trailblazer who challenged established norms
and institutions in the pursuit of modern values
such as equality, liberty, and democracy.
Rousseau’s philosophy underscores the
profound distinction between society and
human nature. He posited that in the state of
nature, humans were inherently good but
became corrupted by the artificial constructs of
society, particularly critiquing the concept of
private property. Additionally, he championed
the idea of human equality within society and
aimed to harmonize liberty and equality.
Rousseau also advocated the concept of the
General Will as the true foundation of
legitimate power and authority, all while
advocating simplicity, innocence, and virtue as
the means to unlock the full potential of human
nature. His philosophy resonated deeply with
those who yearned for a return to a more
natural and unspoiled existence, free from the
trappings of modern society.
Table of Contents
113. Introduction
114. Early Life of Rousseau
115. His Major Works
116. Revolt Against Reason
117. Rousseau’s Political Philosophy
118. State of Nature
119. The Emergence of Private Property
120. Analyzing Inequality
121. Concept of “General Will”
122. The Social Contract Theory
123. Popular Sovereignty
124. Challenging Representative Government:
The Call for Direct Democracy
125. Rousseau’s views on Family and Women
126. Critical Appreciation
127. Famous Quotes by Rousseau
128. Conclusion: Rousseau’s Vision of a Just
Society
Early Life of Rousseau
Jean-Jacques Rousseau was born into a poor
family in Geneva, with his mother dying shortly
after his birth. His father struggled to provide a
coherent upbringing, and at the age of twelve,
Rousseau was apprenticed to various masters
but failed to establish himself in any trade.
Throughout his life, he lived in poverty, relying
on his ingenuity and the generosity of women.
For material advantages, he even changed his
religion and accepted charity from people he
disliked.
In 1744, Rousseau moved to Paris, where he
explored various fields, including theatre,
opera, music, and poetry, but achieved little
success. Despite this, his charismatic
personality allowed him to gain access to the
prestigious salons of Paris, where he mingled
with leading encyclopedists and influential
women, some of whom he had close
relationships with. However, he distanced
himself from the upper class, maintaining the
values of his low-middle-class, puritanical
upbringing.
During Rousseau’s lifetime, France was ruled
by the absolutist regime of Louis XV, where
political power and social prestige were
monopolized by the king, clergy, and nobility,
who lived extravagantly at the expense of the
struggling masses. The corrupt bureaucracy
denied even basic needs, fostering widespread
discontent and a desire for change. The
emerging bourgeoisie, feeling restricted by
the current order, allied with the peasantry to
seek reform.
The French Enlightenment significantly
influenced the climate of dissent against the
ancien régime, emphasizing reason and
experience. While Rousseau aligned with
some Enlightenment ideas, he diverged in his
emphasis on feelings over rationality. He
believed modern man had lost touch with his
emotions, leading him to reject the
Enlightenment’s prioritization of reason and
advocating for a more emotional connection to
humanity.
His Major Works
Rousseau’s intellectual contributions
manifested through a series of influential
writings that challenged conventional wisdom
and ignited fervent debates:
Discourse on the Arts and Sciences
(1750): In this work, Rousseau provocatively
asserted that ‘Our souls have been corrupted
in proportion to the advancement of our
sciences and our arts towards perfection’.
Discourse on the Origin and Basis of
Inequality (1755): Rousseau’s second
discourse delved into the origins of inequality,
tracing it back to the establishment of civil
society and the emergence of private property.
Discourse on Political Economy (1755): This
discourse explored the concept of democratic
ideals, further solidifying Rousseau’s
commitment to the principles of equality and
liberty.
Emile (1762): Rousseau’s treatise on
education, Emile, had a profound impact on the
development of the French education system
during the tumultuous period of the French
Revolution.
The Social Contract (1762): In this magnum
opus, Rousseau expounded on the concept of
the General Will as the cornerstone of
legitimate authority, presenting a vision of a
just social contract that resonated with
revolutionary thinkers of his time.
Essay – “Has the progress of sciences and
arts contributed to corrupt or purify
morals” – For this particular essay Rousseau
also won a prize in 1749 sponsored by the
Academy of Dijon.
The Confession – Autobiography of Rousseau
Revolt Against Reason
During the Enlightenment, a time of great
scientific advancement and the belief in reason
as the guiding principle of life, Jean-Jacques
Rousseau emerged as a critical voice. He
challenged the Enlightenment’s focus on
intelligence, science, and reason, claiming that
these elements were harming the faith and
moral values of society. Rousseau believed
that the “thinking animal is a depraved
animal,” arguing that reason suppressed
natural feelings like sympathy and compassion.
He contended that reason led to pride, which
conflicted with sympathy, and he viewed pride
as inherently evil. In his book Political
Thought, Wayper stated, “Rousseau, ardent
apostle of reason, has done more than most to
prepare the way for the age of unreason in
which he lived.”
Rousseau’s criticism of the Enlightenment was
articulated in a prize-winning essay written in
1749, where he addressed the question, “Has
the progress of science and arts
contributed to corrupt or purify morality?”
He argued that
science did not enhance morality but rather
caused moral decline. Rousseau believed
that what was perceived as progress was, in
fact, a regression. He asserted that the arts of
civilized society merely adorned the chains that
bound people. In his view, modern civilization
did not make people happier or more virtuous;
instead, it corrupted them, with greater
sophistication leading to greater corruption.
He was skeptical of the Baconian dream of
creating abundance on Earth, believing that
abundance led to luxury, which was a known
source of corruption. Rousseau pointed to
historical examples, stating that Athens fell
because of its luxury and excess, and that
Rome lost its strength after becoming wealthy
and indulgent. He argued, “Our minds have
been corrupted in proportion as the arts
and sciences have improved.” For
Rousseau, the praised civility and refinement
of society concealed negative traits such as
jealousy, suspicion, and deceit.
Against the Enlightenment’s faith in intelligence
and progress, Rousseau promoted kindness,
goodwill, and moral feelings. He argued that
sentiments and conscience should guide moral
values. He believed that without reverence,
faith, and moral intuition, there could be no
character or society. Rousseau saw modern
society as false and artificial, having strayed
from a true culture that reflects genuine human
nature and the collective will of the people.
Rousseau’s Political
Philosophy
State of Nature
Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s political philosophy
takes us on a
journey back to the origins of human existence,
challenging the conventional wisdom of his
time. According to Rousseau, in the state of
nature, individuals were guided by instinct
rather than reason. He painted a vivid picture
of noble savage i.e. living in idyllic bliss,
leading lives characterized by independence,
self-sufficiency, and a profound connection with
nature. In this pristine state, happiness was not
contingent on reason but thrived in simplicity,
free from the artificial desires that reason often
gave birth to. He further quoted – ‘A happy
individual was not much a thinking being’.
Rousseau’s critique of reason was rooted in
the belief that it led to the unquenchable
desires of individuals, making them perpetually
unhappy. The more one embraced reason, the
more their desires multiplied, creating a cycle
of discontentment.
“Rousseau observed that although life was
peaceful in the state of nature, People were
unfulfilled” – Edward W. Younkins
The Emergence of Private
Property
The advent of civilization, marked by the
discovery of metals and agriculture, brought
about the division of labor and the rise of
private property. He asserts that the cultivation
of land resulted in property claims, famously
remarking, “The first man who after felling off a
piece of land, took it upon himself to say ‘This
belongs to me,’ and found people simple-
minded enough to believe him, was the true
founder of civil society.” With the concept of
property came inequality, as differences in
talents and skills led to varied fortunes. Wealth
enabled some individuals to enslave others,
provoking
competition and conflict. This conflict created a
demand for a legal system to maintain order,
particularly from the wealthy, who feared losing
their possessions in a state of violence.
According to Rousseau, this demand resulted
in the formation of civil society and laws that
imposed new constraints on the poor while
empowering the rich. He claimed that these
developments destroyed natural liberty,
established laws of property and inequality,
and transformed wrongful usurpation into
accepted rights, subjecting humanity to labor,
servitude, and misery for the benefit of a few
ambitious individuals.
Rousseau argued, however, that things need
not have turned out so poorly. He suggested
that when men willingly entered chains with the
establishment of government, it was because
they recognized the advantages of political
institutions without the experience to foresee
their potential dangers. This idea would be
revisited in his later work, Social Contract. It is
crucial to note that Rousseau did not depict the
transition from the state of nature to civil
society as a historical fact; rather, he employed
hypothetical reasoning to explore the nature of
humanity and society, rather than ascertain
their actual origins.
Analyzing Inequality
Rousseau’s analysis of inequality was rooted in
the stark contrast between the natural state of
individuals—pure, good, and roughly equal to
one another—and their corrupted, unequal,
and degraded state within society. He
classified inequality into two types – Natural
inequality (Based on birth,
skills, talent, age, sex etc) and Conventional
equality (Constructed by society primarily with
the advent of private property).
He further advocated for social equality,
although not absolute equality, permitting
distinctions based on contributions to society
and natural factors like age and wealth.
Concept of “General Will”
Rousseau posited that the General Will should
serve as the foundation for all laws, with its
embodiment realized through direct
democracy. He distinguished between
the actual will, driven by immediate self-
interest, and the real will, which is motivated
by the collective good. The General Will
functions as a unifying force, aligning individual
interests with those of the community, thereby
crucial for achieving social and political
equality.
He emphasized that the General Will must
genuinely originate from and focus on the
common good, ensuring that decisions involve
every member of society. Rousseau viewed
economic equality as essential for preserving
individual liberty and attaining true social and
political equality.
However, critics have described Rousseau’s
concept of the General Will as “forced to be
free.” Scholar Jacob Talmon labeled
Rousseau a “totalitarian
democrat,” while Bosanke argued that
Rousseau’s theory misleads readers by
establishing sovereignty on an uncertain
foundation. By making the General Will
sovereign and viewing individuals as
participants in it, Rousseau reconciled authority
with freedom more effectively than his
predecessors.
In his Discourse on Political Economy,
Rousseau stated that the General Will aims
for the preservation and welfare of both the
whole and each part, serving as the source of
laws. He differentiated it from the “will of all,”
which merely aggregates private interests. The
General Will is not merely a numerical majority
but reflects moral quality and goodness,
emerging when individuals sacrifice personal
interests for the collective good.
Rousseau recognized that unanimity on the
General Will may not always be possible, as
individuals might not fully understand the
common good. He suggested that if one
removes conflicting particular interests from
individual wills, what remains is the General
Will.
Moreover, he asserted that those who refuse to
obey the General Will would be “forced to be
free.” This compulsion is justified, he argued,
because individuals have already consented to
be governed by the social contract, which
promotes their long-term interests. In essence,
obeying the General Will reflects an individual’s
moral freedom, representing rational self-
governance that aligns with the common good.
Thus, when the General Will prevails,
individuals should not perceive it as a loss of
liberty but as adherence to their rational self.
The Social Contract Theory
In his influential work, The Social Contract,
Rousseau proposed that a political community
should protect the general interests of its
members while transforming the noble savage
into a cooperative and humane member of
society. He asserted that liberty is the most
cherished
possession of individuals, and the right kind of
society could enhance this freedom by
governing through what he called the “General
Will.”
For Rousseau, the social contract was a
method to reconcile liberty with authority,
where consent served as the foundational
principle. He emphasized that a community
exists to serve the individual by safeguarding
their freedom. This community reflects the
collective best interests of all its members,
operating in harmony with the General Will,
which represents the shared will of individuals
thinking beyond their self-interests.
While Rousseau criticized ‘civil society’, he did
not advocate for a return to a savage
existence, as some of his contemporaries
misinterpreted him. For instance, Voltaire
mocked Rousseau’s ideas, suggesting he
wanted people to revert to walking on all fours.
In the Discourse, Rousseau exclaimed, “What
then is to be done? Must societies be totally
abolished? Must meum and tuum be
annihilated, and must we return again to the
forests to live among bears? This is a
deduction in the manner of my adversaries,
which I would as soon anticipate and let them
have the shame of drawing.”
Rousseau believed there was no going back to
the state of nature. He argued that society is
inevitable; without it, humanity could not fulfill
its potential. His critique of civil society was
rooted in its unjust foundations and corrupting
influences. Therefore, he aimed to create a
new social order that would enable individuals
to realize their true nature.
To this end, Rousseau dedicated himself
in The Social Contract. He sought to address
the issue of political
obligation, asking why individuals should obey
the state through a proper reconciliation of
authority and freedom. He felt that previous
philosophers had inadequately tackled this
critical task. The Social Contract opens with
the powerful declaration, “Man is born free, and
he is everywhere in chains.” Rousseau’s goal
was to legitimize the chains of society,
contrasting them with the illegitimate chains of
contemporary governance.
Rousseau’s theoretical challenge was to find a
form of association capable of defending and
protecting each individual’s person and
property while ensuring that each person, in
uniting with all, could still obey themselves and
remain as free as before through a social
contract. This contract requires “the total
alienation of each associate, together with all
his rights, to the whole community.” Each
individual gives themselves to all, thereby
giving themselves to no one in particular. As
Rousseau explains, “As there is no associate
over whom he does not acquire the same right
as he yields over himself, he gains an
equivalent for everything he loses, and an
increase of force for the preservation of what
he has.”
In essence, participants in the social contract
agree to place their person and all their power
at the common use, under the supreme
direction of the General Will, with each
member being viewed as an indivisible part of
the whole. As a result, the private individual
ceases to exist; the contract generates a moral
and collective body that gains its unity,
common identity, life, and will from this act.
This public person formed from the union of all
individual members becomes the State when
passive, the Sovereign when active, and a
Power when
compared with similar institutions.
After establishing a state, Rousseau envisions
a significant transformation in human beings.
This transformation replaces instinct with a rule
of justice, bestowing a moral character to
actions that were previously lacking. He goes
so far as to say that humanity evolves from a
“stupid and limited animal” into an intelligent
being.
However, Rousseau acknowledges that this
transformation would be implausible if the
contract were viewed as a singular event.
Instead, he posits that the social contract
represents a way of thinking, indicating that it is
a process rather than an isolated occurrence.
Consequently, the evolution of human nature
occurs gradually alongside the deepening of
social relationships, fueled by ongoing
participation in the General Will. This
perspective presents a vision of humanity
whose moral sensibilities and intellectual
capacities evolve in tandem with the expanding
nature of their social interactions.
Popular Sovereignty
Rousseau introduced the radical concept of
Popular Sovereignty, significantly shaping
modern political thought. For him, sovereignty
resided not in a distant monarchy but directly
within the political community. He synthesized
John Locke’s idea of popular government and
Thomas Hobbes’ notion of absolute
sovereignty to formulate his concept of Popular
Sovereignty.
Rousseau asserted that sovereignty originates
from the people themselves, not as a gift from
natural or divine laws, but as an organized
power derived from the collective will.
This supreme authority empowers the people
to determine right from wrong, making them
responsible for lawmaking, enforcement, and
adjudication. He referred to this as cosmic
sovereignty.
Rousseau famously stated, “the moment
there is a master, there is no longer a
sovereign,” illustrating his departure from
Hobbes and Locke. In Hobbes’s view, people
create a sovereign and relinquish their powers
to him, while Locke’s social contract
establishes a limited government for specific
purposes but avoids equating sovereignty—
whether popular or monarchical—with political
absolutism. In contrast, Rousseau’s
sovereign is the people, formed into a
political community through the social contract.
Unique among political thinkers, Rousseau
regarded the sovereignty of the people as
inalienable and indivisible, asserting that they
cannot transfer their ultimate right to self-
governance. Unlike Hobbes, who proposed a
ruler as sovereign, Rousseau maintained a
clear distinction between sovereignty, which
resides entirely with the people, and
government, a temporary agent of that
sovereignty.
Rousseau also emphasized that since the
sovereignty of the General Will is inalienable
and indivisible, it cannot be represented or
delegated. He criticized representative
assemblies for developing their own particular
interests, thus forgetting the community’s
needs. This is why he favored direct
democracies, such as those in Swiss city-
republics, despite their anachronism during the
rise of modern nation-states. He insisted that
any attempt to delegate the General Will
signifies its end, famously stating, “the moment
there is a master, there is no longer a
sovereign.” For Rousseau,
the “voice of the people” embodies the
“voice of God,” emphasizing the profound
connection between popular will and moral
authority.
Challenging Representative
Government: The Call for
Direct Democracy
Rousseau’s critique extended to the prevalent
systems of government in his time, particularly
the English Parliamentary System. He argued
that these systems offered a mere illusion of
freedom. In reality, people were only free
during elections, and once they elected their
representatives, their freedom dwindled.
Rousseau advocated for a more direct form of
democracy where people actively participated
in the decision-making process.
He championed participatory democracy, a
system that not only secured individual
freedom but also promoted self-rule, equality,
and virtue. In his view, true democracy required
the active involvement of citizens in shaping
the laws that governed them.
Rousseau’s views on Family
and Women
Rousseau, like Aristotle, considered the family
as the fundamental unit of society. He
defended the patriarchal family structure,
seeing it as a natural institution grounded in
love, affection, and the inherent differences
between the sexes. However, his stance on
women in society mirrored the prevailing views
of his time. Rousseau assigned a
subordinate position to women, both in the
family and society at large, with male authority
prevailing.
Rousseau believed that women should be
represented by men in a liberal democracy,
and he discouraged their participation
in politics. His rationale stemmed from a fear
that women would prioritize the interests of
their families over the public good, unable to
transcend their love and affection for the
particular to embrace the general.
Critical Appreciation
Rousseau’s philosophical journey reveals a
fundamental logical divide between his earlier
work, Discourse on Equality, and his later
work, The Social Contract. Vaughan notes that
while the former is characterized by
“defiant individualism,” the latter embraces
“equally defiant collectivism.” However,
Rousseau himself did not perceive this
opposition; in his Confessions, he asserts that
the strong ideas in The Social Contract were
previously articulated in Discourse on Equality.
Sabille supports Rousseau’s viewpoint, yet
acknowledges the presence of seemingly
contradictory ideas in his writings.
The distinction between the two works lies in
Rousseau’s transition from freeing himself from
systematic individualism to formulating a
counter-philosophy. Systematic individualism,
as criticized by Rousseau, posits that humans
are moral and rational beings motivated by
enlightened self-interest, leading to the
creation of a community primarily for the
protection of rights and promotion of
happiness. Rousseau contended that this
framework did not align with human nature. He
argued that attributes such as rationality
and self-interest are acquired through societal
living rather than being inherent traits.
Rousseau challenged the notion that reason
alone could unify individuals focused solely on
their happiness, emphasizing that self-interest
is as socially constructed as the innate social
needs that bring people together. He posited
that human sociability is based on feelings, not
reason. In his analysis, he rejected Hobbes
and Locke’s views of the state of nature,
asserting that the Hobbesian portrayal of man
as a natural egoist is a fiction.
Drawing insights from classical Greek thought,
Rousseau emphasized that individuals achieve
their true nature only within a community,
where rights, freedom, and morality are
cultivated. He maintained that the community
serves as the primary moral agent and
stressed the necessity for collective thinking
about public good rather than individual
interests.
Rousseau’s concept of the General Will aims
to reconcile authority and freedom, but it
inadvertently lends itself to totalitarian
interpretations. Critics argue that his theory
could justify coercive governance, with Sabine
highlighting that dissenting moral views might
be seen as capricious and suppressed.
Despite criticisms, Rousseau’s significance
endures. Ebenstein points out that he was
the first modern thinker to attempt to
synthesize good governance with self-
governance through the General
Will. Furthermore, he highlighted that
government must not only protect individual
liberties but also promote equality. Rousseau’s
reflections on civil society’s limitations resonate
today, urging vigilance against executive
overreach and the need for moral integrity
in governance.
Famous Quotes by
Rousseau
129. ‘Man is born free and everywhere is in
chains’.
130. ‘I prefer liberty with danger than peace
with slavery’.
131. ‘I would rather be a man of paradoxes than
a man of prejudices’.
132. ‘No man has any natural authority over his
fellow men’.
133. ‘Our greatest evil flows from ourselves’.
134. ‘Everyman has a right to risk his own life
for the preservation of it’.
135. ‘What wisdom can you find that is greater
than kindness’.
136. ‘The moment there is a master, there is no
longer a sovereign’.
137. ‘Voice of the People may be the voice of
the god’.
138. ‘The larger the state, the less the liberty’.
139. ‘The strongest is never strong enough to
always be the master, unless he transforms
strength into right, and obedience into duty’.
Conclusion: Rousseau’s
Vision of a Just Society
In conclusion, Rousseau’s political philosophy
envisioned a moral and just society, one that
prioritized the welfare of all individuals. He
sought to transform human nature from a
narrow, self-seeking state into a public-spirited
one. His writings challenged the modern
institutions of his time, exposing their
shortcomings in delivering on promises of
democracy, liberty, and equality.
Rousseau‘s state represented the pinnacle of
human existence, a source of morality,
freedom, and community that not only resolved
conflicts but also liberated the individual. He
emphasized the close relationship between
liberty and equality, arguing that without
equality, true liberty could not exist. His
philosophy aimed to reconcile individual
interests with the broader interests of society,
promoting a harmonious coexistence.
Yet, Rousseau’s ideas were not without
paradoxes. He championed the inalienable
right to freedom while acknowledging that
individuals could be forced to be free. He
considered reason unnatural and artificial but
recognized that without it, moral development
was impossible. These paradoxes underscore
the complexity of Rousseau’s thought and its
enduring influence on political theory and the
quest for a just society.
Read More:
J.S Mill: The Philosopher
of Liberty and
Representative
Government
By:Politicalsciencesolution.Com
Date:
24 September 2023
John Stuart Mill was a 19th-century
philosopher and economist known for his
influential writings on individual liberty,
utilitarian ethics, and the potential dangers of
majority tyranny in democratic societies. His
ideas continue to shape modern political and
ethical discourse.
J.S Mill (1806 – 1873)
Introduction
John Stuart Mill, one of the most influential
philosophers and economists of the 19th
century, was a key figure in the development of
utilitarianism and liberalism. Born on May 20,
1806, in London, he was the eldest son of the
historian and philosopher James Mill. Unlike
many of his contemporaries, Mill’s education
was unconventional; he was privately tutored
by his father and the utilitarian thinker Jeremy
Bentham, bypassing formal schooling
altogether. This unique upbringing significantly
shaped Mill’s intellectual outlook, embedding
within him the principles of utilitarianism
and rationalism from a young age.
Utilitarianism, with its economic
foundations rooted in Adam Smith’s The
Wealth of Nations (1776), was politically
developed by Bentham, who applied a
rationalistic approach to societal issues.
Bentham harbored a deep suspicion of the
“sinister interests” of those in power and
advocated for reforms like annual elections,
secret ballots, and recall mechanisms to
protect public interest. He famously
declared, “pushpin is as good as
poetry,” suggesting that all pleasures are of
equal value and can be measured
quantitatively.
Mill, however, found this perspective
unsatisfactory. Despite being Bentham’s most
notable pupil, Mill later critiqued his mentor’s
simplistic view of pleasure, admitting he
was “Peter who denied his master.” Drawing
inspiration from romantic poets like
Wordsworth, Mill attempted to synthesize
rationalism with romanticism, thereby
transforming Benthamite utilitarianism. He
introduced the idea that not all pleasures are of
equal value, arguing that “it is better to be a
human being dissatisfied than a pig
satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied
than a fool satisfied.”
In addition to his reformation of utilitarian
thought, Mill made lasting contributions
to liberalism. He is widely recognized for his
robust defense of freedom of speech and
individuality, as well as his belief that a liberal
society is a necessary foundation for a
liberal state. Mill’s writings on these subjects,
particularly in his work On Liberty, have left an
enduring legacy in political theory, positioning
him as a crucial advocate for individual rights
and freedoms in modern democratic societies.
Table of Contents
140. Introduction
141. Early Years and Career
142. Major Works by J.S Mill
143. An Equal Freedom for Women
144. Concept of Liberty by J.S Mill
145. Concept of Liberty
146. Critique of Utilitarianism
147. Democracy and Representative
Government
148. Economy and State Intervention by J.S Mill
149. Economy and State Intervention
Early Years and Career
John Stuart Mill, born in London on May 20,
1806, was the eldest of nine children. His
education was entirely orchestrated by his
father, James Mill, a historian and philosopher.
John Stuart Mill’s formative years were
characterized by an intensive intellectual
regimen, focusing on the same books his
father used for his own writing, such as The
History of British India (1818). By the age of
eleven, Mill was already assisting his father by
proofreading his works, and by fourteen, he
published Elements of Political
Economy (1820), an introductory textbook on
economics, marking his early immersion in the
subject.
James Mill’s appointment as Assistant
Examiner at the East India House in 1819
provided the family with financial stability and
allowed him to focus on his philosophical
pursuits. In 1823, John Stuart Mill secured a
position as Assistant Examiner in the British
East India Company, where he worked for
nearly three decades until his retirement.
Mill’s education was unconventional. Denied a
formal school experience, he learned Greek at
the age of four and Latin by eight. By ten, he
had read Plato’s dialogues and was familiar
with works by Euripides, Homer, Sophocles,
and Thucydides. His education extended to
higher mathematics, including algebra,
geometry, and calculus. Mill’s upbringing under
the strict guidance of his father left him with
little recollection of his mother’s role in his early
life. In his Autobiography (written in the
1850s), Mill acknowledged that his intense
education deprived him of a normal childhood,
though it deeply shaped his intellectual
abilities.
Mill’s intellectual growth continued as he
explored the works of thinkers like Thomas
Carlyle, Samuel Taylor Coleridge, Auguste
Comte, Goethe, and Wordsworth. The poetry
of Wordsworth and Coleridge had a profound
impact on Mill, especially after a “mental crisis”
in 1826, where he struggled with severe
depression. Romantic poetry helped him
recover, broadening his perspective and
allowing him to integrate emotion and
imagination into his previously rationalist
worldview.
Mill’s political writings gained prominence in his
twenties as he contributed to newspapers and
periodicals. His System of Logic (1843),
which he began writing in the 1820s, was a
groundbreaking work that combined British
empiricism with a Newtonian approach to
social sciences. His essays On Liberty (1859)
and The Subjection of Women (1869), co-
authored with his wife Harriet Taylor, became
classics in the defense of individual rights,
freedom of speech, and gender equality.
Mill’s reexamination of Jeremy Bentham’s
utilitarianism
marked a significant shift in his thought. While
Bentham’s “greatest happiness principle”
quantified pleasure and pain equally, Mill
introduced a qualitative distinction, famously
stating, “it is better to be Socrates dissatisfied
than a fool satisfied.” This critique was further
explored in his pamphlet Utilitarianism (1863),
where he argued that happiness could only be
defended if distinguished from mere pleasure.
Mill’s relationship with Harriet Taylor, whom he
met in 1830 and married in 1851, was a major
influence on his work. Harriet contributed
significantly to his writings on liberty and
women’s rights. Mill described her as the
“honor and chief blessing” of his life,
believing that had she lived in an era with
greater opportunities for women, she would
have been “eminent among the rulers of
mankind.”
John Stuart Mill died in 1873 in Avignon,
France, leaving behind an enduring legacy in
philosophy, political theory, and social reform.
Major Works by J.S Mill
Mill’s major works are a testament to his
profound impact on philosophy and politics:
150. A System Of Logic (1843)
151. Principles Of Political Economy (1848)
152. On Liberty (1859)
153. Considerations On Representative
Government (1861)
154. Utilitarianism (1863)
155. The Subjection Of Women (1869)
Note – Philosophy of J.S Mill – R.P Anschertz
An Equal Freedom for
Women by J.S
Mill
In The Subjection of Women (1869), John
Stuart Mill opens with a radical assertion: “the
principle which regulates the existing social
relations between the two sexes—the legal
subordination of one sex to the other—is wrong
in itself, and now one of the chief hindrances to
human improvement; and… it ought to be
replaced by a principle of perfect equality” (p.
119). Mill’s criticism was directed at 19th-
century English law, particularly the marriage
contract, which legally subordinated women to
men. Married women could not hold property in
their names; any property or income they
earned automatically belonged to their
husbands. Even if gifted property by their
parents, it was transferred to their husbands
upon marriage. Moreover, fathers were the
sole legal guardians of children, and no laws
addressed marital rape, underscoring women’s
lack of rights.
Mill was struck by the inconsistency of modern
society, which had embraced liberty and
equality in many domains but still denied these
principles to women. While slavery had been
abolished, women were still often treated
worse than slaves. Mill explained this
persistence by asserting that all men, unlike
slaveholders and despots, had a vested
interest in maintaining women’s subordination.
Mill refuted four main arguments for women’s
inequality:
156. Universal Tradition: The first argument
was that women’s subordination had been
universal across history, implying its
justification. Mill countered by stating that
universal acceptance did not make a practice
just. He pointed to slavery, once universally
accepted, which had been abolished, arguing
that women’s subordination could similarly be
overcome.
157. Natural Inferiority: The second argument
claimed that women were naturally inferior to
men. Mill rejected this, asserting that
differences between the sexes were due to
socialization, not nature. He noted examples of
accomplished women, such as European
queens and Hindu princesses, who excelled
despite societal limitations.
158. Voluntary Acceptance: The third
argument was that women accepted their
subordination willingly. Mill demonstrated that
this was false, as many women had written
against inequality and were already protesting
for their rights in London. He argued that
women feared worse treatment if they resisted
their husbands’ control, hence their silence.
159. Family Leadership: The final argument
held that for families to function smoothly, a
single decision-maker was necessary, and that
role naturally fell to the husband. Mill dismissed
this, asserting that both husband and wife were
adults capable of shared decision-making.
Mill further argued that granting women
equality would benefit society in four ways.
First, it would abolish the patriarchal family, a
“school of despotism” that taught inequality.
Second, it would “double the mass of mental
faculties” available to society by unleashing
women’s intellectual potential.
Third, equality would improve relationships, as
women would
no longer assert their wills through subversive
means.
Finally, it would increase happiness for
women, aligning with Mill’s utilitarian belief in
promoting the greatest happiness for the
greatest number.
Mill also emphasized that democracy itself
would remain fragile unless egalitarian families
were established, linking private life with public
democratic citizenship. His critique of the
patriarchal family remains central to feminist
discussions today, though some feminists
argue that modern capitalism reinforces, rather
than eliminates, patriarchal structures.
Concept of Liberty by J.S
Mill
John Stuart Mill’s On Liberty (1859) is a
powerful defense of individual liberty, arguing
that personal freedoms are essential for the
intellectual, moral, and material advancement
of human beings. Mill emphasized the
importance of liberty in nurturing mental and
moral faculties such as perception, judgment,
decision-making, and self-control. These
faculties, he argued, develop only when people
are free to make their own choices. He said,
“The human faculties of perception, judgment,
discriminative feeling, mental activity, and even
moral preference, are exercised only in making
a choice… the mental and moral, like the
muscular powers, are improved only by being
used.”
Mill advocated for three specific liberties:
160. Liberty of Thought and Expression: Mill
argued that freedom of thought and expression
is fundamental for the progress of society. He
stated that if all of humanity but one person
held the same opinion, silencing that one
person would be unjust. He declared, “If all
mankind
minus one were of one opinion, mankind
would be no more justified in silencing that
one person than he, if he had the power,
would be justified in silencing
mankind.” Mill further emphasized the
importance of this freedom by
stating, “Placing restrictions on freedom of
expression of human beings is like robbing
off the present and the future races.” For
Mill, even if a minority opinion is wrong,
allowing it to be expressed ensures that the
truth of the majority opinion is not taken for
granted and becomes a “living truth” rather
than a “dead dogma.”
161. Liberty of Action: Mill introduced
the “Harm Principle” to define the limits of
personal freedom. He stated, “The only
purpose for which power can be rightfully
exercised over any member of a civilized
community, against his will, is to prevent
harm to others.” Mill believed that individuals
should have complete control over their own
actions and choices, so long as they do not
harm others. He noted, “Over himself, over
his own body and mind, the individual is
sovereign.” Mill also discussed the difficulty of
distinguishing between self-regarding and
other-regarding actions, using examples like
property destruction to explain that some
actions, while appearing personal, can
indirectly harm others.
162. Liberty of Association: Mill argued that
individuals should have the right to associate
freely, forming groups to pursue common
interests. He believed that association
contributed to personal and social
development. Mill wrote, “When the thing to be
done is likely to be done better by individuals
than by the
government… allowing individuals to get
together to do something, even if they do not
do it as well as the government might have
done it, is better for their mental education.”
Mill warned that liberties are often more under
threat in democratic societies than in despotic
regimes. In democracies, where people feel
less threatened by their own government, they
can become complacent, making it easier for
social pressures and customs to erode
individual freedoms. He argued that individuals
must remain vigilant not only against
government oppression but also against
societal norms that could stifle personal liberty.
He concluded, “The only unfailing and
permanent source of improvement is
liberty, since by it there are as many
possible independent centers of
improvement as there are individuals.”
Mill’s belief in individual liberty was rooted in
the idea that human improvement is achieved
through freedom, and a society that promotes
liberty fosters continuous moral, intellectual,
and material progress.
Critique of Utilitarianism by
J.S Mill
John Stuart Mill consistently identified himself
as a utilitarian, despite the evolution of his
principles. Even when discussing concepts like
rights, Mill subsumed them under the broader
framework of utility. He defined rights as
extremely important utilities, emphasizing that
his utilitarian foundation remained intact. Mill’s
upbringing under his father, James Mill, a close
associate of Jeremy Bentham (the founder of
utilitarianism), deeply influenced his intellectual
formation. Although Mill faced an emotional
crisis in his early twenties, he continued to
defend utilitarianism in his work, always
applying the standard of utility in his
arguments. For example, he believed that
granting equality to women would increase
overall happiness. Similarly, he defended
liberty on the grounds that it promoted social
utility, and he supported a modified liberal
democracy because it proved useful for social
progress.
Mill’s key text Utilitarianism (1862) was written
to address criticisms of the philosophy. He
opened by pointing out that moral philosophers
had long disagreed on the criteria for
differentiating right from wrong. Rejecting the
idea that humans have a natural moral sense
—similar to physical senses like sight or smell
—that can intuitively detect right actions, Mill
proposed utility, or the Greatest Happiness
Principle, as the true foundation of morality.
This principle dictates that an action is moral if
it increases pleasure and reduces pain.
A notable divergence from Bentham’s
utilitarianism was Mill’s emphasis on the
quality, not just the quantity, of pleasure. While
Bentham had viewed all pleasures as
essentially equal and calculable, Mill argued
that certain pleasures were qualitatively
superior to others. He famously stated that it
is “better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a
pig satisfied,” indicating that higher
intellectual and moral pleasures should be
valued above base physical pleasures. This
marks a significant shift in the philosophy, with
Mill asserting that some forms of happiness
carry more weight because of their intrinsic
quality.
One major criticism of utilitarianism is that it
assumes
humans act purely from self-interest, akin to
animals seeking pleasure. Mill responded by
highlighting the “social feelings of
mankind”—the natural human desire for unity
with others, which he believed was a powerful
aspect of human nature. According to Mill,
people inherently care about the happiness of
others because the “social state” is natural,
necessary, and habitual for humanity. This led
Mill to argue that an interest in others’
happiness was not a forced or artificial
condition but an organic aspect of human life.
The most significant objection Mill faced was
the idea that justice, rather than utility, should
be the foundation of morality. In response, Mill
linked justice to rights. He argued that injustice
occurs when someone’s rights are violated, but
crucially, these rights themselves are justified
through utility. For Mill, rights are valuable
because they serve a social purpose: they
allow individuals to enjoy a secure and
progressive society. He concluded that society
should defend rights not because of an
inherent moral sense but because doing so
benefits the general utility. As Mill
explained, “To have a right is to have
something which society ought to defend
me in the possession of,” and society should
defend rights purely because of their utility.
Mill took issue with some aspects of Bentham’s
original utilitarianism, which he felt overlooked
the importance of individual character and
moral motives. In response, he modified
utilitarianism to include a sense of universal
altruism, empathy, and impartial justice. For
Mill, the ultimate goal of life was not merely the
pursuit of pleasure but a more nuanced
happiness that included moral virtues, self-
control, and the balance of individual and
collective interests. Mill
also rejected the idea of Bentham’s “felicific
calculus”—the notion that pleasures and
pains could be objectively measured and
compared. He considered this approach overly
simplistic and impractical.
In his writings, Mill maintained the utilitarian
creed while modifying it to address its
shortcomings. He incorporated elements of
morality, social feelings, and justice into his
framework, defending rights and liberty based
on their utility. For Mill, happiness was more
than just pleasure—it was the perfection of
human nature and moral virtue, making him a
pivotal figure in the development of a more
sophisticated utilitarian philosophy.
Democracy and
Representative
Government by J.S Mill
John Stuart Mill began his work Considerations
on Representative Government by asserting
that the best form of government is one that
most effectively fulfills its purposes. According
to Mill, the government must serve two
primary functions: utilizing the citizens’
talents and skills to serve their interests and
improving their moral, intellectual, and active
qualities. A despotic government may achieve
the first function, but it would fail at the second.
Only a representative government can achieve
both, by combining the principles of
participation and competence to protect and
educate its citizens.
Mill introduced Bentham’s idea of “sinister
interests” to explain how representative
government could ensure the common interest
of society is advanced rather than the partial
interest of a group or class. He believed that all
individuals, including different social classes,
are the best judges of their own interests. Mill
dismissed the idea that people may not
understand their “real” interests, asserting that
their current habits and choices reflect their
actual interests. Therefore, participation in
government should be as widespread as
possible, extending to all individuals, including
women. He advocated for suffrage to everyone
except those who could not read or write, didn’t
pay taxes, or were reliant on parish relief.
To ensure minorities were also represented,
Mill supported Thomas Hare’s system of
proportional representation. While Mill
championed widespread participation, he also
believed in competence, advocating for plural
voting. He argued that the franchise should be
extended, but with educated citizens receiving
additional votes to ensure better-caliber
representatives. For example, professionals
and university graduates would receive
more votes based on a “graduated scale of
educational attainment.”
Mill sought to combine participation and
competence in other democratic institutions,
such as the representative assembly. He
envisioned it as a “committee of grievances”
and a “congress of opinions,” where every view
in society would be voiced. However, he
argued that this body should not handle
legislation or administration, which required the
expertise of a Codification Commission and a
competent bureaucracy. Mill differentiated
between instrumental competence—the ability
to find the best means to fulfill given goals—
and moral competence, which involved
recognizing the general interest over partial
interests.
On the issue of improving citizens, Mill
believed that
representative government was superior to
despotism because it elevated the intellectual
and moral qualities of the citizens. He
advocated for open voting, where voters must
justify their choices publicly, fostering
intellectual and moral growth. Participation in
local government and voting would help
citizens develop their capabilities, but this
participation needed to be guided by
competence to have an educational effect.
Mill also warned that civil liberties could be at
risk in democratic regimes unless citizens
remained vigilant, but he still considered
democracy the most favorable form of
governance. However, Mill argued that
representative government could only work in
active, self-reliant societies; passive citizens in
backward civilizations could not sustain it. He
believed that democracy required plural voting
to balance the majority and ensure that
educated individuals had more influence. His
famous quote, “Liberty cannot be utilized
properly if people are not educated
enough,” emphasized the importance of
education in a functioning democracy.
He further quoted that “No one but a fool and
only a fool of a peculiar description, feels
offended by the acknowledgement that there
are others whose opinion and even whose
wish is entitled to greater amount of
consideration than this”.
As Mill supported democracy, critics like
Wayper called him a “reluctant democrat,”
while Ernest Barker regarded “Mill as
prophet of an empty liberty and an abstract
individual” because of his double standards of
liberty where he gives more consideration to
people who are more educated and restricts
the essence of actual liberty that
every individual deserves irrespectively.
Tyranny of Majority
Mill’s perspective on safeguarding individual
liberty is broad, as he does not solely rely on
popular sovereignty for protection against
threats to human freedom. Instead, he aligns
himself with thinkers like Benjamin Constant
and Alexis de Tocqueville, sharing the view that
the tyranny of the majority poses a significant
danger in an era of popular governance. Mill’s
concern about potential encroachments on
individual liberty extends beyond the idea that
popular rule alone is sufficient for safeguarding
human freedom.
He further provides a view that due to this
popular government there are three potential
threats to minorities – State, Mass society and
Populism. These threats can undermine the
interests of minorities. Mill was worried that the
influence of public opinion has the potential to
suppress individuality, and he sees these
informal societal pressures as a type of
coercion. He believes that the dominance of
public opinion can be just as detrimental to
human freedom as the imposition of legal
constraints.
Economy and State
Intervention by J.S Mill
When did not represent the classical economic
theory of laissez faire he advocated that some
areas of interference should be there. He
preferred laissez-faire to state intervention in
matters of social and economic policy. Even
though the idea of laissez faire is ideal, it could
be set aside for welfare works like education
and child care etc. He
believed that the state must ensure that no one
is starving. He further quoted “Political liberty in
absence of economic liberty is a myth”.
Mill viewed the State as a moral institution with
a primary concern for promoting virtue and
excellence in individuals’ lives. He stressed
that the concept of a good life was more crucial
than a life solely devoted to pursuing pleasure.
“State is the moral institution with a moral end”.
But at the same time the state should not
interfere in the affairs of individuals.
Wayper contended that J.S Mill shows a good
deal of sympathy for socialism and wishes to
use the state to remove obstacles in the way of
individual development.
Conclusion
John Stuart Mill‘s liberalism provided the first
major framework for modern democratic
equality, particularly in his advocacy for
women’s rights. He sought to end the
subjugation of women, becoming the first male
philosopher, as noted by Okihiro, to explicitly
address women’s oppression. As a Member
of Parliament, Mill campaigned for women’s
suffrage but was disappointed when it did
not pass. He also emphasized protecting
individual liberty from societal intrusion,
distinguishing between self-regarding actions,
which belong to the private sphere, and other-
regarding actions, related to the public domain.
This distinction was crucial in safeguarding
minority rights within a democracy.
Mill recognized the flaws of classical
utilitarianism, advocating for compulsory state
education and social control to address them.
He understood that his views
differed from Bentham’s utilitarianism and
described himself as a socialist. Mill envisioned
a future where individual liberty was balanced
with collective ownership of resources and
equitable distribution of labor’s benefits. In
his Autobiography, he reflected on this shift: “I
was a democrat, but not least of a
socialist.” He believed the social problem of
the future lay in uniting individual freedom with
common ownership, questioning the
compatibility of capitalism and democracy.
Mill’s revision of liberalism laid the groundwork
for thinkers like T.H. Green, who incorporated
the idea of a common good into liberal
philosophy. His works, including “On Liberty”
and “Utilitarianism,” remain influential, shaping
discussions on individual freedom, the role of
the state, and the balance between personal
liberty and collective welfare.
Read More:
WESTERN POLITICAL THOUGHTCLASS
STRUGGLEMARXISM
Karl Marx: Class Struggle,
Historical Materialism and
Communism
By:Politicalsciencesolution.Com
Date:
26 September 2023
Karl Marx, a 19th-century philosopher and
economist, revolutionized political thought with
his critique of capitalism and advocacy for a
classless society. His ideas continue to
influence social and economic discourse to this
day.