Craig Duncan, Tibor R. Machan, Martha Nussbaum - Libertarianism - For and Against-Rowman & Littlefield (2005)
Craig Duncan, Tibor R. Machan, Martha Nussbaum - Libertarianism - For and Against-Rowman & Littlefield (2005)
LIBERTARIANISM
For and Against
PO Box 317
Oxford
OX2 9RU, UK
JC585.D83 2005
320.51'2—dc22 2004027526
Foreword ix
Martha C. Nussbaum
Acknowledgments xv
A Note to Readers xvii
Tibor R. Machan and Craig Duncan
PART I
vii
viii / Contents
PART II
ix
x / Foreword
action. If the police, the fire department, the legal system, and
the military do not do their jobs, nobody is particularly free. But
beyond this point there is great disagreement. People disagree
about taxation—who has a right to what, and what is a reason-
able tax structure. They differ about anti-discrimination laws,
libertarians typically holding that they are a bad thing but
many other Americans holding that they are essential to a soci-
ety that values racial justice, gender justice, and justice for peo-
ple with disabilities. They differ about environmental
protection, some holding that industry should be free to make
any choice that seems profitable, others holding that state pro-
tection of the environment contributes to the well-being of all.
Both sides ought to agree, however, that the choices we
make in this matter are complex. There is no option of simply
“letting” everyone be “free” through “state inaction.” If one
lives (as I have for periods of time, in rural India) in a place that
has no clean water supply, no electricity, no public transporta-
tion, no public education, and no reliable legal system, one will
discover that one is not very free there to do the things one
wants to do. We should all agree that any meaningful human
freedom requires the state to provide some essential services
and guarantees. Moreover, in a rich nation such as the United
States, the choice to leave these matters unattended to is not in-
action but a choice; it is action. The differences between sides
must concern the extent and the nature of various state protec-
tions, and the nature of the actions the state should choose.
The debates that typically go on over such matters in
American politics are hasty and strident. They employ “sound
bites” and slogans rather than reasoned arguments. But de-
mocracy requires something better of us all—it requires that
we really think through our choices and stand for what we can
defend with good arguments. To make good arguments, we
also need to listen to the arguments of others. Often two sides
in a debate share important assumptions, and progress can be
made simply by setting out the argument in detail and finding
out where the differences really are. There has been a long tra-
Foreword / xiii
Note
1. The only nations that rank ahead of the United States in the data of the
2004 Human Development Report are Norway, Ireland, and Luxembourg.
Acknowledgments
Craig Duncan would first like to thank Tibor Machan for be-
ing such a civil and amiable debate partner, despite the depth
of disagreement between us. Thanks are due too to the editors
of the Philosophers’ Magazine for publishing the “Open De-
bate” on libertarianism (First and Third Quarters 2003) out of
which this project grew. Special thanks go as well to Peter
Bardaglio, provost of Ithaca College, for arranging (with very
short notice) a faculty summer research grant, which was cru-
cial to the completion of this project. After a draft of my chap-
ters was completed, the comments of my colleagues Stephen
Schwartz, Frederick Kaufman, and Sean McKeever led to
many improvements and were much appreciated. Finally, I
am grateful to my wife Trena Haffenden, whose support sus-
tains me, and to our children Joseph and Beth, who have
taught me as much about responsibility as I have them.
Tibor Machan, in turn, wishes to thank Craig Duncan for
proposing this exciting project and for handling much of the
red tape associated with it, as well as for the civil tone of his
side of the discussion. He is also grateful to the Philosophers’
Magazine for hosting the initial debate on libertarianism. Jim
Chesher, Tibor’s longtime friend and his coauthor for several
xv
xvi / Acknowledgments
books, has been very generous with his time and skill as he
provided suggestions and some criticism of Tibor’s portion of
the input in this debate. Chapman University and Freedom
Communications, Inc., should also be thanked for the support
Tibor has received for working on this project. Of course, the
content of his contributions are entirely his responsibility.
Finally, both authors would like to thank Eve DeVaro and
Melissa McNitt of Rowman and Littlefield for their able assis-
tance with this project.
A Note to Readers
xvii
xviii / A Note to Readers
3
4 / Chapter 1
which assert the primacy of rights are those which take as the
fundamental, or at least a fundamental, principle of their po-
litical theory the ascription of certain rights to individuals
which deny the same status to a principle of belonging or ob-
ligation, that is a principle which states our obligation as men
to belong to or sustain society, or a society of a certain type, or
to obey authority or an authority of a certain type.”7
I have argued elsewhere, however, that rights theories in the
Lockean tradition do not take rights to have normative primacy.
Rights are derived from the requirements of the ethics of indi-
vidual flourishing within the context of human communities.
There is no denial of the essential sociality of human beings, but
the Lockean tradition maintains that the individual needs to be
at liberty to determine to what sort of community he or she will
belong—if only by means of tacit or implicit consent—and that
the right kind is one in which his or her sovereignty has primacy.
It is only such a community that is fitting—that is, meets the
standard of justice—for human beings.
Libertarians, following the political vision of the Ameri-
can founders (who themselves took their cues from the likes
of John Locke), believe that people have to take care of their
own specific welfare, within and by the voluntary coopera-
tion of their various communities and associations—families,
churches, service organizations, companies, clubs, and so on.
Only the general welfare is to be promoted by government,8
the securing of our basic rights—just as referees may be said
to promote the general welfare of an athletic event by up-
holding its rules. People, in turn, are capable of doing their
job of promoting their specific welfare—pursuing their own
happiness—effectively if the government sticks to this refer-
eeing role, namely, running the courts, the police, and the
country’s defense.
Obviously, there are nuances and complications when one
translates these libertarian ideals into practical policy. Still it is
fairly clear that libertarian political thinking would contrast
sharply with a great deal of the current mainstream thinking
The Case for Libertarianism / 9
in even the Western world, let alone the rest of the world, con-
cerning the purpose of politics.
Interestingly enough, in the international arena the lan-
guage of this libertarian classical liberal political position is vi-
brant now. Ideas such as privatization, globalization, property
rights, and the infrastructure of a free market system concern
the extension throughout the world of the ideas laid out in the
U.S. Declaration of Independence. If the people of all the var-
ious societies around the globe want to prosper and improve
their lives, they do better by adopting the principles of a free
society associated with the American political tradition than
those of competing systems. Although in the United States
such ideals are not fully embraced or manifest, there remains
throughout the world a rhetorical identification of America
with the ideals of a fully free, voluntarist society of civil liber-
ties, freedom of thought and worship, free trade, free markets,
and capitalism. It is these ideas that are exported in the move-
ment roughly identified as “globalization.”
Also, interestingly, when the foreign policies of the U.S.
government are evaluated, libertarian notions tend to appear—
such as the critique of preemptive military attack, which rests,
at least implicitly, on the idea that unless someone initiates force
against a country—or is about to do so—that country is not au-
thorized to take forcible action. In short, the idea that force must
be limited to self-defense is quite prominent in such discus-
sions, yet of course many abandon it when it comes to the role
they assign to government in domestic affairs (e.g., precaution-
ary government regulations of various professions, which ar-
guably violate the ban on prior restraint, the prohibition of
using force on those who have not violated anyone’s rights but
merely might do so).
Now, what is crucial is why this libertarian alternative is a
good idea. It is one thing to say “We’re for it” but another thing
to say “We’re for it because it’s right.” In a column in The New
Republic, the author once recalled having attended an economic
conference in Japan and being cornered by a Japanese official
10 / Chapter 1
Individualism
Government Regulations
Libertarianism rejects the justice of government regula-
tions of business or any other profession or private activity—
gambling, prostitution, drug use, and commerce—on the
grounds that unless a person is violating another’s rights
(or is demonstrably threatening to do so), no one is justified
in interfering with what that person is doing. Just as in the
American legal system no one may interfere with any citi-
zen speaking his or her mind, worshiping, or publishing
written works, so in a free society no one, including the
government, is justified in such interference. Such interfer-
ence is best described by the legal term “prior restraint”—
that is, imposing burdens or restrictions on the conduct of
someone who has not been convicted of having violated or
threatening the violation of someone’s rights. It is only rights-
violating conduct—involving one person or persons taking over
the sovereignty of another—that justifies restraining a person,
and the rights involved would have to be negative, not posi-
tive, rights, since the latter are actually impositions of servi-
tude on persons. But let us spend a moment on the issue of
20 / Chapter 1
earned by somebody else, that’s all that counts. One day it’s
aiding AIDS research that tops the to-do list; the next it’s fos-
tering the arts by splurging on PBS; the next it’s curing every-
one of smoking and plundering the tobacco companies. No
principles, no logic, no standards of restraint tell us from day to
day what one will be free to do and what one will be prohibited
from doing; there is no surefire way to know. As under fascism,
whatever the leaders say, goes, so long as they continue to gen-
uflect mechanically before the altar of democracy.
If we are to reverse course, and achieve a more consis-
tently free society, we must tear up the counterfeit standard of
rights and restore a gold standard—the standard that enables
us to actually pursue, and achieve, life, and happiness.
Conclusion
Notes
1. There are different routes to libertarian political conclusions, and in
this discussion I will be sketching one within the normative natural law and
rights tradition, not a consequentialist, utilitarian, or positivist one. It is my
view that the widely championed consequentialist approach, which ap-
pears to reject principles in favor of expected utilities—so that, for example,
a regime of liberty is just because it maximizes value—has serious prob-
lems, since the value of consequences cannot be assessed without principles
as standards for evaluating them. There is also the non-consequentialist as-
sumption in most versions of consequentialism that the results of policies
can be correctly estimated before they occur. Yet that is just what the more
principled approach to politics—and libertarianism in particular—con-
tends. For more, see Tibor R. Machan, The Passion for Liberty (Lanham, Md.:
Rowman & Littlefield, 2003), chap. 3, “Against Utilitarianism: Why Not Vi-
olate Rights If It Would Do Good?”
2. For a defense of this, see Tibor R. Machan, ed., Individual Rights Recon-
sidered: Are the Truths of the U.S. Declaration of Independence Lasting? (Stanford
Calif.: Hoover Institution, 2001), especially Ronald Hamowy, chap. 1, “The
Declaration of Independence.” This, of course, is a mere historical fact, not
any argument for the stance itself.
3. G. A. Cohen’s complaint that disadvantaged workers are forced to
work, therefore, is no argument against a capitalist, free market system. Life
forces nearly everyone to work. See his “Are Disadvantaged Workers Who
The Case for Libertarianism / 41
Take Hazardous Jobs Forced to Take Hazardous Jobs?” in Moral Rights in the
Workplace, ed. Gertrude Ezorsky, 61–80 (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1987). For a discussion of a libertarian view of labor, see Tibor R.
Machan, “Rights and Myths at the Workplace,” in Moral Rights in the Work-
place, 45–50, and James E. Chesher, “Employment and Ethics,” in Commerce
and Morality, ed. Tibor R. Machan, 77–93 (Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Little-
field, 1988).
4. For more on this, see Tibor R. Machan, Generosity: Virtue in Civil Soci-
ety (Washington, D.C.: Cato Institute, 1998), chap. 6, “Generosity via Gov-
ernment.”
5. For a detailed discussion of this issue, see Tibor R. Machan, “Anar-
chism and Minarchism, A Rapprochement,” Journal des Economists et des Es-
tudes Humaines 14 (December 2002): 569–88. See also Aeon Skoble, Freedom,
Authority, and Social Order (Chicago: Open Court, 2005).
6. Available at www.usdreams.com/LincolnW7.html.
7. Charles Taylor, Philosophy and the Human Sciences (Cambridge, U.K.:
Cambridge University Press, 1985), 188. For more on this, see Tibor R.
Machan, “Libertarian Justice,” in Social and Political Philosophy: Contemporary
Perspectives, ed. James P. Sterba, 93–114 (London, U.K.: Routledge, 2001). An
important element of rights theory is identified in Douglas B. Rasmussen
and Douglas J. Den Uyl, Liberty and Nature (Chicago, Ill: Open Court, 1990).
The authors understand rights to be meta-norms, meaning these are princi-
ples of the societal framework within which action-guiding ethical or moral
principles may be followed or neglected. A society with basic Lockean
rights is one that secures for everyone the opportunity to be a moral agent.
8. See, for a libertarian interpretation of “general welfare,” www.house
.gov/science/taylor_4-9.html.
9. I have argued, in “America’s Founding Principles and Multicultural-
ism,” chapter 6 of my book Classical Individualism (London: Routledge,
1998), that in comparison to other political systems, the relatively libertarian
polity of the United States accommodates the requirements of multicultur-
alism better than do others wherein conformity to common practices is
stressed far more than is diversity and, especially, individuality.
10. Libertarians tend, in the main, to oppose wars of liberation or na-
tional building, not because it is wrong to help with such efforts abroad but
a country’s military already has a job, namely, to secure and defend the
rights of the citizens there.
11. Available at www.adherents.com/.
12. Equality is, of course, a core value in libertarianism, only it is the
equality of respecting the rights of individuals—all of them—rather than
the equality of sharing benefits and burdens available in society. This lat-
ter type of equality, perhaps better dubbed “fairness,” is supported from
42 / Chapter 1
wires and connections and linkages.” James Wood, The Book against God
(New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2003), where the first person protag-
onist consider himself to be free if he can escape the bonds of obligation he
himself has incurred and that others, in turn, are made to assume.
23. In recent times the doctrine has been reshaped by such philosophers
as Ronald Dworkin, James P. Sterba, Henry Shue, and legal scholars like
Stephen Holmes and Cass R. Sunstein. Shue’s Basic Rights (Princeton, N.J.:
Princeton University Press, 1983) goes so far as to argue that no negative
rights exist at all, since in any realistic sense rights are meaningless unless
given protection, which is a positive service from others. But Shue forgets
that the libertarian establishes secondary, derivative positive rights without
contradicting himself, via compact and contract. Holmes and Sunstein, who
echo Shue twenty-one years later, also fail to appreciate the idea that pro-
tecting rights via government and law requires consent. As the Declaration
of Independence puts it so succinctly, governments derive “their just pow-
ers from the consent of the governed.”
24. For a full exposition of the positive rights doctrine as developed by
theorists of the political left, see Tom Campbell, The Left and Rights (London
and Boston: Routledge, 1983).
25. See, Sterba, note 7 above.
26. See, e.g., Shue, note 23 above.
27. For a more detailed discussion of this issue, including viable alterna-
tives to taxation, see Tibor R. Machan, “Dissolving the Problem of Public
Goods: Financing Government without Coercive Measures,” 28, in The Liber-
tarian Reader, ed. T. R. Machan (Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield, 1982).
28. Amartya Sen, “Markets and Freedoms: Achievements and Limita-
tions of the Market Mechanism in Promoting Individual Freedoms,” Oxford
Economic Papers 45 (1995): 519–41. See, on the recently launched capabili-
ties approach project, the explanation provided at: www.fas.harvard.edu/
~freedoms/capability_defined.html.
29. Nussbaum, “Human Functioning.” A similar conception of human
rights to welfare or empowerment is defended by Alan Gewirth, Reason and
Morality (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978). For libertarian cri-
tiques of Gewirth’s political views, see Eric Mack, “Deontologism, Negative
Causation, and the Duty to Rescue,” and Douglas J. Den Uyl and Tibor R.
Machan, “Gewirth and the Supportive State,” in Gewirth’s Ethical Rational-
ism, ed. Ed Regis, Jr. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984).
30. Nussbuam, “Human Functioning,” 225–26. Another contemporary
theorist who advances an argument along similar lines is Jürgen Habermas,
The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory, eds. Ciaran Cronin and
Pablo De Greif (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1998), whose conception of a
just society based on discursive democracy involves various prerequisites
44 / Chapter 1
that will enable the citizenry to be able to take part in the discussion of pub-
lic policy. Of course, the discussion then focuses on incidentals, since the im-
portant issue of whether such provisions must be made is already settled
before the discussion gets under way. For more on this, see Tibor R. Machan,
“Individualism and Political Dialogue,” in Classical Individualism (London:
Routledge, 1998), chap. 13.
31. See Machan, Generosity, Virtue.
32. One standard justification for Good Samarian laws is that they apply
to professionals, such as doctors, who have gone on record offering their
services to those in dire medical need, that the law merely spells out the oc-
casion when that offer must be delivered. Still, even this rationale has prob-
lems, as shown in Mack, “Deontologism.”
33. That is one reason the California law enacted by Proposition 209
makes good sense, though its substance should never have required a ref-
erendum.
34. Richard Epstein, Forbidden Grounds (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 1992).
35. Jim Sleeper, Liberal Racism (New York: Viking, 1997).
36. See, for example, Tibor R. Machan and Mark Thornton, “The Re-
Legalization of Drugs,” Freeman 41, no. 4 (April 1991): 153–55.
37. This is not the whole story or the whole problem with critics of the
libertarian stance. In any case, those who wish to explore the various liber-
tarian approaches to the problem of drug abuse—including the failed poli-
cies of the federal and local governments on this problem—can begin by
checking the bibliography of (and reading) Mark Thornton’s essay, “The Re-
peal of Prohibition,” in Liberty for the 21st Century, eds. T. R. Machan and
D. B. Rasmussen (Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield, 1995).
38. For a somewhat longer outline of libertarianism, see Tibor R. Machan,
The Liberty Option (London: Imprint Academic, 2003). For a good selection
of varied libertarian ideas, see Tibor R. Machan, ed., The Libertarian Alterna-
tive (Chicago: Nelson-Hall, 1974); Machan, The Libertarian Reader; and David
Boaz, ed. The Libertarian Reader (New York: Free Press, 1997).
2
The Errors of Libertarianism
Craig Duncan
45
46 / Chapter 2
some rough balance between the benefits one gains and the
burdens one shoulders in contributing to society. (For more
details on this ideal of reciprocity, see my essay in chapter 4.)
This potential sort of moral criticism of tax schemes, however,
is off limits to libertarians like Machan, for according to him it
is wrong for ideals of fairness to shape laws and public policy;
laws and public policy must be confined purely to defending
individuals’ rights. (In the following section, I will in fact ar-
gue that individuals have rights to fair treatment, but in this
section I will not pursue this line of thought.) Hence Machan’s
need to object (implausibly) to taxes on the grounds that they
violate an absolute moral property right to all of one’s pre-tax
earnings, rather than on grounds of fairness.
There is another important objection to Machan’s claim
that one has a moral property right to every penny of one’s
pre-tax earnings. This is that Machan’s claim does not follow
from the foundation he provides for it. In fact Machan devotes
scant attention to the task of justifying property rights—much
less attention than this task warrants, given the importance of
property rights to libertarianism. What argument there is ap-
parently comes with the following sentence: “The right to pri-
vate property, via property law in developed communities,
secures for everyone a sphere of personal jurisdiction so it can
be determined when one is acting within one’s own sphere or
intrudes on the spheres of others” (p. 13; cf. p. 38).
The problem is that legal property rights of the sort we al-
ready have in the United States—rights that legally allow for
taxation—suffice to define adequately each individual’s
sphere of personal jurisdiction. One does not need rights to
every penny of one’s pre-tax earnings in order simply to de-
fine these spheres. How many of us, after all, currently have
our lives blighted by uncertainty as to whether the actions we
take with our possessions are legal or illegal?5
I presume Machan’s actual thought is that maximal prop-
erty rights are necessary to create a maximal sphere of per-
sonal jurisdiction—a maximal sphere of liberty, in a word. It is
The Errors of Libertarianism / 49
These other ways are possible because there is after all such
a thing as economic power over others.9 The power to hire a per-
son (or not) is obviously a significant form of power. Addition-
ally, being fired from one’s job can be a serious disruption to
one’s life. A failure to be promoted as expected can also seriously
disrupt one’s plans. Thus people with the ability to hire, fire, and
promote other people (or not) have a significant sort of power.
This is inevitable, so long as firings and refusals to hire or pro-
mote people are possible, as they should be in some fashion. But
as with political power (the abuse of which libertarians are so
fond of noting) this private economic power can be abused: on a
societal level, economic discrimination against minorities can be
used to maintain a castelike system of social stratification; on an
individual level, employees can (among other things) be threat-
ened with job loss or lack of promotion unless they dispense sex-
ual favors, perform unreasonably dangerous tasks, work an
insane number of hours, or do other humiliating things they
would never do but for their employer’s power over them.
Fortunately, the state’s power can be used to make these
private forms of power more accountable, by (among other
things) enabling some form of sexual harassment suits; en-
abling the formation of employee organizations (e.g., unions);
and by passing anti-discrimination laws, health and safety
laws, minimum-wage laws, and mandatory overtime-pay
laws. The abuses of economic power listed above are abuses in
virtue of being acts of exploitation, which we can define as tak-
ing unfair advantage of a person’s vulnerabilities. More specif-
ically, exploitative exchanges are not appropriately reciprocal;
in them, one party is treated more as an instrument for an-
other’s private gain, rather than as a person in his or her own
right. In this way the exploited party’s dignity as a person is
insulted. The same is true of unfair treatment generally—the
recipient of unfair treatment is not treated as a person whose
worth is equal to others. Unfairness is a threat to dignity.
In short, there are other serious sorts of threats to human
dignity beyond the threat of intentional, forcible, physical
52 / Chapter 2
Conclusion
Notes
1. In this critique I will focus on the fundamental claims of libertarian-
ism, rather than its policy implications regarding affirmative action, drug le-
galization, and so on. The issue of affirmative action in particular is indeed
a complex one. For important defenses of it, see Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign
Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 2000), chaps. 11 and 12; and Elizabeth S. Anderson, “Integra-
tion, Affirmative Action, and Strict Scrutiny,” NYU Law Review 77 (2002):
1195–271.
2. This is an oft-made point in the literature against libertarianism. For
some references, see Fried “Left-Libertarianism: A Review Essay,” Philoso-
phy and Public Affairs 32 (2004), note 49. See also section 4 of chapter 6 of this
book for quotations from “founding fathers” who make this very point.
3. One important disanalogy between the vendor case and the case of
taxation is the fact that vendors choose to join the antique market on the
owners’ terms, whereas most citizens are born into the state. I will explore
the implications of this important fact in section 3 below, “The Dilemma of
Consent Objection.”
4. This truth can be easily obscured by the terms used in sentences like,
“The government taxes your earnings.” For one might ask: If, as this sentence
says, the earnings in questions are yours, does this not mean that you own
them, and thus that government taxes do in fact confiscate money you own?
The answer to this question, however, is no. Possessives like “your,” “my,”
“his,” “her,” etc., do not always signify ownership. When you speak of “my
mother,” “my country,” “my shadow,” “my first kiss,” and so on, you do not
mean that you own your mother, your country, your shadow, or your first kiss
(whatever that would come to!). At a general level, the phrase “your x”
merely indicates that you stand in a relation to x that not everyone else in your
audience stands in; this leaves it open as to whether the relation in question
is one of ownership or some other relation. Legally speaking, then, the sen-
tence “your pre-tax earnings are $x” just means that you stand in a particular
relation to $x, namely, that this number is the amount that will be entered into
the tax equations that determine how much money you legally own.
5. Moreover, where there is uncertainty due to a vaguely worded prop-
erty law, one solution is to rewrite the law. Eliminating rather than rewrit-
ing a vague law is like treating a case of dandruff with decapitation.
The Errors of Libertarianism / 63
11. The only exceptions concern those who are necessarily dependents:
children, and people who owing to profound disability are incapable of par-
ticipating in the economy. For them, fair access to the means of subsistence is
a right to be provided with means necessary for a decent life. (Note the mis-
placed emphasis involved in Machan’s complaint [p. 20] that no parent has a
right “to the education of his or her children.” On the contrary, it is not the
parents who have the right to have their children educated; it is first and fore-
most the children who have the right to an education.) Children, of course,
will upon reaching maturity assume the correlative duty of this right, namely,
a duty to support a system that gives children a fair start in life. The pro-
foundly disabled will not. This is one case where the fairness rights I am de-
fending take an asymmetric form—that is, are not counterbalanced with a
correlative duty. I cannot see that this is an objection, however; the plight of
the profoundly disabled is hardly an enviable one. As such, a complaint that
the profoundly disabled are exploiting their fellow citizens does not ring true.
12. Arguably, though, Locke waffles on the issue of whether the consent
of all or of just the majority is needed. See for instance John Locke, Two Trea-
tises of Government, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, 1960), 362, para. 140. For a non-libertarian interpretation of Locke
generally, see A. John Simmons, The Lockean Theory of Rights (Princeton, N.J.:
Princeton University Press, 1992), especially chap. 6.
13. John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, 348, para. 119.
14. David Hume, “Of the Original Contract,” in Modern Political Thought:
Readings from Machiavelli to Nietzsche, ed. David Wootton (Indianapolis, Minn.:
Hackett, 1996), 387–96.
15. In 2002, for instance, American multinational companies reported a
record $149 billion in profits in tax-haven countries (i.e., countries with low
or no corporate taxes). “Taxing Global Profits,” New York Times, September
17, 2004.
16. Roderick Floud, The People and the British Economy: 1830–1914 (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1997), 23. Quoted in Emmet Barcalow, Justice, Equal-
ity, and Rights (Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth/Thomson Learning, 2004), 216.
17. Floud, The People and the British Economy, 23, 31, 78.
18. I borrow the character of Joe Sleazo from Richard B. Freeman and
Kimberly Ann Elliott, Can Labor Standards Improve under Globalization?
(Washington, D.C.: Institute for International Economics, 2003), 37. This is
an example of the collective action problem known as the “Prisoner’s
Dilemma.” For further discussion of this and other collective action prob-
lems, see Jon Elster, Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences (Cambridge, U.K.:
Cambridge University Press, 1989).
19. For further discussion of public goods, see Joseph Stiglitz, Economics
(New York: W. W. Norton, 1993), 180–82, and John Rawls, A Theory of Justice,
rev. ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press), 234–42.
3
Fairness—or Equality—
Is No Imperative
Tibor R. Machan
65
66 / Chapter 3
ents and skills while others must fend for themselves without
such enthusiastic support. The main issue of political morality
is, instead, that none of this involves forcing people to do what
they do not choose to do—that is, using coercion on them.14
That is what civilized life requires, not the abolition of distinc-
tions and differences that may yield variable advantages.
Concerning fairness or equality, one reason that these
seem such ubiquitous imperatives in our time could well be
that in a reasonably abundant society children grow up being
treated rather fairly by parents, who owe all of them (in the
family) decent treatment. Just as a teacher is supposed to at-
tend to all of his or her students—having in effect made a
promise to all of them to serve them with his or her skills—so
parents have basically promised their kids to treat them
equally well, provided they have the wealth to do so.15
But all of this is highly conditional and by no means
basic—what is basic is the responsibility to keep the promise
to provide service or good rearing. Yet having grown up with
the justified expectation, based on the promise, of equally
good treatment or fairness from parents and teachers, it makes
some psychological sense that this expectation be extended to
governments that claim to be providers for their citizens—not
just providers of equal protection of their basic rights to be
free but of whatever governments (politicians) promise (in a
welfare state, for instance).16
Yet this expectation is misguided, for two reasons: the
government is not a parent, and governments should not at-
tempt to provide citizens with everything they would like.
The Rawlsian case is a bit more complicated, because, as
we already noted, it rests on a very controversial yet widely
championed idea in our time, namely, determinism. This view
holds that all people behave as they must, based on the factors
that impel them to do so. Be these factors genes, evolutionary
forces, peer pressure, or whatever, there is a widespread idea,
drawn from the extrapolation from classical physics, that
none of us is free or responsible and thus deserving of either
gains or losses. It is all a matter of accident.
70 / Chapter 3
to shake their disdain for the rich, thinking it is quite unfair that
they are so much better off then the rest of us. Even lovers of lib-
erty often think of the rich as they might of prostitutes—sure, it’s
wrong to stop them, but they are an unsavory lot, aren’t they?18
Why is this attitude toward the rich so widespread? Why
do some find it so awful that certain people who can afford it
take long vacations on the French or Italian Riviera and drive
fancy cars and wear snappy outfits that cost a bundle even
while others struggle? It is generally not some particular rich
person who draws such ire, not someone who may have em-
bezzled or otherwise illicitly gained his wealth. Not at all—it
is the fact of their being rich, period.
An anecdote may be of some use here. A few summers
ago I had a chance to tour Versailles, where I took a close look
at the palace of Marie Antoinette and Louis the XVI.19 A point
recurred to me during this visit that I had thought of on sim-
ilar visits to castles and palaces around the globe, how easily
people still confuse the wealth that comes by way of conquest
with wealth that is achieved. French royalty, for example, or
the Habsburgs, or any other dynasty, became wealthy and
spent enormous sums on luxuries not in consequences of
hard work, diligence, or even simple good luck but because
millions of others were kept in servitude and had their labors
taken from them. Unlike, say, a Bill Gates, Warren Buffett, or
the late Sam Walton, as well as many, many others who have
earned and kept earning their wealth through innovation,
wheeling and dealing, or other honest means, the bulk of the
rich in the past gained it mainly by way of conquest and sub-
jugation.
In the economic theories of ancient times—say, Aristotle’s—
it was generally believed that wealth had to be expropriated,
that it was all a zero-sum process: those who gained had to
make others lose. That, of course, created a widespread moral
disapproval of riches, to the point that calling riches “filthy”
was nearly axiomatic—if by “filth” is meant “wrongful,”
“nasty,” or “inexcusable.”
72 / Chapter 3
ing to equalize it all can only lead to the worst type of inequal-
ity, namely, inequality of the power of some over others.
The reason is plain: Equality of conditions, even of oppor-
tunity (apart from the legally protected right to freedom to
seek what one wants) is, technical philosophical considera-
tions aside, simply quite impossible. It introduces a plethora
of conflicts, inconsistencies, and problems, and it implies, ul-
timately, a totally socially engineered culture that can easily
serve as a model of dystopia for politically geared science fic-
tion novels.21
In his critique of my opening essay, Professor Duncan ob-
serves that we share a premise as we begin our defense of our
respective political position, that being the basic dignity of the
human individual. This is roughly right, except that built into
his idea of human dignity there is in Professor Duncan’s under-
standing room for one person’s taking from another portions of
his or her life and works, whereas in mine this is precluded. No
one is entitled to other people’s person or estate, however unfair
this may seem when looked at as if these persons had some sort
of covenant to share. But they do not have such a covenant, not
unless they enter into one freely, uncoerced.
Notes
1. Although the ideas and ideals of laissez-faire capitalism or, more
broadly, libertarianism are in sufficient circulation to be subjects of discus-
sion and, certainly, severe criticism, the egalitarian stance is clearly the fa-
vorite of major figures in political philosophy and theory who teach at the
most prestigious institutions and publishing with the most prominent
presses, both commercial and university. I do not believe there can be any
reasonable dispute about this.
2. Libertarians consider respecting everyone’s right to liberty (and so forth)
a right that is, of course, held equally by everyone, so there is a measure of
equality in the libertarian view of justice—consider, as a case in point, that the
Declaration of Independence states that we are all “created equal,” just before
it states, as well, that we possess “unalienable rights; that among these are life,
liberty, and the pursuit of happiness.” (See, for more on this, Roderick Long,
74 / Chapter 3
10. “The assertion that a man deserves the superior character that enables
him to make the effort to cultivate his abilities is . . . problematic; for his char-
acter depends in large part upon favorable family and social circumstances
for which he can claim no credit.” Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 104. If this is not
a flat-out denial of free will and personal responsibility, it difficult to tell
what it amounts to. Cf. David L. Norton, Personal Destinies: A Philosophy of
Ethical Individualism (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1976), 328:
“To my knowledge, nowhere has attention been called to the fact that egali-
tarianism’s ubiquitous suspicion of advantage precludes to its adherents our
natural delight in the presence of persons of surpassing moral excellence.”
11. W. Somerset Maugham, A Writer’s Notebook (Baltimore: Penguin,
1967), 325.
12. Intuitions are initial clues because they are unexamined but strong
convictions or beliefs. They are, however, acquired haphazardly, unself-
consciously, so upon scrutiny can be found to be misguided.
13. The source of this idea is the philosophy of Thomas Hobbes who, in
his Leviathan, laid out an understanding of human beings as entirely unique
and who join society as a matter of a social contract they enter. They have
no human nature in line with which they conform to certain limits, and
whatever limits that befall their lives are a matter of their own decision.
14. Two especially insightful works elaborate these points along classical
liberal, libertarian lines: Murray N. Rothbard, Egalitarianism as a Revolt
against Nature, and Other Essays, 2nd ed. with an introduction by David Gor-
don (Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2000), and Antony Flew, The
Politics of Procrustes: Contradictions of Enforced Equality (Buffalo, N.Y.:
Prometheus Books, 1981).
15. Within a theological framework of political justice the idea that we are
all God’s children also encourages the idea that whoever stands in for God on
earth—say, the king or the government—owes us all care, and we in turn must
share whatever burdens face humanity. Since I am operating here from a nat-
uralist framework, I merely mention this point and do not discuss it further.
16. For a development of this point, see Tibor R. Machan, Private Rights
and Public Illusions (New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Books, 1995).
17. A similar imperative is that of impartiality—so that, for example, if
one has moral responsibilities toward some persons, impartiality will re-
quire that these be fulfilled toward all others (at least in reach). As Peter
Unger puts it, “On pain of living a life that’s seriously immoral, a typical
well-off person, like you and me, must give away most of her financially
valuable assets, and much of her income, directing the funds to lessen effi-
ciently the serious suffering of others.” Peter Unger, Living High and Letting
Die: Our Illusion of Innocence (London: Oxford University Press, 1996) [my
emphasis]. Thus we have the spectacle of some contemporary moral
76 / Chapter 3
79
80 / Chapter 4
The most devastating way one can fail to respect another per-
son’s dignity is by failing to recognize any presumption
against impairing that person’s capacity for responsible choice.
In general, one impairs a person’s capacity for responsible
choice by crippling the mental capabilities necessary for re-
sponsible agency or by preventing their healthy development.
Certain forms of abuse, both physical and psychological, can
produce this result, especially if the victim is a child. Quite
plausibly, too, a person’s capacity for responsible choice is crip-
pled while he or she is in the grip of a severe substance addic-
tion. Additionally, one can impair other people’s capacity for
choice by paralyzing them with fear or by incapacitating them
with intense and prolonged pain—and so on. In all these cases
the implications for dignity are especially severe. For when a
person’s capacity for responsible choice is destroyed, we may
say that his or her dignity is correspondingly diminished.7
The second way in which one can fail to respect another
person’s dignity is by failing to observe any presumption
against constraining the exercise of that person’s capacity for
responsible choice. The clearest case of this lies in physical
constraints on a person’s body. At the extreme, the person is
shackled to a dungeon wall, thereby removing nearly all op-
portunity for action. A prison cell allows a greater scope of ac-
tion than a set of shackles but drastically less scope than exists
outside of prison—and so on for other less confining physical
restraints. In the case of constraint, it is not genuinely apt to
say that the constrained person’s dignity is diminished, for un-
like the case of impairment, the person’s capacity for respon-
sible choice will remain intact so long as the constraint is not
so extreme as to be mentally incapacitating. Rather, the harm
84 / Chapter 4
5. Improving Democracy
One hundred years later, the life of the Negro is still sadly
crippled by the manacles of segregation and the chains of
discrimination. One hundred years later, the Negro lives on
a lonely island of poverty in the midst of a vast ocean of ma-
terial prosperity. One hundred years later, the Negro still
languishes in the corners of American society and finds
himself an exile in his own land.35
a reform they will share the costs along with inner-city resi-
dents of raising the latter’s schools to suburban levels. This is
unpleasant, of course, but it just reflects the fact that basic fair-
ness, like other good things in life, is not free of charge. If we
want a fair society in which all citizens are treated as equals,
we need a level training field as much as a level playing
field.38 Thus the ideal of respect for dignity identifies fair
equality of opportunity, rather than merely formal equality of
opportunity, as the superior conception of equal opportunity.
We should not, however, deceive ourselves into thinking
that improved education can by itself genuinely equalize the
opportunity to acquire job qualifications. Differences in fam-
ily cultures will remain, including the extent to which parents
emphasize education; the amount they read to their children;
the amount they are willing and able to help with homework;
whether they can provide quiet areas for study; whether they
teach their children good grammar and social skills; whether
they are willing and able to take their children to museums,
libraries, and other stimulating places; and so on.39 These acts
should not be required by law; among other reasons, to do so
would violate the right to privacy mentioned above in section
4. Moreover, while the phenomena so far listed concern just
education, family differences matter at the level of job compe-
tition too, of course. Family connections can help one get a job,
and family wealth can pay for an elite college education, fund
an unpaid summer internship to gain job skills, and provide
much needed start-up funds for opening a business (or collat-
eral for a business loan). In addition, individuals from rich
families can take steep risks as young would-be entrepre-
neurs, secure in the confidence that they will not have to live
in poverty should they fail.40 And so on. While the economic
advantages owing to family wealth can be blunted by public
policy (say, with a more equitable distribution of wealth),
those owing to family culture and connections cannot.
Economic opportunity, in short, will never truly be equal
so long as the private family exists in some form, as it should.
While we should strive to make opportunities more equal, we
104 / Chapter 4
Suppose we really did live in a society that was free of racial and
other types of discrimination and that provided all its members
with high-quality schools. Apart from the unequal opportuni-
ties stemming from differences in family wealth and family cul-
ture, could we say that in such a society all people get exactly the
economic rewards they deserve to get, so that it would be
morally objectionable to disturb whatever income distribution
was produced by the workings of a capitalist marketplace (as
happens, say, when taxes on the well-off help to fund health
care, housing, and other forms of assistance for the poor)?
No. Far too many factors go toward determining your eco-
nomic reward for there to be any simple correlation between
this and your just deserts. For starters, much of your reward
depends on luck. This luck takes several forms: simply being
in the right place at the right time (say, a chance noticing of
some job opening, or a chance meeting that leads to a useful
business contact, etc.); or being born to the right family; or be-
ing born with genes that make one “gifted” in some way that
the market values. Much of your economic compensation also
depends on large-scale phenomena that are in no single indi-
vidual’s control: how scarce your skills are, what patterns of
consumer taste prevail, what level of unemployment prevails
in your society, where in the business cycle (the cycle between
growth and recession) your society is, how competent the po-
The Politics of Dignity / 105
have far less time for their other tasks.41 The same, moreover,
can be said of any essential task, from stocking shelves to op-
erating a cash register to loading trucks with freight.
A critic might try to defeat this point by saying that indi-
viduals could have avoided these lower-rung jobs had they
merely “applied themselves” by studying harder in school.
On this view, low wages are one’s just deserts—punishment,
of a sort—for past imprudence. This view, however, suffers
from a number of flaws. First, we should remember our ear-
lier observation that fair equality of opportunity to acquire
qualifications or find a job does not yet prevail in our society
and in fact never will, given differences in family culture and
connections that no institution can fix. Not everybody has a
fair go in life. Second, even if fair equality of opportunity did
prevail, it is hardly the case that imprudent decisions made as
a teenager truly make one deserving of lifelong low wages;
such a “punishment” does not fit the “crime.” Third, it may be
that some people through bad genetic luck (a low innate in-
telligence, say) are simply not capable of performing more
highly paid jobs. Finally, and most decisively, this view ig-
nores the fact that such jobs as cleaning floors and emptying
wastebaskets must be done by someone. If everyone were to
gain a college degree, then this only means that someone with
a college degree would end up cleaning floors, barring some
technological breakthrough or some unprecedented system of
sharing cleaning tasks among a wide pool of employees
(which would in any case boost the wages associated with
cleaning well above their current level). All of this reveals a
mismatch between wages of workers at the bottom end and
those workers’ actual contributions to production.
A similar mismatch exists at the top end as well. Consider
for instance the case of CEO pay compared to the pay of
workers on the shop floor. According to The Economist (a right-
of-center periodical), the top one hundred CEOs have an av-
erage annual compensation of $37.5 million each, over a
thousand times the pay of the average worker.42 This ratio
The Politics of Dignity / 109
8. A Dignified Minimum
only 5 percent were poor for ten years or more.58 This variety
is indeed what one should expect, given the large number of
poor people in America—35.8 million people in 2003, accord-
ing to the most recent data at the time of writing, equivalent to
12.5 percent of all Americans (up from 12.2 percent in 2002).59
Hence the poor comprise more kinds of people than pop-
ular belief supposes. The same is surely true of the causes of
poverty. Yes, a significant chunk of poverty is undoubtedly
due to imprudent decisions made on the part of individuals.
But not all of it is. As just noted, many of the poor are work-
ing hard, struggling to make ends meet. In addition, many are
unemployable on account of old age or severe disability. Lim-
itations on opportunities explain a significant amount of
poverty as well. We have already noted the inequalities in op-
portunity that exist in public education and in family cultures
and connections. Moreover, even apart from these inequali-
ties, economic opportunity itself is not unlimited; in particu-
lar, it is not the case that everyone who wants a job can easily
find one. This is obvious in a recession, when the unemploy-
ment rate is high. But involuntary unemployment is always
present to some extent, owing to the way the economy is
managed by the Federal Reserve. If the unemployment rate dips
too “low”—below what economists call the “non-accelerating
inflation rate of unemployment” (NAIRU)—then the Federal
Reserve will raise interest rates to slow down the economy
(the economy will slow, because higher interest rates mean
less business investment in new projects); this deceleration in
turn will bring the unemployment rate back up (fewer new
business projects means less need for employees).60 This is not
a nefarious plan on the part of the Federal Reserve; its goal is
to prevent runaway inflation (which can be sparked by an ex-
tremely tight labor market), and runaway inflation is indeed
worth avoiding, even at the cost of some unemployment.61
But the Fed’s policy does mean there will always be a signifi-
cant number of people who at any given moment are unable
to find a job through no fault of their own.
The Politics of Dignity / 117
9. Conclusion
Notes
1. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, Prima Secundae, q. 87, a. 4, arg. 2.
Quoted in Marilyn McCord Adams, “Hell and the God of Justice,” Religious
Studies 11 (1979): 442.
2. Adams, “Hell and the God of Justice,” 442. Wergild literally means
“manprice” in Anglo-Saxon (www.en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Wergild).
3. William James, Essays in Pragmatism (New York: Hafner, 1948), 68.
4. In focusing specifically on human dignity, I do not mean to suggest that all
talk of dignity is out of place as regards nonhuman animals. For excellent dis-
cussion of this issue, see Martha Nussbaum, Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Na-
tionality, Species Membership (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
2005), chap. 6.
5. The preamble to the United Nations’ Universal Declaration of Human
Rights (1948), for instance, begins, “Whereas recognition of the inherent dig-
nity and of equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family
is the foundation of freedom, justice, and peace in the world” [emphasis
added]. Available at www.un.org/Overview/rights.html.
6. I speak of observing a strong presumption against impairing, constrain-
ing, and ignoring the capacity for responsible choice, rather than an absolute
prohibition against these, because the theory I will defend is not an absolutist
theory. We may face tragic choices in which, say, constraining a person is
necessary to prevent even graver indignities to others. I will have more to
say about this later in section 3.
7. It is not necessarily destroyed altogether, for as I observed in note 4,
there may be other forms of dignity besides the characteristic human sort lo-
cated in the capacity for responsible choice.
8. To be sure, this account of human equality does not grant equal sta-
tus to absolutely every living being with human DNA. Profoundly re-
tarded individuals and young children do not make the cut, for instance.
This by itself is not an objection to my proposed foundation for moral
equality, however, since to my knowledge no one proposes treating
young children or the profoundly retarded—someone who understands
no language of any kind, for instance—exactly the same as citizens gen-
erally (e.g., granting them the right to vote). This does not imply, how-
ever, that these human beings have no rights of any kind. Children’s
status as responsible beings in training will give them certain rights. Pro-
foundly retarded people’s status as bearers of tragic misfortune will
morally rule out subjecting them to further indignities beyond what they
already suffer by nature; one should not kick people who are already
down. Beyond these merely suggestive remarks, however, in the short
space I have here I will not address further the difficult question of what
The Politics of Dignity / 121
19. Cf. the words of the French philosopher Helvétius: “To limit the press
is to insult a nation; to prohibit reading of certain books is to declare the in-
habitants to be either fools or slaves” (Claude Adrien Helvétius, De
L’Homme [London: Thoemmes, 1999], vol. 1, sec. 4). The main idea of this
passage is surely correct, though as I note in what follows, some narrowly
defined limits to freedom of expression are necessary.
20. Brandenburg v. Ohio (1969), 395 U.S. 444.
21. New York Times Co. v. Sullivan (1964), 376 U.S. 254
22. For some innovative suggestions along these lines, see Bruce A. Ack-
erman and James F. Fishkin, Deliberation Day (New Haven, Conn.: Yale Uni-
versity Press, 2004).
23. For useful information on these various ways (and their pros and cons),
see the website of the Center for Voting and Democracy at www.fairvote.org.
24. These statistics are available at the website of the Center for Respon-
sive Politics (www. opensecrets.org/bigpicture; click on links labeled “The
Price of Admission” and “Different Races, Different Costs”).
25. URL www.opensecrets.org/pressreleases/Post-Election2000.htm.
26. URL www.opensecrets.org/bigpicture.
27. URL www.opensecrets.org/pressreleases/Post-Election2000.htm.
28. URL www.opensecrets.org/presidential/index.asp. .
29. For one such example involving the company Enron and House ma-
jority leader Tom DeLay, see Paul Krugman, “Machine At Work,” New York
Times, July 13, 2004. For an in-depth study of an earlier example, see Jeffrey
H. Birnbaum and Alan S. Murray, Showdown at Gucci Gulch: Lawmakers, Lob-
byists, and the Unlikely Triumph of Tax Reform (New York: Vintage Books, 1988).
30. Public Campaign, “The Road to Clean Elections,” (www.publicam-
paign.org/publications/trtce/TheRoadToCleanElections.pdf ).
31. Clean Elections Institute, Inc., “2002 Success of Clean Elections”
(www.azclean.org/documents/2002SuccessStats.doc).
32. Clean Elections Institute, Inc., “2002 Success of Clean Elections.”
33. Clean Elections Institute, Inc., “2002 Success of Clean Elections.”
34. Clean Elections Institute, Inc., “The Road to Victory” (www
.azclean.org/documents/ 2002RoadtoVictory-Final.pdf). The money comes
from fees on lobbyists who represent for-profit activities and from a ten per-
cent surcharge on civil and criminal fines (Public Campaign, “The Road to
Clean Elections”).
35. Martin Luther King, Jr., “I Have a Dream,” in The Moral Life, 2nd ed.,
ed. Louis Pojman (Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press, 2003), 649.
36. Race relations have improved significantly since the time of King’s
speech, thanks in large measure to the Civil Rights Movement’s victories in
the form of the 1964 Civil Rights Act and 1965 Voting Rights Act. We still have
a significant way to go before racial discrimination is eliminated, however.
For evidence of continued discrimination, see chapter 6, section 3 of this book.
The Politics of Dignity / 123
37. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1999), 63.
38. For valuable suggestions as to how to spend the extra money raised
for failing schools, see Matthew Miller, The Two Percent Solution: Fixing
America’s Problems in Ways Liberals and Conservatives Can Love (New York:
Public Affairs, 2003), chap. 6.
39. Cf. Richard Rothstein, Class and Schools (Washington, D.C.: Economic
Policy Institute, 2004).
40. This point is made in Brian Barry, Why Social Justice Matters (Cam-
bridge, U.K.: Polity, 2005), 194.
41. Cf. Elizabeth S. Anderson, “What Is the Point of Equality?” Ethics 109
(1999): 322. My defense of democratic liberalism is heavily indebted to this
article.
42. “Special Report: Ever higher society, ever harder to ascend—Meritoc-
racy in America,” The Economist, January 1, 2005, 22–25. This article also re-
ports that social mobility (i.e., individuals’ likelihood of moving up the class
ladder) has declined in the United States since the 1970s, to point where the
United States now has less social mobility than many other countries, such
as Germany, Sweden, Finland, and Canada. This decline in mobility has be-
gun to worry even conservative commentators; see for instance David
Brooks, “The Sticky Ladder,” New York Times, January 1, 2005.
43. “Special Report,” The Economist, 24. This figure is adjusted for inflation.
44. Matthew Boyle, “When Will They Stop?” Fortune, May 3, 2004, 123.
45. Robert Trigaux, “Executive Compensation Rises through Lavish to
Absurd,” St. Petersburg Times, April 26, 2004 (www.sptimes.com/2004/
04/26/Columns/Executive_compensatio.shtml). For further data see the
summary at www.faireconomy.org/press/2004/CEOPayRatio_pr.html and
Lucian Bebchuk and Jesse Fried, Pay without Performance: The Unfulfilled
Promise of Executive Compensation (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 2004).
46. Alan B. Krueger, “When It Comes to Income Inequality, More Than
Just Market Forces Are at Work,” New York Times, April 4, 2002.
47. Paul Krugman, “For Richer,” New York Times Magazine, October 20,
2002, 66. See Derek Bok, The Cost of Talent: How Executives and Professionals
Are Paid and How It Affects America (New York: Free Press, 2002) for an ex-
tended study of CEO pay.
48. Paul Krugman, “The Death of Horatio Alger,” The Nation, January 5,
2004 (www.thenation.com/doc.mhtml?i=20040105&s=krugman).
49. Krugman, “The Death of Horatio Alger.”
50. Krueger, “When It Comes to Income Inequality.”
51. For a sophisticated defense of worker-owned firms, see Samuel
Bowles and Herbert Gintis, “A Political and Economic Case for the Demo-
cratic Enterprise,” Economics and Philosophy 9 (1993): 75–100.
124 / Chapter 4
52. Laws like this already exist in the United States, but the monetary
sanctions levied against firms who fire union-seeking employees are so
minimal that many businesses break these laws with little hesitation and
treat the fines as just another routine cost of business. Another problem is
firms’ ability to delay recognition of a union for years (sometimes as much
as ten years) owing to a ridiculously slow recognition process overseen by
the National Labor Relations Board. For details see Human Rights Watch,
Unfair Advantage: Workers’ Freedom of Association in the United States under In-
ternational Human Rights Standards (2000), available online at www.hrw.org/
reports/2000/uslabor. For valuable suggestions as to how to improve U.S.
labor laws, see Richard Freeman, “Lessons for the United States,” in Work-
ing under Different Rules, ed. Richard Freeman, 223–39 (New York: Russell
Sage Foundation, 1994). These problems help explain the extraordinary de-
cline in unionization rates in the United States, to the point where by 2003
under 9 percent of the private sector was unionized, less than half the union-
ization rate of every other industrial democracy (www.aflcio/ecouncil/
ec02262003b.cfm). This is surely part of the reason that average wages have
fallen in the United States over the past two decades, while in the same pe-
riod they have risen in every other OECD country—that is, every other ma-
jor developed country. (See Richard Freeman, “The New Inequality in the
United States,” in Growing Apart: The Causes and Consequences of the Global
Wage Inequality, eds. Albert Fishlow and Karen Parker [New York: Council
on Foreign Relations Press, 1999], 29).
53. David Card and Alan B. Krueger, Myth and Measurement: The New Eco-
nomics of the Minimum Wage (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University, 1995).
Other natural experiments are also examined in this book. See also the sym-
posium on the book in Industrial and Labor Relations Review 48:4 (1995). For
a concise summary of the shift in thinking among many economists regard-
ing the minimum wage, see Thomas Palley, “Building Prosperity from the
Bottom Up,” Challenge 41 (1998): 59–72.
54. Center on Budget and Policy Priorities, “Facts about the Earned In-
come Credit: Tax Time Can Pay for Working Families” (2004), 21, citing the
U.S. Census Bureau’s Current Population Survey; available online at
www.cbpp.org/eic2004/eic04-factbook.pdf.
55. Associated Press, “Ranks of Poverty and Uninsured Rose in 2003,
Census Reports,” New York Times, August 26, 2004 (www.nytimes.com).
Forty-five million Americans constitute 15.6 percent of the population. This
is an increase from the 15.2 percent of Americans who lacked health insur-
ance in 2002.
56. For a helpful overview of America’s employer-based health insurance,
see Uwe E. Reinhardt, “Employer-Based Health Insurance: A Balance
Sheet,” Health Affairs 18 (1999): 124–33. See Miller, The Two Percent Solution,
The Politics of Dignity / 125
chap. 5, for a discussion of what is probably the most feasible option in the
American context for fixing this hole in the safety net (namely, “community
rated” private insurance plus a requirement that all citizens purchase health
insurance, with the poor assisted by public subsidies). For examples of
health systems from other countries, which can serve as useful compar-
isons, see Laurene Graig, Health of Nations: An International Perspective on
U.S. Health Care Reform (Washington, D.C.: Congressional Quarterly Books,
1999). Finally, for insightful philosophical reflection on health care, see
Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality (Cam-
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000), chap. 8.
57. Mary Jo Bane and Lawrence M. Mead, Lifting Up the Poor: A Dialogue
on Religion, Poverty and Welfare (Washington, D.C.: Brookings Institution
Press, 2003), 59. The figures are for the year 2001 and come from the U.S.
Census Bureau’s March 2002 Annual Demographic Supplement, tables 2–4.
The Census Bureau’s threshold for poverty was $18,104/year for a family of
four in 2001. One reason for popular misconceptions about the poor lies
with media images that disproportionately display poverty as a black phe-
nomenon. For a sophisticated media critique, see Martin Gilens, Why Amer-
icans Hate Welfare: Race, Media, and the Politics of Antipoverty Policy (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2000). For full-length studies of the working
poor, see Katherine S. Newman, No Shame in My Game: The Working Poor of
the Inner City (New York: Vintage Books, 2000) and David K. Shipler, The
Working Poor: Invisible in America (New York: Knopf, 2004).
58. Bane and Mead, Lifting Up the Poor, 58.
59. Associated Press, “Ranks of Poverty and Uninsured Rose.”
60. Paul Krugman, “Labor Pains,” New York Times Magazine, May 24, 1999,
24–26.
61. A significant number of economists, however, believe the importance
of NAIRU has been overrated and that the Federal Reserve could do more
to lower unemployment without creating runaway inflation. See for exam-
ple James K. Galbraith, Created Unequal: The Crisis in American Pay (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2000); Thomas I. Palley, Plenty of Nothing: The
Downsizing of the American Dream and the Case for Structural Keynesianism
(Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2000); and George A. Akerlof,
“Behavioral Macroeconomics and Macroeconomic Behavior,” American Eco-
nomic Review 92 (2002), 411–33. For a variety of viewpoints, see the sympo-
sium on NAIRU in the Journal of Economic Perspectives 11:1 (1997).
62. In saying that the seriously disabled are not employable, I have in
mind primarily those with very serious mental disabilities. A person in a
wheelchair is employable, of course, provided he or she can reach the work-
place. Considerations of dignity point to the need for laws requiring busi-
nesses to make reasonable accommodations for the physically disabled, so
126 / Chapter 4
that they too can participate in work. Cf. Nussbaum, Frontiers of Justice,
chaps. 2 and 3.
63. For a summary of recent studies see Alan B. Krueger, “Inequality, Too
Much of a Good Thing” (Unpublished manuscript), available online at
www.irs.princeton.edu/pubs/pdfs/inequality4.pdf). See also the Com-
mittee for Economic Development’s 2002 report, “Preschool for All: Invest-
ing in a Productive and Just Society” (www.ced.org/docs/report/report
_preschool.pdf).
64. This point bears on an assessment of the Personal Responsibility and
Work Opportunity Reconciliation Act of 1996 (PRWORA), by which the U.S.
Congress instituted work requirements as a condition of welfare receipt. On
the whole, the framework I am employing supports this reform, though I
think much less attention was paid to crucial issues of childcare and job
training than was necessary. The most successful systems of welfare in
America, such as the Minnesota Family Investment Program, pay a great
deal of attention to these issues. For details, see Dave Hage, Reforming Wel-
fare by Rewarding Work: One State’s Successful Experiment (Minneapolis: Uni-
versity of Minnesota Press, 2004). I am skeptical, moreover, of one other
significant element of PRWORA, namely, its time limits, which restrict fed-
eral welfare receipt to a total of five years over the course of a single lifetime.
I know of no a priori guarantee that misfortune never totals to longer than
five years for any individual.
65. I take the term “system of joint production” from Anderson, “What Is
the Point of Equality?” 321.
5
The Follies of
Democratic “Liberalism”
Tibor R. Machan
127
128 / Chapter 5
But, did “we” not enter into a social compact that resulted
in the tax system we have? No we didn’t, not if we indeed have
unalienable rights—no contract can give up anyone’s rights. I
certainly may not enter a contract the provisions of which in-
clude that your rights are violated. A contract—or compact—
can only be entered into voluntarily; unwilling third parties
may not be conscripted to it.18 If, as in the case of the closest to
a free country in the modern era, namely, the United States, the
society is supposed to be grounded on unalienable individual
rights, the only way government can come about is through
“the consent of the governed.” While this had been under-
stood too loosely in the past, even by the American founders,
its meaning is clear: You and I must consent to be governed.19
Now, we do consent to being governed if we remain within
the legal jurisdiction of a certain sphere, but only to the extent
that is just; it is the just powers of government only to which we
can consent, and to tax is not one of the just powers of govern-
ment. To be properly funded, some other, but in any case volun-
tary, means must be found. Since, however, this is a very novel
idea—about as novel even in the United States as free markets
are in the former Soviet bloc countries or freedom of religion in
Iran—studies as to how to bring it off are in short supply. (Re-
member, most universities are tax funded, so they are not likely
to encourage alternative ways of funding government.)
Still, there has been some progress in the study of funding
government without any coercive means. One method pro-
posed is to charge for all contracts that are, ultimately, backed
by the courts. Certainly, one can just shake hands and pro-
ceed, but this is not likely when multimillions are at stake and
legal recourse is wanted in case of some kind of mishap. There
is also the possibility of funding government via lotteries.20 At
the beginning, governments could make ample money so as
to fund plenty of their proper undertakings by selling off all
the properties that they should not own in the first place.
These observations do not exhaust the field of public fi-
nance for a government of a free society. Still, if the idea were
138 / Chapter 5
fied as the best moral system. But neither expects the system
to be lived up to fully, despite the fact that that is what should
happen. As with the best ethics, so with the best politics—all
one can do is strive to promote it. It would be foolish, know-
ing about the human proclivity to yield to many temptations
to be less than excellent, to expect the best polity to be realized
with any regularity.
Notes
1. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univer-
sity Press, 1971).
2. John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University
Press, 1993).
3. W. Somerset Maugham, A Writer’s Notebook (Baltimore: Penguin,
1967), 325.
4. Ernest W. Pettifer, Punishments of Former Days (East Ardsley, U.K.: EP,
1974), 35–36.
5. For a more detailed account of this point, see Tibor R. Machan, “Hu-
man Dignity and the Law,” DePaul Law Review 26 (1977): 119–26.
6. See, for more of my own libertarian approach—but one developed
from a neo-Aristotelian naturalist ethical based—Tibor R. Machan, Putting
Humans First: Why We Are Nature’s Favorite (Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Lit-
tlefield, 2004).
7. See an especially focused paper on this topic from Professor Nuss-
baum: Martha Nussbaum, “Human Functioning and Social Justice: In De-
fense of Aristotelian Essentialism,” Political Theory 20 (1992): 202–46.
8. Arguably Duncan builds into his understanding of society the ques-
tion-begging element of the requirement of choice—cooperation of the
membership. Clearly, innumerable societies, ordinarily understood, lack
this element.
9. For an elaboration of this point, see Tibor R. Machan, “Why Agree-
ment Is Not Enough,” Philosophia 28 (2000): 269–81.
10. It is valuable here to recall that there are certain libertarian hints even
in Aristotle, as far as what may count for a just society, as when he notes that
“the virtues are modes of choice or involve choice.” (Nicomachean Ethics,
1106a3 & 4.) This suggests that for Aristotle only a polis wherein choice is re-
spected and protected can qualify as encouraging moral virtue since only in
such a polis can “modes of choice” be made secure. For more on this way of
142 / Chapter 5
reading Aristotle, see Fred D. Miller Jr., Nature, Justice, and Rights in Aristotle’s
Politics (Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press, 1995).
11. As an additional small but not negligible matter, Duncan uses “lib-
eral” in the unique contemporary, post New Deal American, sense of that
term. “Liberal” had, of course, meant anyone who championed liberty in the
sense that one ought to be free from other people’s intrusiveness, from op-
pression or rule by others (monarchs, tsars, dictators, and others who aspire
to rule unwilling subjects). The meaning of “liberal” changed for a variety of
reasons, not the least of which is that in American calling oneself a social
democrat or democratic socialist simply did not meet with open arms. In Eu-
rope, in contrast, liberals are still viewed as mostly classical liberals, guided by
the thought of John Locke, Adam Smith, John Stuart Mill, and Lord Acton.
12. Fareed Zakaria, The Future of Freedom: Illiberal Democracy at Home and
Abroad (New York: W. W. Norton, 2003). Zakaria, of course, does not ad-
vance a radical libertarian case here, although arguably he intimates one.
13. Considering that billions of people around the world, even today, are
barred from taking part in any sort of political process, to which they clearly
have a basic, natural right (given that everyone has such a right to liberty of
action, including political action), it is no surprise that democracy means for
them the crux of political liberty. But as Zakaria and others, including John
Locke, warned, liberty may be endangered by democracy, despite democ-
racy exemplifying liberty in a certain sphere of human activity. If democracy
means the right of all citizens to take part in the political process, there is
still the issue of what counts as political. If the scope of politics is minimal,
as in the libertarian framework, that may mean that all may vote on certain
limited issues. For more, see Tibor R. Machan, Private Rights and Public Illu-
sions (New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Books, 1995).
14. For the details of the sort of legal order I am sketching here, see
Randy R. Barnett, Restoring the Lost Constitution: The Presumption of Liberty
(Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2004).
15. For more on this, see Tibor R. Machan and James E. Chesher, “Capi-
talism and Racial Justice,”A Primer on Business Ethics (Lanham, Md.: Row-
man & Littlefield, 2003), chap. 6.
16. See, for example, Liam Murphy and Thomas Nagel, The Myth of Own-
ership, Taxes and Justice (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), and
Stephen Holmes and Cass R. Sunstein, The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty De-
pends on Taxes (New York: W. W. Norton, 1999).
17. The Bill of Rights includes the Ninth Amendment in order to make
clear that not only enumerated rights ought to be respected and protected
in a free society.
18. An exception would be a compact involving children and their par-
ents. For more on this, see Tibor R. Machan, “Between Parents and Chil-
dren,” Journal of Social Philosophy 23 (1992): 16–22.
The Follies of Democratic “Liberalism” / 143
1. On Moral Intuition
145
146 / Chapter 6
Aquinas, Locke, and all the rest of the thinkers associated with
this tradition hardly speak with one voice. Indeed, Machan
himself recognizes the diversity of practices that were once
thought “natural” but no longer are (p. 128). I do not know
why he thinks this diversity is a problem for my theory but
not his; after all, it is his theory, not mine, that purports to be
a “natural” law/rights theory.
Second, Machan’s claim to derive ethical principles directly
from human nature is implausible, because human nature is it-
self a mixed bag, with some good elements and some bad ele-
ments. We probably have built-in tendencies toward sympathy
with and respect for other people, and these are good tenden-
cies. But we probably also have some built-in tendencies to clas-
sify people as “insiders” and “outsiders” and to treat the latter
group worse. We probably have built-in susceptibilities to su-
perstitious thinking—and so on. Thus one needs moral judg-
ment to distinguish between the good and bad elements of
human nature. Once we recognize this, we can see that Machan
is doing essentially the same thing as I am. Like me, he is fixing
his attention on the unique human capacity for choice and
judging that this is a capacity that is worthy of respect. We dif-
fer in what this respect amounts to, but this is a substantive dif-
ference in our moral views. It is not an epistemological
difference in which I rely on “intuition” and he does not.
Third, in his chapter in defense of libertarianism (chapter 1),
Machan himself concedes the need for moral judgment when it
comes to applying his principles. Libertarianism, he there
states, is “not a rigid, deductive system of implied public poli-
cies” (p. 18). He compares the art of applying political theory
with the art of applying medical knowledge, which requires
much uncodifiable judgment in particular situations. All of this
is true and wise and to Machan’s credit. But it flies in the face
of his criticisms of my theory. For I need not appeal to “intu-
ition,” if this is mysteriously thought of as a faculty by which
we gain insight into a rational realm of moral truths that exist
in some Platonic heaven. Instead my appeal is to people’s ca-
Democratic Liberalism Defended / 147
2. On Democracy
then talk to him or her and convince him or her of the wrong-
ness of discrimination.”
Is this enough? No doubt eradicating legally required dis-
crimination is necessary. But it is not enough. Writing in 1955,
the eminent historian C. Van Woodward observed,
within each black pair and each white pair one of the testers
reported that he had spent eighteen months in prison for co-
caine possession. Alarmingly, the white tester who reported a
criminal record was more likely to be called for an interview
(called back 17 percent of the time) than was the black tester
with no criminal record (called back 14 percent of the time).7
Simply being black is apparently more of a liability in the cur-
rent job market than is being a convicted felon.
Other studies back up these results. Economists Marianne
Bertrand and Sendhil Mullainathan, for example, recently sent
out five thousand résumés to 1,300 employers advertising job
openings in Boston and Chicago. The résumés were con-
structed to be identical in quality, the one difference being that
the names on some were black-sounding names like “Jamal”
and “Lakisha,” whereas the names on others were white-
sounding names like “Emily” and “Greg.” Disturbingly, appli-
cants with white-sounding names were 50 percent more likely
to be called for interviews than were those with black-sound-
ing names.8 These studies and others9 reveal a continued need
for anti-discrimination law.10
Notes
1. For some idea of the moral subtleties involved, see Judith Jarvis
Thomson, “Self-Defense,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 20 (1991): 283–310.
2. I explore fairness via the notion of desert in section 7 of chapter 4. I
mention this here because in his critique in chapter 5 Machan spends a good
deal of time (pp. 139ff.) criticizing John Rawls for his attack on notions of
desert. Whatever its merits against Rawls, however, this criticism does not
impugn my defense of democratic liberalism, since far from attacking
desert, I showed how notions of desert support democratic liberalism rather
than libertarianism. Any theory that allows luck as large a role in determin-
Democratic Liberalism Defended / 157
ing people’s fates as libertarianism does is a theory that assuredly fails to re-
spect claims of desert.
3. Machan also errs interpretively in referring to me as a democratic social-
ist (p. 138). Socialism is defined as an economic system in which the means of
production are publicly owned. I am not convinced that such a system is work-
able, at least not without unacceptable costs in other values besides fairness. So
I am in favor of a regulated capitalist economy, and hence am not a socialist.
Perhaps as debates between capitalists and socialists continue, and as socialist
models get defended in ever more detail, I will eventually be persuaded. (The
most likely contender is David Schweickart’s “market socialist” model, which
has no capital markets but does have competitive markets for consumer goods
and factors of production. See David Schweickart, After Capitalism [Lanham,
Md.: Rowman and Littlefield, 2002].) For now, though, I see no alternative to
some form of capitalism. Fortunately there are many such forms. I favor the
form that (as I argue in chapter 4) best respects human dignity.
4. C. Vann Woodward, The Strange Career of Jim Crow (Oxford, U.K.: Oxford
University Press, 1955), 102 [emphasis in the original]. Quoted in Samuel
Freeman, “Illiberal Libertarians: Why Libertarianism Is Not a Liberal View,”
Philosophy and Public Affairs 30 (2001): 135. Freeman argues that libertarianism
ought not to be considered even a version of classical liberalism, inasmuch as
(among other reasons) it shuns all legal devices for combating castelike priv-
ileges—privileges that liberalism from its inception has always opposed.
5. Moreover, sex discrimination still exists. For evidence, see Ian Ayres,
Pervasive Prejudice? Unconventional Evidence of Race and Gender Discrimination
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2003). In speaking of past sex dis-
crimination, my point above is that even when sexual discrimination in pri-
vate employment was as blatant and severe as it was in the past, a
libertarian government would have been powerless to do anything about it.
6. For evidence of the reality of caste discrimination in contemporary In-
dia, see Human Rights Watch, Caste Discrimination: A Global Concern (2001),
available online at www.hrw.org/reports/2001/globalcaste/. Sex discrimi-
nation is also a large problem in India. On this see Martha Nussbaum, “Sex,
Laws, and Inequality: India’s Experience,” Daedalus 131 (2002): 95–106.
7. Devah Pager, “The Mark of a Criminal Record,” American Journal of So-
ciology 108 (2002): 937–75.
8. Sendhil Mullainathan and Marianne Bertrand, “Are Emily and Greg
More Employable than Lakisha and Jamal? A Field Experiment on Labor
Market Discrimination,” American Economic Review 94 (2004): 991–1013; for
a brief summary of their research, see Alan B. Krueger, “Sticks and Stones
Can Break Bones, but the Wrong Name Can Make a Job Hard to Find,” New
York Times, December 12, 2002.
9. E.g., Marc Bendick Jr., Charles W. Jackson, and Victor A. Reinoso, “Mea-
suring Employment Discrimination through Controlled Experiments,” Review
158 / Chapter 6
of Black Political Economy 23 (1994): 25–48; Ayres, Pervasive Prejudice?; see also
the audit studies described in the U.S. Department of Housing and Urban
Development, Housing Discrimination Study 2000, an executive summary
of which is available online at www.huduser.org/Publications/pdf/
Phase1_Executive_Summary.pdf.
10. Libertarians sometimes argue that the invisible hand of economic
competition can be counted on to eliminate discrimination. This takes too
idealized a picture of economic competition. For a persuasive rebuttal, see
Cass Sunstein, Free Markets and Social Justice (New York: Oxford University
Press, 1997), chap. 6.
11. Jefferson writes: “I approved from the first moment of . . . the power of
taxation [in the new Constitution]. I thought at first that [it] might have been
limited. A little reflection soon convinced me it ought not to be.” Letter to Fran-
cis Hopkinson (1789), in The Writings of Thomas Jefferson, ed. Albert Ellery Bergh
(Washington, D.C.: Thomas Jefferson Memorial Association, 1903–1904), 7:300.
Quoted at etext.virginia.edu/jefferson/quotations/jeff1330.htm.
12. Richard K. Matthews, The Radical Politics of Thomas Jefferson
(Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1984), 28. This source makes clear
how removed Jefferson’s political philosophy is in many respects from
Machan’s libertarianism.
13. Letter to James Madison (October 28, 1785), in The Papers of Thomas
Jefferson, ed. Julian P. Boyd (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press,
1950–1982), 8:681–82. Quoted at press-pubs.uchicago.edu/founders/
documents/v1ch15s32.html.
14. For a helpful overview of the variety of political ideologies that figured
in the public debate over ratification of the Constitution, see Isaac Kramnick,
“The ‘Great National Discussion’: The Discourse of Politics in 1787,” William
and Mary Quarterly 45 (1988): 3–32. For a collection of quotations from the
founding fathers specifically to do with property, see press-pubs.uchicago
.edu/founders/tocs/v1ch16.html. On equality, see press-pubs.uchicago.edu/
founders/tocs/v1ch15.html.
15. Benjamin Franklin, Letter to Robert Morris (December 25, 1783), in The
Writings of Benjamin Franklin, ed. Albert Henry Smyth (New York: Macmil-
lan, 1905–1907), 9:138. Quoted at press-pubs.uchicago.edu/founders/
documents/v1ch16s12.html.
16. Paragraph 59 of Thomas Paine, Agrarian Justice. An online version of this
work is available at www.thomaspaine.org/Archives/agjst.html. In this same
work Paine proposed that a national fund be created by a 10 percent tax on in-
heritances. From this fund would be paid old-age pensions (i.e., social secu-
rity), as well as grants to young adults to help them get started in the world of
work.
17. Thomas Jefferson, letter to Samuel Kercheval (July 12, 1816), in The
Works of Thomas Jefferson, ed. Paul Leicester Ford (New York: Knickerbocker,
1904), 12:12. Quoted in Matthews, Radical Politics, 22.
Index
159
160 / Index
safety net. See social safety net tacit consent. See consent
secession, 55–56 taxation: aimed at wealth
second-class citizens. See redistribution, 66;
citizenship, equality of alternatives to, 137–138; vs.
security, 52, 60 charity, 57–61; as consistent
self-defense, right to. See rights with property rights, 101; as
self-governance, 20 contrary to freedom, 27, 135;
self-sufficiency, as a misleading as a form of theft or
ideal, 119 extortion, 26, 74, 136; “no
Sen, Amartya, 27–38, 139 taxation without
sex discrimination. See representation,” 136; as not a
discrimination form of theft or extortion,
sexual harassment, 51, 94, 113 46–48; universities supported
shape, ability to give to a life, by, 137, 143.
90–91, 93, 95–96, 100, 134, 149 Taylor, Charles, 7, 14, 68
skepticism, 24 theft, 23, 26, 46, 50, 61, 72, 74
slander, 94 Third Reich, the, 130
slavery, 11, 67 threats, 84
Sleazo, Joe, 59
social contract, 54, 75, 137 unalienable rights. See rights
social mobility, 123 unemployment: insurance
social safety net, 114 against, 114; rates of, 116
social security, 114, 158 unions, labor, 112–13, 124
socialism, 28, 68, 100, 138, 157 utopian political thought, 38–39,
sociality, human. See human 81, 140
nature
society, conception of, 87–88, Valjean, Jean, 26
120, 129–30 Versailles, 71
Index / 167
169