Week 5 - Chapter 5
Week 5 - Chapter 5
Chapter 5 – Causation
5 - Causation:
5.1 - General:
Causation, or the causing of damage through conduct, is a necessary requirement of a delict and involves a factual enquiry
into all available facts and probabilities.
It is important to distinguish between factual causation, which refers merely to the fact that one event led to another, and
legal causation, which refers to those factually caused events for which the wrongdoer may be held liable. It is necessary for
legal causation to be much narrower than factual causation since one action could have innumerable consequences and it
would not be equitable to hold the wrongdoer liable for all subsequent events.
5.2.1 - General:
The first stage in an enquiry into causation is to determine whether or not the conduct of the wrongdoer in fact led to the
damage suffered. This is not generally a problem in practice and as a rule the courts merely determine whether one fact
follows on from another.
The dominant theoretically approach in this regard is what is known as the conditio sine qua non theory, which will be dealt
with in more detail below.
According to the "but for" test, an act is the cause of a result if the act cannot be thought away without the result
disappearing simultaneously. The act must in other words be the conditio sine qua non of the result.
An act is the juridically relevant sole cause of a result if the act cannot be thought away without the result disappearing
simultaneously. An act is the juridically relevant joint cause of a result if the act in itself can be thought away without the
result disappearing simultaneously, but cannot, in conjunction with another juridically relevant act or acts which can on their
own be thought away without the result disappearing simultaneously, be though away without the result disappearing
simultaneously.
In cases of a positive act, such act must be 'thought away' but the position in the case of an omission is less clear. According to
the Constitutional Court, an omission must be thought away by substituting such omission for the act that would have been
taken by the reasonable person in the place of the defendant.
However, Harms JA (formerly of the Supreme Court of Appeal) disagrees and believes that the correct approach is to consider
not only the action that would be taken by the reasonable person (the objective action) but also the action that the
defendant would have taken in the situation, had he/she/it taken action. See in this regard Minister of Safety and Security v
Carmichele 2004 (3) SA 305 (SCA) 329.
The conditio sine qua non theory, although still widely accepted and referred to, has been subject to considerable criticism,
some of which is outlined below.
(a) The conditio sine qua non theory is based on a clumsy, indirect process of thought that results in circular logic; and
(b) The conditio sine qua non test fails completely in cases of so-called cumulative causation; and
(c) The conditio sine qua non test is not, in fact, a test for causation but rather an ex post facto way of expressing a
predetermined causal nexus.
S v Mokgethi 1990 (1) SA 32 (A) [Prescribed]:
In casu, a bank teller was shot and paralysed during a robbery. Upon release from the hospital he was told to shift in his chair
to avoid pressure sores and septicaemia.
Held that one could, and indeed must, utilise evidence from other sources (in this case medical practitioners) to determine a
causal nexus.
International Shipping Co (PTY) LTD v Bentley 1990 (1) SA 680 (A) [Prescribed]:
In casu,
Held that in applying the conditio sine qua non, the court must give regard to the other factors which may have led to the
result.
Note must be taken here that although still referred to as an application of the conditio sine qua non test, this is not strictly
true in a theoretical sense since in the case of an omission was is not eliminating something in the mind but is rather adding it
in.
In casu, a policeman neglected to search for children who had fled into the night and later died of exposure.
Held that the test in the case of an omission was to insert positive reasonable conduct in place of the omission and then apply
the "but for" test.
In casu,
Held that the test in the case of an omission was to insert positive reasonable conduct in place of the omission and then apply
the "but for" test.
In light of the above, it is clearly not correct to refer to condition sine qua non as a genuine test for causation and the
question then is what should be used in its place.
In essence, determining factual causation is nothing more than a logical examination of two facts or sets of facts and whether
the one has given rise to the other. Due to the complex and ever-changing nature of reality, it is suggested that it would be
impossible to formulate a general test for factual causation, moreover, there are doubts as to whether such a test, if possible,
would be necessary.
Furthermore, whilst the legal determination of factual causation may, and in many cases must, be informed by other
disciplines, it is important to note that the approaches to causation will differ drastically between fields.
It is also worth noting that the conduct of the wrongdoer need not be the only or even the primary cause of the damage
suffered for there to be factual causation.
5.3 - Legal Causation:
5.3.1 - General:
As previously stated, the mere existence of a factual causal nexus does not mean that the defendant
will be held liable since one act may have many consequences and as such an enquiry into causation
must also include an enquiry into legal causation (otherwise referred to as “limitation of liability” or
“imputability of harm”).
As a general rule, a wrongdoer will not be held liable for harm which is too remote from his/her/its
wrongful conduct.
It is worth noting that in practice there is rarely a need to enquire into legal causation expressly since
this can usually be dealt with tacitly under the investigations into wrongfulness or fault.
Furthermore, an investigation into legal causation is not the only manner in which one can limit the
liability of the wrongdoer – the determination or otherwise of wrongfulness and fault will also have
an impact here. Legal causation will be used to limit the liability of the defendant primarily where the
defendant is to be held liable for certain consequences of his/her/its act and not others.
The current position of our courts on legal causation was set out by the Appellate Division in the case
of S v Mokgethi 1990 (1) SA 32 (A).
The so-called flexible approach, which does not involve a single general criterion but rather whether
or not there is a close enough relationship between the wrongdoer’s conduct and its consequences
for such consequence to be imputed to the wrongdoer in view of policy considerations based on
reasonableness, fairness and justice.
According to the adequate causation theory a consequence which has in fact been caused by the
wrongdoer is imputed to him/her/it if the consequence is adequately linked to the conduct. The
connection is termed adequate if, according to human experience, in the normal course of events
the act has the tendency of bringing about that type of consequence.
In order to determine whether or not an act has the tendency of bringing about a certain
consequence, the following should be asked:
Joubert further notes that a determination of adequate consequences involves the employment of
the knowledge which an ordinary sensible person would have under the circumstances as well as any
specific information which the wrongdoer may have been in possession of at the time. In addition, in
determining the probable result, one must employ all human knowledge, including that only
available to specialists or that only came to light after the fact.
5.3.4 - Direct Consequences:
According to the (English Law) theory of direct consequences, an actor is liable for all the direct
physical consequences of his/her/its actions, provided that there has been no novus actus
Interveniens and that the consequences are suffered by a person whom the wrongdoer could
reasonably have foreseen suffering harm from his/her/its conduct. In other words, liability is not
strictly limited to the reasonably foreseeable consequences and an act and its consequences may be
separate in both space and time.
This theory has only been accepted eo nomine [in so many words] in the reported cases of Fourway
Haulage SA (PTY) LTD v SA National Roads Agency Ltd 2009 (2) SA 150 (SCA) 165 and Frenkel & Co
v Cadle 1915 NPD 173.
It has been suggested that it will only find application in the South African law of delict, as a
subsidiary to the flexible approach, in the so-called egg-skull cases of personal injury.
In casu, the railway company left green twigs next to a railway line. Upon drying, these ignited and
caused damage to a nearby house.
Held that a person is liable for the direct consequences of his/he/its negligent act.
In casu, an employee negligently dropped a plank into the hold of a ship which was filled with petrol
fumes.
Held that a person is liable for the direct consequences of his/he/its negligent act.
In casu, the plaintiff’s husband was injured in an accident and as a result got depressed and
committed suicide.
Held that a person is liable for the direct consequences of his/he/its negligent act.
Overseas Tankship (UK) v Morts Dock and Engineering (Wagon Mound No 1) [1961] All ER 404 (PC):
In casu, the defendants negligently spilled oil from their ship into Sydney harbour. It caught alight
and damaged two ships belonging to the plaintiff.
In casu, a motorcyclist drove negligently past a tram and collided with a car. A passenger, on the
otherside of the tram, for distressed by the sight of the blood coming under the tram.
Held that the direct consequences theory would produce inequitable results and as such the
foreseeable plaintiff theory was introduced.
Held, further, that in terms of the foreseeable plaintiff theory the motorcyclist was liable to the
driver and owner of the motor vehicle but not the passenger of the tram since he could not
reasonably have foreseen that she would suffer damage as a result of his conduct.
5.3.5 - Fault:
Traditionally, this has been the approach most often followed by South African Courts, but it has by
no means been clearly defined, the decision of the Court usually merely reflects that a certain result
was or was not foreseeable.
According to Van Der Walt and Midgley, it is not necessary for the exact extent or precise manner of
the harm to have been foreseeable, it is merely necessary for the general nature of the harm to have
been foreseeable and there to have been a real risk which the reasonable person would not have
brushed aside.
Van Rensburg proposes the following as a general test to be applied pending a decision by the courts:
Was the consequence, as well as the causal progression between the act and its consequence, at the
time of the act foreseeable with such a degree of probability that the consequences can, in light of
the circumstances, reasonably be imputed to the alleged wrongdoer?
In addition, Van Rensburg provides that the basis of considering probability is formed by the
following:
(1) ‘The facts of which the reasonable man in the position of the actor would have taken
note, augmented by the actor’s special knowledge’;
(2) That where the events ‘took quite an unusual turn … the adjudicator also has to decide
whether the causal chain of events was foreseeable with a sufficient amount of probability
to render the actor liable in respect of the result or results that eventuated in such
extraordinary way’;
(3) That the extent of the harm never needs to be foreseeable in order for the wrongdoer to
be liable for it;
(4) That the criterion and principles referred to apply similarly to intentional and negligent
wrongful conduct; and
(5) That the reprehensible motive of a wrongdoer who acts intentionally, would probably
play a role in determining legal causation.
Even though the matter is usually settled after an examination into fault and without an express
examination of legal causation, care must be taken to avoid confusing the requirements for fault and
legal causation, since in the case of the former the reasonable person is not, so to speak, in the shoes
of the wrongdoer but standing next to him/her/it.
5.3.7 - Novus Actus Interveniens: A novus actus interveniens [new intervening cause] is an
independent event which, after the wrongdoer’s act has been concluded, either caused or
contributed to the consequence concerned.
Where such a cause arises and completely extinguishes the causal link, then there is no factual
causation and as such there can be no legal causation.
However, where the novus actus interveniens does not extinguish factual causation, it may have
influenced the result to such an extent that the wrongdoer will not be held liable (there will be no
legal causation).
The requirements for a novus actus interveniens to sever the legal nexus will depend on the
particular approach to legal causation applied in that case.
In terms of the flexible approach, the question is whether or not the novus actus is such that liability
cannot be imputed to the defendant on the basis of policy, reasonability, fairness and justice.
When applying the direct consequences theory, the test is whether or the novus actus broke the
‘directness’ of the causal chain.
When using the reasonable foreseeability approach, the determining factor is whether or not the
novus actus is such that it prevents the consequence from being reasonably foreseeable.
A novus actus may be brought about by the (culpable) action of the plaintiff, a third party or natural
factors. Note must be taken that an act will only qualify as a novus actus if it was not, at the time of
the wrongful conduct, reasonably foreseeable.
In casu, the plaintiff slipped and fell and fractured his already fractured bone.
Held that since this act was not foreseeable, it constituted a novus actus interveniens.
Egg-skull cases arise where the plaintiff, because of one or other physical, psychological or financial
weakness, suffers more serious injury or loss as a result of the wrongdoer’s conduct than would have
been the case if the plaintiff had not suffered such a weakness.
It is generally accepted that the wrongdoer in this case will be liable for the full extent of the damage
suffered, in keeping with the maxim of “take your victim as you find him”.
According to Van Rensburg, this is the case because, for the most part, egg-skull cases arise where
the wrongdoer has threatened the plaintiff’s most precious legal interest – his/her physical-mental
integrity and it is mere coincidental that the harm arose in another manner.
Van der Walt and Midgley link this concept in cases of physical injury to the direct consequences
theory (see above).
By contrast, Van der Merwe and Olivier reject this doctrine as it does not coincide with their strict
adherence to fault as a criterion for the imputability of harm.
In casu, the plaintiff (who relied on his vehicle for financial subsistence) was forced to rent a vehicle
after his own was irreparably damaged by the defendant.
Held that the fact that the plaintiff in a particular case was a so called “egg-skull case” was merely
another factor to be considered when determining causation under the flexible approach.
Chapter 5 – Causation
Introduction
a causal nexus between conduct and damage is required for a delict.
Causation is a question of fact which must always be answered in light of the
available evidence and relevant probabilities.
A causal nexus is simply something which (factually) exists or doesn’t exist.
Factual causation and legal causation.
Koch case = medical evidence
- Court had to decide whether the defendant, the 3 rd party insurer of a vehicle, with which
the driver negligently smashed into the rear of the plaintiffs vehicle.
- Could the defendant be held liable for expenses incurred as a result of a thrombosis
which was allegedly causes by a persistent state of anxiety, arising from the neck injury
which the P suffered during the injury?
- Court held that on medical evidence it was impossible to say that the eventual
thrombosis was a result of the accident.
- The condition sine qua non test fails completely in cases of so-called cumulative
causation: cumulative causation occurs where more than 1 act cause a particular
consequence. Example X and Y shoot Z in the head simultaneously.
- The condition sine qua non test is in fact not a test of causation because its merely an ex
post facto way of expressing a predetermined causal nexus: this is the most important
reason why this theory is unacceptable as a test for causation. One can only employ this
theory after one has in some or other way already determined the cause of the
particular consequence (causal nexus between an act and a particular result). Example Y
gives X a beer, after drinking it X dies...one cannot establish whether the beer in fact led
to the death of X.
Legal causation
- GENERAL:
No legal system holds a wrongdoer liable without some limitation for the endless
chain of harmful consequences which his act may have caused.
The question of legal causation arises when determining which harmful
consequences actually caused by the wrongdoers wrongful, culpable act he
should be held liable for, i.e. which consequences should be imputed to him.
Normally legal causation is only problematic where a chain of consecutive or
remote consequences results from the wrongdoers conduct, and where its
alleged that he should not be held legally responsible for all the consequences.
The concepts legal causation, limitation of liability and imputability of harm are
used synonymously to indicate the process whereby the court determines which
of the heads of damage caused by an actor he should be held liable for:
- Clarke v Hurst = the question is whether the result can fairly be said to be imputable to
the defendant.
- Smit + Nedperm bank ltd = its still necessary to determine legal causation, i.e. whether
there is a sufficiently close or direct link between the defendants wrongful act and the
loss for legal liability to ensue.
Legal causation as an independent element arises specifically where it appears
that the wrongdoers conduct was wrongful and culpable with reference to at
least certain consequences and that the consequences should in addition be
imputed to him.
What criterion should be used to determine legal causation = there a 4 theories
which will now be discussed:
LQ Determining causation?
CAUSATION: ***
Factual? Accepted CSQN tests fin stats – think away present
Legal causation? Confirmed Mokgethi (flexible approach necessary)
ABSENT… wasn’t an act for which the auditor can be held liable; Lapse
of time – long!!! Long since fin troubles established:
Intervening conduct of plaintiff’s employees continued to give out
credit
Foreseeability of damages? because later become aware of financial
problems.
D claim dismissed
- 1ST Q FACTUAL: whether the defendant’s wrongful act was a cause of the
plaintiff’s loss?
- But-for test: enquire what would have happened but for the wrongful
conduct of defendant
No legal liability if wrongful act is shown not to be a causa sine qua non
S v Mokgethi
LQ
S v Van As
F - Policeman neglected to search for children who fled and died of exposure
in the night
-
F Mr Lee contracted tuberculosis (TB) while in prison. He sued the Minister for
damages on the basis that the poor prison health management resulted in his
becoming infected.
LQ
J - Our law has always recognised that the test for factual causation should
not be applied inflexibly as was done by the SCA
- Unlikely that any inmate will ever be able to overcome the hurdle of
causation and further that no effective alternate remedy will be available
to a person in the position of the applicant
D
Smit v Abrahams
F - Defendant chose to rent a car because of his own impecuniosity was unable
to purchase a replacement vehicle.
LQ
LQ
F - Railway company
- Twigs; ignited by passing train spark shoot off
- Fire spread rapidly and burnt down a house
LQ
Polemis
I DIRECT CONSEQUENCES
LQ
Pigney
LQ
I Direct consequences
F - In an attempt to help passenger on to train.
- Knocked packet out of hand which contained fireworks
- A huge explosion ensued; a large scale was dislodged and fell onto
another passenger.
LQ
J - Conductor and railway company can only be held liable for conduct in
causing the explosion from the falling fireworks
- Not reasonably foreseeable that scale would be dislodged and would fall
on and injure another passenger.
Bourhill v Young
LQ
LQ
Wagon Mound II
F SIMILAR TO ABOVE
- Two ships next to each other and different owners
- Defendant’s ship leaked oil into the harbor. Welders working. Plaintiff and
defendant’s ships destroyed
LQ