Argument - Wikipedia
Argument - Wikipedia
Arguments are intended to determine or show the degree of truth or acceptability of another
statement called a conclusion.[2][3] The process of crafting or delivering arguments,
argumentation, can be studied from three main perspectives: the logical, the dialectical and
the rhetorical perspective.[4]
In logic, an argument is usually expressed not in natural language but in a symbolic formal
language, and it can be defined as any group of propositions of which one is claimed to
follow from the others through deductively valid inferences that preserve truth from the
premises to the conclusion. This logical perspective on argument is relevant for scientific
fields such as mathematics and computer science. Logic is the study of the forms of
reasoning in arguments and the development of standards and criteria to evaluate
arguments.[5] Deductive arguments can be valid, and the valid ones can be sound: in a valid
argument, premisses necessitate the conclusion, even if one or more of the premises is false
and the conclusion is false; in a sound argument, true premises necessitate a true
conclusion. Inductive arguments, by contrast, can have different degrees of logical strength:
the stronger or more cogent the argument, the greater the probability that the conclusion is
true, the weaker the argument, the lesser that probability.[6] The standards for evaluating non-
deductive arguments may rest on different or additional criteria than truth—for example, the
persuasiveness of so-called "indispensability claims" in transcendental arguments,[7] the
quality of hypotheses in retroduction, or even the disclosure of new possibilities for thinking
and acting.[8]
In dialectics, and also in a more colloquial sense, an argument can be conceived as a social
and verbal means of trying to resolve, or at least contend with, a conflict or difference of
opinion that has arisen or exists between two or more parties.[9] For the rhetorical
perspective, the argument is constitutively linked with the context, in particular with the time
and place in which the argument is located. From this perspective, the argument is evaluated
not just by two parties (as in a dialectical approach) but also by an audience.[10] In both
dialectic and rhetoric, arguments are used not through formal but through natural language.
Since classical antiquity, philosophers and rhetoricians have developed lists of argument
types in which premises and conclusions are connected in informal and defeasible ways.[11]
Etymology
The Latin root arguere (to make bright, enlighten, make known, prove, etc.) is from Proto-Indo-
European argu-yo-, suffixed form of arg- (to shine; white).[12]
Argument terminology
There are several kinds of arguments in logic, the best known of which are "deductive" and
"inductive." An argument has one or more premises but only one conclusion. Each premise
and the conclusion are truth bearers or "truth-candidates", each capable of being either true
or false (but not both). These truth values bear on the terminology used with arguments.
Deductive arguments
A deductive argument asserts that the truth of the conclusion is a logical consequence of the
premises: if the premises are true, the conclusion must be true. It would be self-contradictory
to assert the premises and deny the conclusion because the negation of the conclusion is
contradictory to the truth of the premises. Based on the premises, the conclusion follows
necessarily (with certainty). Given premises that A=B and B=C, then the conclusion follows
necessarily that A=C. Deductive arguments are sometimes referred to as "truth-preserving"
arguments. For example, consider the argument that because bats can fly (premise=true),
and all flying creatures are birds (premise=false), therefore bats are birds (conclusion=false).
If we assume the premises are true, the conclusion follows necessarily, and it is a valid
argument.
Validity
In terms of validity, deductive arguments may be either valid or invalid. An argument is valid, if
and only if (iff) it is impossible in all possible worlds for the premises to be true and the
conclusion false; validity is about what is possible; it is concerned with how the premises and
conclusion relate and what is possible.[1] An argument is formally valid if and only if the
denial of the conclusion is incompatible with accepting all the premises.
In formal logic, the validity of an argument depends not on the actual truth or falsity of its
premises and conclusion, but on whether the argument has a valid logical form. The validity
of an argument is not a guarantee of the truth of its conclusion. A valid argument may have
false premises that render it inconclusive: the conclusion of a valid argument with one or
more false premises may be true or false.
Logic seeks to discover the forms that make arguments valid. A form of argument is valid if
and only if the conclusion is true under all interpretations of that argument in which the
premises are true. Since the validity of an argument depends on its form, an argument can be
shown invalid by showing that its form is invalid. This can be done by a counter example of
the same form of argument with premises that are true under a given interpretation, but a
conclusion that is false under that interpretation. In informal logic this is called a counter
argument.
The form of an argument can be shown by the use of symbols. For each argument form,
there is a corresponding statement form, called a corresponding conditional, and an
argument form is valid if and only if its corresponding conditional is a logical truth. A
statement form which is logically true is also said to be a valid statement form. A statement
form is a logical truth if it is true under all interpretations. A statement form can be shown to
be a logical truth by either (a) showing that it is a tautology or (b) by means of a proof
procedure.
The corresponding conditional of a valid argument is a necessary truth (true in all possible
worlds) and so the conclusion necessarily follows from the premises, or follows of logical
necessity. The conclusion of a valid argument is not necessarily true, it depends on whether
the premises are true. If the conclusion, itself, is a necessary truth, it is without regard to the
premises.
Some examples:
The forms of argument that render deductions valid are well-established, however some
invalid arguments can also be persuasive depending on their construction (inductive
arguments, for example). (See also: Formal fallacy and Informal fallacy).
Soundness
An argument is sound when the argument is valid and argument's premise(s) is/are true,
therefore the conclusion is true.
Inductive arguments
An inductive argument asserts that the truth of the conclusion is supported by the probability
of the premises. For example, given that the military budget of the United States is the largest
in the world (premise=true), then it is probable that it will remain so for the next 10 years
(conclusion=true). Arguments that involve predictions are inductive since the future is
uncertain. An inductive argument is said to be strong or weak. If the premises of an inductive
argument are assumed true, is it probable the conclusion is also true? If yes, the argument is
strong. If no, it is weak. A strong argument is said to be cogent if it has all true premises.
Otherwise, the argument is uncogent. The military budget argument example is a strong,
cogent argument.
Non-deductive logic is reasoning using arguments in which the premises support the
conclusion but do not entail it. Forms of non-deductive logic include the statistical syllogism,
which argues from generalizations true for the most part, and induction, a form of reasoning
that makes generalizations based on individual instances. An inductive argument is said to
be cogent if and only if the truth of the argument's premises would render the truth of the
conclusion probable (i.e., the argument is strong), and the argument's premises are, in fact,
true. Cogency can be considered inductive logic's analogue to deductive logic's "soundness".
Despite its name, mathematical induction is not a form of inductive reasoning. The lack of
deductive validity is known as the problem of induction.
Defeasible arguments and
argumentation schemes
In modern argumentation theories, arguments are regarded as defeasible passages from
premises to a conclusion. Defeasibility means that when additional information (new
evidence or contrary arguments) is provided, the premises may be no longer lead to the
conclusion (non-monotonic reasoning). This type of reasoning is referred to as defeasible
reasoning. For instance we consider the famous Tweety example:
Tweety is a bird.
Birds generally fly.
Therefore, Tweety (probably) flies.
This argument is reasonable and the premises support the conclusion unless additional
information indicating that the case is an exception comes in. If Tweety is a penguin, the
inference is no longer justified by the premise. Defeasible arguments are based on
generalizations that hold only in the majority of cases, but are subject to exceptions and
defaults.
In order to represent and assess defeasible reasoning, it is necessary to combine the logical
rules (governing the acceptance of a conclusion based on the acceptance of its premises)
with rules of material inference, governing how a premise can support a given conclusion
(whether it is reasonable or not to draw a specific conclusion from a specific description of a
state of affairs).
Argumentation schemes have been developed to describe and assess the acceptability or the
fallaciousness of defeasible arguments. Argumentation schemes are stereotypical patterns
of inference, combining semantic-ontological relations with types of reasoning and logical
axioms and representing the abstract structure of the most common types of natural
arguments.[13] A typical example is the argument from expert opinion, shown below, which
has two premises and a conclusion.[14]
Argument from expert opinion
Each scheme may be associated with a set of critical questions, namely criteria for assessing
dialectically the reasonableness and acceptability of an argument. The matching critical
questions are the standard ways of casting the argument into doubt.
By analogy
Argument by analogy may be thought of as argument from the particular to particular. An
argument by analogy may use a particular truth in a premise to argue towards a similar
particular truth in the conclusion. For example, if A. Plato was mortal, and B. Socrates was
like Plato in other respects, then asserting that C. Socrates was mortal is an example of
argument by analogy because the reasoning employed in it proceeds from a particular truth
in a premise (Plato was mortal) to a similar particular truth in the conclusion, namely that
Socrates was mortal.
Other kinds
Other kinds of arguments may have different or additional standards of validity or
justification. For example, philosopher Charles Taylor said that so-called transcendental
arguments are made up of a "chain of indispensability claims" that attempt to show why
something is necessarily true based on its connection to our experience,[15] while Nikolas
Kompridis has suggested that there are two types of "fallible" arguments: one based on truth
claims, and the other based on the time-responsive disclosure of possibility (world
disclosure).[16] Kompridis said that the French philosopher Michel Foucault was a prominent
advocate of this latter form of philosophical argument.[17]
World-disclosing
World-disclosing arguments are a group of philosophical arguments that according to
Nikolas Kompridis employ a disclosive approach, to reveal features of a wider ontological or
cultural-linguistic understanding—a "world", in a specifically ontological sense—in order to
clarify or transform the background of meaning (tacit knowledge) and what Kompridis has
called the "logical space" on which an argument implicitly depends.[18]
Explanations
While arguments attempt to show that something was, is, will be, or should be the case,
explanations try to show why or how something is or will be. If Fred and Joe address the
issue of whether or not Fred's cat has fleas, Joe may state: "Fred, your cat has fleas. Observe,
the cat is scratching right now." Joe has made an argument that the cat has fleas. However, if
Joe asks Fred, "Why is your cat scratching itself?" the explanation, "... because it has fleas."
provides understanding.
Both the above argument and explanation require knowing the generalities that a) fleas often
cause itching, and b) that one often scratches to relieve itching. The difference is in the
intent: an argument attempts to settle whether or not some claim is true, and an explanation
attempts to provide understanding of the event. Note, that by subsuming the specific event
(of Fred's cat scratching) as an instance of the general rule that "animals scratch themselves
when they have fleas", Joe will no longer wonder why Fred's cat is scratching itself.
Arguments address problems of belief, explanations address problems of understanding. In
the argument above, the statement, "Fred's cat has fleas" is up for debate (i.e. is a claim), but
in the explanation, the statement, "Fred's cat has fleas" is assumed to be true (unquestioned
at this time) and just needs explaining.[19]
Arguments and explanations largely resemble each other in rhetorical use. This is the cause
of much difficulty in thinking critically about claims. There are several reasons for this
difficulty.
People often are not themselves clear
on whether they are arguing for or
explaining something.
The same types of words and phrases
are used in presenting explanations
and arguments.
The terms 'explain' or 'explanation,' et
cetera are frequently used in
arguments.
Explanations are often used within
arguments and presented so as to
serve as arguments.[20]
Likewise, "... arguments are essential
to the process of justifying the validity
of any explanation as there are often
multiple explanations for any given
phenomenon."[19]
Explanations and arguments are often studied in the field of information systems to help
explain user acceptance of knowledge-based systems. Certain argument types may fit better
with personality traits to enhance acceptance by individuals.[21]
One type of fallacy occurs when a word frequently used to indicate a conclusion is used as a
transition (conjunctive adverb) between independent clauses. In English the words therefore,
so, because and hence typically separate the premises from the conclusion of an argument.
Thus: Socrates is a man, all men are mortal therefore Socrates is mortal is an argument
because the assertion Socrates is mortal follows from the preceding statements. However, I
was thirsty and therefore I drank is not an argument, despite its appearance. It is not being
claimed that I drank is logically entailed by I was thirsty. The therefore in this sentence
indicates for that reason not it follows that.
Elliptical or ethymematic
arguments
Often an argument is invalid or weak because there is a missing premise—the supply of
which would make it valid or strong. This is referred to as an elliptical or enthymematic
argument (see also Enthymeme § Syllogism with an unstated premise). Speakers and writers
will often leave out a necessary premise in their reasoning if it is widely accepted and the
writer does not wish to state the blindingly obvious. Example: All metals expand when heated,
therefore iron will expand when heated. The missing premise is: Iron is a metal. On the other
hand, a seemingly valid argument may be found to lack a premise—a "hidden assumption"—
which, if highlighted, can show a fault in reasoning. Example: A witness reasoned: Nobody
came out the front door except the milkman; therefore the murderer must have left by the back
door. The hidden assumptions are: (1) the milkman was not the murderer and (2) the
murderer has left (3) by a door and (4) not by e.g. a window or through an 'ole in 't roof and (5)
there are no other doors than the front or back door.
Argument mining
The goal of argument mining is the automatic extraction and identification of argumentative
structures from natural language text with the aid of computer programs.[22] Such
argumentative structures include the premise, conclusions, the argument scheme and the
relationship between the main and subsidiary argument, or the main and counter-argument
within discourse.[23][24]
See also
Philosophy
portal
Abductive reasoning
Argument map
Argumentation theory
Bayes' theorem
Belief bias
Boolean logic
Cosmological argument
Critical thinking
Dialectic
Evidence
Evidence-based policy
Inquiry
Logical reasoning
Practical arguments
Proof (truth)
Soundness theorem
Syllogism
Notes
References
Further reading
Retrieved from
"https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?
title=Argument&oldid=1212010451"