ZALAZAR - Early Breakdown of The Modern Anthropos
ZALAZAR - Early Breakdown of The Modern Anthropos
BELISARIO ZALAZAR
UNIVERSIDAD NACIONAL DE CÓRDOBA (Argentina)
[email protected]
Published in Mitologias Hoy vol. 22, December 202, pp. 161-174. Universitat Autònoma de
Barcelona, Spain.
Abstract: In this article text we will undertake a posthuman reading (Braidotti, 2015) of Andrés
Vaccari’s novel La Pasión de Descartes. The story of the relationship between Descartes and the
automaton Francine questions the nodal concepts of modern Western philosophy such as the “subject”,
the “immaterial soul” and its secular substitute, “consciousness”, and the very notion of “life”. Figures
like the automaton Francine and her posmodern heirs, such as the cyborg (Haraway), or in our 21st
century the fembot Sophia, developed by Hanson Robotics, enter, from the very beginning and with the
Cartesian metaphysic, in the narrative of modernization, either to destabilize or to reinforce the powers
of the anthropos as the main regulator of the global becoming of the Western form of life. We will
dedicate these pages to go over through a scene of this story, the one of the modern subject, nowadays
crossed by the announcement of many “ends” announces and too many “post-”s. (humanism / human /
biological / natural).
Who directs the scene? Of deceivers, bottomless abysses and transhumanist narratives
The issue becomes complicated when we realize that the machine-mundi, the theater that represents
thought, is directed by the strange and disturbing (unheimlich) character of De la Vega. If, on the one
hand, De la Vega poses a danger to the human exceptionality of the Cartesian story by denying the
primacy of “I think,” on the other hand, it can be thought of as that desiring force without foundation
beyond itself that he tells us about. Serrano Marin. De la Vega would not only be the “deceiver”, who in
his play corresponds to the shadow that haunts Descartes throughout his life, a spectral and pressing
presence especially in the “Sixth Chapter” and the “Epilogue”. ; Furthermore, and through his complete
work, he represents the force behind the machine and urges it to self-design in an infinite engineering
career, without limits. If we were content with the analysis of his figure as a radical materialist “all” a La
Mettrie, perhaps it would not be a big problem for the Cartesian rationalism to which the Epicurean
doctor claimed to do justice by separating it from superstitions such as the immaterial soul. Let us
remember that Julien Offray de La Mettrie radicalized the Cartesian intuition according to which living
beings, animals and humans, shared with everything that made up the material universe the fact of
being complex mechanisms: bodies are machines whose functioning can be known through rational
elucidation (e.g. the new science), and ultimately not only repaired but improved and perfected. The
germ of transhumanist narratives was already found in this materialist metaphor. If Descartes, as
Schaeffer affirms, separates the human from the res extenso - Nature described through the nascent
scientific method applied by new sciences such as anatomy, modern medicine, astronomy, among others
- through the thesis of the cogito, the soul immaterial that redeems him from the mechanistic laws that
govern the entire universe, La Mettrie eliminates what for him is nothing more than a metaphysical
FOOTNOTES
1. Vicente Serrano Marín in his essay Dreaming Monsters. Terror and delirium in modernity (2010)
undertakes an extensive rewriting of the philosophical concept of modernity, while detaching it from its
coincidence with a stage that is often thought of as its definitive and characteristic face: the
Enlightenment. The Spanish author shows in his journey that since the beginning of modernity that was
born with Descartes, the element of the “I”, the “subject” and its deployment (which in the French
thinker occurs through the ingenuity of analytical geometry (with its spaces of action in the planes of
representation) on which this not only epistemological, but also civilizational project of achieving the
3. “The first to use the expression machina mundi ('the machine of the world') was the Roman poet
Lucretius (94-55 BC) in his work De rerum natura. The metaphor (for that was what it was, evidently)
was so apt that it did not take long to make a fortune, to such an extent that in subsequent centuries it
was used by European writers and philosophers to designate the complexity of the world. Perhaps the
first to fully develop it, beyond its purely poetic sense, was the Roman writer and politician Cicero (106-
43 BC) [...] In The Nature of the Gods Cicero compared the precision and order with which it worked the
Cosmos - the work, according to him, of the Stoic Creator - with Archimedes' world machine, a hydraulic
automaton built more than 150 years ago by the Greek mathematician. […] What the mechanistic and
materialist scientists and philosophers [of the 16th, 17th and 18th centuries] were going to put on the
table in the following centuries will no longer be merely a metaphor, but a new theory of life that started
from the fact —verifiable, according to them—that the bodies of animals and men were machines. Not
'as if they were', but they were” (Alonso Burgos, 2017: 53-56).
4. In his Discourse on the Dignity of Man Giovani Pico della Mirandola elaborates one of the first
attempts to find the place of man in the Cosmos in a period where the harmony of the divine Order of
the Middle Ages, which in turn is a model and royal law of the social and terrestrial order began to
shatter and the figure of Man began to appear drawn with the brush of the Humanist movement. This
seemingly indefinite position, the last of the creations of the Supreme Father God, the architect who is
man, nevertheless allows him to be located in an empty center that is paradoxically mobile, capable of
occupying any part of the world ordered by divine laws. Potentially man is capable of ascending to the
very height of the Supreme Father. The hierarchy is then decided in and based on the work of man (his
intention and his judgment) as long as he knows how to take advantage of the perfectibility that defines
him. “To the nascent man the Father conferred seeds of every kind and germs of all life. And according
to how each man has cultivated them, they will mature in him and give him their fruits. If they were
vegetables, they will become a plant; if sensitive, they will become brutal; if rational, it will be elevated
to a celestial animal; if intellectuals, it will be an angel or son of God; and if, not content with the lot of
any creature, he withdraws into the center of his unity, transformed into a spirit alone with God in the
lonely darkness of the Father, he, who was placed above all things, will be above of all of them.” (Pico
della Mirandola, 2008: 209).
6. Project sustained by a set of knowledge, practices and technologies that converge in what critical
posthumanists like Braidotti call Humanism: “At the beginning of everything there is He, the classical
ideal of Man, identified by Protagoras as 'the measure of all things'. ', later elevated by the Italian
Renaissance to the level of a universal model, represented by Leonardo da Vinci in the Vitruvian Man.
An ideal of bodily perfection that […] evolves towards a series of intellectual, discursive and spiritual
values. Together, these support a precise conception of what is human about humanity. Furthermore,
they assert with unwavering certainty the almost unlimited human capacity to pursue individual and
collective perfection. This iconic image is the symbol of the doctrine of humanism, which interprets the
empowerment of biological, rational and moral human capacities in light of the concept of teleologically
oriented rational progress” (Braidotti, 2015: 25).
7. “'Transhumanism is a philosophical movement that enacts the advent of a future state of humanity,
called 'posthumanity.' It is a future in which humanity will have rationally intervened in its own
evolution to reinvent itself in accordance with its own dreams and aspirations, thus transcending the
natural prerogative of its existence and realizing its full potential […] Nick Bostrom, the most prominent
transhumanist thinker currently, he asserts: 'Ultimately, it is possible that these optimizations could
make us, or our descendants, 'posthumans', beings with indefinite longevity, intellectual faculties much
greater than those of any current human being (and perhaps sensitivities). or completely new
modalities), as well as the ability to control their own emotions'” (Vaccari, 2014: 238). Transhumanism,
the son of the material culture of our hyper-technological Globe, proposes to use the technologies
developed in the last decades of the 20th century and so far in the 21st century to produce a better
human”, enhancing and perfecting, or redesigning, our cognitive abilities. , perceptual and biological.
This possible “artificial redesign of the human body and intervention on the molecular bases of life on
earth” (Ludueña Romandini, 2010: 200; italics in the original) is based on a budget, an artifact similar to
the one used by Descartes to found all of life. his philosophy on the foundations of cogito: the “appeal to
values that appear to be universal or self-evident, [i.e.], assumes that we all agree on what constitutes a
'better' human and that it would be ridiculous to oppose something that is better ” (Vaccari, 2014: 241).
On the question of the Cartesian artifact, as we already said, it is a risky thesis by both Serrano Marín
and Schaeffer, with very different claims and arguments. Schaeffer states it like this: “Cartesianism is
the determination of man as ego. The possibility remains that this determination is nothing more than
an artifact. If this were the case, then the privilege granted to the self-founding value of consciousness,
far from constituting the unbreakable foundation of all knowledge of the human being, would be
exposed to prohibiting us from accessing the knowledge of what we are” (2009: 59).
8. In that same movement he takes up the challenge launched by the Cartesian project of engineering
the mechanisms that make up the res extenso, in which man of course participates as a material entity.
Vaccari writes about it: “We should not be surprised that Descartes wrote the first transhumanist
treatise, the Opticks (1634). As I have argued in detail elsewhere (see Vaccari [2012]), Descartes' Optics
rehearses the discourse of human improvement on the basis of a mechanistic model of the living, while
approaching nature as a system flawed to be redesigned from an engineering perspective. There are
strong continuities between classical biological mechanism and transhumanist anthropology. Both
9. Not only would the ontic rupture be repeated with respect to nature subject to regular and stable laws
in which animal bodies participate, but, to put it in Ludueña Romandini's terms, this “is equivalent to
the elimination of all animalitas constitutive of the human until the present” (2010: 214).
10. The ascending route of Pico della Mirandola reaches its telos. In this way, transhumanism stands at
the beginning of the 21st century “as the most subtle form and the last avatar of humanism” (Ludueña
Romandini, 2010: 214; italics in the original).
11. In this regard, Vaccari notes: “Intelligent design, in fact, is an important feature of the explanatory
framework of the machine, and modern science would have enough problems to get rid of this
association between mechanism and design (the contemporary debate in the philosophy of biology on
the notion of “function” comes from this structural association between mechanism and function). One
of the advantages of the mechanistic thesis was precisely this engineering approach to the organism,
which allows a detailed understanding of the relationship between structure and function: the
mechanisms by which each part in the organism carries out its predetermined purpose. As we have
noted, the problem changes when we turn our attention to organisms as a whole: if the principle of
unity of organs is function, what is the 'function' of an organism?” (2017: 332). On the other hand,
regarding the role of technology in this teleology of history crossed from end to end by the “anthropic
principle”, once again Vaccari enlightens us: “We see, then, how the philosophical anthropology of
rationalist humanism is simultaneously , since its inception, a philosophy of technology. Under the
shadow of Descartes, the entire philosophy of technology will include (and in many cases 'start from' or
'be founded on') an anthropology. Technology becomes ontologically absorbed within the category of
mediation and instrumentalization; in other words, it is metaphysically neutralized. Technologies are
transparent pathways that constitute a natural extension of volition, messengers between intentions
and ends that ensure the sovereignty of the mind over the body and the world” (2013: 50; italics in the
original).
12. The critical posthumanism of thinkers such as Braidotti, or the spectrology of Ludueña Romandini,
as well as the tentacular compostism of Haraway, attempt to think and develop, from different
proposals, an alternative to (trans)humanist metaphysics (which almost always favors in an
individualistic ethic). As we see, it is not only about the cogito, but, and perhaps above all, about that
unlimited and groundless desire that appears through a mirror, darkly like the shadow denied by the
artifact of the cogito. 13 “That the automaton is a simulacrum of the human and that its creator
intimately aspires to the condition of demiurge, is perfectly illustrated by the best and most celebrated
automata manufacturer of the 18th century […] the doctor and mechanical engineer Jacques de
Vaucanson (1709 -1782). If La Mettrie had taken naturalistic mechanism to its ultimate consequences,
affirming the man-machine, Vaucanson, starting from Cartesian mechanism and Newton's laws of
motion, will attempt the opposite: to build the machine-man. […] if everything was a machine that
found its most perfect example in the clock, nature could only be imitated by providing an artifice with
14. To enter this labyrinth of beings that feed the materializable dreams of contemporary technoscience
(nourished by the imaginaries of science fiction so far in its short history, from its birth at the end of the
19th century to the present day) is very interesting. the route outlined by Alonso Burgos in the chapter
titled “The Paradise of the Blessed: immortals, clones, cyborgs, alpha ova” of his excellent essay Theory
and history of artificial man. Of automata, cyborgs, clones and other creatures (2017).
WORKS CITED
ALONSO BURGOS, Jesús (2017), Teoría e historia del hombre artificial. De autómatas, ciborgs, clones y
otras criaturas. Madrid, Akal.
BRAIDOTTI, Rosi (2015), Lo posthumano. Juan Carlos Gentile Vitale (trad.). Barcelona, Gedisa.
CALDERÓN DE LA BARCA, Pedro (1873), La vida es sueño. Mexico, Imprenta de Ignacio Cumplido.
LA METTRIE, Julien Offray de (2014), El hombre máquina. El hombre planta y otros escritos. Santiago
Espinosa (trad.). Buenos Aires, El cuenco de plata.
LUDUEÑA ROMANDINI, Fabián (2010), “Época VI: Primo Post Human y ‘el dios por venir’” en La
comunidad de los espectros I. Antropotecnia. Buenos Aires, Miño y Dávila, pp. 199-215.
PICO DELLA MIRANDOLA, Giovanni (2008), Discurso sobre la dignidad del hombre. Silvia Magnavacca
(trad.) Buenos Aires, Winograd.
RODRÍGUEZ, Pablo Manolo (2019), Las palabras en las cosas: saber, poder y subjetivación entre
algoritmos y biomoléculas. Ciudad Autónoma de Buenos Aires, Cactus.
ROSSI, Paolo (1966), Los filósofos y las máquinas 1400-1700. Buenos Aires, Labor.
SADIN, Eric (2017), La humanidad aumentada. La administración digital del mundo. Javier Blanco
(trad.). Ciudad Autónoma de Buenos Aires, Caja Negra.
SANDRONE, Darío, “¿Podemos querer a las cosas?” La voz del interior, 17 de abril, Córdoba. Consultado
en: (12/10/2019).
SCHAEFFER, Jean-Marie (2009), El fin de la excepción humana. Victor Goldstein (trad.). Buenos Aires,
Fondo de Cultura Económica.
SCHUHL, Pierre-Maxime (1955), Maquinismo y filosofía. Horacio Crespo (trad.). Argentina, Galatea
Nueva Visión.
VACCARI, Andrés (2013), “La idea más peligrosa del mundo: hacia una crítica de la antropología
transhumanista”, Tecnología & Sociedad, Buenos Aires, 1 (2), pp. 39-59.
VACCARI, Andrés (2014), “La posthumanidad como un bien objetivo: los peligros sobre el futurismo en el
debate sobre la optimización genética humana”, Acta Bioethica 20 (2), pp. 237-245.
VACCARI, Andrés (2017), “De Descartes a Deckard. Los orígenes cartesianos del posthumanismo” en
Lawler, D.; Vaccari, A.; y Blanco, J. (compiladores), La técnica en cuestión. Artificialidad, cultura
material y ontología de lo creado. Ciudad Autónoma de Buenos Aires, Teseo; Universidad Abierta
Interamericana, pp. 313-342.
VACCARI, Andrés. (2019), La Pasión de Descartes. Ciudad Autónoma de Buenos Aires, El guardián
literario.