0% found this document useful (0 votes)
13 views14 pages

ZALAZAR - Early Breakdown of The Modern Anthropos

Uploaded by

avaccari
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
13 views14 pages

ZALAZAR - Early Breakdown of The Modern Anthropos

Uploaded by

avaccari
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 14

The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos?

: The Evil Demon and the Little


Automaton Francine as wounds to the Cartesian Cogito. Posthuman Speculations in
Andres Vaccari’s La Pasión de Descartes

BELISARIO ZALAZAR
UNIVERSIDAD NACIONAL DE CÓRDOBA (Argentina)
[email protected]

Published in Mitologias Hoy vol. 22, December 202, pp. 161-174. Universitat Autònoma de
Barcelona, Spain.

Abstract: In this article text we will undertake a posthuman reading (Braidotti, 2015) of Andrés
Vaccari’s novel La Pasión de Descartes. The story of the relationship between Descartes and the
automaton Francine questions the nodal concepts of modern Western philosophy such as the “subject”,
the “immaterial soul” and its secular substitute, “consciousness”, and the very notion of “life”. Figures
like the automaton Francine and her posmodern heirs, such as the cyborg (Haraway), or in our 21st
century the fembot Sophia, developed by Hanson Robotics, enter, from the very beginning and with the
Cartesian metaphysic, in the narrative of modernization, either to destabilize or to reinforce the powers
of the anthropos as the main regulator of the global becoming of the Western form of life. We will
dedicate these pages to go over through a scene of this story, the one of the modern subject, nowadays
crossed by the announcement of many “ends” announces and too many “post-”s. (humanism / human /
biological / natural).

Keywords: Descartes, Human, Machines, Trans/Post-Humanism

Descartes: lights and shadows of the humanist story of the cogito


The debates around the figure of Descartes, or perhaps, to be more precise, around his philosophy, have
taken on new strength due to the emergence on the contemporary scene of a set of beings or existents
that populate both materiality and the imaginary. of our turbulent 21st century. This set, made up of
mechanical automata, robots, indeterminate electronic digital systems, cyborgs, spiritual machines and
the combination of the elements of this set - excessive for modern reason founded on the axiom of clear
and distinct ideas - is based on the emergence of “a new episteme” (Rodríguez, 2019) that calls into
question everything that, as Foucault pointed out in Words and Things (1966), modern knowledge
outlined as the face of “the human.” And Descartes is central if what we are talking about is elucidating
what “the human” is being questioned by posthuman sciences such as neurosciences, AI, cybernetics,
TGS, molecular biology, and the social and political sciences of the information; all of them brought into

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 1


contact through a block movement that operates through resonances between expert discourses,
“philosophy” and the arts, including literature.
It has been repeated ad nauseam that the Cartesian discovery of the subject, of the presence of
consciousness through thought, are the foundation on which the Westernizing project that we know as
Modernity was founded. The modern world, its conquest, and we use this concept above all in the
colonialist sense of the word, would have been difficult to carry out without the machine invented by
Descartes: algebraic geometry and the preeminence of an idea of thought and reason reduced to the
operation of decomposing the existing universe into simple, calculable and computable elements, then
relateable in a complex way. However, as Jean-Marie Schaeffer (2009) and Vicente Serrano Marín
(2010) have shown from very different perspectives, the self-evidence of the cogito and its role as a
substance that defines the human of the special organism called homo sapiens, is found in the same
writings. of the Parisian his own limit, or his self-destructive device. The Thesis of the human exception,
the one that superimposes the ontological dualism (body/thought) on the ontic rupture that separates
man from the rest of the living and from the order of the purely material world, is undermined from
within, like a virus, by spectral presences such as the evil genius and automatons, which dazzled the
most diverse social spaces with their artifactual mechanisms in the centuries from the 15th to the 19th.
The Passion of Descartes, the recently published novel by the versatile Argentine posthumanist
philosopher Andrés Vaccari, takes up a dark passage in Descartes's biography, relegated to the shadows
or to the corner of the “world of non-light,” as it is called in the novel to the unknown, death or what
reason cannot clear with its rays of knowledge. And, like everything that inhabits the shadows, at least
from Galileo onwards, and in our genealogy, from the Method devised and prescribed by Descartes, it
belongs to the discursive universe of opinion, legend and myth. Myth, legend and opinion remain
outside the region guarded by Reason that guides the just conduct of human subjects, therefore, they are
necessarily banished as they cannot be demonstrable through the Cartesian logical artifact. (1) History,
thus, is opposed to myth/legend; made to interpretation; science to opinion. Well, that passage tells that
after little Francine, the illegitimate daughter of the French thinker, died of scarlet fever at the age of
five, to “lessen her grief, Descartes ordered the construction of an automatic doll identical to his dead
daughter in size and appearance, capable of moving and walking based on precise clockwork
mechanisms. With this he achieved an artificial happiness that, however, did not last long. One stormy
night, during a boat trip that Descartes was taking with “Francine,” the captain of the ship accidentally
came across the doll and, scared, threw it into the sea. The second death of his daughter, even more
tragic than the first, was a new blow from which the philosopher could not recover this time. He died
five months later, on February 11, 1650” (Sandrone, 2018: s/p).

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 2


A universe full of machines: from the machina mundi to the fictional machine
Vaccari manufactures a complex machinery, we would tend to say, due to the sedimented metaphors, of
clockwork, but it is a fictional machine. A machine that sculpts, as cinema does over time for Tarkovsky,
a life. And if it is a machine, it is because it requires a precise technique to operate it; or, of the
manipulation of a series of knowledge concretized in particular ways. Fiction uses linguistic material
and produces a narrative that operates with different writing techniques: soliloquies, dialogues,
theatrical scenes, correspondences and baroque artifacts such as the theater within the theater. The
machine tells, tells, puts into motion philosophical concepts that in turn generate collisions from which
vivid images emerge. In a setting in the abyss, facing the baroque world in which Descartes participates,
despite the pale image that is “too human”, simplified, rationalist, worn out, schematized that tradition
has inherited from him, the fictional machine finds itself in the tableaux vivants of the work
commanded by the character Vicente de la Vega, his double “material”. Descartes' life is broken down
into narrative chapters, which in turn correspond to scenes represented by actors who wander in a
world moved by mechanisms and gadgets that create a great illusion, not only optical, but also sensitive
and cognitive. The furniture of the world of the work is nothing but a Great Machine. In this regard, the
narrative voice, lost among the voices that circulate through living memories, materialized and
represented in the scenes of the great philosopher, tells:
“The Jesuits will teach young Renatus the word that gives its name to what until then had been
a cloudy sensation, an equivocal but persistent premonition: machina. Scaffolding, support, machine,
structure, fabric. Machina: trick, machination, stratagem, scenery. Machina. The world is a machine
designed by an inconceivable craftsman” (Vaccari, 2019: 51).
That Great Machine that is the world in which the actors represent the life of Descartes is
nothing other than, and virtually, an immense theater. Stratagem, scenography, the Great Theater of the
World designed by Calderón de la Barca. A baroque topic, the perception of the world as a theater is fed
by the game of mirrors in which reason is immersed in its desire for knowledge. In its inner journey, the
cogito, in search of reality, is shipwrecked until it loses itself in its counterpart, the unreality of the
world, illusory, uncertain, populated by appearances that endanger the clear and distinct edifice of ideas
and their coincidence with reality. extensive. For this reason, Calderón stated, in the mouth of
Segismundo: “that all life is a dream, / and dreams are dreams” (Calderón de la Barca, 1873: 96). Modern
monsters (the vampire, Frankenstein, Kleist's puppets, Hoffman's automatons, etc.) are offspring of this
baroque fear, of this shipwreck whose driving force is nothing other than the sinister, the disturbing
that lurks like a shadow on thought, to the cogito, to the modern subject. (2) On the other hand, the idea
of Machina-mundi (3) , the philosophy according to which the universe or “Nature” is nothing but a
complex mechanism governed by laws that the nascent physical science of Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 3


and Renatus Cartesius himself was called to discover, born once the idea of an inscrutable and
mysterious Creation had fallen along with the grammars that gave rise to the lives of men in the Middle
Ages. As Pierre-Maxime Schuhl (1955) and Paolo Rossi (1966) showed, exposing the ideas of the
ceramicist Palissy, the philosophers Vives and Francis Bacon and the inventor and artist Leonardo, at
the beginning of the 1400s a movement that sought knowledge began to take place. no longer reading
the books of the learned, but searching in the observation of nature and experimentation with the
entities and substances that make up the extension of the physical universe, the secrets that allow the
vital movement of everything that exists. Little by little, the figure of the world is being introduced as a
machine made of subtle mechanisms capable of being replicated, although rudimentarily, for the right
reason, which must follow certain steps to achieve its goal. From there arise, for example, the well-
known Novum Organum and the Discourse on Method. The mechanical arts, knowledge made up of
sedimented experiences of groups of men associated with menial labor in the Ancient world (Schuhl,
1970), are valued as the access routes, not only to theoretical knowledge of the world, but also to
practical tasks. of its transformation for “the improvement of the conditions of existence through the
improvement of techniques” (Schuhl, 1955: 50).
In Descartes' The Passion, machinism is omnipresent. We have already spoken of the fictional
machine, of tableaux vivants, of machina-mundi. In fact, De la Vega's theatrical work does nothing more
than try to recreate the organ that the exiled thinker in Holland pointed out as the place where that
which did not belong to the natural, mechanistic order was manufactured: thought. The substance that
exceptionalizes humans as unique and superior beings, a humanist hierarchy already enabled by Pico
della Mirandola (4) , has a seat in the brain, although it does not coincide with it. Entire pages and
treatises have attempted to patch up the mind-body problem inaugurated by Descartes. As an example
further back in time, the debate held by thinkers such as Searle, David Chalmers, Daniel Dennett,
Penrose, Chomsky, and a long etcetera gathered around knowledge such as cybernetics, neurosciences
and Artificial Intelligence.
It is not by chance that De la Vega supports a purely mechanistic worldview of things; The story
gives us clues that his person is none other than the “evil genius” who deceived Descartes in his
inquisitions before discovering the certainties of his metaphysical edifice. Towards the end of Chapter
Two, once the automaton Francine had recovered from her temporary amnesia after being rescued from
the maritime contraptions, after the director of the play whispers to her “Are you ready Francine”, it
reads: “ The evil genie's arm gently guides her towards the stage, towards the light. Towards the world”
(Vaccari, 2019: 35).
If the brain, as De la Vega, a fictional precursor of La Mettrie, tries to (de)show, is a complex
assembly of pieces, springs and mechanisms that connect through openings like tubes with the different

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 4


“parts of the body, transporting sensations and causing movement of the living machine” (Vaccari, 2019:
89). If, furthermore, it does not contain immaterial souls that allow the movement of bodies and their
agency, but rather "life is, like the world, matter, nothing more, operating according to the laws of
mechanics" (Vaccari, 2019: 89), then what made man human disappears, and the ghost behind the
machine disappears, rebelling like an artifice, one more illusion among many created by optical and
perceptual laws. As Serrano Marín (2010) explains, if what triumphs is the structure of the deceptive
evil genius, what remains behind the quicksand left by the sudden disappearance of the cogito is a
power that desires, imagines and reasons, bowed down by the excessive effluvium. of the passions of the
body. An imperfect will that desires infinitely, not only to know, but desires without further ado, and
without limits imposed by Nature as in Antiquity, nor by the revelation of God (Middle Ages). This is a
modern subject freed from all ties, whether internal or external, this does not matter since the edges are
lost in the bottomless abyss of existence.

Who directs the scene? Of deceivers, bottomless abysses and transhumanist narratives
The issue becomes complicated when we realize that the machine-mundi, the theater that represents
thought, is directed by the strange and disturbing (unheimlich) character of De la Vega. If, on the one
hand, De la Vega poses a danger to the human exceptionality of the Cartesian story by denying the
primacy of “I think,” on the other hand, it can be thought of as that desiring force without foundation
beyond itself that he tells us about. Serrano Marin. De la Vega would not only be the “deceiver”, who in
his play corresponds to the shadow that haunts Descartes throughout his life, a spectral and pressing
presence especially in the “Sixth Chapter” and the “Epilogue”. ; Furthermore, and through his complete
work, he represents the force behind the machine and urges it to self-design in an infinite engineering
career, without limits. If we were content with the analysis of his figure as a radical materialist “all” a La
Mettrie, perhaps it would not be a big problem for the Cartesian rationalism to which the Epicurean
doctor claimed to do justice by separating it from superstitions such as the immaterial soul. Let us
remember that Julien Offray de La Mettrie radicalized the Cartesian intuition according to which living
beings, animals and humans, shared with everything that made up the material universe the fact of
being complex mechanisms: bodies are machines whose functioning can be known through rational
elucidation (e.g. the new science), and ultimately not only repaired but improved and perfected. The
germ of transhumanist narratives was already found in this materialist metaphor. If Descartes, as
Schaeffer affirms, separates the human from the res extenso - Nature described through the nascent
scientific method applied by new sciences such as anatomy, modern medicine, astronomy, among others
- through the thesis of the cogito, the soul immaterial that redeems him from the mechanistic laws that
govern the entire universe, La Mettrie eliminates what for him is nothing more than a metaphysical

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 5


obstacle, leaving the “machine man” as a result (5) . However, as we have been saying, it happens that
the motive for that machine is this disturbing character, the evil genius named De la Vega in Descartes'
The Passion. By embodying that blind force, that desiring structure that runs through what we call
Western Modernity as a civilizational project (6) , De la Vega not only rescues the automaton Francine
but directs the work, existence and life of Descartes with a view to create a perfect work, without “failed
scenes” (Vaccari, 2019: 60), an existence capable, among other things, of defeating death. There would
then be no Reason that governs the designs of human and natural history (both are united in the
capacity of the scientist and/or the engineer) drawing a straight line towards The Best, but quite the
opposite. Reason would turn falsely, on an unfounded abyss (unground), “a power not subject to rules,
forced to progress in a kind of flight forward, and fundamentally incapable of finding a limit to its own
desire” (Serrano Marín, 2010 : 67).
In the 21st century, the transhumanist narrative defended by thinkers such as Nick Bostrom,
Ray Kurzweil, Natasha Vita-More, among others, can be thought of as the avatar of that machine, moved
by a limitless desire to perfect itself through the technological ingenuity that we recognized in the
character De la Vega (7) . It is necessary to return here to Pico della Mirandola, who with his metaphor
of man as a chameleon capable of being what he himself imagines and desires for himself, lays one of
the bases of what Fabián Ludueña Romandini calls the discursive formations known as
“transhumanism.” (2010, 212). The Adam of the Miralian story, being created without an archetype, does
know how to take advantage of the artistic and technical powers that he possesses in a germinal state
—“if (…) he withdraws into the center of his unity” (Pico della Mirandola, 2008: 209)— , you can create
your own archetype, becoming. However, this archetype as an open possibility is immediately linked, in
Giovanni's speech, with the figure of God as the Supreme Artificer. Well, in transhumanism, according to
the reading of Ludueña Romandini (2010: 213), a secularization of the Judeo-Christian theological-
political doctrines (where Gnosticism and Orthodox theology come together in an amalgam that form
the political myths-motors of the Modernity), what survives is this idea that “man is something that has
not yet occurred in its fullness” (Ludueña Romandini, 2010: 214). In this way, transhumanism takes over
what Schaeffer calls the Cartesian segregationist thesis (8) and takes it to its extreme, whereby humans
not only separate themselves from what they would share with other material entities, including
animals. (9) , but rising above the laws that govern the life of bodies, it finally reaches its destiny: the
appearance of “the first form of man itself” (Ludueña Romandini, 2010: 214 italics in the original) (10 ).
And all this is achieved through the instrumentalized mediation of a specific set of technologies—
knowledge and techniques that Rodríguez (2019) calls “posthuman sciences”—: AI, nanotechnology,
biotechnologies—especially germline engineering (Vaccari , 2013)—cognitive sciences. The problem
with these discursive formations, heirs of Cartesian mechanism, through which “the ontological game

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 6


between artifacts and organs mobilizes a rhetoric that frames nature as a work of engineering and puts
the scientist in the role of technologist” (Vaccari, 2017 : 337) improving the design according to its
functions (11) lies in the fact that it presupposes that the “ends” are deduced from the direct “benefit” of
the perfectibility of those functions. The plus ultra of history draws a tautology with the perfectibility of
the functions of the organs-mechanisms. However, as Vaccari has noted in his criticisms of
transhumanism, especially refuting Bostrom's arguments:
“... the three [elements called by the mechanism] (capacity, value and well-being) do not
maintain a sufficiently consistent relationship to found the idea that the modification of capabilities is
beneficial in itself” (Vaccari, 2014: 243).
Transhumanism, once the particular Cartesian genealogy that we have traced is recognized, is
the last station of the chameleon-like Adam, whose movement would not be an ascent towards the
spheres of the perfect God through rational engineering (a hyperpotent cogito), but the mad flight
without “ meaning” of this “imperfect God, who is precisely an imperfect power, who desires like a God
and desires infinitely to the same extent that he lacks his own divine condition.” (Serrano Marín, 2010:
68).
Perhaps a remedy for that movement without direction, limits or references (“Ello thinks, De la
Vega thinks, bottomless desire thinks”) that, paradoxically, is denied but coincides with the story of the
solitary cogito, isolated from the world—and therefore with the power to design it according to its
autistic and illusory image—we find it in a passage of the novel object of our analysis. In the eleventh
Chapter, Descartes' shadow reveals a fact that destabilizes the foundations of that story of the cogito in
solitude capable of discovering the hidden truths of the cosmos and using them for his own benefit.
When speaking about the Meditations, a synecdoche of rationalist-mechanistic-transhumanist
humanism, the shadow says:
“A book so pure and orderly, a book that brings to mind the image of a man alone and calm in
his room, far from the responsibilities and daily hustle and bustle of the crowd. A self-confident man,
who is not afraid of the whirlwinds of extreme doubt. Except you weren't alone, no! Helena and
Francine were the necessary condition of your solitude […] your meditations are not a soliloquy, but a
dialogue” (Vaccari, 2019: 134).
Not only are we not alone, and it is not true that thought precedes existence. It is the drama of
co-existence, the shared destiny in the tumultuous theater of the world that requires cooperative work,
and no longer only between Humans detached from the existing others (12) .

Francine or the passionate wound: automata and posthuman machines

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 7


There is an even more important machine in De la Vega's work, that of the evil genius that moves the
cables, pulleys and arranges the total scenery on which "the story of a man who set out to find the Truth
and discover all the secrets of nature in times when the New Science had to confront the doctrines of the
powerful Church” (Vaccari, 2019: 31) rescued from the plans and instructions deposited in a trunk by
Descartes himself. That machine is the Francine automaton, whose body is made of thin receptacles that
contract and expand at different rates, circulating steam or electricity, we do not know what force
animates the little one, and covered in a flexible material that "imitates" the perfection of human skin,
they make it equal to a living human being. However, Francine is a very subtle artifact, closer to the
posthuman idea of a machine (Rodríguez, 2019: 315-322) than to that founded by the mechanism of the
modern episteme. If De la Vega builds the man-machine through his tableaux, Francine, at first, would
replicate the automata of the 18th century, the machine-men like those devised by Vaucanson.13
However, as Francine takes center stage in the narration, a much more complex figure of a machine
thickens and takes shape. It is no longer a deterministic automaton, destined to repeat functions
following a finite combination of operating patterns. The Francine-machine has become a machine
designed by the discursive formations of the 20th century such as system, organization, information,
program and code. Francine resembles a cutting-edge computer program capable of capturing
information from the environment and accumulating it to transform its operating system. Francine
operates through deep learning. As foreseen by the theories of Varela and Maturana regarding complex
and autopoietic living machines, and as Simondon stated about the concept of the post-mechanistic
machine:
“The true improvement of machines, that which can be said to raise the degree of technicality,
corresponds not to an increase in automatism, but, on the contrary, to the fact that the operation of a
machine preserves a certain margin of indeterminacy.” . It is this margin that allows the machine to be
sensitive to external information” (Simondon in Sadin, 2017: 25).
If the young Descartes, in his student days at the College of Port Royal, experimented with
automata, manufacturing one that materialized the ghost of Eurydice in a work that recreated the
descent of Orpheus to the underworld (Vaccari, 2019: 75), as this No more than a stage artifice, a deus ex
machina like that of Greek tragedies, the new generation of automatons embodied by Francine is an
Artificial Intelligence capable not only of speaking and imitating the movements of the human body,
but, in the manner of cyborg-replicant immortalized by the film version of Blade Runner, he can feel,
cry and suffer, thus being able to manipulate symbols-signs with meaning. Francine is designed based
on plans, equations and algorithms conceived in the times of Winner and Alan Turing's cybernetics. In
fact, she herself proposes to her father, towards the end of the narrative, that he submit her to an

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 8


experiment, potentially experienced as a game by the girl: it is the Turnig test developed to decide
whether a computational machine is thinking or not. (see Vaccari, 2019: 101).
The modern invention, the epistemic figure of Man, was threatened since its appearance in the
arenas of discourse and the materiality of the world built on the knowledge of the New Science.
Descartes sensed this, and that is why he clung to the wood of the cogito in the midst of the storm of
mechanism and the shadows that his own reason had wanted to exile to the reality of non-light.
Francine stands as the early wound in the narcissistic certainty of the omnipotent subject who created
the Modern world. And yet, at the same time it is his promise fulfilled, an artifice that knew how to
defeat death itself. At this point, the little story woven by the story is the final stage of transhumanist
teleology and its delusions of infinite perfection, space-time where death will have no dominion. Today,
entered the 21st century, Francine has spread throughout the world, and the complex machine stands as
the epistemic figure that guides us groping in a world populated by beings of a thousand shapes (14) ,
where man occupies a precarious, fragile, indeterminate position, in a cosmogram without mathesis
universalis. We, anthrobological bodies, as Sadin says, exist between applications that create a virtual
world-interface that exceeds us in power and capacity for action, robots that supplant human labor in
globalized metropolitan centers, artificial organs that are coupled to the biological organism, AIs like the
Saudi citizen Sophia, we live in a posthuman world, and we know more than ever, as Vaccari's
fictionalized Claudine knew, that we all “are something else, uncertain, beneath the surface” (Vaccari,
2019: 47).
The drama today, between virtual existences and intelligent silicon machines that promise us an
indefinite life, where death will be nothing more than an archeology of the future, the drama we said,
continues to be the way in which the fictional machine develops, the story of our existence, now
accompanied, perhaps for a long time, by thousands of artifacts, devices and machines that we have
invented.

FOOTNOTES

1. Vicente Serrano Marín in his essay Dreaming Monsters. Terror and delirium in modernity (2010)
undertakes an extensive rewriting of the philosophical concept of modernity, while detaching it from its
coincidence with a stage that is often thought of as its definitive and characteristic face: the
Enlightenment. The Spanish author shows in his journey that since the beginning of modernity that was
born with Descartes, the element of the “I”, the “subject” and its deployment (which in the French
thinker occurs through the ingenuity of analytical geometry (with its spaces of action in the planes of
representation) on which this not only epistemological, but also civilizational project of achieving the

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 9


truth would be built, is stalked and in some way falsified in nuce by a spectral, terrifying figure: the
bottomless abyss that It “sustains” the self, the thought, the will to truth. Instead of “I think,” Descartes,
based on the intrusion of the evil genius, would have avoided saying, according to Serrano Marín, as
Nietzsche and Freud would later say: “ “It thinks.”

2. See Serrano Marín (2010) “Second Section. Terror."

3. “The first to use the expression machina mundi ('the machine of the world') was the Roman poet
Lucretius (94-55 BC) in his work De rerum natura. The metaphor (for that was what it was, evidently)
was so apt that it did not take long to make a fortune, to such an extent that in subsequent centuries it
was used by European writers and philosophers to designate the complexity of the world. Perhaps the
first to fully develop it, beyond its purely poetic sense, was the Roman writer and politician Cicero (106-
43 BC) [...] In The Nature of the Gods Cicero compared the precision and order with which it worked the
Cosmos - the work, according to him, of the Stoic Creator - with Archimedes' world machine, a hydraulic
automaton built more than 150 years ago by the Greek mathematician. […] What the mechanistic and
materialist scientists and philosophers [of the 16th, 17th and 18th centuries] were going to put on the
table in the following centuries will no longer be merely a metaphor, but a new theory of life that started
from the fact —verifiable, according to them—that the bodies of animals and men were machines. Not
'as if they were', but they were” (Alonso Burgos, 2017: 53-56).

4. In his Discourse on the Dignity of Man Giovani Pico della Mirandola elaborates one of the first
attempts to find the place of man in the Cosmos in a period where the harmony of the divine Order of
the Middle Ages, which in turn is a model and royal law of the social and terrestrial order began to
shatter and the figure of Man began to appear drawn with the brush of the Humanist movement. This
seemingly indefinite position, the last of the creations of the Supreme Father God, the architect who is
man, nevertheless allows him to be located in an empty center that is paradoxically mobile, capable of
occupying any part of the world ordered by divine laws. Potentially man is capable of ascending to the
very height of the Supreme Father. The hierarchy is then decided in and based on the work of man (his
intention and his judgment) as long as he knows how to take advantage of the perfectibility that defines
him. “To the nascent man the Father conferred seeds of every kind and germs of all life. And according
to how each man has cultivated them, they will mature in him and give him their fruits. If they were
vegetables, they will become a plant; if sensitive, they will become brutal; if rational, it will be elevated
to a celestial animal; if intellectuals, it will be an angel or son of God; and if, not content with the lot of
any creature, he withdraws into the center of his unity, transformed into a spirit alone with God in the
lonely darkness of the Father, he, who was placed above all things, will be above of all of them.” (Pico
della Mirandola, 2008: 209).

5. The thesis of human exceptionalism devised by Descartes disappears in La Mettrie's materialist


philosophical discourse: both the ontic rupture and the ontological dualism that define the human
disappear. “The soul and the body fall asleep together. As the movement of the blood calms, a sweet
feeling of peace and tranquility spreads throughout the machine; The soul basically becomes heavy with
the eyelids and submerges itself in the fibers of the brain: it thus gradually paralyzes all the muscles of
the body. These can no longer support the weight of the head, that one (the soul) can no longer support
the burden of thought; It is in the dream as if it were not there.” (La Mettrie, 2014: 43) “Let us therefore

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 10


boldly conclude that man is a machine and that there is only one substance in the universe with various
modifications” (120).

6. Project sustained by a set of knowledge, practices and technologies that converge in what critical
posthumanists like Braidotti call Humanism: “At the beginning of everything there is He, the classical
ideal of Man, identified by Protagoras as 'the measure of all things'. ', later elevated by the Italian
Renaissance to the level of a universal model, represented by Leonardo da Vinci in the Vitruvian Man.
An ideal of bodily perfection that […] evolves towards a series of intellectual, discursive and spiritual
values. Together, these support a precise conception of what is human about humanity. Furthermore,
they assert with unwavering certainty the almost unlimited human capacity to pursue individual and
collective perfection. This iconic image is the symbol of the doctrine of humanism, which interprets the
empowerment of biological, rational and moral human capacities in light of the concept of teleologically
oriented rational progress” (Braidotti, 2015: 25).

7. “'Transhumanism is a philosophical movement that enacts the advent of a future state of humanity,
called 'posthumanity.' It is a future in which humanity will have rationally intervened in its own
evolution to reinvent itself in accordance with its own dreams and aspirations, thus transcending the
natural prerogative of its existence and realizing its full potential […] Nick Bostrom, the most prominent
transhumanist thinker currently, he asserts: 'Ultimately, it is possible that these optimizations could
make us, or our descendants, 'posthumans', beings with indefinite longevity, intellectual faculties much
greater than those of any current human being (and perhaps sensitivities). or completely new
modalities), as well as the ability to control their own emotions'” (Vaccari, 2014: 238). Transhumanism,
the son of the material culture of our hyper-technological Globe, proposes to use the technologies
developed in the last decades of the 20th century and so far in the 21st century to produce a better
human”, enhancing and perfecting, or redesigning, our cognitive abilities. , perceptual and biological.
This possible “artificial redesign of the human body and intervention on the molecular bases of life on
earth” (Ludueña Romandini, 2010: 200; italics in the original) is based on a budget, an artifact similar to
the one used by Descartes to found all of life. his philosophy on the foundations of cogito: the “appeal to
values that appear to be universal or self-evident, [i.e.], assumes that we all agree on what constitutes a
'better' human and that it would be ridiculous to oppose something that is better ” (Vaccari, 2014: 241).
On the question of the Cartesian artifact, as we already said, it is a risky thesis by both Serrano Marín
and Schaeffer, with very different claims and arguments. Schaeffer states it like this: “Cartesianism is
the determination of man as ego. The possibility remains that this determination is nothing more than
an artifact. If this were the case, then the privilege granted to the self-founding value of consciousness,
far from constituting the unbreakable foundation of all knowledge of the human being, would be
exposed to prohibiting us from accessing the knowledge of what we are” (2009: 59).

8. In that same movement he takes up the challenge launched by the Cartesian project of engineering
the mechanisms that make up the res extenso, in which man of course participates as a material entity.
Vaccari writes about it: “We should not be surprised that Descartes wrote the first transhumanist
treatise, the Opticks (1634). As I have argued in detail elsewhere (see Vaccari [2012]), Descartes' Optics
rehearses the discourse of human improvement on the basis of a mechanistic model of the living, while
approaching nature as a system flawed to be redesigned from an engineering perspective. There are
strong continuities between classical biological mechanism and transhumanist anthropology. Both

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 11


instrumentalize the relationship between body and mind, unfolding the human into subject and object
of its action, into designer and designed. The process of human moral elevation, both for Descartes and
for transhumanists, involves the correction of their biomaterial condition” (2013: 50).

9. Not only would the ontic rupture be repeated with respect to nature subject to regular and stable laws
in which animal bodies participate, but, to put it in Ludueña Romandini's terms, this “is equivalent to
the elimination of all animalitas constitutive of the human until the present” (2010: 214).

10. The ascending route of Pico della Mirandola reaches its telos. In this way, transhumanism stands at
the beginning of the 21st century “as the most subtle form and the last avatar of humanism” (Ludueña
Romandini, 2010: 214; italics in the original).

11. In this regard, Vaccari notes: “Intelligent design, in fact, is an important feature of the explanatory
framework of the machine, and modern science would have enough problems to get rid of this
association between mechanism and design (the contemporary debate in the philosophy of biology on
the notion of “function” comes from this structural association between mechanism and function). One
of the advantages of the mechanistic thesis was precisely this engineering approach to the organism,
which allows a detailed understanding of the relationship between structure and function: the
mechanisms by which each part in the organism carries out its predetermined purpose. As we have
noted, the problem changes when we turn our attention to organisms as a whole: if the principle of
unity of organs is function, what is the 'function' of an organism?” (2017: 332). On the other hand,
regarding the role of technology in this teleology of history crossed from end to end by the “anthropic
principle”, once again Vaccari enlightens us: “We see, then, how the philosophical anthropology of
rationalist humanism is simultaneously , since its inception, a philosophy of technology. Under the
shadow of Descartes, the entire philosophy of technology will include (and in many cases 'start from' or
'be founded on') an anthropology. Technology becomes ontologically absorbed within the category of
mediation and instrumentalization; in other words, it is metaphysically neutralized. Technologies are
transparent pathways that constitute a natural extension of volition, messengers between intentions
and ends that ensure the sovereignty of the mind over the body and the world” (2013: 50; italics in the
original).

12. The critical posthumanism of thinkers such as Braidotti, or the spectrology of Ludueña Romandini,
as well as the tentacular compostism of Haraway, attempt to think and develop, from different
proposals, an alternative to (trans)humanist metaphysics (which almost always favors in an
individualistic ethic). As we see, it is not only about the cogito, but, and perhaps above all, about that
unlimited and groundless desire that appears through a mirror, darkly like the shadow denied by the
artifact of the cogito. 13 “That the automaton is a simulacrum of the human and that its creator
intimately aspires to the condition of demiurge, is perfectly illustrated by the best and most celebrated
automata manufacturer of the 18th century […] the doctor and mechanical engineer Jacques de
Vaucanson (1709 -1782). If La Mettrie had taken naturalistic mechanism to its ultimate consequences,
affirming the man-machine, Vaucanson, starting from Cartesian mechanism and Newton's laws of
motion, will attempt the opposite: to build the machine-man. […] if everything was a machine that
found its most perfect example in the clock, nature could only be imitated by providing an artifice with

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 12


the cables and pulleys that anatomists could observe in man and then making it work with the precision
of a clock ” (Alonso Burgos, 2017: 90-91).

14. To enter this labyrinth of beings that feed the materializable dreams of contemporary technoscience
(nourished by the imaginaries of science fiction so far in its short history, from its birth at the end of the
19th century to the present day) is very interesting. the route outlined by Alonso Burgos in the chapter
titled “The Paradise of the Blessed: immortals, clones, cyborgs, alpha ova” of his excellent essay Theory
and history of artificial man. Of automata, cyborgs, clones and other creatures (2017).

WORKS CITED

ALONSO BURGOS, Jesús (2017), Teoría e historia del hombre artificial. De autómatas, ciborgs, clones y
otras criaturas. Madrid, Akal.

BRAIDOTTI, Rosi (2015), Lo posthumano. Juan Carlos Gentile Vitale (trad.). Barcelona, Gedisa.

CALDERÓN DE LA BARCA, Pedro (1873), La vida es sueño. Mexico, Imprenta de Ignacio Cumplido.

LA METTRIE, Julien Offray de (2014), El hombre máquina. El hombre planta y otros escritos. Santiago
Espinosa (trad.). Buenos Aires, El cuenco de plata.

LUDUEÑA ROMANDINI, Fabián (2010), “Época VI: Primo Post Human y ‘el dios por venir’” en La
comunidad de los espectros I. Antropotecnia. Buenos Aires, Miño y Dávila, pp. 199-215.

PICO DELLA MIRANDOLA, Giovanni (2008), Discurso sobre la dignidad del hombre. Silvia Magnavacca
(trad.) Buenos Aires, Winograd.

RODRÍGUEZ, Pablo Manolo (2019), Las palabras en las cosas: saber, poder y subjetivación entre
algoritmos y biomoléculas. Ciudad Autónoma de Buenos Aires, Cactus.

ROSSI, Paolo (1966), Los filósofos y las máquinas 1400-1700. Buenos Aires, Labor.

SADIN, Eric (2017), La humanidad aumentada. La administración digital del mundo. Javier Blanco
(trad.). Ciudad Autónoma de Buenos Aires, Caja Negra.

SANDRONE, Darío, “¿Podemos querer a las cosas?” La voz del interior, 17 de abril, Córdoba. Consultado
en: (12/10/2019).

SCHAEFFER, Jean-Marie (2009), El fin de la excepción humana. Victor Goldstein (trad.). Buenos Aires,
Fondo de Cultura Económica.

SCHUHL, Pierre-Maxime (1955), Maquinismo y filosofía. Horacio Crespo (trad.). Argentina, Galatea
Nueva Visión.

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 13


SERRANO MARÍN, Vicente (2010), Soñando monstruos, Terror y delirio en la modernidad. Madrid, Plaza
y Valdés Editores.

VACCARI, Andrés (2013), “La idea más peligrosa del mundo: hacia una crítica de la antropología
transhumanista”, Tecnología & Sociedad, Buenos Aires, 1 (2), pp. 39-59.

VACCARI, Andrés (2014), “La posthumanidad como un bien objetivo: los peligros sobre el futurismo en el
debate sobre la optimización genética humana”, Acta Bioethica 20 (2), pp. 237-245.

VACCARI, Andrés (2017), “De Descartes a Deckard. Los orígenes cartesianos del posthumanismo” en
Lawler, D.; Vaccari, A.; y Blanco, J. (compiladores), La técnica en cuestión. Artificialidad, cultura
material y ontología de lo creado. Ciudad Autónoma de Buenos Aires, Teseo; Universidad Abierta
Interamericana, pp. 313-342.

VACCARI, Andrés. (2019), La Pasión de Descartes. Ciudad Autónoma de Buenos Aires, El guardián
literario.

Zalazar - The Early Breakdown of the Modern Anthropos? - 14

You might also like