100% found this document useful (1 vote)
115 views

Critical Thinking Notes: Kelly Parker

This document discusses different types of arguments and fallacies. It defines arguments as statements intended to support a conclusion, and distinguishes them from assertions. Arguments can be either inductive, relying on examples or analogy, or deductive, where the premises necessarily imply the conclusion. For an argument to be sound, it must have a valid logical form and true premises. However, arguments can be fallacious due to incomplete information, false causes, questionable logical forms, or appeals to emotion rather than reason. Common fallacies include hasty generalizations, false claims of causality, and circular reasoning.

Uploaded by

Yoohnee Mi
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
100% found this document useful (1 vote)
115 views

Critical Thinking Notes: Kelly Parker

This document discusses different types of arguments and fallacies. It defines arguments as statements intended to support a conclusion, and distinguishes them from assertions. Arguments can be either inductive, relying on examples or analogy, or deductive, where the premises necessarily imply the conclusion. For an argument to be sound, it must have a valid logical form and true premises. However, arguments can be fallacious due to incomplete information, false causes, questionable logical forms, or appeals to emotion rather than reason. Common fallacies include hasty generalizations, false claims of causality, and circular reasoning.

Uploaded by

Yoohnee Mi
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 12

Critical Thinking Notes

Kelly Parker
Revised September 2000

Arguments and Non-arguments

An argument is a series of statements that oers reasons or evidence intended to support a conclusion. An argument must have at least one premise supplying reasons or evidence for accepting that the conclusion of the argument is true. Often an argument will rely on the hearers knowing something obvious or implied. Such knowledge is said to be contained in an unstated or missing premise. The rst step in analyzing arguments is to distinguish arguments from assertions.

1.1

Assertions:

No statement is presented as a conclusion whose truth is supported by any others. [1] Dr. Jack Kevorkian has become known as Dr. Death because of his willingness to assist patients in committing suicide. Most medical professionals have refused to sanction his activities, and some have equated assisted suicide with murder. A majority of the public, on the other hand, believe that assisted suicide is permissible in some cases, and a court recently found Kevorkian not guilty of criminal wrongdoing in a key case.

1.2

Arguments:

The truth of one statement is (supposedly) established by other statements. [2] Dr. Jack Kevorkian was trained as a pathologist and legally licensed by the state to practice medicine. His assisted suicide is thus a legitimate medical practice. [3] Dr. Jack Kevorkian should not be seen as a monster or criminal, but rather as a medical revolutionary. His assisted suicide is a valuable service that certainly extends the traditional role of the physician in end-of-life care. It does not, however, violate the basic duty of the physician to provide for the patients well-being and quality of life.

Strength and Validity of Arguments

An argument is considered strong if its premises in fact support the conclusion. This has nothing to do with whether the premises are true or not, but only with the relevance of the premises to the conclusion. Argument 2 is not strong, while Argument 3 is. Certain argument forms are such that if the premises are true, the conclusion is necessarily true. These are said to be valid argument forms. [4] The following is a valid argument in form, even though it is made of nonsense words: Premise 1 Premise 2 All glubs are sputs. William is a glub.

Conclusion Therefore, William is a sput. There is no way that William could not be a sput, if the two premises were true.

Soundness of Arguments

For an argument to establish that its conclusion is true, its premises must also be true. A bad argument may thus have weak form, one or more false premises, or both. An argument is sound if it has both good form and true premises. Argument 2 has true premises but weak form. Argument 3 has good form. In order to refute the truth of the conclusion in Argument 3, one would have to show that one (or both) of its premises is untrue.

Practice: Argument Identication

Determine whether each of the following passages contains an argument. For those passages that do contain an argument, identify the premises (including unstated premises) and the conclusion of the argument. Cross through statements that are not a part of the argument. [5] You should stop killing every spider you see. Spiders help keep down the insect population, and most of them pose no threat to people. [6] The snow is making driving conditions very dangerous. But I must still go out and vote even though my candidate has no chance of winning. [7] A meter is longer than a yard. Therefore, since this ship is one hundred meters long, it is longer than a football eld. [8] People who study history are wiser than those who do not. Studying history makes a person less likely to repeat the mistakes of the past, and not repeating past mistakes is a sign of wisdom. It is a sign of what J. Glenn Gray calls practical wisdom, in fact. Since a primary aim of education is producing wisdom, all universities should teach history.

Inductive Arguments

In a strong inductive argument, the premises introduce examples, a relevantly similar analogy, or past experiences to establish a causal connection. If the conclusion matches the pattern, it is reasonable to believe it is probably true. There is always at least a bit of uncertainty in even the strongest inductive argument.

5.1

Argument by Example
[9] My friend got out of a speeding ticket one time. When the ocer saw from her license that it was her birthday, he gave her a warning and wished her a happy birthday. Today is my birthday, so I wont get a ticket if I speed.

5.2

Argument by Analogy
[10] Be polite when you present your complaints to the manager. Its easier to catch ies with honey than with vinegar.

5.3

Appeal to Past Experience


[11] The sun has always risen in the East in the morning. The sun will rise in the East tomorrow.

6
6.1

Inductive Fallacies
Incomplete information / Too few examples

Induction from past experience or from specic examples requires experience or examples to establish a reliable general pattern. Argument 11 is strong because it is based on a large number of past experiences, with no known exceptions to the pattern. Argument 9 is weak for two reasons: First, its conclusion is based on only one example. There are no doubt a great number of examples that would establish a dierent pattern. Second, no plausible explanation is oered for why an ocer would not issue a ticket on ones birthday.

6.2
6.2.1

Overlooking alternative explanations


False cause

Some of the most common inductive fallacies arise even where there are relevant points of similarity between pattern and conclusion, and where the information is fairly extensive. [12] Numerous studies indicate that students who sit in the front row of a classroom tend to get better grades than those who sit further back. This semester Professor Snape is requiring all students to sit in the front row, so they will get better grades. Is it correct to say that sitting in the front row causes better grades? Maybe, or maybe not. It may be that the front row location somehow aords better comprehension of course material. Or it may be that those students who ordinarily prefer to be in front are usually more conscientious about studying. The point is that we arent told what the connection is. The studies show a correlation between grades and seating location; the argument assumes a certain causal connection that is not explained in the premises and which may be incorrect.

8 6.2.2 Post hoc, ergo propter hoc

Most good inductive arguments provide a reasonable explanation for why the conclusion ts the general pattern established in the premises. Sometimes the causal connection is indeed obvious enough not to need stating: Being hit by a moving train will cause bodily injury, and we all know it. Be careful, though, of any inductive argument that assumes rather than states a causal explanation. People often assume that a chronological succession of events amounts to causal connection among them. [13] In Coleridges Rime of the Ancient Mariner, the ship came into bad weather after a sailor killed an albatross. The other sailors blamed the albatross-killer for causing their bad luck. The Latin phrase for this pattern of thinking is post hoc, ergo propter hoc (after this, therefore because of this). Post hoc, ergo propter hoc is a common form of the false cause fallacy.

Deductive Arguments

In a strong deductive argument, the premises introduce facts or evidence that, when taken together, necessarily imply the truth of the conclusion. The following are examples of deductive arguments: [14] Whenever my brother Dan comes home, he leaves the mail on this table. The mail was still outside in the mailbox when I got here, so I knew he hadnt come home yet. [15] I always knew that Jones was either a fraud or a genius. His latest work shows he is no fraud. He must be a genius after all. [16] Everyone who graduates from GVSU with a Bachelors of Science degree is required to pass a course in statistics. Wilson must have passed his statistics course, because he has a B.S. in engineering from GVSU. [17] All values are relative, but some things are obviously wrong no matter what the situation. Either we identify stealing as one of those things that are always wrong, or I am the Queen of England. The suspect in this case clearly believed stealing to be right, though, so we cannot say that it was wrong relative to her value system. So we cant identify stealing as one of those things that are always wrong. Therefore, I am the Queen of England.

10

7.1

A Very Cool Trick for Expert Logicians (and Overly Clever Salespersons) to Consider . . .

Argument 17 demonstrates how any arbitrarily chosen statement can be deduced from a contradiction: P1. P2. P3. C1. P4. All values are relative and no values are relative. If someone believes something is right, then it is not wrong. The suspect believed stealing is right. [a contradiction] [a simple denition of all values are relative, from P1] [given]

It is not the case that stealing is [from P2 and P3] wrong. Either stealing is wrong or I am the [arbitrary disjunction] Queen of England. I am the Queen of England. [from C1 and P4]

C2.

11

Additional Fallacies

Strictly speaking, there are only a handful of simple and valid deductive argument forms. Any deductive argument is either composed of these simple forms, or it involves a fallacy. Some fallacies are so common, however, that they have received names. See chapter 10 in Westons Rulebook for Arguments for descriptions of the following deductive fallacies:

ad hominem
Appeal to personality (or attack on personaltiy)

ad ignorantium
Apppeal to ignorance, using what is not known as evidence

ad misericordiam
Appeal to pity, looking for agreement out of sympathy

ad populum
Appeal to majority. Everyones doing it!

petitio principii
Begging the question (using the conclusion, usually stated dierently, as a premise)

composition division

12

Two Especially Confusing Pairs of Argument Forms


Two common fallacies closely resemble two of the most common valid deductive forms: A A Valid Form: Modus Ponens a implies b a Therefore, b Cats eat sh. Copper is a cat. Copper eats sh.

An Invalid Form: Denying the Antecedent a implies b Not a Therefore, not b Cats eat sh. Humans are not cats. Humans do not eat sh. B Another Valid Form: Modus Tollens a implies b Not b Therefore, not a If Dan were home, the mail would be in. The mail is not in. Dan is not home.

Another Invalid Form: Arming the Consequent a implies b b Therefore, a If Dan were home, the mail would be in. The mail is in. Dan is home.

You might also like