Cambridge University Press The Origins of Modern Science From Antiquity To The Scientific Revolution Ofer Gal
Cambridge University Press The Origins of Modern Science From Antiquity To The Scientific Revolution Ofer Gal
314–321, 3rd Floor, Plot 3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre, New
Delhi – 110025, India
www.cambridge.org
DOI: 10.1017/9781108225205
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
ISBN 978-1-316-51030-8 Hardback
1 Cathedrals
The Cathedral
Ways of Knowing
Tensions and Compromises
Conclusion: Reflections on the History of Knowledge
Discussion Questions
Suggested Readings
2 Greek Thought
Knowing-About as Know-How
Plato and the Culture of Theory
Parmenides’ Problem and Its Import
Aristotle and the Science of Common Sense
Conclusion
Discussion Questions
Suggested Readings
4 Medieval Learning
The Decline of Greek Knowledge
The Encyclopedic Tradition
Christianity and Learnedness
The University
Muslim Science
Discussion Questions
Suggested Readings
6 Magic
Spectator vs. Participant Knowledge
Magical Cosmogonies
Magical Epistemology
Magical Cosmologies
Scientific Magic
Magic and the New Science
Conclusion
Discussion Questions
Suggested Readings
10 Science’s Cathedral
The Two Savants
The Correspondence: Forging a New Question
Setting the Question Right
Conclusion: The New Celestial Mechanics
Coda: The Principia
Discussion Questions
Suggested Readings
Index
Figures
1.1 Chartres Cathedral, southern façade. agefotostock /
Alamy Stock Photo.
3.2 The motion of the Sun and stars across the sky dome
(Northern Hemisphere). Illustration by Cindy Hodoba Eric ©.
5.1 Left: the Piazza del Duomo, Florence. Blom UK via Getty
Images. Right: Jim Anderson’s depiction of Brunelleschi’s
perspective spectacle. Jim Anderson ©.
5.3 Piero della Francesca’s Ideal City (c. 1470). © Arte &
Immagini srl / CORBIS / Corbis via Getty Images.
7.3 From left to right: map of the Island of Ven, with the
Uraniborg observatory managed by astronomer Tycho Brahe
(Sweden, 1586). De Agostini Picture Library / Getty Images.
Tycho Brahe, Astronomiæ instauratæ mechanica (Tyskland:
Wandsbek, 1598). Danish Royal Library LN 432 2°. Tycho
Brahe, Observationes planetarum (Denmark, 1596). Danish
Royal Library GKS 316 2º, papir, 208 ff.; 34.5 × 20 cm, 136.
8.4 A leaf from The Leechbook of Bald (c. 900 CE). Royal
MS 12 D XVII, f.109R v. London, British Library.
This is not to say that the cathedral does not embody ideals of
order, perfection and harmony. Quite the opposite: these were
exactly the ideals of the people who “climbed on sketchy ladders
towards God.” But it is this very point that needs to be stressed:
harmonious order was an ideal to which the people building the
cathedral subscribed, not a template they could follow. This is the
way we need to think about science. We know that the claims of our
science are ‘true,’ but this truth is an ideal which guides science. It is
not some thing, existing prior to and independently of the inquiry,
waiting to be revealed. When evidence and argument convince
scientists that some claim is true, it does not mean that they have
reached something that was always there, obscured by error and
misjudgment. It definitely does not mean that this ‘something’ will
always be there. What it does mean is that they have succeeded in
using their resources to solve a current challenge in a way that they
find satisfactory, even though they are most likely well aware that
this solution is temporary, and so is the challenge. Like the building
of the cathedral, scientific work has moments of satisfaction, even
glory, but is never completed. And like harmony for the building of
the cathedral, truth is an ideal that guides scientific research; like the
cathedral, science is the product of people striving towards this ideal,
not its accomplishment.
Yet another reason to turn to the cathedral as a metaphor for
science is that like the cathedral, and like most human
accomplishments, science is a work of many hands (Figure 1.4). It
has no single architect, no single design, no single vision it follows. It
is forgivable that we concentrate, in this book and in the
historiography of science in general, on the exciting contributions of
great thinkers such as Aristotle, Galileo and Newton. But great
contributions should not be construed as great leaps forward. In
science, as in the building of the cathedral, all hands are necessary
and every “winch and pulley” is indispensable. Of course, some
craftspeople are more skilled than others, and some crafts are more
difficult to acquire and replicate. But at no point can the master
mason completely transcend the work of the youngest and least
experienced stone-chipper; it is always the “hewn rock” produced by
one that the other has to use. A Copernicus or a Kepler may
construct a new way to look at the astronomical relations between
Heaven and Earth, but he can only do so using the available
intellectual resources developed by the astronomers,
mathematicians and natural philosophers of his and earlier
generations.
Figure 1.4 Work of many hands: Jean Fouquet’s The Construction
of the Temple of Jerusalem by King Solomon (c. 1475) – a
miniature illustration from a manuscript edition of Josephus
Flavius’ The Antiquities of the Jews (man. fr. 247, fol. 163 v. BN,
Paris. Josephus’ text is from c. 94). Fouquet depicts the king
visiting what he imagines as a construction site of a cathedral
(modeled on the Notre Dame in Paris), populated by a swarm of
workers engaged in different facets of the construction, requiring
different tools and expertise.
The Romans didn’t only use the arch – they thought about it and
considered it theoretically, and this allows us to think about the
history of knowledge from a different perspective. Vitruvius, a Roman
master of architecture and technology of the first century BCE,
provides an excellent example. In the eighth book of his De
Architectura libri Decem (Ten Books on Architecture), he explains
how to “discharge the load of the walls by means of archings
composed of voussoirs (see Figure 1.7) with joints radiating to the
centre.” Vitruvius engages with the same structure that is so
important for the masons, but the knowledge he offers is of a
different kind to theirs: we may call it knowing that.
The distinction between knowing-how and knowing-that is
crucial for the history of science. Horse raising is a clear example of
the former: medieval Europeans knew how to raise and use horses.
It was a matter of practice, tradition, trial and error: it is hard to
imagine the medieval farmer, almost certainly illiterate, having
abstract principles or general equine theories. Vitruvius’ is an
example of knowing-that: knowledge carried and communicated in
written words, developed and supported by arguments and
evidence, aspiring for the general and often the abstract.
The ancient and medieval builders obviously knew how to build
arches. But did they know, or bother with, the type of knowledge
offered by Vitruvius? Did they know that the arch, as an idealized
geometrical curve, is an efficient carrier of weight? Did they ask
themselves why this curve was so efficient? Did they have the
vocabulary to ask such questions? It is unlikely that medieval
masons could read at all, let alone ancient Latin, or that they had
access to such literature as a Roman technical treatise. Their
knowledge was in their bodily skills, and it passed from generation to
generation through tutoring and apprenticeship rather than bookish
learning. This is in the very nature of know-how, distinguishing it
from the scripted, transcribed, argued and taught knowing that, and it
is well grounded in social and institutional structures.
But if farmers could raise horses and masons build cathedrals
strictly with know-how, why should the history of science even bother
with knowing-that? Or conversely, if science is knowledge like
Vitruvius’, why should we concern ourselves with the masons? We
can better understand why both are necessary by returning to the
question ‘how did they build so high?’
The answer to that highlights another important feature of the
historiography of science: the surprising contingency of many
developments – namely, the fact that there was nothing necessary in
them. Yet the ability to build the Gothic cathedral to such heights was
not only a contingent development: it came about as a solution to a
different challenge. The Roman arch is very simple to conceive,
design and measure because it is a segment of a circle. But for the
cathedral builder this harbored a problem. Unlike the ancient church,
which, following Roman architecture, was a simple barrel-shaped
basilica, the cathedral aspired to a cross shape and contained many
separate spaces of different status and function. Naves, aisles,
chapels, etc. called for different ceilings of different heights and
openings of different spans. The Roman arch, being circular, had the
same height and width – the same rise and span – so connecting the
different hallways and enclosures required raising the smaller vaults
on columns and supporting them with heavy piers (Figures 1.7 and
1.9, left) – dangerous, unseemly and expensive.
The solution contrived by the medieval masons was simple and
ingenious. Like the other issues considered in this chapter, it
represents a phenomenon that will capture our attention throughout
the book: a local solution to one particular problem, which carries
much wider and more general implications. It turned out that the arch
does not have to be circular. One can pull the arch by its top, as it
were, making it pointy, thereby separating the rise and the span
(Figure 1.9, right). That way, arches and vaults of different spans
could be connected at one height, allowing for the intricate grid of
paths and halls that is the Gothic cathedral. And it turned out that the
pointed arch (named ‘Gothic’ actually as a derogative, by those who
thought it was vulgar and graceless in comparison to the elegant
Romanesque style it supplanted) had another, much more significant
advantage: it was more stable than the circular arch and allowed
building to the tremendous heights we mentioned at the very
beginning.
Figure 1.9 The advantages of the pointed Gothic arch over the
circular Roman one. The diagram on the left, from Alberti’s De re
aedificatoria (originally 1485, the image is from the 1552 French
edition: Leon Battista Alberti, L’architecture et art de bien bastir
(Paris: Jacques Kerver, 1552)) shows clearly how all dimensions
of the vaults are mutually determined. Gothic arches, as in the
diagram on the right of Cologne Cathedral (whose construction
started in 1248), enabled much higher vaults, as well as
connecting vaults of different spans and heights. This image is
from an 1897 wood engraving.
But this account of know-how cannot tell us the ‘why.’ Why build
so high? Why build arches of different heights? Why replace
supporting walls with flying buttresses? In general: what did the
builders of the cathedrals know about their world – and their place in
it – that prompted them to build this way? The Gothic arch was a
piece of know-how which enabled the medieval masons to construct
very high buildings; it didn’t dictate building them so.
We can’t tell the history of science without paying close attention
to both knowing-how, knowing-that and the relations between them,
because both are necessary and neither one determines the other.
Here is a more specific illustration of this idea: the Mezquita in
Cordoba, Spain. It was built through the ninth and tenth centuries as
the grand mosque of Al-Andalus – the southern part of the Iberian
Peninsula, under Muslim rule from the eighth through the fifteenth
centuries – and then turned into a cathedral in the thirteenth and
fourteenth centuries, after the city was conquered by the Christians.
The Muslim masons, the first to introduce the pointed arch, used it
extensively in the original mosque, but they apparently were not
completely happy with its aesthetics. They camouflaged it under
circular ornaments (Figure 1.10, left) and were never tempted to use
the added structural efficiency to “defy gravity” and stretch their
mosques into the sky. They remained loyal to the sprawling,
repetitive forest of circular arches which gives big mosques their
almost hypnotic atmosphere. When the Christians took over,
however, they not only adopted the engineering feat of the pointed
arch; they turned it into their main architectural tool, piling soaring
Gothic arches and domes on top of the circular, modestly elevated
original ones (note how the bright white and gold Christian dome
towers over the Muslim red and brick arches in Figure 1.10, right).
“Hoist[ing] hewn rock into heaven” was a choice, determined not by
knowing how to do so but by what the builders knew and thought
about their world.
Figure 1.10 Know-how does not determine its application, as
exemplified in the Mezquita in Cordoba. The structure on the left
(known as cinqfoil) is a part of the original mosque. The Muslim
masons who built it camouflaged the real weight-bearing
elements, which are the five pointed arches, with four circular
arches. Similarly, they obscured the pointed shape of the two
arches on both sides (of which we see only half) with three circular
adornments on each voussoir (see Figure 1.7). On the right is the
high dome of the cathedral erected on top of the mosque. The
Christian rulers who had it built made no attempt to hide the
pointed arch. They celebrated the enormous height allowed by this
piece of Muslim know-how and the superiority this height implied.
But what did the people who “inhabited the sky with hammers”
know and think? Did they reflect on the fact that the most perfect
curve – the circle – turned out not to be the most physically efficient
one? Did they ask themselves why the pointed arch is more stable
and how its stability relates to its shape? It is very hard to tell. They
did not write down what they knew.
Knowing-That: The World of the Cathedral Builders
Yet some clues of what the masons, their employers and the
members of their communities knew about the world they lived in are
borne by the cathedral itself. Height is of course one of them: the
cathedral builders were making a dangerous and costly effort to
“inhabit the sky”; the reasons for this effort are that other kind of
knowledge. Another clue is light. The Gothic cathedral is full of light.
It’s not simply lit, or situated so as to allow as much light as possible
into its imposing halls. Rather, the cathedral draws light in through
large, elevated windows, and dyes it with spectacular stained-glass
panes. It was a new know-how – new pigments and new
technologies of glass-making – that enabled this spectacle. But it is
the use of this know-how – the drive for such new capabilities and
this keen interest in light – that tells us what the cathedral builders
knew about their world.
A third clue is the surprising cobweb appearance of the
cathedral’s masonry. It is as if the builders purposefully avoided
matter, replacing it wherever possible with massless structures:
instead of massive supporting walls they introduced slim flying
buttresses; in the walls they could not avoid building, they tore huge
windows; and in the remaining wall space they dug ornate apertures.
The cathedral builders had a clear preference for structure over
matter, and for certain structures in particular, which is the final clue:
the high-medieval, Gothic cathedrals were built according to the
fundamental musical consonances. Between the nave, the transept
and the aisles, the builders used the ratios of 1:1, 1:2, 2:3 and 3:4;
the ratios which constitute the harmonious intervals of tones –
unison, eighth, fifth and fourth correspondingly – from which music
can be produced (Figure 1.11; we will discuss later the Greek
discovery of these ratios and the significance they assigned to
them).
Figure 1.11 The musical harmonies embedded into Chartres
Cathedral. The ‘crossing’ – the intersection of the nave and the
transept – is a square, so the ratio between its length and its width
is 1:1, which stands for the musical ‘fundamental,’ or unison. The
ratio between the width of the nave and the width of the side aisles
and between the length of the transept and its width is 2:1,
corresponding to the octave, or eighth. Between the total length to
the length of transept the ratio is 3:2 (fifth), and between choir’s
length and width: 4:3 (fourth).
These are the clues about the world the cathedral builders knew
as they knew it. It is this knowledge that interests us, so let’s begin
by summarizing what we know about it.
Politically, it was the world of the so-called Holy Roman Empire;
famous for being neither holy, nor Roman, nor really an empire. It
called itself Holy for its Christianity, Roman as a self-aggrandizing
reference to the great empire that last ruled much of Europe and
Empire for its own aspirations. In effect, it was a conglomerate of
mostly Germanic kingdoms, princedoms and fiefdoms. They were
dominated by the Franks, and their emperor was elected by the most
powerful kings after the previous emperor died. The original Roman
Empire was much more Mediterranean than ‘European,’ but the
appropriation of the name was not innocent. It meant that the
German rulers of medieval Northern Europe were claiming authority
over the territories taken by the Romans at their height of power,
around the turn of the Christian era. More crucial for us: they were
claiming allegiance to the Greek culture that the Romans adopted
when they conquered the Hellenistic realm at that time.
If politically it was a world with little structure and no clear
center, it was, in the eyes of its dwellers, a very orderly whole. This
order had the religious and aesthetic meanings that the builders
encoded into the cathedral, because it was the benevolent creation
of God. God made the world physically compact, perfectly round,
with Man in its center and the Heavens encompassing it in
concentric spheres. God, His angels and His saints were in the outer
spheres, keeping a loving and caring eye from above (see Figure
1.12). (As is often the case, by the time this beautiful image was
produced – a year after Columbus’ first journey – the ideas it
conveyed were quickly becoming obsolete.) The same order which
God bestowed on the physical world permeated all aspects of life
and thought: all that existed was organized in the ‘Great Chain of
Being,’ with God at the top and matter at the bottom. Humans
inhabited the middle region, below angels and above beasts, their
reason partaking in the pure and active form which was God, their
body made of profane, passive matter. Among humans, the political
order reflected the metaphysical-ethical one: the king and the bishop
were up and the peasant was down, each where they belonged, and
the pope, God’s emissary, was also the highest political authority.
Figure 1.12 The Cosmos according to Hartmann Schedel’s Liber
Chronicarum, known as the Nuremberg Chronicle (folio 5v,
woodcut by Michael Wolgemut’s workshop; see also Figures 3.10
and 5.8, right). The Chronicle was printed in Latin and German in
1493, so it belongs to the first generation of printed books
(incunabula – see Chapter 7), and is one of the very first illustrated
ones. Comprising a Biblical paraphrase and a history of some
European cities, books like that synthesized Pagan and Christian
knowledge in general, and this image illustrates this synthesis in
cosmology. It does not pretend to be to scale, but the compact
orderliness it reflects is intended. At the very center rests the
Earth, surrounded by the other three elements – Water, Air, then
Fire. The realm of the elements is circumscribed by the lunar
sphere (the Moon drawn at the upper right above the sphere of
fire) and above it the planets (with the Sun directly above the
Earth). Around the planets is the Biblical Firmament, identified with
the sphere of the fixed stars and represented by the signs of the
Zodiac; and around it the crystalline heaven and the unmoved
mover – the Primum Mobile. The saints, angels and archangels
populate the upper realm, presided over by God on his throne.
On Augustine:
Evans, Gillian Rosemary, Augustine on Evil (Cambridge University
Press, 1982).
On Plotinus:
Come and I shall tell you what paths of inquiry alone there are
for thinking: The one: that it is and it is impossible for it not to be.
This is the path of Conviction, for it leads to Truth. The other:
that it is not and it necessarily must not be. That … is a path
wholly unthinkable, for neither could you know what-is-not (for
that is impossible), nor could you point it out.
Parmenides, Fragments, David Gallup (ed. and trans.)
(University of Toronto Press, 1984), p. 55 (emphasis added)
A difficulty presents itself: why should not nature work, not for
the sake of something, nor because it is better so, but just as
the sky rains, not in order to make the corn grow, but of
necessity? … Why then should it not be the same with the parts
in nature, e.g. that our teeth should come up of necessity-the
front teeth sharp, fitted for tearing, the molars broad and useful
for grinding down the food-since they did not arise for this end,
but it was merely a coincident result; and so with all other parts
in which we suppose that there is purpose? … [and then] such
things survived, being organized spontaneously in a fitting way;
whereas those which grew otherwise perished and continue to
perish, as Empedocles says his ‘man-faced ox-progeny’ did.
Aristotle, Physics, Book II, ch. 8
Plato, Meno, 81–86, in: Plato, Complete Works, John M. Cooper and
D. S. Hutchinson (eds.) (Indianapolis: Hacket, 1997), pp. 880–887
(also: http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/meno.html).
3 It’s worth noting that Charles Darwin, from whom we learned the
idea of the survival of the fittest, also couldn’t explain how it is that
the same set of teeth keeps appearing in the same species
generation after generation.
3
The Birth of Astronomy
◈
Looking Up
Disregard, for a moment, all you have been taught and consider the
following question, relying only on what you have actually observed:
when you look up at the sky, what do you see? The answer is not as
straightforward as one might expect.
You may start by answering: ‘it depends.’ During the day, we
see the Sun. During the night, we see the stars. Most of us live in
cities, so we don’t see many of them, but it only takes a short ride
out of town and a bright, moonless night to observe the sky as the
ancients did: full of literally countless stars. The Moon is a bit of a
mystery: although it usually appears during the night, we have all, on
occasion, seen it by day. We probably wouldn’t be assuming too
much if we said that both the day and the night skies are perched
above us like a dome (Figure 3.1 shows what this dome looked like
above Jerusalem the day Titus burnt the Temple). It really looks this
way, meeting the horizon at what seems like a segment of a great
circle.
Figure 3.1 The sky dome, as it would have looked above
Jerusalem on August 3, 70 C E , the day the Jewish Temple was set
on fire by the Roman legions, quashing the Jewish rebellion. You
will find other dates in the literature: the Jewish tradition
commemorates the day as Nine of Av – the ninth month of the
lunar calendar. For reasons to be clarified in this chapter and
Chapter 7, synchronizing these calendars isn’t trivial.
This is not an obvious idea. The sky may look like a dome and
the horizon does look circular, but otherwise nature does not declare
its shape anymore than its motions. Egyptian cosmology describes a
world that is by no means spherical and the author of Genesis
doesn’t seem committed to any particular shape for the firmament
that God placed between the waters above and below. In Homer’s
epics and Hesiod’s mythology of the eighth to seventh centuries
BCE, the heaven is apparently a sphere – it’s not completely clear,
but Hades, the realm of the dead, is below and supposedly as deep
as the Heavens above are high – yet Earth is a circular disc. Similar
considerations of symmetry led some of the philosophers of the next
three centuries (the so-called ‘pre-Socratics’) to argue for a spherical
heaven, but many kept the Earth flat. Aristotle actually explains why
the combination of a spherical (or hemispherical) heaven and a flat
Earth is appealing yet wrong: the celestial horizon appears to be just
a continuation of the terrestrial one, and because the celestial
horizon is so far away, the curvature of the Earth becomes
negligible. So it seems like we’re on a flat surface, with a perfect
hemisphere above us, he continues, but in fact the terrestrial horizon
is very different from the celestial one. It’s determined by the Earth’s
curvature and how high we are, and is rather close by (in modern
terms: about 5 kilometers standing at sea level, and about 20
kilometers on a hill 100 meters high). Even those who considered
Earth spherical didn’t necessarily think of the Sun as completing a
circular orbit around it. The idea that it might be spending the night
under the Earth didn’t occur to them all, and when it did, it seemed to
go against common experience. Springs, for example, come from
below ground, but they are colder early in the morning, so they
couldn’t have been warmed from below by the Sun during the night.
The Pythagorean fascination with the power of geometry and
the Parmenidean arguments about the necessary oneness and
perfection of being seem to have gradually outweighed these
empirical considerations. Through the fifth century BCE, the two-
sphere model became the favorite of Greek philosophers of nature,
and both Plato and Aristotle provided elaborated versions of it. Plato,
as one might expect, supports the notion that the Earth is spherical
with abstract metaphysical arguments. Aristotle, as is his wont, adds
to his cosmological analysis two arguments from observation as to
why it should be spherical.The first is that “the horizon always
changes with a change in our position, which proves that the Earth is
convex and spherical” (Aristotle, Meteorology, II.7,
http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/meteorology.2.ii.html). Observed from
different places, the same stars set (and rise) at different times and
rise to different heights in the sky. This is most evident with the Sun:
the same day is longer or shorter the farther north or south one
travels. Were we residing on a flat surface, we would all have one
horizon; the stars would rise and set at the same time and climb to
the same angle above the horizon. This means that we have a dome
not only above our heads, but also under our feet. Aristotle’s other
argument is that “in eclipses, the outline [of the shadow on the Moon]
is always curved: and, since it is the interposition of the earth that
makes the eclipse, the form of this line will be caused by the form of
the earth’s surface, which is therefore spherical” (Aristotle, On the
Heavens, II.14, http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/heavens.2.ii.html).
Aristotle unmistakably has the two-sphere image clearly ingrained in
his mind: the world is a sphere; the Sun is the source of light and is
also lighting the Moon; an eclipse is the shadow of the Earth on the
Moon – so since its shadow is circular, Earth is a sphere.
Aristotle’s considerations demonstrate that even in this
rudimentary form the two-sphere model already assumes at least
two crucial insights about the cosmos, neither of them trivial: that the
Sun and the stars move together as one rotating spherical whole;
and that the Sun produces daytime, the light of day being nothing but
sunlight. These insights are far from obvious. Consider, by way of
comparison, the monotheistic tradition: according to Genesis, you
may recall, God created light, and designated it ‘day,’ on the first day
of creation. He only created the sky2 on the third day, and only on
the fourth day did he create the heavenly bodies, anointing the Sun
to rule the day and the Moon and stars – the night. All heavenly
bodies were created “to give light upon the Earth,” and the Sun’s
light isn’t unique – it isn’t the cause of the day. For the writer of
Genesis, day and night are different entities, different creations – not
astronomical phenomena.
It is with the two-sphere model that the confusingly changing
positions of the bodies we see in the sky become the heavenly
motions that concern the astronomer. The model itself tells us
nothing about the causes of these motions. The Babylonians, for
example, left no visual or verbal account of this model. They gave no
evidence that they were interested in heavenly causes or expected
their astronomy – their mathematical theory of heavenly motions – to
fit their cosmology – their general understanding of the making of the
cosmos. Their tables of planetary positions (about the planets
momentarily), an exemplary achievement of observational
astronomy to be discussed later, are patently free of theory. But even
in these strictly empirical tables the two-sphere model is embedded.
One can hardly understand them without the categories introduced
by the model (and which we will discuss below): ecliptic, equinoxes,
solstices, oppositions, and so on.
How It Works
With the two-sphere model, the appearances become astronomical
phenomena. Let’s reiterate and expand (Figure 3.4).
The celestial sphere – the heavens – rolls from east to west at a
regular pace. The axis of this rotation goes through the Earth (the
yellow dotted line), from the North Pole to the South Pole, and the
largest plane perpendicular to this axis cuts Earth at its equator and
the celestial sphere at the celestial equator (the red circles). The axis
points always in the same direction.3 In the Northern Hemisphere it
points at a particular star: the North Star or Polaris, which is not a
very bright star, but usually visible, so very useful for navigation. In
the Southern Hemisphere, it points (almost) at Sigma Octantis,
which is not nearly as visible, and hence not as useful. One full
rotation of the heavens around Earth we call a day. 4
The Sun and the stars rotate around Earth with the celestial
sphere. Because the axis of this circular rotation is not above our
heads (unless we’re stationed at one of the poles), the Sun spends
some of its orbit under the horizon – night – and some over it – day
(the yellow circles). The length of the day depends on the angle
between our horizon and the axis of rotation; that is, it depends on
our latitude – our position on the Earth relative to the equator and the
poles. The same is true for the stars: carried by the celestial sphere,
they rise above the horizon in the east, travel in the same direction
as the Sun (through the south in the Northern Hemisphere and
through the north in the Southern Hemisphere) and disappear under
the horizon towards the west. Stars which are close to the North Star
(or to Sigma Octantis in the Southern Hemisphere) – whose angular
distance from the celestial pole is smaller than the pole’s angular
distance from the equator – rotate in the same direction, but always
remain above the horizon. These are the Circumpolar stars (on the
right in Figure 3.2). Conversely, we can assume that there are stars
we never see, because they always remain under the horizon.
This is what happens daily – the diurnal motion. What about the
seasons? And the shorter and longer days? Here the two-sphere
model allows an even more interesting understanding.
The length of the day changes because the Sun changes where
it rises and sets. We can think of this change as the Sun shuffling
back and forth within a small segment of the horizon – moving north
in the Northern Hemisphere as the summer comes and south with
the winter (and the inverse in the Southern Hemisphere) – making its
path get longer and shorter accordingly, as in Figure 3.2. But if we
think of the whole celestial sphere as rotating around us from east to
west with the Sun on it, we can think of the Sun, instead of
oscillating, as moving regularly, in a constant direction, on the
rotating heavens. In other words: the Sun, according to the two-
sphere model, has two motions: one with the celestial sphere (east
to west), and one on it (west to east).
In a little more detail: the two-sphere model explains the
changes in the length of the day by having the Sun travel east along
a big circle that is at an angle (which turns out to be 23½°) to the
celestial equator (Figure 3.4). The Sun’s journey through the
heavens is much slower than the Sun’s journey with the heavens.
This means that every time the daily rotation of the celestial sphere
carries the Sun above the horizon, the Sun is at a different position
on the sphere. So every day the Sun rises at a slightly different point
on the horizon and travels at a slightly different trajectory. It takes the
Sun a little more than 365 astronomical days – 365 revolutions of the
heavens around Earth – to complete one circling of the heavens.
This is what we call ‘a year,’ or in more pedantic astronomical terms
– ‘a solar year.’
The Sun’s annual path in the heavens – the circle it draws on
the celestial sphere – is the ecliptic. When the Sun is at one of the
two points where the ecliptic crosses the celestial equator, it spends
as much time above the horizon as under it, making the day and
night of equal length; Figure 3.4 shows why. This is the vernal
(spring) or autumnal equinox. When the Sun is at the northernmost
point of this path – the furthest from the equinoxes to the north –
then in the Northern Hemisphere it spends the longest time above
the horizon and the day is the longest. This is the summer solstice.
The southernmost point is the winter solstice with the shortest day.
When the Sun is under the horizon in the Northern Hemisphere, it’s
above the horizon in the Southern Hemisphere, so the solstices are
exactly reversed. Our horizon, we have noted, changes according to
our latitude – how far north or south we are from the equator – and
the two-sphere model now explains why. So how far on the horizon
the Sun will get from solstice to solstice, how high in the sky it will
get on each day, and how long the day will be all depend on our
latitude. On the equator, the angle between the point on the horizon
in which the Sun will rise on the solstice and the point it will rise on
the equinox is the angle between the celestial equator and the
ecliptic – those 23½°. On the equator the Sun’s daily path is always
perpendicular to the horizon. The two-sphere model explains that
this is because the equator is perpendicular to the axis on which the
celestial sphere rotates, so the day is always the same length as the
night. On the poles, the Sun rises once a year, on the vernal
equinox. It spirals up to 23½° above the horizon then spirals back
down, disappearing under the horizon on the autumnal equinox, not
to reappear until the next vernal equinox.
As fundamental and pre-theoretical as the model is, it already
allows crucial insights and discoveries. Here is a particularly
important one: almost all the stars are fixed – they remain in the
same place in the heavens relative to one another, rising and falling
at the same spot on the horizon. But it turns out that the Sun is not
alone in its journey through the great celestial sphere. With it are a
few other heavenly bodies, which also change their position among
the fixed stars, rising and setting at different points along the horizon.
These have come to be called planets; ‘wanderers,’ πλανήτης, in
Greek. Unlike the fixed stars, these wanderers don’t twinkle, which,
according to Aristotle, is a sign that they are closer. More importantly,
although each planet travels at its own pace (each takes a different
period to complete a whole revolution, meaning that each has its
own year), all planets share a path and direction with the Sun,
travelling along a narrow band within a few degrees of the ecliptic.
When divided into parts which are given astrological significance,
this band becomes the Zodiac (Figure 3.5), which we’ll discuss in
some detail in the chapter on magic (Chapter 6).
Figure 3.5 The Zodiac. A segment of a mosaic tiling the prayer
hall of a sixth-century (Byzantine period) synagogue near Beit
Alpha, Israel, with Hebrew names for the signs. In a way that
nicely illustrates the different facets of knowledge discussed in
previous chapters, the mosaic is inscribed with two dedications
near the entrance. One, in Aramaic, attends to the political,
cultural and financial side: it dates the mosaic to the reign of
Emperor Justin, and states that it was paid for by donations from
members of the community. The other, in Greek, attends to the
know-how. It reads: “May the craftsmen who carried out this work,
Marianos and his son Hanina, be held in remembrance.”
Making Time
The Astronomer’s Role
As we realized earlier with our stargazing exercise, these concepts
are not easy to come by. Even in this very rudimentary form,
knowledge of the heavenly motions already demands acute and
concentrated observation; a model that requires mastering; and
considerable leisure. Why should anyone invest this labor and
expertise? What can be gained from studying the sky? What’s the
use of astronomy?
Astronomers, one might say, handle time. They provide
calendars. From the point of view of astronomy, calendars are
predictions of regularly occurring events – times and places where
the main heavenly bodies should be expected. The rise and fall of
the Sun is the most prominent of these events, but every other
planetary motion can also serve as a calendar. And each presents
challenges to this demand for regularity, especially the Moon, whose
behavior may seem completely erratic. From a wider cultural point of
view, calendars determine days of significance – Holy Days – and
related considerations, such as the direction of prayers or times of
rituals. Some occurrences, although they happen fairly regularly, are
rarer and thus carry special significance: the occasions when the
Sun spends the most or least time above the horizon (summer or
winter solstice), or the occasions when the day and night are equal
(equinoxes, as we’ve learned). Some occasions are so rare that they
seem extraordinary: the appearance in the heavens of an unknown
object (comet) or the occlusion of the Sun or the Moon (eclipses).
Aristotle even speaks, or tells us of observing the eclipse of Mars by
the Moon – the rarer the occasion, the more competence the
astronomer predicting it can boast. The more spectacular the rare
event is, the more significant it is. What the exact significance is;
what counts as beneficent or maleficent; what kind of influence the
different heavenly arrangements carry for the individual or the
community – this of course changes from place to place; from culture
to culture. The Greeks titled the discipline that assigns and deciphers
this significance astrologia, and in this sense it is not unreasonable
to say that astronomy is the handmaiden of astrology.
It turns out that the answer to ‘who needs astronomy’ is also not
trivial. One might think that everyone would find timekeeping useful:
the time of day to milk the cows or feed the horses and the time of
year to plant or harvest. But this practical time is not what the
astronomer provides. The peasant can’t rely on clocks and
calendars; she listens to her cows and checks the readiness of the
soil or the ripeness of the fruits. Hers is natural time: local,
contingent, changing from year to year. The motions of the heavenly
bodies, which make the abstract and idealized astronomical time,
are of no use to her.5
There are many reasons to think of astronomy as the
paradigmatic science, and this is one of them: that astronomy, and
science in general, is impractical. It requires significant resources. As
we saw, astronomy does not develop naturally from curiously gazing
at the sky. It requires expertise, and expertise is expensive: the
expense of supporting the livelihood of people who devote their time
to developing it instead of producing food and shelter for themselves
and their families. A society where every person has to provide for
their own subsistence cannot afford astronomers. And such a society
also has no use for astronomy. Astronomy is of use only to a culture
organized enough to apply the knowledge astronomers produce: a
culture with priests who consult calendars concerning rituals and
kings who consult astrologers concerning war. So here is the point in
a nutshell: astronomy, and by extension science, is only of use to a
culture organized enough to make use of astrology.
Useful or not, the Time provided by astronomers and recorded
in their calendars is the record of regular, orderly motion of the
heavenly bodies.6 Yet these bodies don’t seem to move all that
regularly. The heavenly sphere as a whole is orderly enough in its
rotation: the length of the astronomical day – from sunrise to sunrise
(or from sunset to sunset, as in the Jewish tradition) – appears to be
always the same. But the length of the day and the night – the time
the Sun spends above versus under the horizon – changes from day
to day, as discussed above. What we haven’t considered yet is that
the pace of the change is not regular. This is a fact we can easily
recognize: the days shorten very quickly, then stabilize so to speak,
then lengthen quickly and so forth. From an astronomical standpoint,
this means that the motion of the Sun on the ecliptic is sometimes
faster and sometimes slower. The motion of the other planets along
the ecliptic is even less orderly; not only do they change their
velocity: they sometimes seem to change their direction. This
phenomenon, called ‘retrograde motion’ (Figure 3.6), has a very
important role in the history of astronomy, and we will return to it
below.
Figure 3.6 Retrograde motion. This is a sequence of photos from
31 January 2015 to 11 September 2016, showing Mars moving in
an S-shape trajectory from upper right to lower left, and Saturn in
a flattened compact loop behind it, against the background of Libra
and Scorpio. The Milky Way is on the left and Antares is the bright
star just under Mars in its fourth last position. This image is
composed of numerous exposures spanning nearly a year, taken
with a modern camera and lens. Such technology was obviously
not available to the naked-eye-observing astronomers of yore. For
them, distinguishing the planets from the backdrop of fixed stars
and plotting the nightly changes of position as a motion over a
long period demanded keen dedication and a powerful set of skills.
Positions and Regularities
Astronomers produce orderly time from their observations of the
motions of the planets, so it is important to explain here what
‘observations’ and ‘motions’ are for the ancient and pre-modern
astronomer. As we noted at the beginning of this chapter, we cannot
see the heavenly bodies move. Even the daily motion of the whole
heavenly sphere is too slow to really see as it’s happening, although
the changes of the place of the Sun or the stars during the day are
obvious enough that we can think of them as having just moved from
the place we saw them a little while ago to the place they are now.
The motion of any of the planets on the ecliptic – even that of
mercury, the swiftest of the lot – is much slower still. All we can
directly observe is the planet’s position against the backdrop of the
fixed stars. The change in that position from day to day is what we
call ‘motion’, and what the traditional astronomers termed ‘anomaly.’
This term illustrates an important point: that the very idea that
the heavenly bodies move is already a bold theoretical assumption.
Moreover: the idea that they are bodies is just as bold. Until the
advent of telescopes in the seventeenth century, only the Sun and
the Moon looked somewhat like bodies – to the naked eye, the rest
of the planets and obviously all the stars are just points of light; as
we learned in the exercise we started with.
Figure 3.7 Naked-eye astronomical observation instruments.
These instruments are used for measuring angles: between two
stars; between a planet and a star; between a planet or a star and
the horizon. The woodcuts are from John Seller’s Practical
Navigation, originally published in 1669 and in many editions since
(including modern ones). The gentleman on the left is holding an
advanced version of a very basic angle-measuring instrument:
Cross Staff, also known as Jacob’s Staff. The observer puts the
end of the staff to their eye and moves one of the perpendicular
rods so its ends ‘touch’ two celestial objects – for example, a
known fixed star and a planet. The angle between one end of the
rod, the eye-end of the staff and the other end of the rod is the
empirical datum recorded. The gentleman on the right holds the
most sophisticated instrument of that lineage – the sextant. The
sextant is in a sense no longer a pure naked-eye instrument,
because it comprises a lens and a mirror, but it is still used in a
comparable way to capture an angle.
Figure 3.11 Eudoxus’ system (on the left) and the way it explains
retrograde motion (on the right). Each planet is carried by a
number of rotating spheres. All the spheres are concentric and
each one rotates in a uniform angular velocity, but each rotation is
around a different axis and at a different velocity. The planets’
apparent changes of velocity and direction, of which the
retrograde, ‘hippopede’ shape is the most pronounced, are
produced by the combination of these different motions.
For himself, we saw, Aristotle took the position that the Earth is
stationary at the center of the cosmos. But he admits that this –
unlike the sphericity of Earth – is not a position he can support by
observations, only by general considerations of the shape of the
cosmos.
With even the authoritative Aristotle remaining somewhat
reticent in the matter, both options seem to have remained
respectable, because a century later Aristarchus took the opposite
view: that Earth, together with the rest of the planets, moves about
the Sun.
Although he is the most famous believer of a heliocentric
cosmos (Helios is Greek for the Sun) of Antiquity, we only know
about his claims indirectly. The original work in which this hypothesis
was presented was lost – we know about Aristarchus’ hypothesis
primarily from Archimedes, the great mathematician and inventor of
Syracuse (287–c. 212 BCE) whom we’ll discuss later. But it seems
reasonable to assume that his arguments for the centrality of the
Sun, which imply the motion of the Earth, were similar to those
Aristotle ascribed to the Pythagoreans, though perhaps a little less
general and metaphysical and more specific and astronomical. As
we saw, Aristarchus had particular interest in the light coming from
the Sun, and his analysis of eclipses gave the Earth only a
secondary role – a cause for shadow.
What is most important about Aristarchus’ suggestion is that it
was seriously considered – and rejected. The main argument against
it was evoked by Archimedes. If the Earth moves around the Sun (so
was the reasoning) it has to cover very great distances. It should be
very far away on, say, the vernal equinox, from where it was on the
autumnal equinox. This means that we should have a very different
line of sight to the heavens, and should be able to note what is called
parallax – a difference in the angles we observe between the stars.
But such annual stellar parallax was not observed. The stars are
arranged in the heavens in the same way throughout the year – the
constellations don’t change with the seasons. If we were, as most
agreed with Aristotle, at the center of the cosmos, this is exactly how
it should be. If Aristarchus was right, then the only possible reason
we do not observe any stellar parallax had to be that the stars were
so far away that the size of our orbit around the Sun was completely
negligible in comparison to this distance. In Greek parlance, it had to
be as if the whole orbit of the Earth were like a point in proportion to
the distance to the stars. One could even estimate this outrageously
large proportion. The human eye, at its very best, can distinguish
half a degree. The distance from one side of the orbit to the other is
180°, so if Aristarchus was right, then in order for us not to observe
stellar parallax, the distance to the stars should be more than 360
times the diameter of the orbit. This in and of itself seemed
ridiculously large to the Greeks. Moreover, with the calculations of
Aristarchus himself, as well as Eratosthenes and others, they
thought they had a fairly good estimation of our distance to the Sun,
which is of course the radius of the Earth’s orbit. This number, times
360, was so large they could hardly express it with their number
system. In fact, Archimedes presents this argument in the context of
introducing a new way in which even such ridiculously large numbers
could be written. It was absurd, and the Greeks, in spite of being
apparently somewhat attracted to the idea of a moving Earth (or they
wouldn’t have reintroduced and discussed it occasionally), had to
reject it.
The Legacy of Greek Astronomy: Ptolemy’s
Orbs
Still, the main legacy of Greek astronomy was theoretical. It
culminated in the work of the Alexandrian Claudius Ptolemy (c. 85–
165) whose main book, known throughout the mediaeval world by its
Arabic title Almagest (from the Arabic pronunciation of the Greek
magiste – greatest), remained the most important work in astronomy
well after the collapse of the Hellenic realm, until the second half of
the sixteenth century (Figure 3.14). The significance of Ptolemy’s
astronomy, like that of Aristotle’s philosophy and Galen’s medicine
(which we discuss in Chapter 8), lies much beyond any of its
particular claims. The Almagest shaped the fundamental practices,
criteria and methods of studying the heavenly motions everywhere,
from Europe through the Muslim realm to China. For 1,500 years, to
be an astronomer meant to employ and slightly modify the
theoretical tools provided by Ptolemy in order to improve upon the
calculations of previous generations working within essentially the
same framework.
Figure 3.14 Saturn’s epicycles in a Latin edition of Ptolemy’s
Almagest from 1496. Georg von Peuerbach (1423–1461)
translated and edited the first four books, and his disciple
Johannes Regiomontanus (1436–1476) completed this edition
after his death. Note: as explained in Figure 3.15, the center of the
deferent is d, but the points of reference are t – Earth (terra); and
e – equant.
3 The axis actually moves – we’ll touch on this below – but very
slowly, so from the point of view of initial observation we can treat
it as stationary.
Thus far have I treated of the position and the wonders of the
earth, of the waters, the stars, and the proportion of the universe
and its dimensions. I shall now proceed to describe its individual
parts; although indeed we may with reason look upon the task
as of an infinite nature, and one not to be rashly commenced
upon without incurring censure. And yet, on the other hand,
there is nothing which ought less to require an apology, if it is
only considered how far from surprising it is that a mere mortal
cannot be acquainted with everything. I shall therefore not follow
any single author, but shall employ, in relation to each subject,
such writers as I shall look upon as most worthy of credit. For,
indeed, it is the characteristic of nearly all of them that they
display the greatest care and accuracy in the description of the
countries in which they respectively flourished; so that by doing
this, I shall neither have to blame nor contradict any one.
Pliny, Natural History, Book III, Intro., V. 1: 151
(http://resource.nlm.nih.gov/57011150RX1)
– was original and very influential. The work of some of the great
heroes of Greek learning of the early centuries of the Christian era
was so steeped in Roman culture that, even when it was conducted
in Greek, it may just as accurately be considered Roman
Knowledge. An excellent example is Galen (Claudius Galenus, c.
130–c. 200), the most influential writer on medicine for 1,500 years,
whom we’ll discuss at length in Chapter 8. A Greek aristocrat by
descent who moved in the Hellenistic realm of Asia Minor, Greece
and Alexandria, he first made a name for himself in the distinctly
Roman practice of physician to gladiators, and spent the peak of his
career in Rome.
Yet by the end of Galen’s life most of the writings of his
Hellenistic predecessors were hardly available, and of the grand
edifice of Greek learning only scattered fragments and wistful
memory were left. This memory is what is expressed in the myth of
the burning of the library in Alexandria and what turned the
encyclopedic writings of Varro, Cicero, and especially Pliny into a
long-lasting tradition. The last and very influential pagan member of
this tradition was Martianus Capella, who (like Augustine) flourished
in Roman North Africa in the fifth century and whose On the
Marriage of Mercury and Philology (De Nuptiis Philologiæ et
Mercurii) was so popular there that some 250 manuscript copies of it
still survive and those from the sixth century had already gone
through many earlier hands. The very title of the book reveals the
concept of knowledge embedded in it: philosophy (represented by
philology) and rhetoric (represented by Mercury, the emissary god)
are being joined together. Gone is the strict Greek distinction
between pure episteme and practical doxa as well as Plato’s hostility
to rhetoric and its pretense to knowledge, interfering with
philosophy’s pursuit of Truth. The two are now to be wedded, and
knowledge is served to them as gifts from the seven ‘free’ disciplines
(from Varro’s list, Martianus deleted medicine and architecture and
maintained the seven liberal arts we’ll discuss later), represented by
their respective muses (Figure 4.4, left). As the image in Figure 4.4,
right, powerfully reflects, debate – the lifeline of Greek learning – has
become an anathema, and logic (termed ‘dialectic’) is not there to
order and adjudicate argumentation, but to quash it.
Figure 4.4 Medieval illustrations of Martianus Capella’s De Nuptiis
Philologiæ et Mercurii (The Marriage or Philology and Mercury),
where philology stands for philosophy, and Mercury, the god of
commerce and words – for rhetoric. On the left: a copper
engraving illumination by Herrad of Landsberg (1125/1130–1195),
“Hortus Deliciarum” (Garden of the Delights); an allegory of
“Philosophy surrounded by the seven liberal arts,” each
represented by its muse. On the right: “Dialectic conquers the
serpent of debate.” This is an earlier illustration of a tenth-century
manuscript.
Figure 4.5 The scriptorium. Usually the monk would not be alone
in the scriptorium – like most aspects of monastic life, intellectual
work takes place in the presence of others. But the image, from a
fifteenth-century manuscript and depicting the translator and
copyist Jean Mielot (died in 1472), captures well the devotional
concentration of the work in the scriptorium, which by decree was
conducted in complete silence.
The Monastery and the Scriptorium
With Vivarium as a model, the monastery became Christianity’s
primary institute of knowledge. At the heart of many monasteries
was a library, and at its heart – the scriptorium; the room of the
scribes (Figure 4.5). In the scriptorium, manuscripts – usually on
vellum, fine parchment made of calf skin – were produced and
reproduced: copied, translated, annotated, commented on and
illustrated. Almost no censorship and very little selection were
practiced – the veneration of the wisdom of the ancients outweighed
any dread of “heresies … instigated by philosophy,” as Tertullian had
put it (see Chapter 1). The hunger for this wisdom was insatiable and
any text was deemed worthy of fulfilling it: sacred or profane,
heretical or obscene. A strict law of silence ruled the scriptorium: the
work there was a spiritual exercise. Texts were not only reproduced
materially; they were absorbed, committed to memory, elevating the
soul. And this spiritual learnedness was institutionally sanctioned.
The monk’s vows bound him to a life devoted to prayer and work,
strictly governed by a written “Rule of the Order,” but if he was
literate, he could discharge his work duties in the scriptorium. “My
desire has always been either to study or to instruct or to write” said
Bede, “in that I have always observed the rule of the order and the
daily singing of the hours in church” (Bede, Historia Ecclesia, cited
by Pedersen, 48).
Bede was a Benedictine, and the Rule he was following had
been written some 150 years before his birth by St. Benedict
(Benedict of Nursia, c. 480–550). But in the world surrounding the
monastery, there was very little orderliness. The Roman Empire was
first taken over by the Germanic tribes populating the areas it
occupied to its north, and its final collapse left Europe divided into
numerous kingdoms, princedoms and fiefdoms. The relations
between and within these entities were strictly hierarchical, but they
were ruled much more by loyalties than by law. At the bottom of the
hierarchy stood the serfs – the peasants bound to the land they
cultivated but didn’t own. They paid for it in crops and labor to the
lord of the manor – the fundamentally self-sufficient rural estate. The
lord owed his allegiance to the king who granted him the estate in
exchange for services rendered – usually military. Often the
exchange happened many generations earlier, between ancestors of
both, but the lord’s first loyalty was still to his remote king rather than
to his local serfs. The kings and princes within the Kingdom of the
Franks – that is, the Holy Roman Empire – owed their allegiance to
the emperor, elected by the most powerful of them every time the
previous one passed away.
It befell the Church to offer some structure and stability to this
amorphous cluster of local customs and long-distance loyalties –
known as ‘feudalism’ – by which Europe was governed. With its
official structure, its uniform language (Latin) and its universal code
of law (the Roman), the Church provided the only institutional cross-
European uniformity. Even more important was the Church’s role we
discussed in Chapter 1: to grant overall legitimacy to this political
system. This legitimation it provided by embedding the political
hierarchies in to the ‘Great Chain of Being’: the metaphysical and
religious hierarchy stretching from profane matter up to the abstract
divine (Figure 1.13). It was a legitimacy essential for ruling.
Emperors who tried to defy the pope’s decrees learned that their
military might was no match to the power he could unleash through
the symbolic act of excommunication. So much so, that Henry IV’s
willingness to take upon himself any measure of humiliation in order
to relieve the pope’s wrath – to ‘walk to Canossa,’ where the pope
withdrew himself – became a proverb of surrender.
Medieval Know-How
It was only under the auspices of the Church that organized
production of knowledge could take place. Declining commerce with
the great cities of the Mediterranean and little indigenous urban
culture meant that Europe of the centuries after the collapse of
Rome had no cultural infrastructure to support anything similar to
Hellenistic learning. This is not to say that the people of the manor or
the budding medieval town developed no knowledge worthy of our
story, only that this was almost exclusively the ‘know-how’ that by its
very nature leaves behind artifacts, but few testimonies as to how
they were produced.
Traces of this know-how, however, are to be had – sometimes
embedded in the artifacts, sometimes more directly. Recipe books,
for example, tell of elaborate knowledge of local flora and fauna and
their nutritional and medicinal value. This was the domain of the
witch, the rural physician and the herbalist; the recopies of the town
apothecary show that his knowledge (unlike the rural ‘medicine
woman’ or herbalist, the apothecary was always a man) spanned
further: he was literate, imported materia medica, and mixed his own
preparations. In the manor, as we learn from paintings and remains,
natural energy was harnessed in increasingly efficient ways. The
improved use of beasts of burden, which we discussed in Chapter 1,
is perhaps the simplest of examples. Mills, marshalling the elements
and comprising sophisticated mechanical devices such as cranks
and geared wheels, provide a more elaborate example. Mills steered
water and wind, moving grindstones to produce flour from grain, big
saws to cut wood, and large bellows to stir up furnaces in which iron
was smelted. The mills were a great classical invention whose use
significantly declined with the collapse of the Western Roman
Empire, but re-emerged in the eighth century and onwards: the
Domesday Book, a 1086 survey of England and Wales prepared for
William the Conqueror, reports 5,624 (!) water mills in England alone,
and the number seems to have doubled every century. Many
monasteries, as they aggressively transformed themselves into
manors by appropriating the land around them, became centers of
technological development of this kind. Brewing, distilling, dyeing
and founding were ways to add value to the raw materials by which
the serfs paid their tithes – their charges for using the land. The
monasteries thus had the wherewithal and the motivation to develop
practical disciplines like herbalism and metallurgy – and with them
alchemy – as well as mill technology.
Within the monastic realm, ‘practical’ didn’t only mean ‘material.’
Observance required observing time: both “the daily singing of the
hours” (as Bede termed it above) and the yearly arrivals of the holy
days. The daily task was greatly aided by the same mechanical
technology that allowed for mills: geared wheels were essential for
the great medieval invention of the mechanical clock. Wheels were
not enough: the clock required the insight that in order to measure it,
time needed to be broken down into segments, and thus too the
mechanical contraption to perform the task: the verge-and-foliot
escapement (Figure 4.6). The origins of the European escapement
are unknown – a very different escapement was used in the great
eleventh-century Chinese astronomical clock of Su Song. We’ll also
probably never know if and how the medieval application of geared
wheels related to the technology of the Antikythera mechanism we
discussed in Chapter 3, which also had a chronometric task. If there
were such ancient resources from which this technological
knowledge stemmed, the monastery would indeed be the place
where they could be expected to surface.
Figure 4.6 Verge-and-foliot escapement – the heart of the
medieval mechanical clock. Illustration by David Penney ©. The
crown wheel c is moved clockwise by weights – the clock’s engine
– and its axle h is connected to the dial, directly or through some
more gears. The teeth a and b, in right angle to each other, are
pushed by the wheel, causing verge g, hanging on the chord f, to
oscillate left and right. The swing of the balance (‘foliot’ – fool) d
alternately engages and disengages the teeth, allowing the crown
wheel to ‘escape’ (hence the term) and leap only one tooth at a
time. The pace of oscillation is regulated by moving the weights e
inside or out. The further out the weights are, the higher is their
‘positional weight’ (see Chapter 9), the longer the oscillation, and
the slower the pace of the clock.
Monastic daily life followed artificial time, ordered by the bell
marking the hours for prayer (think of the children’s rhyme Frère
Jacque), in which the mechanical clock with the ticking of the foliot
had a natural place. The annual time was kept with the help of the
computus: an applied version of the Hellenistic astronomical
calendar, by which the dates relevant to the Christian were
determined (Figure 4.7). The computus was a ‘paper tool,’ rather
than a mechanical one, but it was as much a piece of practical,
technological know-how and the time it kept was as artificial as the
clock’s. It did not attempt to capture accurate heavenly positions
(such as the equinox and the full Moon which mark Easter) but to set
regular dates, more or less around those astronomical events, by
which rituals could be regulated and instituted.
Figure 4.7 Medieval knowledge of Hellenistic astronomy. A
diagram of the relation between the phases of the Moon and its
position relative to the Sun (Sol, on the right) from Abbo of Fleury’s
(c. 945/950–1004) Opinion concerning the System of the Spheres.
The text is part of a compilation of astronomical texts, written in
Durham cathedral by a number of scribes during the second
quarter of the twelfth century, now at the University of Glasgow
Library (MS Hunter 85). The most important is Bede’s 19 Year
Cycles (referring to the Metonic cycle – see Figure 3.12), a
computus providing the dates for Easter for the years 1–1253 (so
for some 500 years ahead of his time), showing powerful
command of the practical sides of that astronomy.
Aristotle said that (there are) two principles, namely, matter and
species, and a third called the “operative (cause)”; also that the
world always is and was. Refuting the error, therefore, of these
and similar (men), the Holy Spirit, handing down the discipline of
truth, signifies that God at the beginning of times created the
world and before times eternally existed, commending (thereby)
His Eternity and Omnipotence.
Lombard, Sentences, Book 2, Dis. 1, ch. 3.
Figure 4.10 The primary astronomy textbook in the medieval
university: Tractatus De Sphaera by Johannes de Sacrobosco
(John of Hollywood, c. 1195–1256). As befitting a working book,
this manuscript copy, from c. 1230 (currently at the Stillman Drake
collection of the University of Toronto), is heavily annotated by at
least two hands from two different times.
Rashed, Roshdi, “The Ends Matters” (2003) 1(1) Islam & Science
153–160.
For in the same way as we do not know what was His wisdom in
making it necessary that the spheres should be nine – neither
more nor less – and the number of the stars equal to what it is –
neither more nor less – and that they should be neither bigger
nor smaller than they are, we do not know what was His wisdom
in bringing into existence the universe at a recent period after its
not having existed. The universe is consequent upon His
perpetual and immutable wisdom. But we are completely
ignorant of the rule of that wisdom and of the decision made by
it.
3. The invention of the movable press and its cultural impact begs a
comparison to the rise of twenty-first-century communication
technologies. Is the comparison helpful? What insights does it
suggest? Historically? Philosophically?
Aquinas, Thomas, “Q. 14, Art. 9: Can Faith Deal with Things Which
Are Known as Scientific Conclusions?” in Truth (Quaestiones
Disputatae de Veritate), Robert E. Schmidt (trans.) (Cambridge:
Hacket, 1995 [1954]), Vol. 2, pp. 247–252.
Smith, Pamela H., The Body of the Artisan: Art and Experience in
the Scientific Revolution (University of Chicago Press, 2004).
Ong, Walter J., Ramus, Method, and the Decay of Dialogue: From
the Art of Discourse to the Art of Reason (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1983).
On Jesuit science:
On Jesuits in China:
Mind, the father of all, who is life and light, gave birth to a man
like himself whom he loved as his own child. The man was most
fair: he had the father’s image; and god, who was really in love
with his own form, bestowed on him all his craftworks. And after
the man had observed what the craftsman had created with the
father’s help, he also wished to make some craftwork, and the
father agreed to this. Entering the craftsman’s sphere, where he
was to have all authority, the man observed his brother’s
craftworks; the governors loved the man, and each gave a share
of his own order.
Corpus Hermeticum I.12–13 in: Copenhaver, Hermetica, 3
In this quote, taken from the first of the Hermetic dialogues, one
finds perhaps the best expression of the main themes of all magical
creation stories and a model of how stories make sense of and
justify the aspirations of the magician. In such cosmogonies, creation
is not a one-time divine utterance, incomprehensible and
unchangeable. It is an ongoing “craftwork,” in which “man” – the
primordial, androgynous representation of all humans – is explicitly
invited to take part. The magician is not necessarily, therefore, a
delusional heretic, trying to take an impossible bypass around
unchangeable general laws of nature; he is rather a “loved”
participant in the process of shaping these laws.
Magical Epistemology
Antiquity and Secrecy
The figure of Hermes Trismegistus captures another crucial aspect
of magical thought. The Hermetic Corpus was likely written in the
second century, which is the age of the oldest manuscript we have at
hand. This manuscript was only discovered in 1945 (in Nag
Hammadi in Upper Egypt), so it could not have been known to early-
modern readers of the Hermetica. Yet Hermes, its alleged author, is
said to have been an Egyptian priest, a contemporary of Moses. This
allowed his Christian devotees to find in the Corpus prophesies of
the coming of Christ, supposedly pre-dating the Old Testament,
giving credence to their belief in both Christ and Hermes. But this
emphasis on antiquity was not unique to the Christian magicians.
The magical text, as we also saw in the Kabbalistic examples, draws
its authority from its (often feigned) antiquity. This is not to say that
the ideas in the Hermetica or Sefer Hazohar are not ancient: modern
scholarship has shown that many of them had indeed originated in
Egypt and Mesopotamia many centuries before these two texts (and
the others we mentioned) were written. What is important is that
magicians never proclaim novelty or demand credit for innovation:
the more antique their knowledge, the more trustworthy it’s
supposed to be, and the more potent.
The story of the re-emergence and consequent decline of the
Hermetic Corpus in Renaissance Europe illustrates this point well. In
1462, Cosimo de’ Medici obtained a fourteenth-century manuscript
of the first fourteen dialogs of the Corpus. Byzantium was collapsing
under Ottoman pressure and many of its cultural treasures were
becoming available, at the proper price, to the supremely wealthy
and marvel-hungry princes of Italy and their Humanist clients. But in
the eyes of Cosimo this clearly was no run-of-the-mill marvel.
Marcilio Ficino (1433–1499), the best scholar of his entourage and
probably the most skilled scholar of his generation, was at the time
busy with no less than a new translation of Plato. Cosimo instructed
him to abandon it and fully dedicate himself to preparing an edited
Latin version of these newly discovered magical texts. Within less
than a century, Ficino’s 1471 Corpus Hermeticum went through two
dozen editions and was translated into French, Dutch, Spanish and
Italian – an imposing best-seller. Then, in 1614, the Hermes craze
ended abruptly. A French scholar by the name of Isaac Casaubon
(1559–1614) demonstrated, using new philological techniques, that
the Hermetic Corpus could not have been that ancient: he found
terms, phrases and puns which referred to ideas and events that
happened much later than Hermes’ alleged time. And although
magical ideas continued to thrive, Hermes and the texts ascribed to
him sunk into the realm of antiquarians and uninformed acolytes.
Why would such a thing have happened? If ideas are important
and convincing, why should it matter if they were authored a
millennium later? The first words of Ficino’s preface demonstrate
why:
For Ficino, Hermes was more important than even Plato because he
was more ancient. Casaubon was proud of his novelty – of his new
philological skills and of his ability to produce new knowledge with
them. This pride is at the heart of the natural philosophical tradition:
the great veneration of the authority of Aristotle notwithstanding, the
discovery or invention of something not known before has always
been its main pride and purpose. Figure 6.5 provides a nice
illustration: it is the first page of a sixteenth-century edition of a
thirteenth-century text on optics by the Polish friar Erazmus Ciołek
Witelo (c. 1230–c. 1300). Although he follows the work of the great
Muslim optician Ibn al-Haytham (Alhazen – see Chapter 4) very
closely, Witelo makes a point to celebrate his own novelties, and the
very first words on this page read: “you have in this work, lucid
reader, a great number of geometrical elements, which you would
not find in Euclid …” For the magician, in contrast, there is no new
knowledge – only a secret truth revealed once, and corrupted by
time and fading memory, so only direct access to that secret, as from
a truly ancient text, is worth careful attention.
Figure 6.5 The frontispiece of the 1535 printed edition of Witelo’s
Perspectiva (or Opticae libri decem) from the 1270s. The text
above the image promises explanations, practicality and
innovation: “you have in this work, lucid reader, a great number of
geometrical elements, which you would not find in Euclid …
concerning the projection, infraction, and refraction of rays … of
light in transparent bodies and in mirrors plane, spherical,
columned, pyramidal … on which the visual deceptions of Natural
Magic mostly depend” (see Figure 6.8).
Amara Tonta Tyra post hos firabis ficaliri Elypolis starras poly
polyque lique linarras buccabor uel barton vel Titram celi massis
Metumbor o priczoni Jordan Ciriacus Valentinus.
Kieckhefer, Magic in the Middle Ages, p. 4
ablanathanablanamacharamaracharamarach
ablanathanablanamacharamaracharamara
ablanathanablanamacharamaracharamara
ablanathanablanamacharamaracharamara
Kieckhefer, Magic in the Middle Ages, p. 20
For van Helmont, as for many witches over the centuries (whose
practices he aims to emulate and legitimize), this meant trying to
circumvent reason – to arrive at a mental state in which perception
was not hampered by reason’s judgment. This could be achieved
through fasting, dancing, avoiding sleep, alcohol or drugs – like the
famous unguent produced from toads and smeared on the witch’s
skin. It could also be achieved by reciting, repetitively, words and
formulas – since ‘enchantment’ comes from ‘chanting,’ this repetitive
intonation is a fundamental magical practice.
Magical Cosmologies
The Symbolic World
Language, in the magical tradition, is not an aid and a tool of reason,
but a means to avoid it, and magical words are powerful not for the
meaning they carry, but for their direct, vocal effect. But while magic
takes meaning away from language, it ascribes it to everything else
in the world. For the natural philosopher, we saw, the substances in
the world are related to one another in causal and deterministic
ways. For the magician, their relations are symbolic – they have
meaning.
Things in the magical cosmos resemble, reflect and express one
another, and these similarities are potent. Mars is red like an angry
face, so it causes war. Mercury is a name for both a planet and a
metal, so they must be somehow related – and indeed, they are both
quick (hence the metal’s other name: quicksilver). Mercury is also
the name of a god – who is fleet-footed and therefore the messenger
god – and his priest by the same name (or in Greek – Hermes) is the
messenger of the great magical secrets. Wine mixed with water
resembles blood, so it can be used by the necromancer (and indeed,
by a priest conducting the Eucharist); and the tongue of a frog, put
on a sleeping woman’s heart, will untie her tongue. Some symbolic
relations are sympathetic: a walnut is folded like the brain, so it can
cure headaches; draconium, whose leaves look like dragons, cures
snakebites; the eye of the keen-sighted vulture, wrapped in wolf skin
and hung around the neck, cures eye ailments. Some relations are
antipathetic: the antipathy between the sheep and the wolf is such
that a drum made from wolf skin will mute one made out of
sheepskin; and because the shrew-mouse is afraid of the wheel rut,
dirt from the rut will cure its bite.
The most important and general symbolic relation for the
magician is that between the human body – the ‘microcosmos’ – and
the world as a whole – the macrocosmos (or ‘megacosmos’). The
terms seem to have been coined in an influential twelfth-century
manuscript, Cosmographia, by Bernard Silvester – another example
of those who dabbled in both practical and learned magic – and we
also find a version of this idea in the Kabbalistic concept of Adam
Kadmon (primordial man). John Dee (1527–1608/9), who succeeded
in combining life as an extraordinary practical mathematician –
Elizabeth’s most cherished and busiest expert on land surveying and
navigation – with an active magical career ranging from astrology to
communicating with angels, provided a particularly poetic version of
this grand analogy:
The magical world is thus not the causal system that science
inherited from Aristotelian natural philosophy; this is why this world is
opaque and resists both reason and the senses. But magical nature
is not completely obscure and capricious – even if the powers that
magic aspires to harness and manipulate are occult. It has a
structure that can be deciphered: an organic network of signs and
representations whose symbolic heart is the human body. These
assumptions gave learned and practical magicians common
grounds: they were embedded into the talismans, amulets and
incantations of the practitioner, and analyzed and elaborated upon
by the scholar. They are also the core beliefs of the most academic
of magical pursuits: alchemy and astrology.
Scientific Magic
It is far from clear that alchemy and astrology belong in this chapter,
because they lack many of the fundamental properties by which we
distinguished magic. They are hardly secretive: astrology was taught
in universities well into the seventeenth century (primarily in relation
to medicine), and alchemy, although never established as part of the
curriculum and quite guarded about its substances and operations,
was a respectable subject matter of learned texts and encyclopedias
throughout the Middle Ages. Although alchemists and astrologists
shared their veneration of antiquity with all mediaeval scholars, they
were much less averse to innovation than the magicians whom we
discussed above. Alchemy was an empirical discipline, whose
practitioners were proud of new means and new effects, and
astrology went through a series of reforms intended to improve its
empirical accuracy and philosophical foundations. Neither had much
use for demons or difficult cosmogonies – indeed, they fit well within
the Aristotelian framework and the fundamental source for astrology,
the Tetrabiblos (simply ‘Four Books’), was authored by the great
father of medieval astronomy – Claudius Ptolemy. But no discussion
of magic can be complete without considering these two disciplines,
because within them are crystalized, in theory and practice, the two
fundamental beliefs that distinguished the magical tradition from
mainstream, institutionalized, natural philosophy: the belief in the
symbolic make-up of the cosmos and the belief in the vital,
hierarchical order of its elements. Things in the world reflected,
expressed and signified one another; they grew and transformed into
one another, evolving from base to noble; they related to one
another passionately and intently and influenced one another in
ways reminiscent of human language. The world was full of
meanings and intentions that the alchemist and the astrologer
deciphered and manipulated with great skill and erudition.
Alchemy
Alchemy took its name from the Arabic al-kimiya, a term whose
origin could have been the Coptic word for pouring and mixing or the
ancient Egyptian word for black earth. Both meanings are based on
good reasoning: the alchemist attempted to untangle the weave of
meanings within the realm of matter; to unlock matter’s powers of
transformation and assist and hasten the process by which
substances ennobled themselves. The goal was itself noble, even
heroic: to uncover the all-transforming Philosopher’s Stone and the
all-curing Panacea. The process made good Aristotelian sense: all
things in the world strive to actualize their potential – acorns to oaks
and children to adults – and so did matter. Base metals were formed
inside the earth, from dry earthy and moist watery evaporations, and
evolved into the most perfect of metals – gold. This evolution,
explained Aristotle (as discussed in Chapter 2), was driven and
directed by the form – matter itself was passive – so the alchemist
trod on solid theoretical grounds in trying to strip the base metal
down to primal matter – materia prima – and grafting onto it new
forms. This process – “The Great Work” (Opus Magnum) – began
with calcination by slow heating; continued with solution in sharp
liquids; putrefaction in warm compost; and reduction in
“philosopher’s milk” (perhaps lime water of some concentration).
This produced the materia prima, which after sublimation in spiritual
substances, coagulation and fermentation with yeast of gold, was
elevated into superior matter (materia ultima) or Philosopher’s Stone
– lapis philosophorum: “this stone which isn’t a stone, this precious
thing which has no value, this polymorphous thing which has no
form, this unknown thing which is known to all” (cited in Hanegraaff,
Dictionary, p. 25), as it’s described by Zosimos of Panopolis, whose
fourth-century fragments represent the earliest alchemical texts in
existence. The Philosopher’s Stone could then be multiplied and
spread onto the base metal to produce gold.
Many of the processes and materials employed in this process
are shrouded in mystery, including the substance with which The
Great Work (and “The Lesser Work” – producing silver) begins, and
the language the alchemists used is often purposefully coded: “red
rose” for an elixir; “eagle” for evaporation; and “raven” for black. But
there are many hints, such as the colors matter takes, after which
the stages are called: nigerdo (black); albedo (white); rubedo (red)
and so forth. Some of the remaining alchemical notebooks from
periods far apart, like those of the Persian Rhazes (Abu Bakr al-
Razi, 865–925) or the Bermuda-born, Harvard-educated George
Starkey (1628–1665), are orderly enough to be deciphered, and with
an impressive combination of chemical and textual skills historians
have recently replicated some of those stages and effects (although
not the production of gold, regrettably), like the Philosophical Tree in
Figure 6.6, made of mercury and “a seed of gold.” The modern
replication may tempt us to think of alchemical knowledge as nothing
more than practical chemistry couched in strange terms, but this
would be a mistake. We may translate ‘calcination’ into ‘metallic
oxidation,’ for example, and from this translation we do gain some
understanding of how we can comprehend and perform the process.
But by the same token we lose some of our understanding of the
way the alchemist comprehended and performed it. The organic
connotations of ‘putrefaction,’ for example, are not empty: the
alchemist sees all matter – metal, wood or human flesh – as
decomposing and decaying in similar ways. Similarly, the moral
connotations of ‘sublimation’ are crucial for the alchemist: he expects
to be elevated by the process no less than the material he works on,
and knows that the success of the material transformation depends
on his own capacity for spiritual transformation. Here is how this
close affinity between the alchemist and his subject matter is
expressed by a very cool-headed and forward-looking thinker –
Francis Bacon:
Figure 6.6 The ‘Philosophical Tree’ produced by Lawrence
Principe in his laboratory. Following directions deciphered from
cryptic instructions given by George Starkey, Principe sealed a
pasty mixture of gold and a specially prepared mercury in a long-
necked flask (the “philosopher’s egg”) and heated it. After several
days, the enclosed mass that initially occupied less than a fifth of
the flask suddenly ‘grew’ upwards into a tree-like structure that
filled the flask. For Starkey and his fellow alchemists, this striking
phenomenon proved that they could cause the ‘seed of gold’ to
vegetate – a significant step towards producing the transmutatory
Philosopher’s Stone.
But certain it is, whether it be believed or no, that as the most
excellent of metals, gold, is of all other the most pliant and most
enduring to be wrought; so of all living and breathing
substances, the perfectest (Man) is the most susceptible of help,
improvement, impression, and alteration. And not only in his
body, but in his mind and spirit. And there again not only in his
appetite and affection, but in his power of wit and reason.
Francis Bacon, “A Discourse Touching Helps for the
Intellectual Powers,” The Works of Lord Bacon (London:
Henry Bohn, 1854), Vol. II, p. 46
These great deeds are all natural; the members of Salomon’s House
don’t call upon any demons or angels to assist them or try to bypass
the order of nature. But the deeds are magical, in the sense
discussed at the beginning of the chapter: they are not simply
spectacular but aspire to manipulate nature at its very foundations.
Bacon was not alone among his contemporaries, the advocates
and virtuosi of the New Science (whom we’ll consider in detail in the
following chapters), in adopting this magical confidence in the power
of human knowledge to mimic and even compete with the divine.
Galileo boasted such confidence unabashedly: “with regard to those
few [things] which the human intellect does understand, I believe that
its knowledge equals the divine in objective certainty” (Galileo
Galilei, Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems, Stillman
Drake (trans.) (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1967), p.
103). This was the type of epistemological pride that the Bible
powerfully rebuffed with the story of the Tower of Babel, and it may
well have been the main reason for Galileo’s difficulties with the
Church. Yet Kepler, whose piety is unquestioned, puts it as strongly:
“geometry is coeternal with God” (Johannes Kepler, The Harmony of
the World, A. J. Aiton et al. (trans and ann.) (Philadelphia, PA:
American Philosophical Society, 1997 [1619]), p. 146).
Bacon’s science is magical, and so is his world: it’s full of many
particular facts, not clearly related to one another. He tried to collect
as many instances as possible in his Sylva Sylvarum (Forest of
Forests, in ten parts, titled “Centuries”) – whose name, again,
reveals Bacon’s clear and explicit indebtedness to the magical
tradition. Some of the facts are quite inane, like: “It is observed by
some, that all Herbs wax sweeter, both in smell and, if after they be
grown up some reasonable time, they be cut, and so you take the
latter Sprout” (Francis Bacon, Sylva Sylvarum (London: William Lee,
1670), Cent. V, p. 99). Some of them are a little more practical and
esoteric:
Take a Glasse with a Belly and a long Nebb, fill the Belly (in
part) with Water: Take also another Glasse, whereinto put Claret
Wine and water mingled, Reverse the first Glasse, with the Belly
upwards, Stopping the Nebb with your Finger; then dipp the
Mouth of it within the Second Glasse, and remove your Finger:
Continue it in that posture for a time; And it will unmingle the
wine from the Water: the wine ascending and setling in the topp
of the upper Glasse, and the water descending and setling in
the bottom of the lower Glasse. The passage is apparent to the
Eye; for you will see the wine, as it were, in small veine, rising
through the Water. For handsomnesse sake … it were good you
hang the upper Glass upon a Naile.
Bacon, Sylva Sylvarum, Cent. I, pp. 3–4 (I left the spelling,
capitals, italics and punctuation as they are in the original, but
in the following, for ease of reading, I’ll use the modern
transcription.)
This is not to say that della Porta doesn’t take his experiments
seriously, only that he does not expect them to tell him something
new about the nature of things: they are performances;
“demonstrations” of known “truths” and of his skills as a magician.
For Bacon, on the other hand, the experiments are ways to examine
the validity of the magical claims, which he takes with many grains of
salt, and find order in the phenomena that they produce:
Bacon was very much setting the tone for the way in which the new
natural philosophers would approach magic: adopt the practical
knowledge while attempting to maintain a distance from all of its
suspect baggage. A particularly important version of this approach
was the assimilation of alchemical knowledge and magical remedies
into medicine, especially by Philippus Aureolus Theophrastus
Bombastus von Hohenheim, better known as Paracelsus (1493–
1541), and Jan Baptist van Helmont whose words we saw above.
We will discuss the place of magic in their medical work in detail in
Chapter 8. For our discussion here it’s more significant to stress how
important it was for Paracelsus and van Helmont to naturalize these
magical means and practices, and, for all the obvious reasons,
detach themselves sharply from any association with demonic
magic. In similar ways, Kepler could incorporate astrology’s
fascination with mathematical harmonies into his new astronomy,
and Newton could find in astrology’s ‘influences’ a way to
conceptualize celestial forces in his new celestial mechanics, while
both steered carefully clear from any problematic association with
the supernatural.
Figure 6.8 The frontispiece of Natural Magick, the best-selling
1658 English translation of della Porta’s Magia Naturalis. Note the
alchemical symbols on the left: the many-breasted Nature, the
Salamander in Fire and so on; and the mixture of mundane and
occult topics in the Table of Contents on the right: from “Of the
Causes of Wonderful things,” through the “Production of new
Plants” and “Cookery” to “Invisible Writing,” “Pneumatic
Experiments” and “Chaos.”
3. Some astrology is still practiced today – there are still experts who
can have one’s nativity drawn and interpreted. Can it therefore be
argued that the tradition has survived? If not – what has been
irretrievably lost?
On alchemy:
On astrology:
The magician:
Bono, James J., The Word of God and the Languages of Man:
Interpreting Nature in Early Modern Science and Medicine (Madison,
WI: University of Wisconsin Press, 1995).
3 It is not clear if the Hebrew term comes from the Greek ‘sphaira’
(σφαίρα – sphere), relating to the Hellenic cosmology, or from the
Hebrew ‘sappir’ ( – ספירsapphire), which connotes radiance.
The heavenly bodies seem to rise and fall and move with the
seasons, but all this “celestial ballet” is but an appearance:
Osiander’s preface does little justice to the great ambition and self-
confidence embedded in Copernicus’ project and expressed in his
dedication to the pope, but is worth quoting at length for a number of
reasons. First, because the question of whether such
epistemological humility befits scientists, or is reasonable to expect
of them, still engages philosophers. Secondly, because it reminds us
that this complex distinction between what is to be accepted within
philosophical discussion and what is to be ‘truly’ believed was an old
technique that allowed the Church to ignore the contradictions
between naturalistic philosophy and monotheistic belief and retain its
position as the leading European institution of knowledge. Osiander,
though protestant at the time, was a Catholic convert for whom this
difficult intellectual maneuver made perfect sense when facing such
an unsettling challenge to “the sound basis of the liberal arts.” Lastly,
this strange constellation demonstrates well the upheaval of the
times: a Protestant priest using a medieval Catholic ploy to protect
an astronomical doctrine created by a Catholic friar in the context of
the Counter-Reformation; moreover, a doctrine Luther was
apprehensive about.
Giordano Bruno and the Radical Interpretation
What Osiander seems to have feared – a true religious scandal –
took some forty years to materialize – but it finally did. Claims with
deep cosmological implications, such as those advanced by
Copernicus, are bound to have religious implications. The scandal
came in the hands of a known rascal, Giordano Bruno (1548–1600),
who reasoned as follows: since Copernicus’ theory demands that the
world be so enormous, we may as well consider it infinite. And an
infinite world is no longer a cosmos; it is a universe: it has neither
center nor periphery, nor any privileged points. It can, and therefore
should (because God is omnipotent), contain infinitely many suns
and, around them, infinitely many planets. Most crucially: this implies
infinitely many earths, and on them, presumably, infinitely many
human races. It is easy to see how different this image of the
universe – and the place of humans in it – is to the traditional one,
represented so emblematically in Figure 1.12. In that convincing and
reassuring marriage of Aristotelian cosmology and Christian
cosmogony, deeply rooted for many centuries, humans were nestled
at the center of the cosmos, with God’s loving eye resting on them.
In its stead Bruno was suggesting an infinite universe scattered with
infinite humans – how could one God attend to them all? How could
He reveal himself to them? And how could He do it in the flesh?
In 1593, Bruno found himself in the hands of the Inquisition, and
in 1600 he was burned at the stake for heresy in Campo di Fiori in
Rome. The exact nature of the allegations against him remains
uncertain, as the protocols were lost, in sloppiness not characteristic
of the Inquisition – but there were many good reasons for the
authorities to consider him an unrelenting heretic. Born in Nola, in
southern Italy (he subsequently called himself “the Nolan” in many of
his writings), he became a Dominican friar in Naples in 1575, and
already in 1576 was accused of Arian heresy (a doctrine
distinguishing between Jesus and God), which pushed him to flee to
the more tolerant north and commence a life of wandering. In 1579
Bruno was in Geneva, where he converted to Calvinism, only to be
excommunicated later on charges of disrespect. He moved on to
France, where he published works on the nature of memory and on
Neo-Platonic philosophy, as well as anti-Church satires. He made his
way to England and wrote extensively and brilliantly enough that by
1583 he became very popular in the court and in Oxford, but when
he turned his satire against his new benefactors he was forced to
return to the continent and to Catholicism. He then made the mistake
of returning to Italy in 1591, where a Venetian patron, disappointed
with him as a tutor, denounced him to the Inquisition. It’s hardly
likely, then, that Bruno was burned strictly for his support of
Copernicanism, but the pattern is clear: in a climate of religious
volatility, with the radical ambitions of astronomers and natural
philosophers, and with enthusiasts adopting new scientific ideas to
support deviant theological doctrines, the delicate balance on which
Church-sponsored science depended was quickly eroding.
Tycho Brahe and the New Empirical Astronomy
For astronomers in the second half of the sixteenth century, the
hypothesis of the recently departed Copernicus brought enthusiasm
of a different sort. As long as the Earth was assumed static and at
the mean center of all orbits, the changing positions of the planets
against the backdrop of the fixed stars meant only that: changing
angular positions. Even the notion that they were moving was in a
sense an interpolation: all that could be observed was that a planet
was in one place one day and in another the next. From an off-
center vantage point, these changing angles could be translated into
real motions, over real distances – not just theoretically, as we saw
in Copernicus’ reasoning above, but empirically. Figure 7.2, center
and left, demonstrate how, with simple trigonometric calculation,
Copernicus could infer the real distances of the planets from the
Sun: the radii of their orbits, expressed in Astronomical Units (the
caption explains the procedure).
After millennia in which they were concerned almost exclusively
with theoria – with constructing geometrical models – European
astronomers found new excitement in observations, an excitement
Johannes Kepler (1571–1630) would poetically express a couple of
generations later:
… if the earth, our home, did not measure out its annual circuit
in the midst of the other spheres, changing place for place,
position for position, human reasoning would never struggle to
the absolutely true distances of the planets, and to the other
things which depend on them, and would never establish
astronomy.
Johannes Kepler, The Harmony of the World, A. J. Aiton et al.
(trans. and ann.) (Philadelphia, PA: American Philosophical
Society, 1997 [1619]), p. 496
The person most responsible for the empirical surge was Kepler’s
short-term employer, Tycho Brahe (1546–1601). Tycho was a Danish
nobleman who had received his education in German, Protestant
universities (where he famously lost his nose in a duel, to be
replaced with a metal one). Returning to Denmark in 1567, he
secured the support of King Friedrich for a project the like of which
Europe had never seen: a very large, purpose-built astronomical
observatory, which he had constructed on the Island of Hven, in the
straits between Denmark and Sweden.
We can borrow the term ‘Big Science’ to describe Tycho’s
Uranienborg, or ‘The Castle of Urania’ (astronomy’s muse – Figure
7.3, left). It was financed by the court and employed some 100
people at any given time, from servants, through instrument-builders,
apprentices, calculators and expert astronomers, to Tycho himself.
Most crucially: it featured large, expensive, purpose-built instruments
(note how much bigger they are than the astronomers operating
them in Figure 7.3, center). The largest was a building-sized mural
quadrant, reminiscent enough of Maraˉgha observatory (see
Chapters 4 and 5), that historians have speculated about there being
a direct relation between the structures. These instruments were the
same angle-measuring, naked-eye instruments described in Chapter
3, if expertly built and more accurate. What made them unique was
their sheer size, which allowed minute division, and hence a much
higher resolution than their traditional, hand-held versions (Figure
3.7), enabling Tycho to make observations many orders of
magnitude more accurate than those of his predecessors (Figure
7.3, right).
Therefore let Galileo take his stand by Kepler’s side. Let the
former observe the moon with his face turned skyward, while the
latter studies the sun [with his camera obscura] by looking down
at a screen (lest the lens injure his eye). Let each employ his
own device, and from this partnership may there some day arise
an absolutely perfect theory of the distances.
Kepler’s Conversation with Galileo’s Sidereal Messenger,
Edward Rosen (trans. and ann.) (New York: Johnson Reprint
Corporation, 1965 [1610]), p. 22
For Galileo, the Earth either moved or did not, and if the evidence
was for the former possibility, it made no sense to hold the latter.
Bellarmine and Galileo agreed that the scriptures were beyond
doubt and that “it is not the same to show that one can save the
appearances with the earth’s motion … and to demonstrate that
these hypotheses are really true in nature” (this is the way Galileo
put it! – Finocchiaro, The Galileo Affair, p. 85). Their conclusions,
however, differed in a way that would turn out dangerously, despite
the inquisitor’s goodwill.
Bellarmine didn’t force Galileo to give up Copernicanism or to
adopt a literal interpretation of the relevant verses. He even carefully
considered the Copernican arguments for the possibility that we
move without experiencing it, although he found them unconvincing.
What Bellarmine demanded of Galileo was to take into consideration
what “a dangerous thing” it would be to play around with scriptural
interpretations, and “whether The Church can tolerate giving
Scripture a meaning contrary to [that of] the Holy Fathers and to all
the Greek and Latin commentators,” who are “all agreeing in the
literal interpretation that the sun is in heaven and turns around the
earth with great speed, and that the earth is very far from heaven
and sits motionless at the center of the world” (Finocchiaro, The
Galileo Affair, p. 67). A good scholar, in Bellarmine’s view, would
take it all into account – the theological and political implications as
well as the intellectual price: to refute 1,500 years of arguments
would require an extremely powerful counter-argument. Still,
Bellarmine added:
Nor can one or should one seek any greater truth in a position
than that it corresponds with all particular appearances.
Finocchiaro, The Galileo Affair, p. 85
Biographies:
Caspar, Max, Kepler, C. Doris Hellman (trans. and ed.) (New York:
Dover, 1993).
On Rudolf’s court:
Evans, Richard J., Rudolf II and His World (Oxford: Thames &
Hudson, 1997).
On Kepler’s optics:
On Kepler’s cosmology:
On Kepler’s astronomy:
Freedberg, David, The Eye of the Lynx: Galileo, His Friends, and the
Beginnings of Modern Natural History (University of Chicago Press,
2002).
On Galileo’s telescope:
On Galileo’s discoveries:
Reeves, Eileen, Painting the Heavens: Art and Science in the Age of
Galileo (Princeton University Press, 1997).
Edgerton, Samuel Y., Jr., The Mirror, the Window, and the Telescope:
How Renaissance Linear Perspective Changed Our Vision of the
Universe (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2009).
On Galileo’s trial:
The reader might wonder how Galen could think that an argument
like this, clearly based on empirical observations and contestable
assumptions, may lead to certainty – perhaps he was using
‘certainty’ in a less restrictive way than we do. But his readers in the
next 1,500 years hardly perceived a problem, and in the universities
of the Middle Ages he was taught as the prime example of a brilliant
application of the Aristotelian tools in the acquisition of natural
knowledge.
The most influential aspect of this application was Galen’s
fundamental theory of the body. Galen adopted and canonized the
single text in the Hippocratic Corpus – On the Nature of Man – that
specifies exactly four humors: blood, phlegm, yellow bile and black
bile. This quartet allowed him to release the Hippocratic concept of
body from its bond to Platonic ideas about the constantly fluctuating
matter, and frame it instead in the symmetries of Aristotelian natural
philosophy. In this Aristotelian interpretation of the Hippocratic ideas,
the four humors correspond to the four elements and, like the
elements, Galen conceives them less as physical, flowing liquid
substances, and more as realizations of the fundamental properties
– cold and hot; dry and wet. Each humor he relates to an organ:
blood to the heart; phlegm to the brain; yellow bile to the liver; and
black bile – the spleen. Each is dominant in a different personality
type: the blood in the music- and fun-loving sanguine; the phlegm in
the slow and lazy phlegmatic; yellow bile in the ill-tempered and
querulous choleric; and black bile in the moody melancholic (Figure
8.3). Galen can then further map the humors and their corresponding
organs and personalities onto the seasons of the year and of human
life, onto climates and planets (whose astrological characters we
discussed in Chapter 6): the northerners living in a cold climate are
phlegmatic; teenagers are sanguine, etc.
Galen thus describes the healthy human body as varied and
changing yet stable and balanced – just like nature as a whole. Dis-
ease, as the English word still captures, is conceived as a loss of this
balance. For example: when the cold and wet winter enhances the
cold and wet phlegm (which was related to the element of water), it
could travel from the brain to the sinuses and the lungs, causing
those maladies characterized by coughing, like bronchitis and
pneumonia. Spring increases the amount and flow of blood (the
humor aligned with air, hence warmth and moistness), so one could
expect high fevers and nose bleeds. Choler (yellow bile) and black
bile are associated with harm, and are held culpable in more serious
diseases. Some fatal conditions (probably what we’d call hepatitis)
come with yellowed eyes and swollen liver – signs of excess of
yellow bile; the excrements and puss of people dying of the Black
Death (the Bubonic Plague) are indeed black, and the inner organs
of people dying of severe melancholy (likely malaria) are also badly
darkened – both clear signs of the effects of the black bile.
For hair lip, pound mastic very small, add the white of an egg,
and mingle as thou dost vermillion, cut with a knife the false
edges of the lip, sew fast with silk, then smear without and
within with the salve, ere the silk rot. If it draws together, arrange
it with the hand; anoint again soon.
Learned Resources
The local and practical nature of the Leechbook’s remedies is hardly
surprising: the physician was supposed to heal rather than explain,
so his knowledge needed to be effective and his means readily
available. More surprising is that the healing tradition was in fact
quite attentive to the learned medical tradition, and showed interest
in both abstract ideas and remote, inaccessible remedies.
Some of the ideas did have immediate practical implications.
Bloodletting is recommended in the Leechbook – for example,
“against pocks, a man shall freely employ bloodletting and drink
melted butter.” It is not recommended as often as it is in Galenic
medicine, but the book does attempt (not in nearly as many details)
to follow Galen’s instructions regarding its proper application. It
considers, for example, “[o]n what season bloodletting is to be
foregone” and “how a man shall forego bloodletting on each of the
six fives in the month, and when it is best.” It’s not easy to say by
what route these Hellenistic teachings trickled into ninth-century
England – remember that the Leechbook dates before the
establishment of the universities and the great Christian translation
project. But many of the leechdoms are clearly translations from the
Greek, presumably through Latin, and names of teachers are
mentioned – Oxa and Dun, presumably learned physicians.
Perhaps most surprising and telling, though, is that the
Leechbook shows interest in remedies which are clearly impractical
because they are very far away and thus almost impossible to
obtain:
Apothecaries
Closest to the learned physician in cultural and intellectual standing
was the apothecary, who gathered and dispensed materia medica
and prepared medications. Most of the apothecary’s knowledge was
local and particular: his ingredients came from the nearby paddock,
forest and quarry. Apothecaries affiliated with institutions –
monasteries or hospitals, and later faculties of medicine – often had
their own herbaria. There they would grow fragrant plants to drive
away miasmas – vapors carrying epidemics and recognized by their
foul smell – and medicinal herbs. These plants and minerals were
the ‘simples,’ which the apothecary could provide to be used as-is, or
mix to create compound remedies.
But as Bald’s exotic ingredients remind us, from very early on –
perhaps as far back as this book is concerned – knowledge and
goods traveled, if with difficulties, across Asia, North Africa and
Europe – especially materia medica. This was true even if the
medical theories making sense of the ingredients and procedures
were often lost when crossing linguistic and cultural boundaries. This
became particularly true with the dramatic globalization of commerce
from the fifteenth century onwards: from Malabar, European
apothecaries imported the calumba root; nutmeg, mace and cloves
from Moluccas; hell-oil from Madagascar; from Mexico, jojoba and
physic nut; guaiacum from the Bahamas and many, many more.
The distant and esoteric origins of many of the apothecary’s
ingredients meant that it was almost necessary for him to be literate,
at least to some degree and at least in the vernacular. This was
required in order to communicate with merchants of exotic materials
and to consult with learned physicians, and it also gave him access
to two definitive textual resources. The first was the book On Medical
Material of the first-century Greek physician Pedianos Dioscorides
(Figure 8.5). In it, the apothecary found the description of some
1,000 plants and minerals, almost exclusively from Dioscorides’
native Asia Minor, carefully arranged according to their medical
properties. On Medical Material remained available in the original
and in Arabic and Latin translations throughout the Middle Ages (the
Latin title – De materia medica – is the origin of the term we’ve been
using), finally finding its way to the vernacular and remaining in use
until the nineteenth century. Dioscorides’ book was the most popular,
but not the only one of its kind. Apothecaries in the Muslim realm, for
example, could also make use of the Compendium on Simple
Medicaments of the Andalusian physician Diyaˉʾ Al-Dıˉn Ibn al-
Baytaˉr (1197–1248), which contained three times the number of
medical substances as Dioscorides’ book. Surprisingly, neither Ibn
al-Baytaˉr’s Compendium nor his commentary on Dioscorides were
known in the Christian world, although his Treatise on the Lemon
was.
The other learned resource of importance to the apothecary was
Galen’s theory of simples, which he could find either in translations
of Galen’s own On the Powers of Simple Remedies or in its
elaborations by Ibn Sina and his Arabic- and Latin-writing disciples.
This was the theory of elementary substances and their medical
efficacies, which gave sense to the use of the simples and direction
to compounding them. The theory explained the properties of the
simples in terms of Aristotelian elements and their fundamental
properties, and also explained why the powers of some simples
could not be analyzed in this way. These powers were ‘occult’ in the
way we discussed in Chapter 6, namely: they arose from properties
that belonged to the unique natural essence of the substance and
couldn’t be further analyzed – they just were.
Figure 8.5 A drawing of a blackberry from Dioscorides’ On
Medical Material in the original Greek. Images like this were added
later, and can be found in various editions. This one is from the
Codex Medicus Graecus, which is a particularly interesting
manuscript for its longevity and its continuous use. It was created
in 515 in Constantinople for the Byzantine princess Anicia Juliana
and contains 435 (!) mostly naturalistic illustrations, including no
fewer than 383 of them full page, but it was used for centuries as a
textbook in Constantinople’s imperial hospital, and intensively so,
as the annotation in cursive Greek attests (including βάτος –
batos, or bramble – at the top). It was still in the hospital’s records
as a working text in 1406 (!) when it was restored, re-bound and
augmented with a table of contents and scholia. After the fall of
Byzantium to the Ottomans, it came to the use of Moses Hamon,
the Jewish physician of the Sultan, and the knowledge was still
relevant enough that the name of each plant was added in Arabic
(which can be seen among the branches: ﻋﻠﯾّﻖ ُ اﺗوش
ُ – ٰوwa’atoosh
ullaik) and Hebrew (written in very small Rashi script, bottom right:
– בטושbatosh). The Codex Medicus was the basis for many
copies of Dioscorides, including one for the pope in the middle of
the fifteenth century, and only a century later did it take on its
apparent original intended use as an object of marvel, when
purchased for the Holy Roman Emperor in Vienna, where it has
been since, coming to be known as The Vienna Dioscorides.
Witches
Occult properties, you may recall, were important for magical
thought, and magic indeed provided another theoretical framework
for the practitioners of medicine. ‘Wise women’ like Matteuccia or
Walpurga (Chapter 6) may have been only marginally literate, but
what they did know about the magical ideas ingrained in their healing
made sense of their practices and related them to learned medicine.
The fundamental concepts of the learned medical tradition did
lend themselves to the magician’s approach. The Galenic body, we
saw, represented its environment, both immediate and remote, and
was open to its influences. These representations and influences
were the symbolic relations assumed and manipulated by magicians,
and the macrocosm-microcosm analogy we discussed above
captures these common grounds of magic and medicine. Bald,
practical in approach but familiar with learned sources, dedicates in
his Leechbook significant space to remedies for magically induced
harms, like “Leechdoms against every pagan charm and for a man
with elvish tricks; that is to say, an enchantment for a sort of fever,
and powder and drinks and salve.” He’s also keen on magical
remedies for natural maladies, for example:
For joint pain; sing nine times this incantation thereon, and spit
thy spittle on the joint: “Malignus obligavit; angelus curavit;
dominus salvavit.”
Midwives
Of all who nursed and healed the human body, midwives deserve
special consideration. First, because in childbirth, they tended to a
healthy bodily process, if often difficult and dangerous. This meant
that they had physiological and functional knowledge of the body
shared by neither learned physicians nor other healers – who
attended to the body mostly in distress. Secondly, because midwifery
was the one discipline – not just of medicine but of knowledge in
general – dominated by women. As noted, women were relatively
welcomed in medicine, but men wrote almost all the books (Trota
and Hildegard are the exceptions that highlight the rule), including
books on women’s medicine. There were men-midwives, but when
men tried to gain control over the lucrative practice of midwifery,
women successfully defended their relative independence.
It was a partial independence. The medical guilds were closed
to women just as the university was, and midwives don’t seem to
have established one of their own. Moreover, being a mysterious,
feminine process, childbirth was an object of nervous attention by
city, court and especially the Church. This was because the child, not
yet baptized, was particularly susceptible to witchcraft (Sleeping
Beauty documents this fear well). So as the fascination with and
anxiety about witchcraft mounted in the late Middle Ages and
through the Renaissance, the authorities appropriated the licensing
and supervison of midwives.
But these restrictions also had a liberating effect on midwives:
they gave them a clear sense of professional identity and integrity,
as well as the legal means to protect them. The self-confidence that
this identity bred is nicely captured by Jane Sharp’s dedication of her
1671 The Midwives Book “to the midwives of England”:
Sisters.
I Have often sate down sad in the Consideration of the many
Miseries Women endure in the Hands of unskilful Midwives;
many professing the Art (without any skill in Anatomy, which is
the Principal part effectually necessary for a Midwife) meerly for
Lucres sake. I have been at Great Cost in Translations for all
Books, either French, Dutch, or Italian of this kind. All which I
offer with my own Experience. Humbly begging the assistance
of Almighty God to aid you in this Great Work, and am
Your Affectionate Friend Jane Sharp.
Sharp, The Midwives Book, Forward
All that is known about Jane Sharp is what she tells her readers: that
she’s had thirty years of experience as a midwife. But we can
conclude, obviously, that she could read and write (in a free and
sure-handed style), and less obviously, that she indeed possessed
and made competent use of the library she brags about: she refers
to and quotes with great accuracy all the important (male)
authorities, both ancient and contemporary (many of these probably
came via the translations and compendia of Nicholas Culpeper from
the 1650s and 1660s). For Sharp, “[t]he Art of Midwifry is doubtless
one of the most useful and necessary of all Arts, for the being and
well-being of Mankind,” and
Ancient medicine:
Medieval medicine:
Other medicines:
Figure 9.1 The steelyard and the principle of the lever. The image
on the left is a woodcut from Gaultherus Rivius' Architecture …
Mathematischen … Kunst (Nuremberg, 1547). This sixteenth-
century diagram stresses that the practical tool can be
mathematically analyzed. The image on the right, however, is a
Roman steelyard, preceding it by more than a millennium. It
demonstrates that the principle of the lever was understood well
enough to be embodied in a material, artificial device well before it
was formulated and formalized.
The first law of nature: that each thing, as far as it in its power,
always remains in the same state, and that consequently, when
it once moved, it always continues to move …
The second law of nature: that all movement is, of itself, along
straight lines; and consequently, bodies which are moving in a
circle, always tend to move away from the center of the circle
which they are describing.
Descartes, Principles of Philosophy, pp. 37–40
These laws were Descartes’ version of Galileo’s conclusion that a
body moving along the horizon will continue until stopped by force,
but as Laws of Nature they were no longer insights about motion on
the surface of the Earth. They were universal truths concerning all
motions of all bodies in the world: motion in a straight line and
uniform velocity was not a form of change but a state. It didn’t need a
cause to continue, only to change: to start, stop, or alter direction or
velocity.
The New Mechanized Sciences
This was a final divorce from the Aristotelian way of understanding
nature which directed scholars throughout Europe, North Africa and
much of Asia for two millennia. Historians argue over whether the
change should be termed ‘revolution,’ and that of course depends on
how one uses the term. There is no doubt, on the one hand, that
Galileo, Kepler, Descartes and others who engaged in the New
Science perceived themselves as bringing about a dramatic and
radical change, doing away with old ways of knowledge and creating
new ones – almost at any cost (mostly intellectual, but sometimes
personal). But neither is there any doubt that the change wasn’t
instantaneous and wasn’t ex nihilo, as the cathedral metaphor
illustrates: novelties are constructed over time, using available
resources. Galileo’s work was an essential resource for Descartes,
and Galileo himself drew heavily on Archimedes, Buridan and
sixteenth-century mechanics. Kepler’s work was as essential: his
optics (Chapter 7) provided Descartes with a model of purely
mathematical-physical science; the unpublished Le Monde (The
World) was to be subtitled A treatise on Light.
Light, according to Kepler’s new optics, was a physical agent
that could be fully analyzed in mathematical terms, and Descartes
demonstrated this in his analysis of the rainbow, a phenomenon
which baffled traditional natural philosophers. Aristotle taught that
transparency was a property of some media, like water and air, while
opaqueness was a property of solid objects, and color was a form of
opaqueness. So how could colors float in mid-air? Descartes’
answer was both mathematical and empirical. The light ray, he
explained, is refracted and reflected multiple times within the
raindrop, as diagramed in Figure 9.8, and the colors are determined
by the angles of these changes in direction – red, he discovered by
experimenting with a water ball, is the result of a 42° angle of
refraction. It is likely that thinking of light as pure motion, always
rectilinear, is what allowed Descartes to turn Galileo’s ideas about
‘neutral motion’ around the Earth into the law that straight motion of
uniform velocity needs no cause (to continue). Descartes would go
on to try to develop, along the same principles, theories of planetary
motions, of meteors and comets, of magnetism, physiology and
human sensations. Although none was as successful as his version
of Keplerian optics, these attempts became the paradigms of the
new mechanical philosophy of nature.
Figure 9.8 Descartes’ analysis of the rainbow from his Meteors of
1637. The ray coming from A passes through the raindrop, which
Descartes mimicked with a water ball. It is refracted at B, reflected
at C and refracted again at D, and the angle in which it falls on the
eye E determines its color.
Founding the New Science
The Collapse of the Old Order
Europe in the first half of the seventeenth century – the decades that
saw the emergence of the New Science in the work of Kepler,
Galileo and Descartes – was a troubled place. The tensions building
up for a century – since the Reformation – finally burst in 1618 in a
war that would last until 1648, earning the moniker ‘The Thirty Years’
War.’ It began as a squabble between Catholic and Protestant
countries, but as Descartes’ mercenary adventures demonstrate (he
was a Catholic; Prince Maurice, his employer and commander – a
Protestant), it soon deteriorated into a cruel all-against-all war, driven
by greed and opportunism. To the direct wreckage it caused – in
some parts of Germany more than 50 percent of the population was
lost – a new sort of devastation was added. The plethora of princes
and fiefs rushing to enjoy the spoils were making use of new banking
techniques (Chapter 5), taking monetary obligations way beyond
their means. Promissory notes with princes’ signatures and coins
with kings’ images flooded Europe, losing their value
correspondingly. Inflation was a new and strange phenomenon: how
could money, the allegedly transparent means of exchange, have a
price? What did it represent? And what did the prince’s image on the
coin stand for, if it didn’t guarantee its value?
The crisis extended to all forms of stability and lawfulness:
religious, political and economic; and its most rattling expression
came, of all places, from England. Physically detached from the
continent and institutionally detached from the Church already a
century earlier by Henry VIII, it should have been less affected. In
fact, the war sent its worst shock through the old relations in England
between the divine and political order, which also made sense of the
natural order philosophers were searching for (Chapter 1). King
Charles, keen to join the seemingly profitable great war, kept raising
taxes to finance his (unsuccessful) military ventures until Parliament
rebelled. The members of the House of Commons – lesser nobility
and representatives of major towns – felt that tradition and common
law gave them the authority over taxation, and were willing to fight
for it. Charles’ suspect religious affiliations – he was of Scottish
descent and married to a Catholic – and his (failed) attempts to
arrest the House leaders exacerbated the rift. In 1642, a proper war
erupted between Parliament’s army and the king’s army, which
ended on January 20, 1649 with the king being put on trial:
God knows everything, and humans – only very few things. But
whatever we do know – notably mathematics – we know as well as
God. To Church authorities and more conservative-minded scholars
claims like this were much more alarming than any argument for the
motion of the Earth. Medieval philosophers made the distinction
between human and divine knowledge a fundamental part of both
their theology and epistemology. God didn’t only know everything,
He also knew it differently from humans. Our knowledge was
discursive – it had to be put in into words and sentences, and thus
necessitated generalization and categorization, which meant
disregarding much of the true essences of particular things. God’s
knowledge, on the other hand, was intuitive – He knew each and
every part of His world ‘from within,’ wholly and individually. God
knew the world as its maker – to suggest that we could know it in the
same way was to suggest that humans could somehow emulate
Creation – an inexcusable show of hubris. Yet as we saw in Chapter
6, even the practical Bacon’s ambitions were not far removed from
this near-heresy, and the priest-scientists of “Salomon’s House” in
his New Atlantis brag that they have, indeed, unlocked the mysteries
that would allow them to mimic creation: “we make demonstrations
of all lights and radiations; and of all colours … we practice and
demonstrate all sounds and their generation … We imitate smells,
making all smells to breathe out of other mixtures than those that
give them …” (Bacon, New Atlantis, pp. 33–35).
The Academies
It is not surprising that Bacon was promoting his idea of the New
Science by envisioning a new kind of institution, like Salomon’s
House. Knowledge needs a place, and the New Science needed a
new place. The universities were too entrenched in the traditional
conglomerate of beliefs and practices that directed education and
scholarship for centuries while giving them a measure of freedom
(Chapters 4 and 5). Court sponsorship, as both Tycho and Galileo
learned, was too capricious to trust.
New institutions of knowledge indeed started sprouting,
informally, already in sixteenth-century Italy. The model may have
been the Accademia Aldina, which the publisher and humanist Aldo
Manuzio (1452–1515) had established in Venice, in 1492. It was
supposed to be a “new academy” – a new incarnation of Plato’s
Academia – whose purpose was to help him solve the philological
challenges of printing classical texts, and it comprised, as its
successors would, gentlemen of independent means and intellectual
interests who met regularly to discuss new ideas. Later academies
would have more practical, and increasingly experimental, agendas.
The Florentine Camerata, an academy concentrating on music and
music theory, sponsored Vincenzo Galilei, and we’ve mentioned the
Accademia dei Lincei, which supported Galileo. To these one can
add the Accademia del Cimento (‘of experiment’), founded by
Galileo’s students in Florence in 1657.
These academies usually didn’t survive the death of their
founder, so it was an important milestone when, in 1635, Cardinal
Richelieu, the most powerful man in French politics, convinced Louis
XIII to grant ‘letters patent’ to a Parisian group interested in French
philology. This created the Académie Française – the first state-
sponsored academy with an official status – and allowed its almost-
continuous existence to our time. It also provided the great French
politician of the next generation – Jean-Baptiste Colbert – with a
model he could offer The Sun King, Louis XIV: a state-sponsored
scientific academy, whose members and statutes were determined
by the state and its representatives. This institution was established
officially in 1666 as the Académie des Sciences, and together with
the Académie Française it became the core of the Institut de France.
Perhaps more than any other institution, the Académie des Sciences
represents the unofficial pact that the New Science struck with the
political elites – quite a different one from that represented by the
universitas. The state would provide funds and institutional support,
while the new scientific institutions would take into consideration the
state’s priorities – commerce, industry, transportation, arms – and
work to enhance them.
Boyle and the Royal Society
It is also not surprising that the Baconian rhetoric appealed to
practical men like Richelieu and Colbert: less “verbosities” and more
“demonstrations,” “perfumes” and “engines” (see full quote in
Chapter 6). The activists of the New Science were no less keen
about their side of this pact: the flagship of all early modern
academies put much of its early energy into acquiring the mandate
to call itself The Royal Society of London for Improving Natural
Knowledge.
The Royal Society evolved from two informal groups. One called
itself “The Invisible College,” and had been meeting from about 1645
around London, especially in Gresham College. The college was a
public education institute of the city, named after its 1597 founder,
Thomas Gresham, who endowed a number of resident professors to
give regular open lectures. The other group was “The Experimental
Philosophical Club,” which used to meet in Wadham college, Oxford,
where its leader, John Wilkins (1614–1672), was the warden. The
two were brought together by a person for whom the realization of
Bacon’s vision was a life-long undertaking, with deep personal and
even religious significance: Robert Boyle (1627–1691).
Robert was the youngest son of Richard Boyle, an ‘adventurer’
who had made an enormous fortune – becoming perhaps the richest
person in England – in the colonization of Ireland as its Lord High
Treasurer. Boyle Junior was educated as was appropriate of his
father’s acquired status as First Earl of Cork; by private tutors at
home, then at Eton, then in a long Grand Journey through the
continent. Returning to England in 1644, he settled at the Dorset
estate left to him by his father and began to compose religious-
moralistic treatises, but his interests started to shift towards the new
experimental sciences. In 1649 he successfully set up a laboratory at
the estate and in 1656 he moved to Oxford to join Wilkins’ group,
spending there twelve years of intensive experimenting and writing.
In 1668, he moved to London and to his sister’s, Lady Ranelagh,
building himself a laboratory there and rarely leaving the city
thereafter.
Boyle, then, was well acquainted with both the London and
Oxford groups and had the financial and social resources to
formalize them. He felt comfortable doing so when England’s failed
attempt to become a republic ended and the king – Charles II, son of
the beheaded Charles I – was reinstated. Relative calm settled
among the English ruling classes and intellectual elites – only
Cooke, Charles’ prosecutor, was made to bear the brunt of the
monarchy’s fury – and in November 1660, in a meeting following a
talk at Gresham College, the College for the Promoting of Physico-
Mathematical Experimental Learning was established, receiving the
Royal charter two years later.
The early membership of the Society tells much about the kind
of institute it was and the kind of science it would promote and
bequeath. The first president was William Brouncker (1620–1684) –
a viscount, commissioner of the Royal Navy and mathematician;
Seth Ward (1617–1689) was a bishop, mathematician and
astronomer; Sir William Petty (1623–1687) was an economist,
geographer and physician-general to Oliver Cromwell (the leader of
the Parliament army and England’s ‘Lord Protector’ during its
republican decade). We’ve mentioned John Wilkins, the warden and
natural philosopher; in his Oxford group were also John Wallis
(1616–1703), a chaplain and a mathematician-cryptographer, and
Thomas Willis (1621–1675), a court physician and anatomist. John
Evelyn (1620–1706) was the most urbane of the group: diarist and
historian, he came from a wealthy gunpowder-producing family. The
secretary of the Society was Henry Oldenburg (1619–1677), a
German immigrant and theologian by education. Oldenburg
developed his ideas about the structure and mode of operation
proper for such a society when he visited many of the European
academies during his travels through Europe as a diplomat (and a
spy). He was one of the two paid members of the Society (at least in
theory – the Society was slack in collecting membership fees and in
meeting its financial obligations). The other was Robert Hooke
(1635–1703), its ‘curator of experiments.’ Hooke was the one
professional among the fellows: he designed and built instruments;
planned and performed experiments; suggested theories and
reviewed new books. When he was (rarely) unavailable, the weekly
meeting would usually be called off. We will return to him at length in
Chapter 10.
The official ideology of the Society – the way it understood and
presented itself – is well displayed in its emblem (Figure 9.9):
Charles II is wreathed by an angel, flanked by Brouncker on the
viewer’s left and Bacon on the right; books are set to the side;
instruments of observation and experiment are ready at hand; and a
clear, sunny vista opens at the back. Their motto on the coat of arms
above Charles’ bust is even clearer: Nullius in Verba – “in no-one’s
word.” The emblem served as the frontispiece for The History of the
Royal Society of London, commissioned in 1662 as part of the effort
to secure the royal charter, and the author, Thomas Sprat (1635–
1713), expressed this ideology in powerful words:
Figure 9.9 The Royal Society’s emblem, engraved by Wenceslaus
Hollar as the frontispiece to the first edition of Thomas Sprat’s
(1635–1713) History of the Royal Society of London (1667).
Charles II’s bust at the center, Brouncker on its left and Bacon on
its right. Note the barometers on the right, the clock on the left,
Hooke and Boyle’s air pump above Charles’ right shoulder, and a
large hanging telescope behind it. © The Royal Society.
TO THE KING.
SIR, OF all the Kings of Europe, Your Majesty was the first,
who confirm’d this Noble Design of Experiments, by Your own
Example, and by a Public Establishment. An Enterprize equal to
the most renoun’d Actions of the best Princes. For, to increase
the Powers of all Mankind, and to free them from the bondage of
Errors, is greater Glory than to enlarge Empire, or to put Chains
on the necks of Conquer’d Nations …
Thus they [the fellows of the Society] have directed, judg’d,
conjectur’d upon, and improved Experiments. But lastly … there
is one thing more, about which the Society has been most
sollicitous; and that is, the manner of their Discourse: which,
unless they had been very watchful to keep in due temper, the
whole spirit and vigour of their Design, had been soon eaten
out, by the luxury and redundance of speech. The ill effects of
this superfluity of talking, have already overwhelm’d most other
Arts and Professions …
They have therefore been most rigorous in putting in
execution, the only Remedy, that can be found for this
extravagance: and that has been, a constant Resolution, to
reject all the amplifications, digressions, and swellings of style:
to return back to the primitive purity, and shortness, when men
deliver’d so many things, almost in an equal number of words.
They have exacted from all their members, a close, naked,
natural way of speaking; positive expressions; clear senses; a
native easiness: bringing all things as near the Mathematical
plainness, as they can: and preferring the language of Artizans,
Countrymen, and Merchants, before that, of Wits, or Scholars …
The Society has reduc’d its principal observations, into one
common-stock; and laid them up in publique Registers, to be
nakedly transmitted to the next Generation of Men … as their
purpose was, to heap up a mixt Mass of Experiments, without
digesting them into any perfect model: so to this end, they
confin’d themselves to no order of subjects; and whatever they
have recorded, they have done it, not as compleat Schemes of
opinions, but as bare unfinish’d Histories.
Thomas Sprat, The History of the Royal Society of London
(London: J. Martin, 1662), Dedicatory Epistle
First, then, upon the drawing down of the Sucker (the Valve
being shut) the Cylindrical space, deserted by the Sucker, is left
devoid of Air; and therefore, upon the turning of the Key, the Air
contained in the Receiver rusheth into the emptied Cylinder, till
the Air in both those Vessels be brought to about an equal
measure of dilatation. And therefore, upon shutting the Receiver
by re-turning the Key, if you open the Valve, and force up the
Sucker again, you will find, that after this first exsuction you will
drive out almost a whole Cylinder full of Air …
Robert Boyle, New Experiments Physico-Mechanical
Touching the Spring of Air (Oxford: Robinson, 1662), pp. 11–
12
But was there anything – air or “subtle matter” – in the receiver after
pumping or wasn’t there? As far as Boyle was concerned, it was
enough that
In the long run, it was Boyle who won. The experimental tradition
created by the “Virtuosi … of the Royal Society” learned to display
the same indifference towards metaphysical worries. In their stead,
experimenters were happy to admit what came to be called
‘operational definitions’ like the one Boyle offered here for vacuum:
as long as “the very little that remained” didn’t affect the experiment,
the receiver could be considered empty. But the debate clarifies that
theory could always contest experiment. Pace Bacon, Boyle and
Sprat, nothing could be seen “nakedly.”
Conclusion: The Independent Life of the
Instrument
Even though openness and language-free observation turned out to
be unattainable, progress was not an empty ideal. Yet the “increase
[of] the Powers of all Mankind” didn’t all come in the way Boyle and
the ‘gentlemen virtuosi’ expected. It had less to do with their
virtuosity and more to do with that of their rarely mentioned
instrument builders.
Hooke didn’t invent the pneumatic engine ex nihilo (nor did
Galileo the telescope, as we saw in Chapter 7). Glass balls had
already been used in optical experiments for centuries, and pistons,
cranks and valves were in common use by artisans of different
trades (like mining and waterworks). His basic design followed a
machine invented in 1650 by the Prussian civil servant and natural
philosopher Otto von Guericke (1602–1686), who traveled with it
around Germany, demonstrating how marvelously difficult it was to
separate two attached hemispheres once the air was exhausted
from between them (one could not conduct experiments inside von
Guericke’s sphere; the option of reaching into the receiver was
Hooke’s addition). Moreover, Hooke’s design was far from the last
one. In 1727, another Englishman and a member of both the Royal
Society and the Académie des Sciences – Stephen Hales –
presented a way to collect gases in Hooke-like glass spheres by
heating substances and letting the released fumes bubble through a
trap – ‘trough’ – of water. By the 1760s, a number of experimentalists
replaced the water in the trough with mercury, through which gases
soluble in water could also pass, and most eighteenth-century
chemical research revolved around experimenting on and theorizing
about the ‘airs’ collected in the glass vessels, whose shape was also
evolving. And already in 1679, a junior colleague of Hooke and an
employee of Boyle – the Frenchman Denis Papin (1647–1713) –
used the principles developed by the budding tradition of vacuum
machines to invent an apparatus whose future effects would be even
more dramatic than the trough’s. It was, originally, a ‘steam digester’
– a pressure cooker for bones – but observing the pressure valve
(which distinguished his invention from earlier versions, prone to
explosions) bobbing by the power of the steam, he realized that this
power could be harnessed. In 1712, Thomas Newcomen (1664–
1729), a blacksmith and Baptist lay preacher, received a patent for a
working application of this idea, inventing the “engine” – literally and
metaphorically – of the Industrial Revolution: the steam engine.
In the grand story about erecting the cathedral of science, these
mostly (though not always) anonymous instrument-makers were not
only the bricklayers, required for their labor and fundamental skills,
but also – to press the metaphor a little further – the master masons.
They not only carried traditional craft knowledge from generation to
generation, but also honed, refined and developed it for new uses.
They were obliged to do so: their livelihood depended on selling the
artifacts they produced, so those needed to be useful and affordable,
evolving to suit changing needs. So when Hooke felt obliged to pay
homage to his Royal Society employers, he retreated to the
traditional hierarchy between episteme and techne, writing:
The “the makers and the grinders of … Glasses” didn’t only “furnish
… materials”; the mechanical world was very much a world
constructed by the mechanic. The innovations of the virtuosi
challenged the instrument-makers to come up with new ways to
gauge and query nature. At the same time, “the makers,” with their
own initiative and innovations, created a whole “new visible World”
for “the great Philosophers of [the] Age” to study.
Discussion Questions
1. Is the discrepancy between the Royal Society’s ideology of
openness and its exclusionary practices important? Does it have an
ethical significance? An epistemological significance? Does it reflect
on science or our times?
4. The inside of the glass vessel of the air pump is the only vacuum
on Earth. Does this represent a new stage of experimentation? Does
is say something about contemporary empirical science?
On Galileo’s science:
Landes, David S., Revolution in Time: Clocks and the Making of the
Modern World (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 1983).
From late 1660 until his death, then, Hooke was a very
‘modern,’ urban character: moving fast around London, working
professionally as a practical mathematician, experimental expert,
teacher, architect and inventor, keeping a diary and meeting his
colleagues to discuss scientific matters over cocoa in the new coffee
houses around town. He supported this feverish lifestyle with an
unrestrained regimen of self-medication, passing away in 1703
unhealthy but wealthy (he left some £10,000 in a chest in his rooms).
Isaac Newton
While Hooke was establishing his credentials as an experimenter
and instrument builder in Oxford, Isaac Newton (1642–1726) was
gaining a name as a mathematical wiz in Cambridge. Like Hooke, he
was an orphan of a provincial clergyman, from a little town in
Lincolnshire on the east coast of England, and like him he had to
work as a servant-student until his talents shone through. Unlike
Hooke of the taverns and cafés, Newton was a recluse, yet he
seemed to have had an intellectual charisma that Hooke lacked. He
became such a prodigy student of the great mathematician Isaac
Barrow (1630 – 1677) that in 1669 Barrow resigned in his favor from
Cambridge’s newly established, prestigious Lucasian Professorship
of Mathematics. Newton’s notebooks from his student years
demonstrate why: they are full of extremely innovative ideas for
creating the type of mathematics that could meet Kepler and
Galileo’s challenge; mathematics that could capture real physical
bodies and causes – real motions, real forces (Chapters 7 and 9,
and see Figure 10.2 for an example).
Figure 10.2 An example of Newton’s early application of his new
mathematical tools to solve a physical problem (from a manuscript
written between 1666 and 1669). It is crucial to remember that
Newton never had a proof for the mathematical rigor of the bold
approximations he is making – he develops this infinitesimal
approach as he goes along.
A body moves uniformly in circle ADE around C counterclockwise.
In uniform motion, times are proportional to distances, so tAD∝AD.
Following Descartes, if the body is released at A to move freely, it
will continue uniformly along the tangent AB, and for an
infinitesimally small time, Newton assumes AB=AD. The ‘little line’
BD therefore represents the centrifugal force at point D – it’s the
distance this force would take the body, if allowed. Newton permits
himself to assume that for infinitesimally short time tAD, CDB is a
straight line, and this enables him to use the Euclidean theorem
AB2= BD•BE. He then adds the assumption that the centrifugal
force works like gravity, so according to Galileo, BD is proportional
to the square of the time: BD∝tAD2 or BD∝AD2. A series of simple
transformations leads Newton to the conclusion that the centrifugal
force of the orbiting body is proportional to the radius divided by
the square of the period: f ∝ R/T2. Merging this with Kepler’s Third
Law, according to which for the planets T2∝R3 (the square of the
period is proportional to the cube of the distance from the Sun)
Newton concludes that the centrifugal force on the planets is
inversely proportional to their distance from the Sun: f ∝ 1/R2.
Birch, The History of the Royal Society, Vol. II, p. 91: May 23,
1666
The planets, Hooke was assuming without much ado, are “regular
solid bodies,” and as such should follow the same laws that apply to
all bodies. This is one of the most fundamental insights of the New
Science: there is no cosmos divided into Heaven and Earth, only one
world full of “bodies.” As bodies, they should follow the laws of
mechanics, which means, first and foremost, that they are supposed
to “move in a straight line,” unless there is “some other cause … that
must bend their motion into that curve.” What can this cause be?
How does it operate? How does it create the planetary orbits the way
the astronomers describe them?
Setting the Question Right
This is where Hooke’s originality lies. Not in providing a solution – he
did not really have one, although he did have some important clues
he provided Newton with – but in setting the question. The question
did follow from the teachings of Galileo, Kepler and Descartes, and
in hindsight, it may seem as if one of them should have already
asked it. Hooke did not possess any new knowledge, but the fact is
that he asked, and they did not. There is a big difference, so we
learn, between having all the ingredients for a crucial new idea and
actually formulating it. If ‘Hooke’s Programme’ appears in hindsight
as a straightforward, even trivial, development of those early ideas, it
is because he succeeded (with a lot of effort and after much
frustration) to convince his peers to adopt it. The only celestial
mechanics we know are developed as an answer to his query, and
we cannot but read Hooke’s immediate predecessors through this
lens.
It’s therefore telling, historically and philosophically, to consider
the three on whose work Hooke drew – Kepler, Galileo and
Descartes – and see where he left that work behind.
Kepler had tried to apply physics to the heavens, but his physics
had not been mechanics. He neither thought that straight-line motion
should be the basis of the explanation of all motions, nor that the
planets were “regular solid bodies.” For him, it was still the case that
“circular motions (and hence revolutions) belong to the everlasting
bodies … ; [and] rectilinear motions certainly [belong] to evanescent
bodies” (Kepler, De Cometis, translated and cited by J. A. Ruffner,
“The Curved and the Straight: Cometary Theory from Kepler to
Hevelius” (1971) 2 Journal for the History of Astronomy 181). So
Kepler didn’t ask ‘why do the planets move in a curve?’ but ‘why do
the planets move?’ To Kepler, matter was inert – it resisted all motion
– so for him the business of celestial physics was to explain how the
planets move in the first place. His tentative answer, you’ll
remember, was that the Sun is the cause of their motion. It rotates
and drags the planets along by some “motive force,” which may or
may not be magnetism; perhaps it was light. So unlike Hooke and
his ‘compounding’ hypothesis, for Kepler the rotation of the planets
was explained by the rotation of the Sun; one closed-curve motion
could only be created by another closed-curve motion.
Galileo had been closer to thinking about the heavens and the
Earth as following the same physical laws. His arguments for
Copernicanism had been based on analyzing motions on Earth – of
ships and tides – and in the Dialogues Concerning Two New
Sciences he gestured towards “the beautiful agreement between this
thought [about mechanics] and the views of Plato concerning the
origins of the various speeds with which the heavenly bodies
revolve” (Galileo Galilei, Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences,
Henry Crew and Alfonso de Silvio (trans.) (New York: Dover
Publications, 1954), p. 261). But this was as far as he went in the
direction that Hooke would take. First, although his analysis of
projectile motion presented one motion curving another motion, he
did not assume that rectilinear motion had some unique
metaphysical status. His ‘neutral’ continuous motion, you may recall
from Chapter 9, was actually circular – along the surface of the
Earth. Moreover, despite the alleged “beautiful agreement,” he never
attempted to actually apply his considerations of terrestrial
mechanics to celestial motions.
Most surprising, and telling, is that Descartes never asked
Hooke’s question. After all, “every moving body tends to continue its
motion in a straight line” was one of his “Laws of Nature.” But, even
for Descartes, the idea that the motion of the planets was not truly
theirs was too far removed from common sense. Even he assumed
that they revolve because it is their nature – because such motion,
as Kepler said, “belongs to the everlasting bodies” – and didn’t see
that his own laws of nature implied otherwise. When he came to
speculate about the motion of the heavenly bodies, Descartes
seemingly forgot that bodies were supposed to move in straight
lines, unless their motion is curved, and wrote instead that “the
matter of heaven, in which the planets are situated, unceasingly
revolves” (René Descartes, Principles of Philosophy (Principia
Philosophiæ, 1664), Valentine R. Miller and Reese P. Miller (trans.)
(Dordrecht: Reidel, 1983), Part III, Article 30, p. 96 – emphasis
added). Look back at Figure 9.7: it shows a body in circular motion –
a stone in a sling – created by another circular motion – the whirling
hand. It claims that such a body has a tendency to continue in a
straight line, which for Descartes meant that if released from the
sling, the stone would continue along a straight line, tangential to its
circular trajectory at the point of release. The diagram is crucially
different from Hooke’s idea: it doesn’t treat the circular motion as
created by this straight-line motion. Descartes never asked the
question that Hooke would ask: how do two straight-line motions
‘compound’ into a curved, orbital trajectory?
We, in the post-Newtonian era, are taught as a matter of course
that the planetary orbit is an outcome of inertial motion along the
tangent and an attraction that constantly curves it towards the Sun.
And in hindsight, it may seem that it was a trivial elaboration of the
ideas that Galileo, Kepler and Descartes had already formulated.
But, so it turns out, no one before Hooke had drawn this picture in
their mind: that the planets – and we on Earth with them – constantly
tumble along, falling towards the Sun but never reaching it. Until it
did occur to Hooke, and then it seemed obvious to him, and the
obvious question followed: “I have often wondered why …”
Let’s return to the correspondence. We can now see why
Newton had missed Hooke’s point in the initial letter, and why
Hooke’s reply to his suggested experiment piqued Newton’s
attention. Not only did Newton positively dislike being caught in error,
he now recognized the importance of Hooke’s hypothesis and again
replied within four days (December 13, 1679). Newton understood
immediately where he got confused – and denied he ever did – and
cunningly tried to work out how much of the solution to his own
question Hooke already had. Why did Hooke think that he could get
a closed-curve orbit (presumably an ellipse, but any neatly closed
orbit) from two rectilinear motions? Why not something like the
complex trajectory in Figure 10.7, where the planet keeps changing
its path? Newton presented the diagram as if it was the outcome of a
calculation, but there is no reason to take his word for it. What is
crucial is that Newton, having now grasped the significance of
Hooke’s proposal, immediately put his finger on the extreme
challenge it represented, which was both cosmological and
mathematical-physical: how can we think of the orbit as an effect?
The heavenly orbit had always been a symbol of perfect order and
harmony. Its circular shape was a direct consequence of this
perfection, and required no further explanation. This assumption was
so deeply entrenched in cosmology and astronomy that most
working astronomers still didn’t understand Kepler’s idea of physics
of the heaven (an idea which by the time of the correspondence was
seventy years old). For them, Kepler’s ellipse was still a combination
of two circular motions – a deferent and an epicycle – as in
traditional astronomy from Ptolemy through Copernicus.
Figure 10.7 Newton’s diagram from his letter to Hooke of
December 13, 1679. Newton accepts Hooke’s correction, but
questions his conclusion: why should the body moving by a
combination of free fall and tangential motion describe a neat
orbit? Why not this complex trajectory? Put the other way: why
should we assume that the neat orbits of the planets are produced
by such a combination? Does Hooke have an independent
argument to support his hypothesis?
The eulogies to Newton may read as quite over the top, but the
three books of the Principia are indeed composed as if deciphering
the very “Laws which God, framing the universe … made the fixed
foundations of His work,” and the approach sketched in De Motu is
magisterially laid out. Newton begins with a set of “Definitions” and
“Axioms, or Laws of Motions.” Then comes the First Book – “The
Motion of Bodies” – in which Newton lays out his new mathematical
tools and demonstrates how to apply them to his definitions and
axioms to solve and prove increasingly complex problems and
theorems concerning the motions of bodies orbiting according to
‘Hooke’s Programme.’ The Second Book deals with “The Motions of
Bodies in Resisting Mediums.” These are the motions we know
around us – within the atmosphere and in water, so if the First Book
prepares the way to deal with what in traditional cosmology used to
be the heavenly realm, the Second Book deals with the terrestrial
realm. But there are no longer distinct realms: the definitions and
axioms laid out at the beginning are true of all bodies and all
motions. This deep insight of the New Science is celebrated in the
Third Book: “The System of the World,” in which Newton shows how
the “phenomena” – namely Kepler’s laws, as expressed by the
moons of Jupiter and Saturn – follow the “mathematical principles”
developed in the First Book.
Calling his book The Mathematical Principles of the Philosophy
of Nature, Newton points to the work he is attempting to emulate and
surpass: Descartes’ Mathematical Principles. And in one
fundamental way, Newton follows Descartes’ lead better than
Descartes himself. Descartes demanded that only mathematizable
elements be allowed into natural philosophy, but with him this
demand remained mostly a philosophical aspiration. Newton put it
into practice. His very elements are quantities. Instead of ‘matter’
and ‘motion’ he defines “Quantity of Matter” (“density and bulk
conjoint”) and “Quantity of Motion” (“velocity and quantity of matter
conjoint”). But by the third Definition Newton veers sharply from
Descartes, breaks the latter’s decree that there is nothing in the
world but matter and motion, and introduces the third element at
work in Hooke’s Programme and in his own De Motu: force. Newton
had been studying the mathematics of force since his student years,
and the correspondence with Hooke had apparently convinced him
that Descartes’ philosophical requirements were too restrictive: a
physica coelestis, as imagined by Kepler, can’t be achieved without
giving force an independent ontological status, as Hooke did in his
Programme. So Newton defines “innate force of matter,” which is the
force by which bodies resist change of motion (or rest); “impressed
force” – the force which causes such change; and “centripetal force”
– like the attraction he had discussed with Hooke, which during the
correspondence they began to simply call ‘gravity.’ He then returns
to quantities, and defines “the quantity of force” from three different
perspectives: absolutely, measured by acceleration, and by
acceleration over time.
Before turning to apply these quantities to the analysis of nature,
Newton does feel the need to provide them with a metaphysical
framework. In Descartes’ spartan matter-and-motion universe, all
motion was strictly a relative change of place: whether I walk through
the door or the doorway slides around me (or whether the doorway
and I were moving simultaneously in opposite directions) is merely a
matter of perspective. But adding real forces to the fundamental
elements of the world, Newton had to establish a real distinction: it is
I who moved, not the doorway, because it is I who starts and stops
and turns – it is I who accelerates and decelerates. So it is in me, not
in the doorway, that the force resides.
But how can this distinction be made? What is the difference
between a body which accelerates because it experiences real force
and the body whose change of place is only apparent, an artifact of
the motion of bodies surrounding it? The difference between real and
relative motion requires a frame of reference independent of the
moving things, a frame of reference against which I was moving and
the doorway – not. Newton provides that frame by postulating an
“Absolute Time” and “Absolute Space”: a vessel in which the objects
of the world are and a duration in which the objects move, time and
space existing prior to and independently of the objects. This is not
an easy idea – Newton was later sternly criticized for it – and he
illustrates it with a little thought experiment. Imagine a bucket of
water hanging on a wound-up string. When the string is allowed to
unwind, the bucket spins around the water, which first remains still.
When the water gradually starts spinning with the bucket, it rises
against the bucket’s side. But when the bucket spins and the water
rests, the water’s relative motion – its motion relative to its immediate
environment, the bucket – is high. When the bucket and water spin
together, the water’s relative motion is low. Why does the water
change – why does its surface curve – when it spins with the
bucket? It has to be because it moves absolutely, argues Newton –
not relative to the bucket, but with respect to absolute space!
With the elements of his mathematical natural philosophy
defined – quantity of matter and motion; force; absolute time and
space – Newton continues the difficult but extremely fruitful synthesis
of Descartes’ and Hooke’s insights with his own “Axioms, or Laws of
Motion.” The first law is a neat combination of Descartes’ two Laws
of Nature: “Every body continues in its state of rest or of uniform
motion in a straight line, unless compelled to change that state by
force impressed on it.” The second law is a strictly mathematical
version of the idea of force entailed in Hooke’s Programme: “Change
of motion is proportional to the motive force impressed and is made
in the direction of the straight line in which this force is impressed.”
The third law adds symmetry to the developing structure: “to every
action there is always opposed an equal reaction.” A series of
“Corollaries” then teaches the reader how to conceive these laws of
motion and force. The first, simplest corollary is a good example: “a
body, acted by two forces simultaneously, will describe a diagonal of
a parallelogram in the same time as it would describe the sides of
those forces separately.” This is the ‘parallelogram of forces’ rule
from De Motu, and the attentive reader might recognize a strategy in
its Principia formulation. The parallelogram of forces entails Galileo’s
insight that different motions can be combined in a body without
eliminating one another. It is the idea that played such a crucial role
in his correspondence with Hooke, articulated as both a physical law
of nature and a workable mathematical tool. It can then be used for
constructing (and proving) much more complicated and less obvious
claims about nature.
This is indeed a powerful strategy. Newton’s use of it to
generate increasingly surprising propositions and endow them with
seemingly mathematical certainty may explain the enchantment
expressed by Halley, Pope and Voltaire – an enchantment shared by
many of their contemporaries. The treatment of Kepler’s Area Law –
taken quite directly from De Motu – provides another early and
simple, yet powerful, example. Newton begins “Book One” with
laying down his innovative “method of first and last ratios,” which
enables him to deal mathematically with singular points along a
trajectory of motion. He then takes the Area Law, which for Kepler
had been nothing more than an empirical generalization, and with a
combination of simple Euclidean geometry, physical assumptions
and mathematical approximations of questionable rigor, proves that
this law applies to any body orbiting a center of force (Figure 10.9).
With the Area Law now a theorem, Newton can express time
geometrically. A few propositions later he uses this capacity to
construct a simple geometrical expression, deducing from the
dimensions and period of an orbit the law by which the attraction
between the central body and the one orbiting it diminishes with
distance. A few propositions later, this geometrical formula for the
calculation of force laws is used to reveal the law governing the orbit
for which the exercise is carried out: an ellipse with the attracting
body in one of its two foci; the orbit Kepler assigned to the planets
around the Sun. The force that bends planetary motions into
Keplerian orbits, it turns out, declines by the square of the distance
between the two bodies. The attraction between the Sun and the
planets obeys the inverse square law – the law that Kepler
established for light; that Hooke applied to gravity on Earth and later
applied to his Programme; and that Newton himself, earlier in life,
had calculated for (the centrifugal force of) the planets. As we
already saw in De Motu, with the inverse square law, Newton ties
Kepler’s laws into a coherent mathematical-physical whole, and in
the Third Book it acquires another crucial significance to which we’ll
return below. But in the First Book Newton is careful to show that his
commitment to the inverse square law is strictly limited by empirical
considerations. He teaches his readers to calculate force laws for
orbits of a variety of curves and also adds a series of corollaries that
show how different force laws would have followed had Kepler’s
‘Harmonic Law’ (the proportion between the square of a planet’s
period and the cube of its distance) been different. Deep into the
book, in Propositions 53–55 and 66–68, he teaches the reader how
to handle complex orbits, which are interrupted by attraction from a
third body, as with the Earth orbiting the Sun together with the Moon:
by treating the orbit itself as if it’s rotating.
Originally, Newton had planned to add to the highly technical
Book One a second book, explaining this new way of conceiving
Heaven and Earth “in a popular method, that it might be read by
many” (as he writes in his introduction to the final Book Three). This
early “Treatise of the System of the World” was eventually published,
but only posthumously (Figure 10.10; the book is still readily
available: https://books.google.com.au/books?id=DXE9AAAAcAAJ).
In a decision that clearly marked the exclusive, elitist route that
modern science would take, Newton replaced the proposed “popular
method” with the deliberately technical and defiantly difficult “Motion
of Bodies in Resisting Mediums.” He had realized, he wrote to
Halley, that he didn’t want to be drawn into debates by people whose
philosophical agendas outweighed their mathematical skills. Science
was now for the professionals.
Book Two, as it came to print, was thus a late addition.
Historians often read it as a long argument against Descartes’
vortices theory: motion in resisting mediums is too complex to allow
explaining planetary orbit. Its Section III, for example, deals with “the
motion of bodies that are resisted partly in the ration of their velocity
and partly as the square of this ratio,” and its concluding scholium
summarizes the resistance of spherical bodies in fluids arising “partly
from the tenacity, partly from the attrition, and partly from the density
of the medium.” Section IV analyzes mathematically the point Hooke
had made to Newton in his December 9, 1679 letter (Figure 10.6):
resistance would turn an orbit into a spiral towards the center of
attraction.
Replacing the original “System of the World” with the final, more
technical version of Book Three did more than limit it to “readers with
good mathematical skills.” It turned the book from an explication of
the principles of the new celestial mechanics into an argument for
their power. Newton presents careful tables of the periods of the
planets as well as those of the moons of Jupiter and Mercury; the
best measures of planetary distances; outcomes of pendulum
comparisons at different heights and in different places around
globe; the results of his own experiments on falling bodies (many of
those available only or corrected for the second edition); and more.
All, Newton shows, fit well within the structure erected with the
mathematical-physical theorems of Book One:
5. Does the idea that the Earth, and the other planets, constantly
‘falls’ towards the Sun but never makes it still seem strange? If it is,
what does it say about science that it assigns such an important role
to such a strange idea? If not, what does it say about us as
‘consumers’ of science that we have gotten used to an idea that was
so strange?
Suggested Readings
Primary Texts
Newton, Isaac, “De Motu III-B” in J. W. Herivel (ed. and trans.), The
Background to Newton’s Principia (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1965),
p. 301.
Earth, the, x, xviii, 20, 58–63, 72–74, 87, 90, 93, 100, 106–107, 134,
196–198, 202, 219–244, 248–255, 311, 317, 322, 326–333,
356, 359–361, 364, 380
East India Companies, 167
eclipses, xii, 74, 78, 89–94, 170, 237
ecliptic, xi, xii, 73–83, 89, 92, 202, 221–222, 241
Egypt, xi, 23, 42–43, 46, 71, 83, 101–103, 129, 142, 146, 177–178,
189, 194, 206
Egyptian. See Egypt
empirical, xi, 7, 36–38, 53–56, 61–62, 72–74, 81, 86, 90–93, 100,
134–136, 144, 149, 182, 197, 200–208, 221, 224, 231–236,
248, 261, 273–275, 295, 302–303, 311–312, 318, 327,
330–331, 338, 347, 370
empiricism, 66, 303
empiricist. See Empiricism
enlightenment, 24
enthusiast. See enthusiasts
enthusiasts, 230, 250
ephemerides, 165, 202, 246
Epicurean, 103
Epicurus, 49, 103
epicycle. See epicycles
epicycles, xii, xiii, 95–98, 133, 220, 225–226, 228, 240
episteme, 35–37, 45, 83, 109, 119, 149, 265, 346
epistemology, 26, 35, 67–68, 145, 206, 329, 333, 339
equant, xii, xiii, 95–99, 133–134, 225, 241
equinoxes, xi, 73–82, 92–94, 117, 218, 222
Erasmus, 290
Eratosthenes, 92, 94, 101
escapement, xiii, 116
estrangement, vii, 36
Euclid, xiii, xiv, xvi, 101, 124–131, 166, 172, 190–191, 275, 314, 317
Euclidean. See Euclid
Eudoxus, vii, xii, 87–90, 96, 101
Europe, xii, xiv, 7–10, 18, 22–24, 62, 89, 96, 111–114, 119, 129, 134,
140–146, 154, 157, 161–164, 169–172, 175, 182, 186–189,
204, 215–216, 219, 223, 231, 253, 261, 274–279, 283, 290,
305–307, 324–330, 336–337, 356
European. See Europe
Evelyn, John, 336
evil, vii, 23, 32
ex cathedra, 121
ex hypothesi, 121, 246
experience, xi, 24, 36, 49–62, 71–72, 144–145, 157, 165, 169, 289–
290, 315, 341, 360
experiment, xi, xv, xviii, 39, 47, 152, 208–210, 213, 243, 264, 273,
312, 318–319, 330–332, 334–345, 350, 354–355, 358–362,
365
experimental, xvii, xviii, 263, 295, 319, 333–335, 338–344, 349–351,
355, 358 See Experiment
expertise, x, 6, 78–79, 164–165, 172, 216, 234, 238, 289, 296, 304,
308
eye, the, xi, xv, xvii, 4, 21, 56, 80–81, 94, 107, 118, 136, 195, 238–
239, 244, 248–249, 256, 273–274, 286–287, 292, 327, 352
Galen (Claudius Aelius Galenus), ix, 95, 101, 108, 127, 177, 181,
192, 211, 273–278, 282–290, 296–306
Galenic tradition, 127, 274–278, 281–282, 284, 288, 291–292, 294–
295, 304
Galileo (Galilei, Galileo), viii, ix, xiii, xv, xviii, 6, 153, 157, 203, 207,
244–256, 258–262, 295, 308–310, 312–315, 317–329, 331,
333–334, 341–343, 345, 348, 352–353, 356–360, 362–365,
367, 369, 380
Genesis, xiv, 71, 74, 90, 160, 183–184, 194, 250
Genoa, 146–147, 161
geometry, xi, xvi, 15, 40, 42–44, 72, 83–85, 92, 96–99, 125, 131–
133, 150–151, 190–191, 201, 207, 225–228, 242, 313,
324–325, 333–334, 370
geostatic model, 225
Gerard of Cremona, 129, 277
Gilbert, William, 243
global commerce. See globality
global institutions. See globality
global knowledge. See globality
globality, 7, 161–175, 283, 307
God, x, xi, xiv, 1, 4, 7, 20–28, 33, 60, 71, 74, 121, 127, 139–145,
164, 178, 182–186, 190, 193–194, 197, 207, 214–217,
229–230, 234, 252, 289, 292–293, 310, 317, 331, 333
gods, 23, 85, 104, 139, 178, 196
good, 23–24, 27, 185
goods, 127, 132, 149, 153, 161–166, 171–173, 283
Gothic Cathedral. See cathedral, the
gravitas, 311
gravitation, 254
gravity, xviii, 1, 17, 176, 223, 310, 315, 353, 366
Great Chain of Being, x, 21, 28–29, 114, 184
Greek, vii, viii, xi, xii, xvi, 10, 13, 18–19, 23–25, 27, 33, 37–39, 45–
49, 53–55, 60, 66–68, 72, 77, 83–87, 90–95, 101–113, 118,
129–132, 137–138, 148–149, 166, 170, 177–178, 183,
186–187, 193–195, 206, 219, 252, 273–274, 282–286, 300
Gregory of Tours, 112
Gresham College, 335–336, 339, 341, 351
Guangzhou, 162
Guidobaldo (del Monte, Guidobaldo), xvi, 317–319
guilds, 118–120, 152, 169, 261, 286, 288
Gutenberg, Johannes, xiii, 154–156, 215
Latin, x, xii, xiv, xvi, 15, 20, 26, 50, 95, 104–106, 111, 114, 120–124,
128–129, 136–137, 141–145, 166, 170, 187–193, 206, 211,
219, 250–252, 273–277, 280–286, 299, 302
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 170, 355
Leucippus, 49
Li Zhizao, 171
Libavius, Andreas (Andreas Libau), 294
light, xiv, xvii, xviii, 18, 21, 28–30, 34–37, 51–52, 74–75, 80, 82, 84–
85, 90, 94, 136, 154, 186–187, 191, 201–202, 207, 238–
240, 243–244, 249, 293, 327, 332, 352–354, 363, 366
Light of Reason, 145
light, divine, 24
Lipperhey, Hans, 244
literati, 171
London, ix, xv, xvii, 118, 138, 170, 261–262, 266, 296–297, 330,
335–337, 350–351, 355, 368, 370
Lorenzo de’ Medici (‘il Magnifico’), xiii, 147, 152–153, 162
Lucretius, 50–53, 67, 148
Luria, Isaac, 181, 185–186
Luther, Martin, 215–219, 229, 290
Macao, 170–171
Machiavelli, Niccolò, 147
Maestlin, Michael, 237
Magellan, Ferdinand, 162
magical tradition, the, xv, 177–179, 185, 195, 198, 208, 211–213,
235
Maimonides (Moshe ben Maimon), 142–145
Malacca, 165
Mallebarbe, Barbe, 179–180
Manuzio, Aldo, 334
mappa mundi, 171
Mara¯gha observatory, 134, 173
Marco Polo, 146
Mars, xi, xii, xv, 78, 80, 87, 195, 201–202, 226–227, 235, 238, 240–
241
Mary, 255
Masons, x, xiii, 6, 13–18, 26, 30, 33, 46, 108, 118, 152–153, 176,
179, 279, 286, 319, 346
mass, xiv, 3, 122, 199, 262
materia medica, 115, 276, 283–284
materia prima, 198
materia ultima, 198
mathematics, xi, xv, xvi, xxi, 3, 10, 36–38, 43, 56, 64, 67, 84, 96,
101, 113, 122, 125, 130, 149, 165–166, 169, 172, 217,
226–228, 236–238, 243–247, 308, 314, 317, 324–325,
332–333, 342, 348–349, 352, 367, 370
matter, x, xvi, 3, 14, 18, 21–24, 28–29, 38, 47, 50, 53, 56–64, 71, 82,
85, 93, 96–98, 110, 114, 127, 145, 184, 190, 192, 197–200,
206, 228, 236–239, 250, 255, 262, 276, 291, 298, 312–313,
322, 325, 339, 344, 363–364
mechanical curves, 314
mechanical philosophy, 324–325, 328, 347
mechanics, 22, 210, 238, 262, 295, 308, 312, 322–324, 327, 354–
355, 357, 362–364, 367
Medici (the Medicis), 147, 162, 165, 189, 248
Mediterranean, 18, 23, 103, 114, 130, 161, 163, 176
Mercury, xii, xiii, xv, 87, 109, 112, 133, 190, 195, 201, 226–227,
234–235, 293, 295
Mersenne, Marin, 324, 344
method, 175, 273, 324, 332–333, 348
Mezquita, x, 16–17
Michelangelo (Buonarroti, Michelangelo), 147, 302, 304
microscope, xvii, 262, 346, 351–352
Middle Ages, xii, xxi, 10, 22, 62–63, 89, 110, 132, 134, 138–139,
145, 148, 177–181, 193–194, 197, 213–215, 238, 273, 279,
284, 288
mills, 9, 115
mixed sciences, 238, 314
momentum, 222, 310
money, 146, 328
Mongols, 134, 146, 161, 172
monotheism, viii, 23, 139, 174
Monte Casino, 127, 144, 277–278
Moon, the, x, xi, xiii, xv, 20, 60–63, 74, 82, 91, 117, 178, 201, 218–
221, 224–226, 232–236, 244–245, 248–249, 255–258, 360
Moses, 130, 189–190
motion, xi, xii, xv, xvi, xviii, 10, 48–63, 69, 75, 78–99, 132–134, 143,
196, 202, 220–228, 234, 240–242, 248, 250–255, 265,
308–317, 320, 322–327, 333, 353, 356–370
circular, 363
planetary, 364
rectilinear, 363
movable press, the, xiii, xiv, 123, 154–160, 174, 186, 215–216
musical consonances, xi, 18, 38–40
Muslim, viii, x, xiii, 10, 17, 30, 54, 96–97, 102, 127–148, 154, 161,
172, 190, 204, 225, 234, 274–278, 283–284
myth, 85, 108, 130, 202, 248, 252, 255
mythology, 24, 66, 71, 104, 140, 178, 181
observation, xi, xv, xvii, 54, 69, 71, 73, 75, 78, 81, 93, 142, 193, 218,
239, 249, 275, 336, 345, 352
observatory, xiii, xv, 134–135, 173, 220, 231–232, 237
occult, xiv, 185, 192–197, 205, 209–211, 284, 294
properties, 284
Oldenburg, Henry, 336, 355
optics, 134, 150, 190, 204, 238–239, 244, 259, 308, 327–328, 347,
352–354
orbits, xv, xviii, 72, 75, 87, 94–98, 220–236, 241–243, 249, 258, 319,
356, 361–370
order, xiv, 4–7, 21, 26–27, 33, 47, 52–58, 63–66, 71, 83–86, 90, 110,
114, 122, 134, 144, 170–171, 182–193, 198, 207, 210, 216,
220, 225–227, 238, 241, 314, 328, 334, 338, 346, 366
Osiander, Andreas, viii, 228–229, 251
Oxford, xv, 230, 266, 335–336, 350–351
quintessence, 62
Qur’an, the, 140, 275
Xu Guangqi, 172