0% found this document useful (0 votes)
2 views

PikettyEcoPub2022Lecture8

Lecture 8 of the Public Economics course by Thomas Piketty focuses on normative and intertemporal theories of social and fiscal justice, examining the conflicts surrounding inequality and government roles. It discusses the influence of different interests, values, and belief systems on attitudes toward taxation and redistribution, as well as the implications of intertemporal justice. The lecture also introduces a model of inequality and beliefs, highlighting how perceptions of mobility and effort shape political preferences and policy conflicts.

Uploaded by

Afonso
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
2 views

PikettyEcoPub2022Lecture8

Lecture 8 of the Public Economics course by Thomas Piketty focuses on normative and intertemporal theories of social and fiscal justice, examining the conflicts surrounding inequality and government roles. It discusses the influence of different interests, values, and belief systems on attitudes toward taxation and redistribution, as well as the implications of intertemporal justice. The lecture also introduces a model of inequality and beliefs, highlighting how perceptions of mobility and effort shape political preferences and policy conflicts.

Uploaded by

Afonso
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 53

Public Economics

(Master PPD & APE)


(EHESS & Paris School of Economics)
Thomas Piketty
Academic year 2022-2023

Lecture 8: Normative and intertemporal theories of


social and fiscal justice
(check on line for updated versions)
• “Public Economics”: see complete Syllabus here
• Lectures 1-7 and 11-12 by A. Bozio and J. Grenet
• You have already covered lots of topics, including optimal
taxation of labor income. Now we’re going to focus on
intertemporal issues and capital taxation:
• Lecture 8: Normative and intertemporal theories of fiscal
and social justice (Tuesday-Wed. October 25-26 2022)
• Lecture 9: Capital income, inheritance & wealth taxes over
time & across countries (Tuesday-Wed. November 8-9 2022)
• Lecture 10: Optimal taxation of capital income, inheritance
& wealth (Tuesday-Wed. November 15-16 2022)
Roadmap of lecture 8
• Do conflicts about inequality and the role of government
come from different interests, different values/objectives, or
different beliefs systems about the the economy is working?
• A simple model of inequality and beliefs
• The dimensions of political conflict and beliefs systems about
inequality: taxation vs education vs globalization
• The problem of intertemporal justice: how much capital and
debt should we leave to our children?
• Aggregating different interests/values/beliefs: Arrow’s
impossibility theorem, Condorcet’s paradox & majority cycles
• Condorcet’s jury theorem & the constructive view of political
institutions
• Q.: Do conflicts about inequality and the role of government come
from different interests, different values/objectives, or different
beliefs systems about the society and the economy are working?
• A.: Probably from all three dimensions. But the « different beliefs
systems » view appears to be more powerful to explain observed
conflicting attitudes toward inequality. And it provides a more
optimistic and constructive view of human nature and democratic
political institutions.

• Different interests. E.g. poor vs rich. Obviously important, but not


enough. Not all poor vote alike, not all rich vote alike. Income or
wealth are correlated with political attitudes, but have never been
perfect predictors of the different possible attitudes.
• Different values/objectives. All individuals care about justice and
fairness. Or at least they feel the need to present their most-
preferred policy as determined by universal objectives &
principles (rather their self-interest).
• E.g. in all civilisations, rich people usually say something like « if
you cut my taxes, then in the end this is also going to be good for
the poor » (rather than « cut my taxes so that I am better off and
the poor worst off »)
• Even if they are not always entirely sincere (problem of self-
serving beliefs), these statements illustrate the need to refer to
universal moral values and objectives
• This in itself is interesting, and it does put constraints on political
discourses and outcomes.
• Therefore the discussion about normative theories of justice is
critical if we want to understand actual policies
• Do different individuals have different values/objectives?
• Yes to some extent: different life objectives, religious values, world
views etc.
• But in order to explain different attitudes toward inequality, it does not
seem to be very useful to characterize different individuals as having
radically different objective functions, in the sense of different views on
utilitarianism vs Rawlsianism, or more generally in the sense of different
concavity parameters in a general social welfare function. Nobody
seems to express his or her views on social justice in this manner.

• On social welfare functions, utilitarianism, concavity parameters, Rawls,


maximin, Sen, capabilities, etc., see slides from Lecture 1 (by A. Bozio)
• Different beliefs systems. It seems more useful and relevant to
characterize different individuals as having the same general
objective function (at least in part), but different - legitimate,
though possibly self-serving - beliefs systems about the society
and the economy are working.

• « Cut my taxes, and in the end it will be also be good for the
poor ». Ok, why not, but where do we stop exactly? A proper
answer to this question requires a lot of empirical and historical
knowledge, and will always be relatively uncertain. How do
different individuals form different beliefs systems about these
difficult issues?
A simple model of inequality and beliefs
• The aim of this simple model is to illustrate the discussion about
values vs beliefs
• Simplified version of the model presented in T. Piketty, “Social
Mobility & Redistributive Politics”, QJE 1995
• Initial objective of this paper: explain why intergenerational income
mobility – and not only current income – seem to matter to explain
voting preferences
• I.e. upwardly mobile individuals (moving from low parental income
to high current income) and downwardly mobile individuals (moving
from high to low) have a probability to vote for left-wing parties that
is intermediate between those of permanently low-income and
permanently high-income groups
• Two possible income levels: y0 < y1
• y0 = low-paid job; y1 = high-paid job
• Probability (yi=y1) = π0 + θei if parental income = y0
• Probability (yi=y1) = π1 + θei if parental income = y1
With ei = effort, θ = index of how much individual effort
matters, Δπ =π1- π0= index of how much inequality in social
origins matters (better access to education, connexions to
find jobs, etc.)
• Redistributive taxation: c0=(1-t)y0+ty, c1=(1-t)y1+ty,
With t = income tax rate, y=(1-p)y0+py1 = average pre-tax income,
p = pop. fraction getting high income
• Per capita tax revenue ty used to pay lump-sum cash transfer
(or to finance equal access to education or other public
services)
• t=0% : no redistribution; t=100%: full redistribution
• Individual i has utility Ui =ci-C(ei), with C(e)=e2/2a:
• Max (1-pi)c0 + pic1 – C(ei), with pi = πi + θei
• FO condition: ei = aθ(1-t)(y1-y0)
→ more redistribution leads to less effort → how much this
matters depends on relative importance of θ vs Δπ
• Assume everybody agrees about some form of maximin
objective:
Max (1-p)c0 + pc1 – C(e), with p = π0 + θe
(i.e. expected welfare of individuals with low parental income)
• Then one can show that optimal t* is given by:
t* = HΔπ/a(y1-y0)θ2
(H = pop fraction of indiv. with high-income parents)
• I.e. optimal tax t*↑ if Δπ ↑ or θ↓, i.e. if parental origins
more important & role of effort less important
• But this does not mean that everybody agrees about t* :
different beliefs about Δπ and θ can lead to different t*
→ politics as a conflict over beliefs
• Why different beliefs?
• Because it is difficult to learn about Δπ and θ
• Self-serving beliefs also play a role: high-income individuals
have a clear incentive to pretend that θ matters more than Δπ,
and to try to spread their views in the media & political parties
• But even if all individuals have fully sincere, and start with
same initial beliefs, one can show that different families will
end up with different beliefs: e.g. if you put a lot of effort
experience an upward mobility experience, you will tend to
believe that effort works and update your beliefs accordingly
• This can explain why mobility experience and not only current
income determines political attitudes
• In the long run, high-income individuals tend to be more right-wing
on average than low-income individuals (they want less
redistribution), even if they are not selfish at all
(in effect, right-wing dynasties believe more in effort and end up with
higher average incomes, whether their beliefs are right or wrong)
(see QJE 1995)
• Other, more sophisticated ways to learn about optimal t*: study the
comparative history of inequality and taxation, read econometric
estimates of labor supply elasticities…
• But there will always be a lot of uncertainty about the conclusions
one can draw from historical or econometric evidence, so the political
conflict will continue, and democratic institutions will do what they
can to aggregate these different beliefs
• This simple model also illustrates the difficulties to define the
proper social objective
• Assume Δπ=0, i.e. family origins do not matter, everybody faces
the same probability π + θe to have high income y1 > y0
• With risk aversion (Ui =V(ci)-C(ei) and V(.) concave), one still
wants redistributive taxation
• But with Ui =ci-C(ei), do we really want t*=0?
• If y1 vs y0 = long-term, lifetime inequality, then risk aversion
might not be the relevant way to determine the socially
desirable level of redistribution (with short-term risk, this is
questionable as well: public unemployment insurance)
• Assume social objective = Max c0 – C(e)
• Max c0 – C(e) = (1-t)y0+ty – C(e)
with e = aθ(1-t)(y1-y0), y=(1-p)y0+py1, p=π + θe
• Then one can show that
t* = 2/3 + π/3a(y1-y0)θ2
(formula to be checked; please do it for next time!)
→ This leads to much more redistribution than with expected
welfare maximization
→ Discussion about objective function matters, together with
the discussion about beliefs and elasticities
The dimensions of political conflict and beliefs systems about
inequality: taxation vs education vs globalization
• There is extensive evidence showing that beliefs about luck vs effort
and about income mobility prospects matter to explain attitudes
towards inequality.
• See e.g. Alesina-LaFerrara 2005 ; A-Angeletos 2005; A-Stantcheva-
Tevo 2017; Alesina et al 2016; Alesina et al 2015 on beliefs in luck vs
effort and mobility in US vs Europe
• On mobility prospects, inequality and beliefs, see also models by
Benabou-Ok 2001; Benabou 2000, Benabou-Tirole 2006, Benabou
2008, Benabou et al 2015
• But the basic model about the role of luck and effort is a bit
simplistic: it captures only a small part of the issues on which people
disagree regarding inequality; in practice, key conflicts involve the
role of education, globalization, etc.
• Basic model on luck & effort: left = pessimistic about mobility
(beliefs in luck and redistributive taxation), right = optimistic about
mobility (beliefs in effort)
• In practice this can be much more complicated. E.g. one can have
« pessimistic right » by introducing individual ability parameters βi:
• Probability (yi=y1) = π0 + θβiei if parental income = y0
• Probability (yi=y1) = π1 + θβiei if parental income = y1
• With ei = effort, θ = index of how much effort matters, Δπ =π1- π0=
index of how much parental inequality matters, βi = individual
ability parameter
• If one believes in different average β1>β0 depending on family
origin, then one can easily get a « conservative right »: beliefs in
low tax and low mobility
• If one believes in high var(βi), but with limited correlation with
parental origins, then one can generate an « eugenist right »:
beliefs in low tax and innate talent
• For a model with beliefs in luck, effort and talent, see T. Piketty,
« Self-fulfilling models about social status », JPubEc 1998
(with no correlation of βi with parental origins)
• Other major limitation of basic model of luck and effor: the only policy
instrument is redistributive taxation
• Historically, left beliefs focus on the role of education (tax revenues can be
used to finance education and reduce parental-origin inequality Δπ =π1- π0),
unions/worker co-determination/power sharing, and other policies affecting
primary inequality (rather than just doing secondary ex-post redistribution) (vs
right beliefs in private property)
• Depending on the beliefs on the efficiency of education spending, one can
generate « optimistic left »: high mobility and high taxation
• Beliefs in education can naturally be influenced by individual trajectories. Can
also explain the rise of high-education & to some extent high-income left vote
• Beliefs in education, family and gender roles are also key to explain changing
political preferences of women (right>left)
• On changing effect of income, wealth, education, gender on left and right
vote, see « Brahmin Left vs Merchant Right: Rising Inequality and the Changing
Structure of Political Conflict »: long-run series on changing political cleavages
in FR-US-UK 1948-2017, + two-dimensional models of redistributive politics
(see also World Political Clevages and Inequality Database, WPID.world)
Two-dim model 1: domestic inequality vs external inequality
• Introducing globalization: in addition to policy dimension TL vs TR
(redistributive domestic tax rate between rich and poor), assume there’s
also some other dimension: openess/migration with OL>OR
• As conflict about OL > OR becomes more salient (rise of extra-European
migration in Europe, rise of civil rights/latinos in US), some the poor
start to vote for the right, assuming preferences for OL >OR are
correlated with education and income
• Further assume that globalization makes it easier to evade taxes: by
putting dissimulation effort f then high-income taxpayers can manage
with proba ωf to pretend that they have y0 instead of y1
• With ω large enough, then the policy conflict about redistribution
vanishes: both TL and TR close to 0 → the political conflict gradually
focuses on OL > OR → « globalists » vs « nativists » party system
Two-dim model 2: education inequality vs wealth inequality
• Introducing educational expension: with rise of higher education, not
possible to provide everyone with same education; depending on
educational effort fi, one face different chances to be admitted to
selective higher education (education x1 rather than x0)
• Probability (xi=x1) = α0 + φfi if parental education = x0
• Probability (xi=x1) = α1 + φfi if parental education = x1
• Higher education increases probability to access a high-paid job:
• Probability (yi=y1) = π0 + θei + µs if xi=x1 (& parental income = y0)

→ « multiple-elite » party system: Brahmin left believes more in


education-related effort parameter φ, while Merchant right believes more
in business-related effort parameter θ
• Two key dimensions of political conflict:
attitudes on vertical redistribution dimension (poor vs rich)
vs attitudes on foreigners/migrants/minorities/openness
• See Roemer-Lee-Van der Straeten, Racism, Xenophobia, and
Distribution: Multi-Issue Politics in Advanced Democracies,
HUP 2007 (see also journal articles: JPubE 2006; JEEA 2006; JE
2005 ; SJE 2006; ) the xenophobia dimension substantially
reduces the equilibrium level of vertical redistribution.
• See also Kuziemko-Norton-Saez-Stantcheva, « How Elastic are
Preferences for Redistribution? », AER 2015 : inequality
dimension vs trust-in-government dimension.
• See also Alesina-Glaeser-Sacerdote, « Why doesn’t the US have a
European style Welfare », BPEA 2001; Alesina-Glaeser, Fighting
Poverty in the US and Europe: a word of difference, OUP 2004
• Main explanation: less demand for redistribution because more
racial prejudice in the US (also: stronger US beliefs in effort and
mobility, but difficult to separate from racial prejudice); negative
cross-country correlation between racial fractionalisation and social
transfers
• One pb with Roemer et al/Alesina et al: lack of historical
perspective on how party systems and inequality change over time;
US was in some ways more equal than Europe in 19c and invented
steeply progressive taxation during 20c; historical changes are more
interesting to study than supposedly permanent differences (see
Advanced Econ History course)
The problem of intertemporal justice: how much
capital and debt should we leave to our children?
• Redistributive taxation of income involves serious conflicts of beliefs
about the functionning of the economy and the way inequality is
generated, the role of effort, education, etc.
• Redistributive taxation of wealth and capital involves equally complex
(or arguably more complex) issues related to the large concentration
of property, the dynamic impacts of taxation, the different forms of
taxation (flows vs stocks). See lectures 9-10.
• But even if there was no wealth inequality at all, i.e. assuming
everybody owns an equal share of the world capital stock, the issue of
capital accumulation would raise serious problems of intertemporal
justice: how much should we leave to our children? Inequality
between generations (rather than within generations) = arguably the
most pressing issue, especially if we include natural capital.
• Phelps AER 1961, « The Golden rule of capital accumulation: a fable for
growthmen »; AER 1965, « Second esssay on the Golden rule of
accumulation » = one of the first mathematical models of Golden rule = « re-
invest the full capital share, until the point where the marginal product capital
r equals the economy’s growh rate g ».
But as we will see this simple r=g rule makes sense only under very special
assumptions (zero productivity growth + exogenous & permanently positive
population growth)
• « Golden rule » = generic name often used to refer to intertemporal rules aimed
at preparing the future; rules about long term investment, deficits, etc.
• In political debates, « Golden rules » (in a vague and general sense) are often
invoked to limit the power of today’s electoral majorities, sometime with good
reasons: otherwise today’s generations might eat up the future
• The pb is that these rules are often instrumentalized in ways that are not so
good for the future...
• E.g. European budgetary rules can be viewed as a sort of « Golden rule »: 3%
maximal deficit rule in Euro zone (Maastricht Treaty 1992), reduced in 2011-
2012 to 0.5% structural deficit (i.e. potentially huge primary surplus)
• It is unclear however whether they’ve had a positive impact on Europe’s welfare:
e.g. Euro recession 2011-13 (not in US); most importantly, these rules entirely
ignore investment in education/human capital, natural capital, public wealth,
etc., so it is not sure at all that they prepare the future
(see e.g. Jackson et al 2013, 2015, 2020 GPI series: Genuine Progress Indicator)
• More generally, constitutional provisions protecting private property have often
been imposed by invoking long-run public interest (e.g. to justify censitory vote:
only the rich should vote, because the poor are not patient!)
• Preparing the future is a complex multi-dimensional task, and no simple
mathematical formula is going to solve the problem for us : we need
permanent & extensive democratic deliberation; be careful with automatic rules
• That being said, it’s interesting to look at what these mathematical formulas
look like, starting with Phelps 1961
• Phelps 1961’s Golden rule formula
• Assume population growth rate n≥0: Nt=N0ent
• Assume productivity growth rate h, so that efficient labour supply
grows at rate g=n+h (with h=productivity growth rate):
Lt=L0egt=L0e(n+h)t
(L0=λN0 , with λ = labour participation rate)
• Assume production function Yt = F(Kt,Lt)
with Yt = output, Kt = capital input, Lt = labour input
• For instance F(K,L)=KαL1-α (with 0<α<1)
• Or any other functional form, assuming constant returns to scale (i.e.
F(aK,aL)=aF(K,L)), so that : y = Y/L = F(K,L)/L = F(K/L,1) = f(k)
(y=Y/L=output per labor unit, k=K/L=capital per lab. unit)
• If Y=F(K,L)=KαL1-α then y=f(k)=kα : y is a rising concave function k →
k is useful, but where should we stop?
• Output can be used to consume (food, i-phones etc.) or to invest (more
machines, buildings, equipment to produce food and i-phones, or more
investment for the future in education, environment, etc.):
• I.e. Yt = Ct + It, with Ct=(1-st)Yt, It=stYt , st = saving rate
• Capital accumulation is determined by saving:
dKt/dt=It=stYt
• Q.: If we care about « long-run welfare » (to be defined), how much capital
Kt should we accumulate, i.e. how should we choose the saving rate st ?
• Here we entirely ignore inequality: everybody is assumed the same
average capital stock (representative agent approach); but this is already a
difficult question to solve
• A.: With zero productivity growth (h=0) and exogenous, permanently
positive population growth (g=n>0), then you should save until f’(k*)=r*=g
• If h>0,or n=0, or n endogenous, it’s difficult to say anything
• Proof. In the long run, it will generally be optimal to follow a balanced growth path, i.e.
capital input Kt will grow at the same rate as labor input Lt: i.e. Kt= K0 egt
• Long-run saving equation: dKt/dt = g Kt = It = sYt (with st → s = long-run saving rate).
I.e. capital-output ratio βt=Kt/Yt → β = s/g
• Long-run capital per labor unit kt → k
Long-run output per labor unit yt → y=f(k), with k/y=β=s/g
• Assume h=0, n>0. No long-run productivity growth implies that per capita long run output
and consumption will be stationary (zero growth). With zero growth, a reasonnable long-
run welfare objective is simply to maximize long-run per capita consumption.
• Long-run per capita consumption c = (1-s)f(k) = f(k) – sf(k) = f(k) – nk
• Max c = f(k) – nk → f’(k*)=n
• I.e. Long-run optimal capital stock k* is such that marginal product of capital r*=f’(k*)=n
(i.e. r*=g, since g=n+h=n if h=0)
• Intuition: with r=n, then long-run saving sy = nk = rk = capital share. There’s no point
saving more than the capital share. Otherwise, what’s the point of accumulating k? k is
supposed to increase c. Golden rule: stop accumulating k if maintaining this per capita
capital level requires you to save more than the capital share.
• Exemple: f(k)=kα, so that r=f’(k)=α kα-1
• I.e. r=αf(k)/k, so that rk=αf(k)=αy, i.e. capital share = fixed fraction
α of output y=f(k)
• With Cobb-Douglas production function, the marginal product of
capital r=f’(k) declines exactly in the same proportions as the
increase in k/y, so that the two effects exactly cancel each other
and the capital share is constant (elasticity of substitution = 1)
• Assume population growth rate n=1% and capital share α=30%.
Then r*=f’(k*)=1% implies β*=k*/y*=α/r*=3000%.
• I.e. we should accumulate 30 years of income in capital.
This is a lot of capital: in practice β=500-600% (5-6 years).
• So here the Golden rule is telling us that we should accumulate a
lot more capital than we do.
• Intuition. Why should we stop accumulating capital at β*=3000%?
• Because with a population growth rate n=1%, then in order to
maintain a per capita capital/income ratio higher than this, then we
would need to save more than 30% of output each year. Given that
the production function is such that the capital share is 30%, this
would mean saving more than the capital share.
• E.g. in order to maintain β=4000%, we would need to save at rate
s=40%. There would be so much capital than the rate of return
would be less than 1%: it would be equal to r=α/β=0.75%. Everybody
would be better off by reducing saving (i.e. by eating some of the
capital stock): the current generation and the future generations.
• Pb: if n → 0% (=UN demographic projections for 21c), then
there is no limit to capital accumulation: r*=n → 0%,
β*=α/r*→ ∞, i.e. we should accumulate infinite capital &
postpone consumption entirely to the future!
• Pb with simple Golden rule r*=n : it does not put enough
weight on current generations, which given the existence of
productivity growth is particularly problematic
→ « modified Golden rule » r* = δ + γg
(other pb: population growth is a choice, so it is strange to treat
population growth rate as given; and what do we do if n<0?
Complicated welfare considerations on optimal population size)
• « Modified Golden rule »: r* = δ + γg
with δ = pure social rate of time preference
g = economy’s growth rate: Yt = egt Y0
γ = concavity of social welfare function
• Same model as before, except that we now assume positive long-run productivity
growth h>0 (and zero long-run population growth n=0, so that g=n+h=h), and except
that we now specify explicitly the intertemporal social welfare function
• r* =f’(k*)=δ + γg is the optimal long-run level of capital accumulation that should be set
by a social planner choosing saving rates so as to maximize V = ∫t>0 e-δt U(ct)
with U(c)=c1-γ/(1-γ) (i.e. U’(c)=c-γ )
• γ≥0 measures the speed at which the marginal social utility of consumption goes to zero
= how useful is it to have another i-phone if you already have 100000 i-phones?
(γ=0: linear utility U(c)=c; γ=1: log utility U(c)=log(c);
γ>1: utility function more concave than log function)
• The modified Golden rule r* = δ + γg is used extensively in policy debates,
e.g. in the global warming debate. The pb is that there is no clear way to pick
parameters δ and especially γ.
• The choice of parameters has a strong impact on the social discount rate r*:
are future generations going to be so rich and so productive that they will be
able to clean up our pollution?
• Stern 2006 Report on the costs of global warming
• An important part of the controversy was due to differences in the social
discount rate
• I.e. assume that we agree that global warming will cause catastrophies that
are equivalent to a loss equal to λ% of world GDP in T years
• Say λ=10%, and T=70 years (sea will rise around 2080)
• Q.: How much welfare should we ready to sacrifice today in order to avoid
this? Should we stop using cars entirely?
• A.: We should be able to sacrifice μY0 = e-r*T λYT ,
with r* = δ + γg = social discount rate = rate at which an ideal social planner
should discount the future
• Intuition behind r* = δ + γg
• If g=0, then r*=δ : social rate of time preference
• From an ethical viewpoint, everybody agrees that δ should be
close to 0%: it is difficult to justify why we should put a lower
welfare weight on future generations
• Both Stern & Nordhaus pick δ=0,1% (Stern mentions estimates of
meteorit crash: the probability that earth disappears is <0,1%/yr)
→ with zero growth, everybody agrees that μ ≈ λ
(of course, private rate of time preference – i.e. how private
individuals behave in their own life – are a different matter: they can
be a lot larger, typically private δ = at least 1-2%, and private γ>1)
• With g>0, one has to compute the impact on social welfare of
reducing consumption by dcT<0 at time t=T and raising it by
dc0>0 at time t=0:
• Social welfare: V = ∫t>0 e-δt U(ct)
with U(c)=c1-γ/(1-γ) (i.e. U’(c)=c-γ )
• dV = U’(c0) dc0 + e-δt U’(cT) dcT
• cT = egT c0 → dV =0 iff dc0 = e-(δ+γg)t dcT
→ MGR: r* = δ + γg
• Intuition: γ very large means that extra consumption not so
useful for future generations, because they will be very rich
anyway → very large r*, even if g is quite small and uncertain
• Stern vs Nordhaus controversy: both agree with the modified Golde
rule formula r* = δ + γg and about the long-run productivity growth
prospects (g=1,3%) but disagree about parameters (especially γ)

• Stern 2006 : δ=0,1%, g=1,3%, γ=1, so r*=1,4%


(see Stern 2006 report, chapter 2A)

• Nordhaus 2007: δ=0,1%, g=1,3%, γ=3, so r*=4,0%


(see Nordhaus, "Critical Assumptions in the Stern Review on Climate
Change", Science 2007; see also JEL 2007 symposium)
• Whether one adopts r*=1,4% or r*=4,0% (for a given growth rate
g=1,3%) makes a huge difference:
• We should spend: μY0 = e-r*T λYT , i.e. μ = e-(r*-g)T λ
(since YT = egt Y0 )
• According to Stern r*-g=0,1%, so with T=70, e(r*-g)T=1,07 : it is worth
spending about 9% of GDP in 2010 in order to avoid a 10% GDP loss in
2080: we need to reduce emissions right now & to finance large green
investments
• But e(r*-g)T=6,61 according to Nordhaus (r*-g=2,7%): it is worth
spending only 1,5% of GDP in 2010 in order to avoid a 10% GDP loss in
2080: don’t worry too much, growth will clean up the mess
• ≈ EU vs US position
• What is strange in this controversy is that both Stern and Norhaus take
opposite sides on concavity parameter γ as compared to the
parameters that they usually favor for cross-sectional redistribution
purposes: Stern would usually favor high γ (high redistribution) and
Nordhaus low γ (low redistribution)

• If future growth was certain (i.e. future generations will be more


productive, whatever they do), then it might indeed make sense to
have high γ or even infinite γ = Rawlsian objective: we should only care
about maximizing the lowest welfare or consumption level, i.e. the
level of the current generation
• Two pb with this intergenerational Rawlsian reasonning:
• (1) growth is endogenous: if we leave infinite pollution (or debt) to
future generations, maybe g will not be so large
• (2) one-good models are not well suited to study these issues: in the
long run the relative price of the environment might be infinite (i.e. if
we all have 100000 i-phones, but unbreathable air, maybe the relative
value of having a little bit clean air will be quite large)
See J. Sterner, "An Even Sterner Review: Introducing Relative Prices
into the Discounting Debate", JEP 2008
See also Drupp et al, « Discounting disentangled », 2015; Nordhaus,
« Climate Change: the Ultimate challenge for economics », AER 2019;
Sterner et al, « Climate Economics Support for UN Mandate », Nature
and Climate Change 2020
• Summing up: the interesting intuition behind the Golden rule is that we should never
accumulate so much k that the return rate r falls below the growth rate g, i.e. so much
that the capital share rk falls below the required saving gk to keep k/y constant
• We always want r>g, so that the return to capital rk is higher than what we need to
save each year to maintain the capital stock.
• E.g. with r=5%, g=1%, we only need to reinvest 1/5th of the return to capital, and we
can consume the other 4/5th.
• The point of capital accumulation is to be able to consume more in the future, not less.
• The Golden rule r=g puts a maximum on capital accumulation : in case we accumulate
more than this, then we are in a situation of « dynamic inefficiency », in which case it
is Pareto-improving to reduce the capital stock (e.g. by setting up a pay-as-you-go
pension system, as in Diamond 1965’s OLG model)
• But it does not say that we should accumulate so much: it provides an upper bound
on capital accumulation (and a lower bound on rate of return), not a target.
• Modified Golden rule r*=δ + γg is not so useful: this is trying to put too much into a
simple mathematical formula.
• Computing optimal capital accumulation for the future is a complex
multi-dimensional task, and no simple mathematical formula is going
to solve the problem for us.
• We first need to make sure that we properly measure the different
dimensions of capital accumulation: e.g. we need to take into account
public assets and not only public debt (if we take a complete view,
current obsession with private debt not justified); we need to take into
account human capital (investement in education) and natural capital
(which existing balance sheets don’t do well at this stage).
• Some economic computations can be useful, but not all: e.g. Stern’s
estimates of lost GDP (fall in economic activity) if sea levels rise can be
useful; but discount rate controversy not so useful
• In order to properly analyze optimal public policies regarding capital
accumulation, one needs to introduce inequality into the picture. See
lectures 9-10.
Condorcet paradox & majority cycles
• Because of different interests, values and beliefs systems, different
individuals have different preferences about policies, and in particular about
inequality, capital accumulation, etc.
• Q.: Which mechanisms and political institutions should be used to combine
these preferences and take a collective decision? = the pb of « social
choice » (or « preference aggregation »)
• K. Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values, 1951
• Arrow’s Impossibility theorem = if we rule out interpersonal comparisons of
utilities, then there is no consistent collective rule to aggregate individual
preferences and take collective decisions (i.e. we need minimal agreement
about common values; if all disagreements are allowed, then chaos prevails)
• In particular, the “majority rule” doesn’t work
• In general, one can find policies A,B,C such that a majority prefers A to B, a
majority prefers B to C & a majority prefers C to A = “majority cycle”
• Condorcet paradox 1785: with multi-dimensional political
conflicts, majority cycles are pervasive (→ democracy needs to be
organized, constitution design is important)
• Concrete exemple of multi-dimensional political conflict: attitudes
toward redistribution (e.g. level of progressive taxation, size of
govt) vs attitudes toward foreigners/migrants
• Then one can easily find 3 candidates A,B,C such that we have a
cycle.
• E.g. A=Le Pen, B=Melenchon, C=Macron?
• A defeats B, B defeats C, C defeats A?
• Arrow’s impossibility theorem = simple generalization of Condorcet
majority paradox : majority rule doesn’t work, and no simple political
rule can work
• Arrow 1951 = negative results about political institutions = often
viewed as the negative equivalent of Debreu 1959 Theory of Value –
An axiomatic analysis of economic equilibrum = positive results about
economic institutions (two welfare theorems on market efficiency)
• In brief: economics is about creating new value, politics is about
dividing the pie in a more or less chaotic manner
= “public choice” school, nihilist view of politics
• But in fact there are many ways out of Arrow 1951’s negative result:
we need minimal agreement on common values and goods, we need
to talk about constitution design… and we should not forget about
Condorcet’s jury theorem = the positive, constructive side of politics
Condorcet jury theorem and the
constructive view of political institutions
• Condorcet 1785 jury theorem. Assume that everybody has the same
objective function (same values and preferences), but has different
beliefs and information about what policy is optimal (given these
values and preferences).
• Further assume that we have to choose between two policies A and B,
that everybody receives a signal providing information as to whether
A or B is the optimal policy, and that everybody has the same
probability p>0.5 to receive the right signal.
• Then with a large population, the probability that the majority rule
leads to the right decision approaches 1. Nobody wants to be dictator,
everybody prefers majority-rule democracy. Simple, but powerful:
democracy is based upon the idea that more than half of the people
are right more than half of the time, & on the law of large numbers.
• With different signal qualities, more than 2 policies, etc. then one
may prefer indirect democracy, etc.: constitution design matters
• See Condorcet 1785, Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la
probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix ; and
Condorcet’s contribution to revolutionary debates on ideal
constitution
• Condorcet jury theorem = basic positive result about democratic
institutions (aggregation of information through voting). Equivalent
to Arrow-Debreu positive result about economic institutions
(aggregation of information through the markets)
• The jury theorem and the majority-cycle paradox should be viewed as
complementary: democracy can work, but it needs to be organized
• If political conflict is about different beliefs and information
(and not simply about conflicting interests and preferences),
then different electoral & political systems allow for different
levels of aggregation of information: trade-off between the
decision-making and political-stability dimensions of the
electoral system and the deliberative dimension
• See T. Piketty “The Information-Aggregation Approach to
Political Institutions”, EER 1999 ; “Voting as Communicating”,
RES 2000
• More generally, if politics is about beliefs and information,
then public deliberation and communication via medias,
political parties, books etc. play a critical role.
• In particular, deliberation can reduce the dimensionality of political
conflict. See D. Spector, “Rational Debate Leads to One-Dimensional
Conflict”, QJE 2000
• Intuition: as long as there are different dimensions of conflict, one
can find ways to solve credibility problems.
• Politics is both about sincere beliefs/ideology and about conflicting
interests and self-serving beliefs. So it is important to regulate
political finance, access to the media, etc. See Bonica-Rosenthal,
« Why Hasn’t Democracy Slowed Rising Inequality », JEP 2013 ;
T. Kuhner, Capitalism vs Democracy: Money in Politics and the Free
Market Constitution, SUP 2014
• More on political parties, electoral conflict & inequality in Advanced
Economic History course

You might also like