Annual Review of Psychology Vol 56 2005 1st Edition Susan T. Fiske Ebook All Chapters PDF
Annual Review of Psychology Vol 56 2005 1st Edition Susan T. Fiske Ebook All Chapters PDF
https://ebookfinal.com/download/annual-review-of-psychology-
vol-55-2004-1st-edition-susan-t-fiske/
https://ebookfinal.com/download/annual-review-of-psychology-
vol-60-2009-1st-edition-susan-t-fiske/
https://ebookfinal.com/download/nber-macroeconomics-annual-2005-1st-
edition-mark-gertler/
Fiske WordPower 1st Edition Edward Fiske
https://ebookfinal.com/download/fiske-wordpower-1st-edition-edward-
fiske/
https://ebookfinal.com/download/2008-annual-review-of-development-
effectiveness-shared-global-challenges-world-bank/
https://ebookfinal.com/download/biotechnology-annual-review-10-1st-
edition-m-raafat-el-gewely/
Annual Review of Psychology Vol 56 2005 1st Edition
Susan T. Fiske Digital Instant Download
Author(s): Susan T. Fiske, Daniel L. Schacter, Alan E. Kazdin
ISBN(s): 9780824302566, 0824302567
Edition: 1
File Details: PDF, 4.24 MB
Year: 2005
Language: english
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
P1: JRX
December 8, 2004
12:13
Annual Reviews
AR231-FM
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
10.1146/annurev.psych.56.091103.070239
CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1
Simplified Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4
Strategies to Study Memory Formation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4
OUR MODEL SYSTEM: EYEBLINK CONDITIONING . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6
Motor Control . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6
The Hippocampus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8
The Essential Circuitry: The Cerebellum . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11
CONCLUSION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16
INTRODUCTION
A major achievement of recent research on brain substrates of learning and mem-
ory, to which our work has contributed, is the recognition that there are several
different forms or aspects of memory involving different brain systems (Figure 1).
Squire (1992) has argued eloquently for the distinction between declarative and
nondeclarative forms of memory, as has Schacter (1987). The distinction be-
tween episodic and semantic memory—“What did you have for breakfast?” versus
“Where is the Eiffel Tower?”—has been stressed by Tulving (1985).
0066-4308/05/0203-0001$14.00 1
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
2
18 Nov 2004 11:52
AR
THOMPSON
AR231-PS56-01.tex
AR231-PS56-01.sgm
LaTeX2e(2002/01/18)
Figure 1 A current view of the various forms of learning and memory and their putative brain substrates.
P1: IKH
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
differing neuronal substrates was not recognized at that time, nor were modern
analytic techniques available then.
We adopt the following definitions from an earlier review (Lavond et al. 1993).
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
The essential memory trace, together with its associated circuitry, is necessary and
sufficient for the basic aspects of a given form of learning (e.g., acquisition and
retention). Other brain structures may also form memory traces, defined loosely as
learning-induced changes in neuronal activity, but these may not be essential for
the basic learning. Thus, in eyeblink conditioning, long-lasting learning-induced
increases in neuronal activity develop in the hippocampus (Berger et al. 1976), but
the hippocampus is not necessary for basic delay associative learning and memory
(Schmaltz & Theios 1972).
Aversive classical conditioning can modify the receptive-field properties of neu-
rons in sensory systems. Particularly striking are the studies of Weinberger and
associates (Edeline & Weinberger 1991, Weinberger et al. 1984) showing that neu-
rons in secondary areas of auditory thalamus and cortex shift their best frequencies
toward the frequency of the conditioning stimulus in aversive Pavlovian condition-
ing (see also Bao et al. 2003). The motor area of the cerebral cortex provides yet
another example. Classical eyeblink conditioning results in marked and persist-
ing increases in excitability of pyramidal neurons in motor cortex (Woody et al.
1984). However, the motor cortex is not necessary for either learning or memory of
the conditioned eyeblink response (Ivkovich & Thompson 1997). These “higher-
order” memory traces appear to play important roles in the adaptive behavior of
the organism.
The obvious point here is that the organism can learn, remember, and per-
form the basic learned response following destruction of nonessential memory
trace systems, but destruction of the essential memory trace system abolishes this
ability. We draw a distinction between the essential memory trace and the es-
sential memory trace circuit. The latter includes the necessary input and output
circuits as well as the essential memory trace itself. These are all identified by
lesions. But lesions, per se, cannot distinguish between the essential trace and the
essential circuitry; lesions of either completely prevent and abolish the learned
response.
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
4 THOMPSON
Simplified Systems
How does one go about finding memory traces? One very productive approach is
the use of simplified “model” systems, emphasized early by Thompson & Spencer
(1966) (see also Kandel & Spencer 1968). Thus, vertebrate spinal reflexes and the
gill-withdrawal reflex circuit in Aplysia have both served as very productive models
to analyze processes of habituation and sensitization. In the case of habituation,
at least, the memory trace is embedded within the reflex pathway under study so
lesions abolish the reflex as well as the trace. For monosynaptic pathways in both
Aplysia and spinal cord the mechanism of short-term habituation appears to be
simply a decrease in the probability of transmitter release as a result of repeated
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
strate can prove to be complex, particularly for long-lasting habituation, e.g., be-
tween sessions as opposed to within session response decrements. In the Aplysia
cellular monosynaptic system, Ezzeddine & Glanzman (2003) have shown that
prolonged habituation depends on protein synthesis, protein phosphatase activ-
ity, and postsynaptic glutamate receptors. Indeed, their data indicate that stimuli
inducing habituation of the gill-withdrawal reflex appear to activate sensitizing
processes as well, as proposed in the “dual-process” theory of habituation by
Groves & Thompson (1970).
Thus, much is still not known about the detailed mechanisms of memory traces
in this simplest form of learning. By mechanisms we mean the physical-chemical
substrate of memory store. Although there are many candidate mechanisms, as of
this writing we do not yet know the detailed physical bases of memory storage for
any form of learning and memory in the mammalian brain. But understanding the
mechanisms of memory storage will not inform us of what the memories are. The
actual memories are coded by the neuronal circuits that code, store, and retrieve
the memories, what I term here the “essential circuits.”
Actually, there are many forms of plasticity in the nervous system, synap-
tic plasticity being only one. There are also changes in neuron excitability due
to factors intrinsic to the neurons, as in decreases in after-hyperpolarization, as
well as structural changes in dendrites, formation of new neurons, and actions
of glial cells. LTP has been the most intensely studied putative synaptic mech-
anism of memory storage, particularly in the hippocampus (e.g., Martin et al.
2000), but the evidence is still far from clear. There is a vast literature analyz-
ing mechanisms of LTP but very little work attempting to show that it is a basis
for the storage of memories (see Shors & Matzel 1997, Wilson & Tonegawa
1997).
The alternative strategy is to begin with a well-characterized form of learning
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
and memory and determine the memory traces involved. In order to do this it is first
necessary to find where in the brain the memories are stored, the classical problem
of localization. Because learning involves changes in behavior as a result of expo-
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
sure to stimuli that do not change, there must be alterations at some loci in the brain.
A given form of learning may involve one or multiple loci of memory storage, but
they must exist. We have used this strategy in our search for memory traces.
How does one go about finding a memory trace in the behaving mammal? Olds,
Disterhoft, and associates wrestled with this issue in pioneering studies (Olds et al.
1972). Their basic approach was to record extracellular unit cluster discharges in
many brain areas in freely moving rats, looking for increases in unit response on
the conditioning day that were significantly greater than responses to the stimuli
on the preceding pseudoconditioning day, i.e., a learning-induced increase in unit
activity. The behavioral situation was simply an auditory conditioned stimulus
(CS+) followed after 2 sec by a food pellet unconditioned stimulus (US) versus a
CS− with no food pellet. The studies were very well controlled.
The initial criterion they set for identification of the memory trace was shortest
latency learned responses:
The “earliest” conditioned brain responses (i.e., those appearing with the
shortest latencies after application of the CS) might thus be considered to be
“at the site” of conditioning, and other later conditioned brain responses might
be considered to be secondary to them. Similarly (and hopefully validating
this supposition) “early” new brain responses might be expected to emerge at
the site of old responses indicating this site to be a junction point between old
and new (Olds et al. 1972, p. 202).
In a most interesting thought piece, Michael Gabriel (1976) argued against the
use of the shortest latency response as the criterion for identification of the memory
trace. He proposed an alternative “bias” hypothesis. In essence, he suggested that a
tonic flow of impulses originating from a distant neuronal locus biased the activity
of the neurons being recorded as the shortest latency learned response. So the
increase of the shortest latency unit response could be due to tonic actions on
these neurons from a distant site where learning has resulted in a tonic increase
in activity. Gabriel draws the following rather strong conclusion: “clearly the bias
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
6 THOMPSON
hypothesis argues against the idea of mapping the brain for short-latency neuronal
responses in order to localize engrams” (p. 279).
In a companion piece to the Olds et al. (1972) article, Disterhoft & Olds (1972)
do consider the possibility of tonic influences, as Gabriel notes. They suggest an
additional criterion, namely the earliest increase in neuronal activity that develops
over the trials of training. I return to this issue below.
In the late 1960s and early 1970s we tried several different types of model
systems to analyze neural substrates of mammalian associative learning and mem-
ory. Because of our success in using spinal reflexes for analysis of habituation
we tackled classical conditioning of the flexion reflex in the acute spinal animal,
with some success (Patterson et al. 1973). However, I concluded it was not a good
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
Motor Control
We began our analysis with a focus on the motor nerves and nuclei that gener-
ated the reflex and learned eyeblink responses (Cegavske et al. 1976, Cegavske
et al. 1979, Young et al. 1976). To oversimplify from our work and the work of
others, the sixth nerve was critically important for the nictitating membrane (NM)
response, but the third and fourth nerves were also involved and the seventh nerve
was critical for closure of the external eyelid (obicularis oculi muscles). In terms
of motor nuclei, the seventh nucleus controlled external eyelid closure and the
accessory portion of the sixth nucleus innervated the retractor bulbous muscle,
which retracted the eyeball and forced the nictitating membrane out across the
front surface of the eye. The fourth and sixth nuclei acted synergistically with
the accessory sixth and seventh. We showed with simultaneous recordings that
NM extension and external eyelid closure [actually electromyographic (EMG)
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
activity of the obicularis oculi muscles] were essentially perfectly correlated over
the course of learning (McCormick et al. 1982b). Indeed, obicularis oculi EMG
appears to be the most robust and sensitive measure of learning (Lavond et al.
1990). Recordings from the relevant motor nuclei, particularly the sixth, acces-
sory sixth, and seventh, showed essentially identical patterns of learning-induced
increases in neuronal activity.
It is important to stress the fact that the pathways mediating the reflex eye-
blink are in the brain stem and do not involve “higher” brain systems such as the
cerebellum and hippocampus. Specifically, there are direct projections from the
trigeminal nucleus (activated by stimulation of the cornea and surrounding tissues)
to the relevant motor nuclei and indirect projections relaying via the brain stem
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
backward to the source, the “engram.” The fact that several motor nuclei showed the
same pattern of learning-induced activation argued against any plasticity unique
to one motor nucleus (e.g., the accessory sixth) or to processes of plasticity at
the level of the motor nuclei. Instead, it seemed most likely that the learning-
induced response in the motor nuclei was driven from a common central source.
The pattern of learning-induced increase in the activity of neurons in the motor
nuclei in the CS period in paired trials and on CS-alone trials (i.e., the neuronal
CR) was strikingly similar in form to the amplitude-time course of NM extension,
external eyelid closure, and of course the EMG recorded from the obicularis oculi
muscles. Indeed, an envelope of increased frequency of discharge of neurons in
the motor nuclei preceded in time and closely predicted the form of the behavioral
eyeblink-NM response (Figure 2). This close predictive parallel was most evident
with unit cluster recordings but was also true for single unit recordings in the motor
nuclei.
USE OF THE MOTOR NEURON NEURONAL MODEL Our initial logic—to work back-
ward from the motor nuclei—was not as simple as it might have seemed because of
the very large number of central brain systems that project to the motor and premo-
tor nuclei. So we adopted a different strategy. It was apparent that the amplitude-
time course form of the conditioned eyeblink-NM response closely paralleled and
followed the pattern of increased unit activity in the motor nuclei. So we focused
on this behavioral model of the learning-induced increase in neural activity in
the motor nuclei and used it as a template or model (Figure 2). The higher brain
systems that acted to generate and drive the learning-induced neuronal CR, the
“model” in the motor nuclei, must show the same pattern of learning-induced ac-
tivity as do the motor nuclei, and hence the amplitude-time course of the learned
eyeblink-NM response. Thus, we searched through higher brain systems looking
for learning-induced neuronal activity that correlated closely with and preceded in
time the form of the learned eyeblink-NM response. In essence, we mapped vir-
tually the entire brain of the rabbit in 1 mm steps, searching for neuronal models
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
8 THOMPSON
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
Figure 2 Histograms of unit cluster recordings from the ABD and simultaneous recording of
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
the eyeblink response (NM, the “third eyelid”) in classical conditioning in the rabbit summed
and averaged over eight trials before (A) and after (B) learning. First cursor onset of tone CS,
second cursor onset of corneal airpuff US, trace duration 750 msec, upward movement of
the NM trace indicates extension (eyelid closure). Note that the pattern of neural discharges
precedes and models the amplitude-time course of the behavioral response. ABD, abducens
motor nucleaus; CS, conditioned stimulus; NM, nictitating membrane; US, unconditioned
response. (From Cegavske et al. 1979.)
of the learned behavioral response (see, e.g., McCormick et al. 1983, Thompson
et al. 1976). We did not search blindly but rather system-by-system.
The basic assumption is that the neuronal sites of memory trace formation will
show a pattern of increased frequency of unit cluster and single-unit discharges
that precedes and closely predicts the pattern of response in the motor nuclei and
hence in the amplitude-time course of the behavioral CR. We felt this criterion
was preferable to the earlier ideas of shortest latency response, earliest response
over trials, or first site to show increased tonic responses. This assumption proved
to be the key that permitted us to localize a memory trace.
The Hippocampus
Because of its involvement in memory, we began with the hippocampus (Berger
et al. 1976). To our delight, both unit cluster recordings and single-unit responses
recorded from CA1 and CA3 showed the requisite learning-induced responses, i.e.,
pattern of increased discharge frequency that preceded in time (within trials) and
correlated virtually perfectly with the amplitude-time course of the behavioral CR
(Figure 3).
We showed that this neuronal model of a memory is generated by identified
pyramidal neurons (Berger & Thompson 1978b). Furthermore, the hippocampal
unit response began to develop in the US period within just a few trials of training
(a criterion by Olds et al. 1972) and moved into the CS period in close association
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
with the development of the behavioral CR (Berger & Thompson 1978a). It seemed
like a perfect candidate for the engram. In addition, electroencephalogram (EEG)
activity recorded from the hippocampus at the beginning of training predicted the
rate of learning (Berry & Thompson 1978). We characterized this learning-induced
response in the hippocampus in some detail (see Berger et al. 1986). Unfortunately,
as we noted above, animals could learn the basic delay-conditioned NM-eyeblink
response following hippocampal lesions (Schmaltz & Theios 1972).
This apparent enigma illustrates a fundamental limitation of using neuronal
recordings to localize memory traces. The fact that a neuronal model of the learned
response occurs at a given locus does not necessarily mean it originates there.
Indeed, the learning-induced neuronal model in the hippocampus, at least in the CS
period, is abolished by appropriate cerebellum lesions (Clark et al. 1984). Actually,
a number of loci in the brain exhibit the learning-induced neuronal model of the
learned behavioral response. I return to this issue below.
The breakthrough insofar as the hippocampus is concerned came in a study in
our laboratory by Paul Solomon and Donald Weisz using the trace-conditioning
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
10 THOMPSON
eyeblink conditioning if the trace interval is sufficiently long but not impaired at
all on delay conditioning (see McGlinchey-Berroth et al. 1997).
Clark & Squire (1998, 1999) made the striking observation that awareness of
the training contingencies in normal human subjects correlated highly with the
degree of learning of trace eyeblink conditioning. Recall that awareness is a key
defining property of declarative memory. They also showed that awareness played
no role in delay conditioning, and that expectancy of US occurrence influenced
trace but not delay conditioning (Clark & Squire 2000, Clark et al. 2001). They
conclude that delay and trace conditioning are fundamentally different phenomena,
with delay conditioning inducing nondeclarative or procedural memory and trace
conditioning inducing declarative memory. Hence, trace eyeblink conditioning
in rabbits would seem to provide a very elementary instantiation of declarative
memory in animals.
These strikingly parallel results of hippocampal lesions in rabbits and humans
for trace eyeblink conditioning suggest the possibility that a memory trace(s) may
develop in the hippocampus in trace conditioning, but do not prove it. Recall that
delay eyeblink conditioning results in the development of a pronounced neuronal
model of the learned response in the hippocampus (as does trace training).
Several lines of evidence support the view that localized changes do develop
in the hippocampus in eyeblink conditioning. Thus, the properties of increased
neuronal activity are strikingly similar to the properties of LTP (Berger et al. 1986,
Thompson 1997, Weisz et al. 1984), and induction of LTP in the hippocampus
can enhance eyeblink learning (Berger 1984). There is also a dramatic learning-
induced decrease in the after-hyperpolarization in pyramidal neurons in eyeblink
conditioning, most evident in trace conditioning, which leads to increased ex-
citability. This alteration is intrinsic to the neurons due to a decrease in one or more
calcium-dependent outward potassium currents (Disterhoft et al. 1986, Disterhoft
& McEchron 2000). There is also a dramatic increase in dendritic membrane-
associated protein kinase C after eyeblink conditioning (Olds et al. 1989). After
trace eyeblink conditioning there is a substantial increase in the number of multiple
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
circuitry from stimulus input to motor output in order to establish definitively that
the essential memory trace, e.g., for trace conditioning, develops and is stored,
albeit temporarily, in the hippocampus (see below). To date, not all the essential
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
circuitry has been identified (see Thompson & Kim 1996). Yet another remaining
puzzle is where the trace memories go after the hippocampus is no longer necessary.
12 THOMPSON
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
Figure 4 Neuronal model of learned eyeblink response recorded from the cerebellar in-
terpositus nucleus. Each graph shows nictitating membrane movement (top trace) and a
histogram of multiple unit activity (bottom trace) averaged and summed over 100 trials.
Animals that received explicitly unpaired presentations of the conditioning stimuli do not
develop altered patterns of neuronal activity (left column). Trained animals develop a neu-
ronal model of the learned behavior. Total trace duration 750 msec. (From McCormick &
Thompson 1984b.)
1985). In brief, the efferent CR pathway projects from the interpositus nucleus ip-
silateral to the trained eye, via the superior cerebellar peduncle, to the contralateral
magnocellular red nucleus and to the relevant motor nuclei ipsilateral to the trained
eye. The cerebellar interpositus lesion abolition of the eyeblink CR is strictly ip-
silateral and is due to damage to neuron somas, not fibers of passage. The inferior
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
They found significant activation in the cerebellar interpositus nucleus and several
loci in cerebellar cortex, in close agreement with our recording studies in the rabbit
cerebellum (Logan & Grafton 1995), again replicated in many other studies.
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
A point that is obvious from our studies but seems not to be widely understood
is that our results on the role of the cerebellum in classical conditioning apply to the
learning of any discrete movement: eyeblink, head turn, forelimb flexion, hind-
limb flexion, etc. (see Shinkman et al. 1996). Eyeblink conditioning is simply
a convenient response to measure. Our findings to date seem to have identified
perhaps the critical function of the cerebellum, namely the learning of discrete
skilled movements, a basic notion proposed in classic theories of the cerebellum
as a learning machine (see Albus 1971, Eccles 1977, Ito 1984, Marr 1969). Indeed,
our work constitutes a compelling verification of these theories.
Our data to this point strongly supported the hypothesis that the essential mem-
ory trace was formed and stored in the cerebellum, but did not prove it. Hence we
adapted use of methods of reversible inactivation to localize the memory trace.
The logic is straightforward. Having identified the essential memory trace circuit,
reversibly inactivate each key locus in the circuit during training. If this completely
prevents learning at a given locus, then this locus either conveys essential affer-
ent information to the memory trace or is the site of the memory trace. However,
if reversible inactivation of a given locus does not prevent learning at all, then
this locus is efferent from the memory trace. But remember that inactivation of
all these essential loci will completely prevent expression of the CR. We infused
muscimol for inactivation of neuron cell bodies—it acts on gamma amino butyric
acid (GABAA) receptors as an agonist and completely shuts down (hyperpolarizes)
the neurons for several hours, after which they fully recover. To inactivate axons
we infused tetrodotoxin (TTX) (see, e.g., Krupa et al. 1993; Krupa & Thompson
1995, 1997; Krupa et al. 1996; Thompson & Krupa 1994). David Lavond and his
students completed parallel studies using reversible cooling (e.g., Clark et al. 1992,
Clark & Lavond 1993).
Results are completely consistent and have since been replicated in other labora-
tories. In brief (see Figure 5) inactivation limited to the anterior interpositus nucleus
completely prevented learning. After removal of inactivation animals showed no
signs of learning; with subsequent training they learned normally as though they
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
14 THOMPSON
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
Figure 5 Highly simplified schematic of the essential memory trace circuit for delay clas-
sical conditioning of the eyeblink response to illustrate the use of reversible inactivation to
localize memory traces. Shading in a, b, and c indicate reversible inactivation of the key re-
gion of each structure during training using muscimol; d indicates inactivation of the axonal
pathway exiting from the cerebellum, the superior cerebellar peduncle, using tetrodotoxin.
Inactivation of the interpositus (c) completely prevents learning, but inactivation of the su-
perior peduncle (d), the red nucleus (b), and the motor nuclei (a) does not prevent learning
at all. (Modified from Thompson & Krupa 1994.)
had no prior training; there was no savings. In complete contrast, inactivation of the
superior peduncle (the immediate efferent projection from the interpositus/dentate
nuclei), the red nucleus, and the relevant motor nuclei, although completely pre-
venting expression of the CR, did not prevent learning at all. After removal of
the inactivation the animals had fully learned to asymptote. Thus, inactivation
localized to the anterior interpositus nucleus completely prevented learning but in-
activation of its immediate output pathway did not prevent learning at all. The fact
that after interpositus inactivation there was no savings argues strongly that no part
of the memory trace developed in structures afferent to the interpositus. Similarly,
the fact that inactivation of structures efferent from the interpositus did not prevent
learning at all argues that no part of the memory is formed in these structures.
I noted above that several loci in the brain exhibited the neuronal model of the
learned behavioral CR, e.g., trigeminal nuclear region, pontine nuclei, etc. In a
series of studies Lavond and associates (and we) showed that with inactivation of
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
the interpositus nucleus, all these models disappeared, i.e., they are all driven from
the interpositus (Bao et al. 2000, Lavond & Cartford 2000).
Because muscimol acts only on neuron cell bodies and not on axons, the in-
activation of the interpositus nucleus does not prevent normal activation of cere-
bellar cortex by the two major afferent systems, climbing fibers from the inferior
olive and mossy fibers from many sources. The fact that no learning at all oc-
curred with inactivation limited to the interpositus nucleus would seem to argue
against formation of memory traces in the cerebellar cortex. However, this inacti-
vation blocks the direct projections from the interpositus nucleus to the cerebellar
cortex.
When we first discovered the essential role of the cerebellum in eyeblink condi-
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
tioning I had hoped the memory traces would be formed and stored in the cerebellar
cortex. The cellular machinery in the cortex is vast (each Purkinje neuron receives
up to 200,000 synapses from granule neurons). However, we were never able to
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
16 THOMPSON
(Figure 5). It is clear that long-lasting changes in the critical neurons in the anterior
interpositus nucleus do develop. Thus, infusion of protein synthesis inhibitors in
this locus completely prevents learning (Bracha et al. 1998, G. Chen & Steinmetz
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
2000, Gomi et al. 1999). Further, training results in selective expression of a protein
kinase in this locus, KKIAMRE, an enzyme for the cell division cycle (Gomi et al.
1999). Pharmacological isolation of the interpositus from the cerebellar cortex re-
veals clear learning-induced increases in excitability of interpositus neurons (Bao
et al. 2002, Garcia & Mauk 1998). Perhaps most convincing, eyeblink conditioning
results in a dramatic and highly significant increase in the number of excitatory
synapses (but not inhibitory synapses) in the interpositus nucleus (Kleim et al.
2002).
CONCLUSION
The essential circuitry for classical conditioning of the eyeblink response is shown
in Figure 6, along with the site of memory trace formation in the interpositus
nucleus and a putative site of plasticity in the cerebellar cortical neurons. The nature
of the memory is defined by this circuit; the circuit is the memory. The CS activates
the sensory afferent pathways to the site(s) of trace storage in the cerebellum,
which activates the efferent pathways to the motor nuclei and the learned behavior.
The content of the memory, the conditioned eyeblink response, is completely
defined and completely predictable from the essential circuit.
The formal criteria developed by Richard Morris and associates to demonstrate
that a given set of phenomena establish what they term the “synaptic plasticity and
memory” (SPM) hypothesis are as follows (Martin et al. 2000):
Figure 6 Simplified schematic (most interneurons omitted) of the putative essential circuitry
for delay classical conditioning of eyeblink (and other discrete responses) learned with an
aversive US. (The sensory and motor nuclei activated depend of course on the nature of the
CS and US; the more central portions of the circuit appear to be general.) The reflex US-UR
pathway involves direct and indirect projection from the trigeminal nucleus to the motor nuclei
(for the eyeblink UR and CR, primarily accessory 6 and 7). The tone CS pathway projects
from auditory nuclei to the pontine nuclei and to the cerebellum as mossy fibers. The US
pathway includes projections from the trigeminal to the inferior olive and to the cerebellum
as climbing fibers. The CR pathway projects from the interpositus to the red nucleus and on
to premotor and motor nuclei. There is also a direct GABAergic inhibitory projection from
the interpositus to the inferior olive. Solid cell bodies and bar terminals indicate inhibitory
neurons; open cell bodies and fork terminals indicate excitatory neurons. Stars indicate sites
of plasticity based on current evidence. See text for details. (From Christian & Thompson
2003.) CR, conditioned response; CS, conditioned stimulus; UR, unconditioned response;
US, unconditioned stimulus.
18 THOMPSON
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Work described in this paper was supported in part by National Science Foundation
Grant IBN 92,15069, National Institutes of Aging Grant AG14751, a grant from
the Sankyo Company, and funds from the University of Southern California.
LITERATURE CITED
Albus JS. 1971. A theory of cerebellar function. eyeblink conditioning. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
Math Biosci. 10:25–61 USA 99:1592–97
Bao S, Chen L, Kim JJ, Thompson RF. 2002. Bao S, Chen L, Thompson RF. 2000. Learning-
Cerebellar cortical inhibition and classical and-cerebellum-dependent neuronal activity
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
in the lateral pontine nucleus. Behav. Neu- ent neuronal control of the reflex nictitating
rosci. 114:254–61 membrane response in the rabbit (Oryctola-
Bao S, Cheng EF, Davis JD, Gobeske KT, gus cuniculus). J. Comp. Physiol. Psychol.
Merzenich MM. 2003. Progressive degrada- 90:411–23
tion and subsequent refinement of acoustic Chapman PF, Steinmetz JE, Thompson RF.
representations in the adult auditory cortex. 1988. Classical conditioning does not occur
J. Neurosci. 23:10765–75 when direct stimulation of the red nucleus or
Berger TW. 1984. Long-term potentiation of cerebellar nuclei is the unconditioned stimu-
hippocampal synaptic transmission affects lus. Brain Res. 442:97–104
rate of behavioral learning. Science 224:627– Chen C, Kano M, Abeliovich A, Chen L, Bao
30 S, et al. 1995. Impaired motor coordination
Berger TW, Alger BE, Thompson RF. 1976. correlates with persistent multiple climbing
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
Neuronal substrate of classical condition- fiber innervation in PKCγ mutant mice. Cell
ing in the hippocampus. Science 192:483– 83:1233–42
85 Chen C, Thompson RF. 1995. Temporal speci-
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
Berger TW, Berry SD, Thompson RF. 1986. ficity of long-term depression in parallel
Role of the hippocampus in classical condi- fiber-Purkinje synapses in rat cerebellar slice.
tioning of aversive and appetitive behaviors. Learn. Mem. 2:185–98
In The Hippocampus, Vols. III and IV, ed. Chen G, Steinmetz JE. 2000. Microinfusion of
RL Isaacson, KH Pribram, pp. 203–39. New protein kinase inhibitor H7 in the cerebel-
York: Plenum lum impairs the acquisition but not retention
Berger TW, Thompson RF. 1978a. Neuronal of classical eyeblink conditioning in rabbits.
plasticity in the limbic system during clas- Brain Res. 856:193–201
sical conditioning of the rabbit nictitating Chen L, Bao S, Lockard JM, Kim JJ, Thompson
membrane response. I. The hippocampus. RF. 1996. Impaired classical eyeblink condi-
Brain Res. 145:323–46 tioning in cerebellar lesioned and Purkinje
Berger TW, Thompson RF. 1978b. Identifica- cell degeneration (pcd) mutant mice. J. Neu-
tion of pyramidal cells as the critical el- rosci. 16:2829–38
ements in hippocampal neuronal plasticity Chen L, Bao S, Thompson RF. 1999. Bi-
during learning. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA lateral lesions of the interpositus nucleus
75:1572–76 completely prevent eyeblink conditioning in
Berry SD, Thompson RF. 1978. Prediction of Purkinje cell degeneration mutant mice. Be-
learning rate from the hippocampal EEG. hav. Neurosci. 113:204–10
Science 200:1298–300 Christian KM, Poulos AM, Thompson RF.
Bracha V, Irwin KB, Webster ML, Wunder- 2002. Purkinje cell activity during classical
lich DA, Stachowiak MK, Bloedel JR. 1998. conditioning of the eyeblink reflex in rabbits.
Microinjections of anisomycin into the in- Soc. Neurosci. Abstr. 79.9
termediate cerebellum during learning affect Christian KM, Thompson RF. 2003. Neural
the acquisition of classically conditioned re- substrates of eyeblink conditioning: acqui-
sponses in the rabbit. Brain Res. 788:169–78 sition and retention. Learn. Mem. 11:427–55
Cegavske CF, Patterson MM, Thompson RF. Clark GA, McCormick DA, Lavond DG,
1979. Neuronal unit activity in the abducens Thompson RF. 1984. Effects of lesions of
nucleus during classical conditioning of the cerebellar nuclei on conditioned behavioral
nictitating membrane response in the rab- and hippocampal neuronal responses. Brain
bit Oryctolagus cuniculus. J. Comp. Physiol. Res. 291:125–36
Psychol. 93:595–609 Clark RE, Lavond DG. 1993. Reversible le-
Cegavske CF, Thompson RF, Patterson MM, sions of the red nucleus during acquisition
Gormezano I. 1976. Mechanisms of effer- and retention of a classically conditioned
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
20 THOMPSON
behavior in rabbits. Behav. Neurosci. 107: ory of learning in the cerebellar cortex. Brain
264–70 Res. 127:327–52
Clark RE, Manns JR, Squire LR. 2001. Trace Edeline JM, Weinberger NM. 1991. Subcortical
and delay eyeblink conditioning: contrasting adaptive filtering in the auditory system: as-
phenomena of declarative and nondeclarative sociative receptive field plasticity in the dor-
memory. Psychol. Sci. 12:304–8 sal medial geniculate body. Behav. Neurosci.
Clark RE, Squire LR. 1998. Classical condi- 105:154–75
tioning and brain systems: the role of aware- Ezzeddine Y, Glanzman DL. 2003. Prolonged
ness. Science 280:77–81 habituation of the gill-withdrawal reflex in
Clark RE, Squire LR. 1999. Human eyeblink Aplysia depends on protein synthesis, protein
classical conditioning: effects of manipulat- phosphatase activity, and postsynaptic gluta-
ing awareness of the stimulus contingencies. mate receptors. J. Neurosci. 23:9585–94
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
mechanisms of the corneal blinking reflex in Lavond DG, Cartford MC. 2000. Eyeblink
cats. Brain Res. 125:265–75 conditioning circuitry: tracing, lesion, and
Ito M. 1984. The Cerebellum and Neural Con- reversible lesion experiments. In Eyeblink
trol. New York: Raven Classical Conditioning: Animal Models, ed.
Ivkovich D, Thompson RF. 1997. Motor cortex DS Woodruff-Pak, JE Steinmetz, 2:51–80.
lesions do not affect learning or performance Boston, MA: Kluwer Acad.
of the eyeblink response in rabbits. Behav. Lavond DG, Hembree TL, Thompson RF. 1985.
Neurosci. 111:727–38 Effect of kainic acid lesions of the cerebellar
Kandel ER. 1975. The Cellular Basis of Behav- interpositus nucleus on eyelid conditioning
ior: An Introduction to Behavioral Neurobi- in the rabbit. Brain Res. 326:179–83
ology. San Francisco: Freeman Lavond DG, Kim JJ, Thompson RF. 1993.
Kandel ER, Spencer WA. 1968. Cellular neu- Mammalian brain substrates of aversive
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
Hippocampectomy impairs the memory Kanzawa SA. 1990. Lesions of the cerebellar
of recently, but not remotely, acquired interpositus nucleus abolish both nictitating
trace eyeblink conditioned responses. Behav. membrane and eyelid EMG conditioned re-
Neurosci. 109:195–203 sponses. Brain Res. 514:238–48
Kim JJ, Thompson RF. 1997. Cerebellar cir- Logan CG, Grafton ST. 1995. Functional
cuits and synaptic mechanisms involved in anatomy of human eyeblink conditioning
classical eyeblink conditioning. Trends Neu- determined with regional cerebral glucose
rosci. 20:177–81 metabolism and positron-emission tomogra-
Kleim JA, Freeman JH Jr, Bruneau R, Nolan phy. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 92:7500–4
BC, Cooper NR, Zook A, et al. 2002. Synapse Marr D. 1969. A theory of cerebellar cortex. J.
formation is associated with memory storage Physiol. 202:437–70
in the cerebellum. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Martin SJ, Grimwood PD, Morris RGM. 2000.
99:13228–31 Synaptic plasticity and memory: an evalua-
Krupa DJ, Thompson JK, Thompson RF. 1993. tion of the hypothesis. Annu. Rev. Neurosci.
Localization of a memory trace in the mam- 23:649–711
malian brain. Science 260:989–91 Mauk MD, Steinmetz JE, Thompson RF. 1986.
Krupa DJ, Thompson RF. 1995. Inactivation of Classical conditioning using stimulation of
the superior cerebellar peduncle blocks ex- the inferior olive as the unconditioned stim-
pression but not acquisition of the rabbit’s ulus. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 83:5349–53
classically conditioned eyeblink response. McCormick DA, Clark GA, Lavond DG,
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 92:5097–101 Thompson RF. 1982a. Initial localization of
Krupa DJ, Thompson RF. 1997. Reversible in- the memory trace for a basic form of learning.
activation of the cerebellar interpositus nu- Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 79:2731–42
cleus completely prevents acquisition of the McCormick DA, Lavond DG, Thompson RF.
classically conditioned eyeblink response. 1982b. Concomitant classical conditioning
Learn. Mem. 3:545–56 of the rabbit nictitating membrane and eye-
Krupa DJ, Weng J, Thompson RF. 1996. In- lid responses: correlations and implications.
activation of brainstem motor nuclei blocks Physiol. Behav. 28:769–75
expression but not acquisition of the rabbit’s McCormick DA, Lavond DG, Thompson RF.
classically conditioned eyeblink response. 1983. Neuronal responses of the rabbit
Behav. Neurosci. 110:219–27 brainstem during performance of the clas-
Lashley KS. 1950. In search of the engram. Soc. sically conditioned nictitating membrane
Exp. Biol. Symp. 4:454–82 (NM/eyelid response). Brain Res. 271:73–88
18 Nov 2004 11:52 AR AR231-PS56-01.tex AR231-PS56-01.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
22 THOMPSON
McCormick DA, Steinmetz JE, Thompson RF. (Oryctolagus cuniculus). J. Comp. Physiol.
1985. Lesions of the inferior olivary com- Psychol. 79:328–33
plex cause extinction of the classically con- Shibuki K, Gomi H, Chen L, Bao S, Kim JJ,
ditioned eyeblink response. Brain Res. 359: et al. 1996. Deficient cerebellar long-term de-
120–30 pression, impaired eyeblink conditioning and
McCormick DA, Thompson RF. 1984a. Cere- normal motor coordination in GFAP mutant
bellum: essential involvement in the classi- mice. Neuron 16:587–99
cally conditioned eyelid response. Science Shinkman PG, Swain RA, Thompson RF. 1996.
223:296–99 Classical conditioning with electrical stim-
McCormick DA, Thompson RF. 1984b. Neu- ulation of cerebellum as both conditioned
ronal responses of the rabbit cerebellum dur- and unconditioned stimulus. Behav. Neu-
ing acquisition and performance of a clas- rosci. 110:914–21
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
sically conditioned nictitating membrane- Shors TJ, Matzel LD. 1997. Long-term po-
eyelid response. J. Neurosci. 4:2811–22 tentiation: What’s learning got to do with
McGlinchey-Berroth R, Carrillo MC, Gabrieli it? Behav. Brain Sci. 20:597–614; discussion
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
has much to do with LTP. Behav. Brain Sci. sponse: I. Primary Field (AI). Behav. Neu-
20:632–33 rosci. 98:171–88
Thompson RF, Berger TW, Cegavske CF, Pat- Weisz DJ, Clark GA, Thompson RF. 1984.
terson MM, Roemer RA, et al. 1976. The Increased activity of dentate granule cells
search for the engram. Am. Psychol. 31:209– during nictitating membrane response condi-
27 tioning in rabbits. Behav. Brain Res. 12:145–
Thompson RF, Kim JJ. 1996. Memory systems 54
in the brain and localization of a memory. Wilson MA, Tonegawa S. 1997. Synaptic plas-
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 93:13438–44 ticity, place cells and spatial memory: study
Thompson RF, Krupa DJ. 1994. Organization with second generation knockouts. Trends
of memory traces in the mammalian brain. Neurosci. 20:102–6
Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 17:519–49 Woodruff-Pak DS, Lavond DG, Thompson RF.
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
Thompson RF, Patterson MM, Teyler TJ. 1972. 1985. Trace conditioning: abolished by cere-
Neurophysiology of learning. Annu. Rev. bellar nuclear lesions but not lateral cerebel-
Psychol. 23:73–104 lar cortex aspirations. Brain Res. 348:249–
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
CONTENTS
Frontispiece—Richard F. Thompson xviii
PREFATORY
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
vii
P1: JRX
December 8, 2004 12:13 Annual Reviews AR231-FM
viii CONTENTS
CONTENTS ix
INDEXES
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:1-23. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
ERRATA
An online log of corrections to Annual Review of Psychology chapters
may be found at http://psych.annualreviews.org/errata.shtml
18 Nov 2004 10:44 AR AR231-PS56-02.tex AR231-PS56-02.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
10.1146/annurev.psych.55.090902.141429
there have been challenges to this view in the physical sciences, where profoundly
indeterminate events have been identified at the quantum level, the presumption that
physical phenomena are fundamentally determinate seems to have defined modern be-
havioral science. Programs like those of the classical behaviorists, for example, were
explicitly anchored to a fully deterministic worldview, and this anchoring clearly in-
fluenced the experiments that those scientists chose to perform. Recent advances in the
psychological, social, and neural sciences, however, have caused a number of scholars
to begin to question the assumption that all of behavior can be regarded as fundamen-
tally deterministic in character. Although it is not yet clear whether the generative mech-
anisms for human and animal behavior will require a philosophically indeterminate
approach, it is clear that behavioral scientists of all kinds are beginning to engage the
issues of indeterminacy that plagued physics at the beginning of the twentieth century.
CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25
Determinism and the Philosophy of Science . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 26
Do Indeterminacies in the Physical World Matter for Behavioral
Scientists? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27
THE RISING TIDE OF APPARENT INDETERMINACY . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29
Indeterminacy in the Social Sciences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29
Empirical Measurements of Behavioral Indeterminacy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35
Reducing Uncertainty: Looking for Determinacy with Neurophysiology . . . . . . . . 40
Indeterminacy at the Cellular and Subcellular Levels . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46
THE CHALLENGE OF INDETERMINACY FOR BEHAVIORAL
SCIENCE . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 50
INTRODUCTION
Our modern view that the central function of scientific inquiry is to reduce uncer-
tainty emerged early in the scientific revolution that constituted the Enlightenment;
by the time of Galileo’s death (cf. Bacon 1620, Descartes 1637, Galilei 1630,
0066-4308/05/0203-0025$14.00 25
18 Nov 2004 10:44 AR AR231-PS56-02.tex AR231-PS56-02.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
26 GLIMCHER
Kepler 1618–1621) it was clear that improving the accuracy with which one could
predict future events as determinate processes would be a central feature of the
scientific method at both theoretical and empirical levels in the physical sciences.
Over the course of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, the early social sci-
ences emulated this trend, seeking to develop causal relationships in a testable and
determinate fashion (cf. Keynes 1936, Smith 1776). By the twentieth century, the
notion that scientific inquiry would reduce animal behavior to deterministic cer-
tainty had become a mainstream notion in psychological circles as well. Nowhere
is this clearer than in the work of Pavlov. As Pavlov put it in Conditioned Reflexes:
The physiologist must thus take his own path, where a trail has already been
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:25-56. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
blazed for him. Three hundred years ago Descartes evolved the idea of the
reflex. Starting from the assumption that animals behaved simply as machines,
he regarded every activity of the organism as a necessary reaction to some
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
external stimulus. . .. A bold attempt to apply the idea of the reflex to the
activities of the [cerebral] hemispheres was made by the Russian physiologist
I.M. Sechenov, on the basis of the knowledge available in his day of the
physiology of the central nervous system. In a pamphlet entitled “Reflexes of
the Brain,” published in Russia in 1863, he attempted to represent the activities
of the cerebral hemispheres as reflex—that is to say, as determined. (Pavlov
1927)
In the period that followed, Skinner and his students (cf. Skinner 1938) strength-
ened this notion, and psychologists as a group largely embraced the idea that a
complete psychological theory would be a determinate one. By studying the causal
relationships between environment, organism, and response, these scientists be-
gan the process of developing a predictive and testable theory of psychology.
The twentieth century witnessed a similar trend in the effective application of the
scientific method toward understanding the biological sources of behavior, and
as a result, saw the development of a powerful deterministic program for under-
standing biological systems. Charles Sherrington (1906), for example, applied this
programmatic approach to the physiological study of reflexes with great effect.
INDETERMINATE BEHAVIOR 27
heads-up. As Popper points out, this is not only an unverifiable theoretical claim,
but also an untestable one; my assertion predicts all possible empirical outcomes
and is thus unfalsifiable. Even more importantly, my theoretical claim predicts as
an experimental result all possible finite series of coin flips that could ever be ob-
served. If the coin is equally likely to land heads-up and tails-up, then any specific
series of heads and tails is equally likely, whether that be six heads in a row or six
flips that alternate between heads and tails. No formal prediction of any particu-
lar outcome is ever possible and for this reason Popper argued that probabilistic
claims about indeterminate processes were irremediably problematic. Indeed, in
his early writings Popper even used this to argue that the notion of a fundamentally
indeterminate universe is at base a nonscientific proposition.
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:25-56. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
In the 1920s and 1930s, however, the emerging discipline of quantum physics
raised an important challenge to this notion that had evolved during the Enlight-
enment and motivated much of Popper’s work. Based initially on the work of
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
Heisenberg and his colleagues (Heisenberg 1930, 1952), strong evidence arose
suggesting that several phenomena that occur at the atomic and subatomic scales
are, in fact, fundamentally indeterminate and thus could be described only proba-
bilistically. This was a critical challenge to the existing philosophy of science as
expressed by Popper because that philosophy argued that a theory of physics built
upon probability theory was unfalsifiable, perhaps even unscientific. Nevertheless,
the empirical evidence gathered during that period seemed to indicate unambigu-
ously that at a small enough scale of analysis, events occur that are fundamentally
indeterminate. This indicated that the philosophy of science, rather than the reality
of our physical universe, might have to change.
28 GLIMCHER
psychologists, and social scientists, he assured us, need not be concerned with
fundamental indeterminacy in the universe:
If it were not so, if we were organisms so sensitive that a single atom, or even
a few atoms, could make a perceptible impression on our senses—Heavens,
what would life be like! To stress one point: an organism of that kind would
most certainly not be capable of developing the kind of orderly thought which,
after passing through a long sequence of earlier stages, ultimately results in
forming, among many other ideas, the idea of an atom. (Schrodinger 1951)
and neurobiological domains that suggests that, at larger scales of analysis than
the one Schrodinger examined in What Is Life, living systems exhibit behavior
that is apparently indeterminate (cf. Hastie 2001, Schall 2004, Shafir & LeBoeuf
2002, Staddon & Cerutti 2003). At the largest scale of analysis, social scientists
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
working in areas such as the theory of games have begun to argue that for behavior
to be efficient under some circumstances, it must be irreducibly uncertain from the
point of view of other organisms and therefore must be studied with the tools of
probability theory. In principle, this raises critical problems for game theory. For all
of the reasons Popper identified, when game theory makes probabilistic predictions
it does so in a manner that is nonfalsifiable. Of course, if Schrodinger was correct,
the apparent indeterminacy of game theory presents only a temporary impediment
to scientific inquiry. A reductionist approach to human behavior during strategic
games would ultimately reveal the mechanisms that give rise to this apparent
indeterminacy and thus should ultimately yield a falsifiable determinate theory of
human behavior. Although contemporary game theory thus faces indeterminacy,
empirical science can hope to resolve this apparent indeterminacy by reduction.
Interestingly, however, psychologists working at a lower level of reduction than
social scientists have also begun to find evidence of apparent indeterminacy in
the systems they study (cf. Staddon & Cerruti 2003). Recently, psychologists
have begun the analysis of apparently stochastic patterns of individual responses
and have been able to demonstrate classes of individual behavior that appear to
be as fully random as can be measured. Indeterminacy, in the hands of these
psychologists, seems to be an apparent feature of the behavior of single humans
and animals. At a yet deeper level of reduction, neurobiologists have also begun
to gather evidence for the existence of apparently indeterminate processes within
the architecture of the mammalian brain (cf. Schall 2004). The patterns of action
potentials generated by individual neurons, for example, appear highly stochastic
for reasons that are not yet well understood.
Growing evidence that apparently indeterminate processes operate at social,
psychological, and even neurobiological levels are bringing behavioral scientists
face-to-face with the same philosophical and scientific issues faced by Popper,
Heisenberg, Schrodinger, and others in the last century. Can such theories be
scientific, or is calling a neural signal or a behavior a random process only an
excuse for ignorance? It may be that behavioral scientists will choose to assert as an
18 Nov 2004 10:44 AR AR231-PS56-02.tex AR231-PS56-02.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
INDETERMINATE BEHAVIOR 29
axiom that all of the physical phenomena we study are fundamentally determinate
in order to avoid these issues, but on the other hand such an assertion may force
us to neglect a growing body of compelling evidence.
study of human behavior. The classic economic theory of that period, for example,
rested on the foundation of a theory of determinate utility developed by Blaise
Pascal (1670, Arnauld & Nicole 1662) and Daniel Bernoulli (1738). This utility
theory argued that humans act predictably to maximize benefits and to minimize
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
costs, and that the costs and benefits of any action can be reliably computed. Pascal
had developed this basic logic in the seventeenth century, arguing that the “ex-
pected value” of an action was equal to the product of any possible gain or loss
incurred by that action and the likelihood of the gain or loss. Bernoulli had ex-
tended this notion with the observation that humans appear at an empirical level to
be more averse to risk than Pascal’s formulation predicts. Bernoulli’s conclusion
was that humans made decisions based on the product of a subjective estimate
of cost or benefit and the likelihood of that gain or loss, rather than based on an
objective measure of gains or losses. Because of the precise form of his hypoth-
esis, Bernoulli was able to show that this notion could successfully account for
the empirically observed aversion of humans to risk. Thus, the critical idea that
utility theory advanced was that one could compute the relative desirabilities of all
possible actions to a chooser and, except in the presumably rare case where two
actions have identical subjective desirabilities, one could then predict the actions
of a chooser with determinate precision. Building on this foundation, Adam Smith
(1776) argued that all economic actors could be seen as effectively trading off costs
and benefits to maximize gain in a complex marketplace. The prices of goods, for
example, were presumed to be set by the determinate interactions of supply and
demand curves that represented the aggregate subjective desirabilities and costs
of goods to consumers and producers. It was thus a central thesis of eighteenth-
and nineteenth-century economic theory that the rational process by which de-
sirability was assessed could be accurately modeled and that these models made
deterministic predictions about human behavior.
Importantly, the incorporation of likelihoods into expected utility theory al-
lowed the approach to make determinate predictions even when the environment
in which human decision makers operated was unpredictable. Choosers were as-
sumed to consider risk when they determined the desirability of an action, and the
theory explicitly and convincingly predicted that no feature of this environmental
uncertainty would be presumed to propagate into the behavior of the choosers.
The only time that utility theory predicted indeterminacy in behavior was when
18 Nov 2004 10:44 AR AR231-PS56-02.tex AR231-PS56-02.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
30 GLIMCHER
two or more mutually exclusive actions had precisely equal subjective desirabili-
ties, and the importance of that particular situation seemed limited to the classical
economists.
In the first half of the twentieth century, the theory of games developed by John
VonNeumann, Oskar Morgenstern, and John Nash directly challenged this deter-
minate approach (Nash 1950a,b, 1951; VonNeumann & Morgenstern 1944). Game
theory represented a deviation from the classical tradition specifically because it
proposed that when a rational chooser faces an intelligent and self-interested oppo-
nent, rather than a passive economic environment, situations could easily arise in
which the subjective desirabilities of two or more actions are driven toward precise
equality. The theory went on to make surprising and fundamentally indeterminate
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:25-56. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
predictions about how rational humans would behave under many conditions that
could be well described by game theory.
To understand this theoretical insight, consider two opponents repeatedly play-
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
ing the childhood game of rock-paper-scissors in which the loser pays the winner
$2 on a round won by playing paper and $1 on a round won by playing scissors or
rock. If the behavior of one’s opponent is unpredictable, any response can win, in
principle. Paper will beat a play of rock for $2, scissors will beat a play of paper
for $1, and rock will beat a play of scissors, again for $1. Classical utility theory
assumes that humans choose between actions by multiplicatively combining the
subjective value and likelihood of each outcome and then selecting the action with
the outcome that yields the highest expected utility. Assuming naively that one’s
opponent is equally likely to play rock, or paper, or scissors, the greater value of
winning with paper should lead all players to select paper deterministically on
each round. What VonNeumann recognized was that this assumption about the
behavior of one’s opponent simply could not be correct. A competitor who simply
selected scissors could reliably defeat any player who actually behaved in accord
with this strategy.
Game theory, as developed by VonNeumann & Morgenstern (1944), addresses
this limitation of classical utility theory by making the assumption that both players
are aware that they face an intelligent opponent who can anticipate their actions
and that both players will shape their behavior accordingly to minimize losses and
maximize gains. To accomplish this, players must take into account the potential
payoffs associated with each choice, as specified by classical utility theory, but
they must also consider how the actions of their opponent will influence those
payoffs. Consider again the situation in rock-paper-scissors. Winning with paper
yields twice as much money as winning with rock or scissors, but deterministically
playing paper leads to certain defeat. What VonNeumann & Morgenstern showed
was that under these conditions we can predict that a rational player will titrate risk
against gain and play paper two-thirds of the time, scissors one-sixth of the time,
and rock one-sixth of the time. Critically, however, he must avoid making his two-
thirds, one-sixth, one-sixth selections in a determinate fashion; for example, in a
repeated version of the game by playing paper, then scissors, then paper, then rock,
then paper, and then paper. Were his opponent to divine the determinate nature
18 Nov 2004 10:44 AR AR231-PS56-02.tex AR231-PS56-02.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
INDETERMINATE BEHAVIOR 31
of such a strategy (through observation, for example), then winning would again
become trivial for that opponent. He would only have to play scissors, then rock,
then scissors, then paper, then scissors, and then scissors to assure a consistent win.
The only way to avoid this trap is for a player to incorporate apparent indeterminacy
directly into his behavior. He must in essence flip a weighted coin on each round
to select between rock and paper and scissors. VonNeumann & Morgenstern were
well aware of the implications of this observation. It suggested that under some
conditions the study of economic choice would have to become a probabilistic
process. As they put it:
Consider now a participant in a social exchange economy. His problem has,
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:25-56. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
32 GLIMCHER
value] to Professor Moriarity [of] catching Sherlock Holmes [at], say 100.
[Alternatively, consider what happens if] Sherlock Holmes successfully es-
caped to Dover, while Moriarity stopped at Canterbury. This is Moriarity’s
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
1
Our result for e, n yields that Sherlock Holmes is as good as 48% dead when his train pulls
out from Victoria Station.
18 Nov 2004 10:44 AR AR231-PS56-02.tex AR231-PS56-02.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
INDETERMINATE BEHAVIOR 33
desirabilities emerge when the competitive interactions of the two players drive
them toward an equilibrium at which the two or more actions being mixed are of
equal desirability. What Nash argued was that mixed-strategy equilibriums emerge
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
from dynamic interactions between the players, which yield equal average desir-
abilities, and thus totally indeterminate patterns of behavioral choice. Classical
utility theory had presumed that situations in which two or more actions have
precisely equal subjective desirabilities would be encountered only rarely. Nash’s
insight was that not only are they encountered, but the dynamic interactions that
occur during strategic games actively create these situations of equal subjective
desirability.
From the point of view of indeterminacy, the critical insight that VonNeumann,
Morgenstern, and Nash offered was that indeterminacy is a requisite feature of
efficient behavior in a competitive world. That insight means either that humans
and animals appear indeterminate to each other under some conditions or they
behave inefficiently.
In 1982, the evolutionary biologist John Maynard Smith also engaged indeter-
minacy during strategic games, but from an evolutionary perspective. He argued
that any species involved in an internal competition for resources could be de-
scribed using game theory and that this mathematical formalism predicted that
organisms capable of producing apparently indeterminate behavior would be fa-
vored by natural selection.
Imagine, Maynard Smith proposed, a species of animals in which individuals
compete for access to territories that increase the number of young an individual
can produce. Individuals without territories produce a small number of young,
while individuals with territories produce a large number of young. Obviously,
under these conditions it is in the interest of individuals to obtain territories. Now
consider a situation in which there are more individuals than territories. In this
hypothetical species, territories change hands when an animal without a territory
“displays” to an animal with a territory, essentially threatening that individual for
control of the territory. In the hawk-dove game, as this competition has come to be
known, after such a display each animal must make a decision: whether to escalate
the conflict (to fight for the territory) or whether to retreat (give up the territory
without a fight). If one of the animals elects to escalate, behaving as a hawk, and
18 Nov 2004 10:44 AR AR231-PS56-02.tex AR231-PS56-02.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
34 GLIMCHER
one decides to retreat, behaving as a dove, then the hawk takes the territory. If both
animals elect to be doves, then one of them at random takes the territory. Finally,
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:25-56. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
if both animals elect to be hawks, then they fight, one sustains injuries that reduce
the number of young that individual can produce, and the other gains the territory.
Table 1 illustrates this simple game as a two-by-two matrix that specifies the costs
and benefits of all possible actions to each player.
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
What Maynard Smith realized at a mechanistic level was that each of these
values could be expressed in terms of evolutionary fitness, the gain in reproductive
success, that an individual achieves with each outcome. Gaining a territory confers
an increase in fitness, whereas sustaining an injury confers a decrease. Thus, if the
value of a territory is high and the magnitude of injury in a hawk versus hawk fight
is low, then animals that behave as hawks are more fit than those that behave as
doves. Under these conditions, Maynard Smith reasoned, the population will evolve
toward a single pure strategy equilibrium: All animals in the population will always
be hawks. Similarly, if the value of a territory is low and the magnitude of injury is
high, then all animals that behave as doves will produce more offspring, be more
fit, than animals that act as hawks. Under these conditions, the population should
converge on a pure strategy equilibrium of dove. If, however, the value of a territory
is high and the cost of an injury also is relatively high, then an interesting thing
happens. The only reproductively stable strategy for the animal and its offspring
is to behave sometimes as a hawk and sometimes as a dove. To be more specific,
a single dominant and unbeatable strategy emerges in a population playing the
hawk-dove game. The probability that on any given encounter an individual will
choose to behave as a hawk must be equal to the value of a territory divided by
the magnitude of the injury sustained in a hawk versus hawk conflict. Critically,
on each encounter individuals have to behave in an unpredictable fashion, never
allowing their opponent to know whether they will be a hawk or dove2. But across
many such encounters the only stable and unbeatable solution for the population
is for the probability of being a hawk to be equal to the value of a territory divided
by the cost of injury.
This theoretical analysis suggests that, at least from the point of view of
other individuals in this same species, evolution would drive behavior toward
2
Maynard Smith showed mathematically that a population of unpredictable individuals
would dominate a population in which separate individuals were committed at birth to
playing hawk or dove. For details of that proof, see (Smith 1982).
18 Nov 2004 10:44 AR AR231-PS56-02.tex AR231-PS56-02.sgm LaTeX2e(2002/01/18) P1: IKH
INDETERMINATE BEHAVIOR 35
36 GLIMCHER
these studies, Bakan (1960) asked humans to simulate the action of a random coin
flip: subjects were asked to make up a sequence of heads and tails that was fully
random in order. When Bakan analyzed the sequences generated by these subjects
they were found to be highly nonrandom despite the instructions that the subjects
received. Bakan found that the subjects tended to overproduce alternations between
heads and tails and to underproduce the occasional long runs of heads or tails that
would be predicted from a truly random process. In sum, the humans behaved in a
fairly determinate fashion, despite their instructions to do otherwise. Since 1960,
dozens of studies have replicated this basic result. When human subjects receive
a verbal instruction to produce a random sequence, they reliably fail. On the basis
of this evidence, many psychologists have concluded that humans lack the ability,
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:25-56. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
INDETERMINATE BEHAVIOR 37
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2005.56:25-56. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org
by Ball State University on 01/05/09. For personal use only.
Figure 1 Mean interresponse times (IRTs) from two replications of three experi-
mental conditions for a single pigeon (Blough 1966). The graph plots the frequency of
each IRT in half-second bins. A fully indeterminate process would produce points that
fall along straight lines in this space. (Reproduced with permission from Journal of
the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, copyright 1966, Society for the Experimental
Analysis of Behavior.)
The qualities which art critics first look for—the sure touch and
line of her modelling, the line composition and massing—are
especially apparent in The Windy Doorstep, in which Miss Eberle
touches the high-water mark of her more objective figures.
Here it will be more interesting to note the steps by which social
values have crept into her work.
First of all, her deep and instinctive love for children, and her
appreciation of human values, led her to select types that until
recently have been almost entirely disregarded.
To this keen observer and lover of human nature, the many years
of contact with this vivid, arduous East Side life—reinforced and
interpreted by constant reading and thinking—brought an ever-
increasing sense of social interrelation and interdependence. Jane
Addams’ books have, more than anything else, she says, helped to
clarify and mould her vision of the constructive part the sculptor may
play in social readjustment.
This growth of social consciousness has been reflected in her work.
Here she has turned from her more objective work to the graphic
interpretation of a social menace; and it is here, perhaps, that she
finds herself with surest touch. Her conception of white slavery is as
searching in its indictment, as ruthless, cruel and scourging as the
fact itself. One visitor who saw those haunting figures at the
International Exhibition said afterward:
“I was passing through that room of the exhibit when suddenly I
faced it—I could not go on. I had vaguely realized that this horrible
thing was in the world, but it had never touched me. I sat there for
perhaps an hour, thinking—and thinking—”
This woman was one who has led what is called a “sheltered”
existence, whose instinct would be to turn from any discussion or
writing on this subject. It is this thought-compelling quality in such
work which links it as a social force with, say, the dispassionate but
terrible report of the Chicago Vice Commission, or with Elizabeth
Robins’ My Little Sister.
It is interesting to know that Miss Eberle worked out the
composition for the White Slave four years ago; but the actual work
of modelling was done in the four weeks’ interval between the time
she was invited to send some of her work to last winter’s
International Art Exhibition and its opening. Until then, she had felt
that the time had perhaps not come when such a group would be
received except as an unwelcome effort toward sensationalism. It is
the first of several such interpretative subjects which she has in
mind, and which, if worked out in an equally sincere spirit, should be
big in social significance.
But after all is said, Miss Eberle consistently holds with the many
who believe that the first function of art is not didactic. Much of her
work besides that shown here is conceived in a spirit of sheer joy in
beauty of form and line, and one may go far to find a more
exquisitely modelled figure than that of the utterly submissive,
despairful child-victim of the white slaver. To use her own words:
“It is the beauty that is in the world today that appeals to me—not what may
have existed centuries ago in Greece. Though I love that, too, I will not shut my
eyes to the present and continue to echo the past. No matter how ugly the present
might be, I would rather live in it. After all, ugliness, as well as beauty is in the eyes
of the beholder,—and the present isn’t ugly at all, but full of a wonderful interest,
as a few of us are beginning to find out. We are trying to find new bottles for new
wine—Greek vases are about worn out.”
THE BATH HOUR
And so we may, as she asks, leave her work to make its own
eloquent plea for what Emerson calls “the eternal picture that nature
paints in the street, with moving men and children, beggars and fine
ladies, ... capped and based by heaven, earth and sea.”
“MY LITTLE SISTER”
In My Little Sister[10] Elizabeth Robins has let us hear a great cry out
of the depths—an actual human cry.
True, many snug, comfortable people, shaken for a moment out of
their apathy, dismiss it all carelessly, even contemptuously. Many
who are gripped to the heart as they read brush away the tears with a
sign of relief and say, “Well, it’s only a story.” But what a “story!”
It is told in a tense, staccato style which hurries the reader on—on
even through the idealistic descriptions of the English country and
the stretching moor, across which, in its little garden planted by
loving hands, stands the “dear home” of the officer’s gentle widow
and her two daughters, the Elder Sister in whose words the story is
told and whose name is never mentioned, and the Little Sister,
Bettina, all golden and bright, a creature so touchingly exquisite, so
like a flower.
Through the sweet, lightly sketched scenes of the childhood,
girlhood and dawning womanhood of these two fair young creatures
there is woven a dark thread of fear, dread, tragedy. Some experience
of brutality this dainty, tenderly devoted mother has had, an
experience which is never more than darkly hinted at. She forgets the
terror of it only in those happy memories that cluster about her
lover-husband. His body was brought home to her from a fatal tiger
hunt. Her only consolation in his loss, she tells the Elder Sister, was
that she knew that there are worse dangers than those of the jungle!
She had the joy of knowing that he died while all was “bright and
untarnished.”
The narrative hastens on, always with a hovering sense of doom.
The innocent, tender love stories of the sisters develop. They are but
seventeen and nineteen, but they are women. It is impossible to do
justice to the telling of this story, so we will pass to the main event,
the invitation of the London aunt, the failing health and fortune of
the mother, which nerves her to accept an offer that will separate her
from her children, and the almost happy bustle of preparation for the
first visit from home, and for that wonder of wonders—a London
season! The sinister part played by Madame Aurore, the little
London dressmaker who, while working for them in their country
home lays the plans that are to decoy them to their ruin in London, is
worked out with sure, rapid touch. Then comes the arrival in
London, the meeting of the girls by the pseudo “aunt,” who has been
dressed for the part by the aid of a photograph sent on to the
procurers by Madame Aurore. Then follows the terrible scene in the
house with the barred windows and the strange overwhelming scent,
the escape of the Elder Sister, the heart-breaking search for the
younger—the madness, the despair! One of the most pathetic things
in the book is the heart-broken young lover who traces Bettina from
London to “their house in Paris”—thence from one place to another
“always too late.” The merciful death of the mother, and the fixed
conviction, the subliminal inspiration, that comes toward the end to
the tortured brain of the elder sister that Bettina has found her
release in death, alleviate and spiritualize the misery of it all.
Now as to the truth of this tremendous story. I suppose that having
put the very soul of truth and reality into the narrative itself, having
written it from the very depths of her own pitying heart, the author
has not reckoned with the callous incredulity which the book often
meets, or she might well have added an introductory note in regard
to the actual facts in this case from real life. The story, she told me
subsequent to its publication, was absolutely true, but much softened
at many points. In the true story, for instance, the mother is not
dead, but is in a state of dementia on the continent, whither the
family have moved, being unable to endure England and its
memories.
Moreover, although Miss Robins’ experience in working for
women and the woman’s cause in England had brought to her
knowledge many life histories more unspeakable than this, after she
had finished this book she said to herself, “Now here is a story that I
know to be absolutely true, but how valuable is it to give to the world
an individual instance of this kind; how far can it be generalized?” To
test this she went, with that sincerity of spirit that characterizes all
she does, to a noted police justice in London and laid the story before
him, asking him what he would do if a person came to him with such
a story. He answered sadly, with no show of being at all roused by
anything unusual, that he would begin to take evidence immediately
and see what he could do about it. He added that the story was really
a commonplace.
Such is the reticence of the English press, and such is the stern
family pride concerning the “blot on the scutcheon,” and all those
traditions which grow out of the double moral standard whereby the
escapade of the son of the house can even be repeated lightly while
the slightest shadow on the name of the daughter is an unspeakable
disgrace, that no one knows how many tragedies of this kind are
hidden from sight in the records of numerous respectable families.
To satisfy herself more completely that the story was susceptible of
extensive application, Miss Robins took it to several London police
inspectors. No one for a moment stopped to doubt or question the
facts. The most horrible stories that the human mind can conceive
are old stories to them. When the Home Secretary was asked a
question on this subject in the House of Commons only a few weeks
ago, he answered that in London city alone, to his knowledge, there
had been reported fifty-three girls lost and never heard of within a
few months. Such facts as this explain the tragic intensity with which
the book is written.
Danger! Danger! Danger! That is the dominant note that sounds
throughout the narrative. How pathetically the mother’s poignant
fears contrast with her ineffectiveness. Ever this haunting danger,
whether mother and daughters are walking in the sunset, or planting
in the garden, or sitting by the hearth. What a wonderful picture
Miss Robins gives of the mother’s desperate dependence on the four
walls of her home—“Soon home, now, little girl, soon safe in our dear
home.” The danger signal of the night-bird’s note is introduced with
inimitable art—a subtle suggestion, even in those early days, of the
gray hawk whose shadow hovers over bright young lives.
The unutterable sadness of it all and the stern warning to mothers
that children’s homes are not just in four walls, but are in towns and
cities and nations! How utterly ineffectual seem an individual
mother’s effort for the safety of her child. How evident is it that a
mother’s care must have back of it power—power in council and
legislative hall. How strongly the lack of social sympathy is brought
out; the mother’s indifference to the great crying needs of the world.
This mother’s “place was the home,” and to what did all her negative
efforts avail in shutting the danger away from her cherished
daughters in a nation, in a world, which holds a traffic system of such
Machiavellian adroitness, a system which can afford, so great are its
profits, to reach into the inner recesses of a home, to work with
endless patience and resourcefulness and which can enlist on its side
such power that even the London police, perhaps the least corrupt in
the world, can answer evasively to the frantic cry, “Do you know such
a house?”—“We have a great many on the list, but not many such as
you describe;” and follow this statement with the maddening
inactivity which Miss Robins describes with vivid accuracy.
Her book is a terrific arraignment of the conditions which make
such a tragedy possible. Respectability and indifference are
personified scathingly in the monumental aunt, deaf to the world
voices of agony. All society is arraigned as the Elder Sister storms at
her aunt, “sitting massive, calm, with a power of inert resistance.”
Her bewildered answer to the mad cry for help,—“It isn’t possible,
this is England,”—sounds strangely natural to us. It is the burden of
so many recent New York editorials, “such things don’t happen”!—
and that in our land where the record of the Chicago Immigration
League tells of 1,700 girls between the railroad terminals of New
York and Chicago alone, reported lost in one year. Thus wails the
Elder Sister,—“So old and unbelieving, I felt she had looked on
unmoved at evil since the world began.... She rose, O! but slowly;—
slow, stiff and ponderous. I felt in her all the heaviness of
acquiescence since time began.”
Thus is the unbelievable apathy of society pictured! Thus Miss
Robins touches lightly, pitifully on the problem of a girl’s handicap in
the lack of preparation for life. What a picture she gives of the
sheltered girl—“Such a little thing, my not knowing how to
telephone, yet it might cost my mother her life.” Again this motive is
sounded when the daughter is begging her mother for knowledge
about her experiences, and the great gray danger—“It is not the kind
of thing you need ever know,” answers the mother with fatuous
finality.
Nor does she make our heart bleed for girlhood alone, but for
manhood, as that blood-curdling conversation, unparalleled in
literature, is gasped out between the Man and the Elder Sister as they
crouch in the shadow in that ghastly room in what he himself tells
her is “one of the most terrible houses in Europe.” Here we see
manhood disfigured, draggled beyond recognition, sitting in the dust
and ashes of a charnel house. How sodden the words fall from his
lips as depraved and perverted manhood defends itself. “This is a
commonplace in the world, in every capital of every nation on earth.
Bishops, old ladies, imagine you could alter these things.” “Human
nature—human nature,” muses the Elder Sister, “like the tolling of a
muffled bell.” Thus are the wickedest, most deadly of the world’s
platitudes on this subject uttered in this glaring scene of
abnormality, so that automatically they are given the lie.
The unbelieving will say, “But how is it possible that we do not
hear oftener of such cases?” Two elements especially conspire to
suppress such knowledge, both based on a false attitude towards
women. First the double standard of morals which holds men’s
purity so much lower than woman’s; second, the unjust attitude
towards women reflected in the press which is more likely to seize
upon a disappearance story in such a way as to make it reflect upon
the girls’ character rather than to acknowledge it a possible case of
abduction or white slavery.
As I write, Miss Robins sends me letters which she has recently
received from people interested in her book. One speaking of the
“awful traffic that is going on” tells how two girls, daughters of a
clergyman, have disappeared on their journey home from school and
have never been heard of since.
A letter from Miss Robins herself adds the following to her
remarks on her book. “Of all the official people I consulted, not one
of these experts doubted my story, and all had known similar cases.
We do not need to be told that the people to whom these things
happen, if they are refined and sensitive, are not eager to make
known their ruin. The natural impulse is to cover the horror from
every eye, even to deny it.”
“If you will consult the findings of your own commissions you will
see that in America ‘no girl of any class is safe.’”
I myself know at first hand an appalling number of cases—wives,
women of standing, college girls on journeys, young girls on their
way to boarding school, and working girls trapped and sold. In Rose
Livingston’s mail in the last few weeks have come heartrending
letters from parents for help in finding their lost daughters. A letter I
read yesterday from a doctor’s wife in Indiana was so terrible in the
lingering pathos with which the mother dwelt on the beauty and
sweetness of this lost daughter that I handed it back without reading
to the end.
In connection with Miss Robins’ letter, I offer the following
quotation from a paper by Stanley Finch of the Federal Department
of Justice where he speaks of the operation of the Federal White
Slave Traffic Act. “The number of complaints and prosecutions is
rapidly increasing.... Such crimes are more numerous than was first
believed possible.... It has become evident that thousands of
people[11] in practically all parts of the country were violating the
law.... [We found] girls were being transported in such interstate and
foreign commerce solely for the purpose of prostitution and were
being treated as mere articles of merchandise for the profit of those
who handled them and who were willing for the profit involved to
sacrifice both the bodies and the souls of their victims.... As we
extend this work [of federal prosecution] throughout the country the
awful interstate trade in women and girls for immoral purposes
which for years has been going on almost without let or hindrance,
has now become a very dangerous occupation.... The practices of
people engaged in the white slave traffic involves in a considerable
number of cases the actual physical detention of women and girls
against their will in this vilest form of involuntary servitude.”
Would that there were space to reinforce these remarks by New
York newspaper headlines dealing with such cases for the month of
March 15 to April 15.
How many fathers and mothers, brothers and sisters, friends and
lovers throughout this country, have lived through the agony
endured by the Elder Sister and the lover in Miss Robins’ book? That
which had been their greatest care and burden, the frail health of
Bettina, becomes the Elder Sister’s one comfort and hope. How many
a bereft father and mother today not only cling in anguish to that
hope, but desperately refuse to believe but that their girl is dead! And
with reliable students estimating the life of the white slave in this
country at five years, we know that many a flower-like highly
organized Little Sister has met mercifully her release in a few weeks
—a few months.
To those who know how considerable a factor in the whole
problem of the white slave traffic is the girl who is taken, not the girl
who goes, the girl who is under compulsion, not the girl who stays,
this book is a great contribution. The Survey printed some time
since a poster that has been used in this country from ocean to
ocean: “Danger! Mothers, beware! 60,000 innocent girls wanted to
take the place of 60,000 white slaves who will die this year in the
United States.” If My Little Sister will only make the truth of this
warning more real, more individual more poignant, then, in the pain-
soothing words that close this book, “She will not have suffered in
vain, and others will thank her too.”
Such a book is not merely a literary production, an exquisite work
of art: it is a high, sincere human service. Front a literary point of
view it is a great book. One is reminded of the Aeschylean definition
of tragedy: “That which purifies the heart through pity and terror.”
But this book not only reaches great tragic and dramatic heights, but
its subtle art is such that it blends with the tragedy in an almost eerie
way a lyric chord which echoes throughout, an unbroken strain of
hope and pity, of the essential dignity and sanity and rightness of life.
MOTHERHOOD
A. LEO WEIL
[Mr. Weil, one of the best known attorneys of western
Pennsylvania, is known outside of his profession as the militant
President of the Pittsburgh Voters’ League, the organization
which exposed the graft scandals of three years ago, sent
councilmen and bankers to jail and brought new and invigorating
spirit into Pittsburgh municipal life. Last Year the Voters’ League
successfully brought charges against the head of the Department
of Public Safety, and provoked a situation which led to the
creation of the Pittsburgh Morals Commission, a semi-official
body without governmental authority, and the cleaning-up of the
big numbered district.
It is on the basis of this experience that Mr. Weil reaches the
conclusions here set forth. He was a witness before the Wagner
commission which has recommended legislation now pending in
New York (with every prospect of passage) that will create a
separate public welfare department, largely divorce it from the
city administration and entrust its commissioners, appointed by
the mayor, with powers with respect to vice somewhat similar to
those held by the Board of Health with respect to sanitary
conditions.—Ed.]
2. It is now reported that the opponents of the law, which goes into effect
August 1, have started an effort to secure the 19,535 signatures necessary for a
petition to have the law submitted to a referendum vote.
3. Drawn from a case record of the New York Charity Organization Society.
5. Most of the quotations here given are taken from Songs from the Ghetto. By
Morris Rosenfeld. Translated into prose by Leo Wiener. Copeland & Day, Boston.
1898. Price $1.00.
7. Pendulum.
8. I work and work and work—without end; I am busy and busy and busy at all
times.
10. My Little Sister. By Elizabeth Robins. Dodd, Mead and Co. 344 pp. Price
$1.25. By mail of The Survey $1.37.
Our website is not just a platform for buying books, but a bridge
connecting readers to the timeless values of culture and wisdom. With
an elegant, user-friendly interface and an intelligent search system,
we are committed to providing a quick and convenient shopping
experience. Additionally, our special promotions and home delivery
services ensure that you save time and fully enjoy the joy of reading.
ebookfinal.com