An Analysis of Heterogeneous Utility Benchmarks in A Zero Return Environment
An Analysis of Heterogeneous Utility Benchmarks in A Zero Return Environment
by
Fred Viole
OVVO Financial Systems
[email protected]
And
David Nawrocki
Villanova University
Villanova School of Business
800 Lancaster Avenue
Villanova, PA 19085 USA
610-519-4323
[email protected]
An Analysis of Heterogeneous Utility Benchmarks in a Zero Return Environment
Abstract
The utility of an investor should be based on an acceptable loss in the loss region and a target
return in the gain region of a set of investment opportunities. The level of these benchmarks will
unveil an opportunity cost, break-even effect, or indifference when the return of an investment
equals zero. This condition has been arbitrarily assumed away for continuity and other
simplification purposes over the last few decades. Historical utility functions, those that are von
Neumann-Morgenstern compliant and not, are all constrained via a single target or reference
point. This single target restriction coupled with the arbitrary zero-return assumption has
ignored the important interpretation of this salient point on the utility curve as a proxy for the
2|Page
I. INTRODUCTION
We propose a utility function comprised of two autonomous functions: one function describing
the utility of losses and one function describing the utility of gains. Each of these autonomous
functions will be represented by a Markowitz Stochastic Dominance (MSD) Reverse-S curve per
Levy and Levy (2002). We expand the notion of a dual target or multiple reference points as
proposed in Lopes SP/A Theory (1987). Historically, with both von Neumann and Morgenstern
compliant functions and not, a commonality is the single reference point or target. Our proposal
better reflects the behavioral aspect of investing by incorporating an acceptable level of loss and
an upside target. Moreover, the dissection of variance into upper (UPM) and lower (LPM)
partial moments allows for the heterogeneous interpretations investors have towards
A valid utility function representing wealth over time should be governed by the simple axiom:
utility is equal to a change in wealth with respect to an initial wealth condition. The formula
We cannot go back to zero wealth and track utility from the first change in wealth such as a
birthday card from a relative or a summer job as a teen. We have to assume some level of initial
wealth. There is a subjective interpretation that individuals have towards a nominal level of
wealth (w). $1,000,000 may mean two different things to two different people. The amount of
3|Page
utility U(1,000,000) will be reflected by how close that wealth is to their Personal Consumption
Satiation level (PCS). Some individuals may feel content with that amount for a lifetime, while
others will simply see it as inadequate to provide satiation. Any differences in interpretations of
a given level of an identical wealth will solely be the result of different PCS benchmarks.
Example, if Investor A has a PCS level of $5,000,000 while Investor B has a PCS level of
$50,000,000 and they both have a level of wealth of $1,000,000, who is going to have a higher
utility U(w)? The $1,000,000 will simply mean more to Investor A as it represents a greater
Harry Markowitz notes in his 1952 work whereby he criticizes Friedman and Savages 1948
hypothesis,
Consider two men with wealth equal to C +1/2(D-C) (i.e., two men who are
midway between C and D). There is nothing these men would prefer, in the way
of a fair bet, rather than one in which the loser would fall to C and the winner
would rise to D. The amount of the bet would be (D C)/2 half the size of the
optimal lottery prize. At the flip of a coin the loser would become poor; the
winner, rich. Not only would such a fair bet be acceptable to them but none
would please them more.
We do not observe persons of middle income taking large symmetric bets. We
expect people to be repelled by such bets. If such a bet were made, it would
certainly be considered unusual and probably irrational.
Upon investigation of this scenario, it is clear that both individuals along with identical wealth
and risk profiles, will have identical symmetrical benchmarks for this wager (D, rich and C,
poor). Thus the benchmarks for this wager are a proxy for wealth and risk profiles. Whether the
two individuals are compelled to take such a wager is not relevant. This focuses our attention the
4|Page
Markowitz (1952) centers his utility curve on a level of wealth that he describes as customary
wealth, or current wealth U(w). We do not differ as our y-axis is U(w). Where we do differ is
that our y-axis is the meeting point for both our autonomous loss and gain functions. As
explained in Viole and Nawrocki (2011), an increased subjective wealth interpretation will be
reflected via a relatively smaller upside benchmark (UPM) relative to the UPM of a decreased
feeling of wealth, and a larger acceptable level of loss (LPM) compared to the LPM of decreased
feeling of wealth. Our curve is simply two Markowitz Stochastic Dominance (MSD) Reverse-S
curves that meet at customary wealth (See Levy and Levy, 2002); one curve is centered on an
upside target, and the other curve centered on an acceptable level of loss. Figure 1 illustrates the
MSD utility curve. In the aggregate wealth function, the upside benchmark is the PCS and the
lower benchmark is S, Roys (1952) safety first level of subsistence. Analysis of these
benchmarks associated with an investment U(x) will be a valid proxy for effects on U(w) in the
instance when x = 0 or no return. The MSD utility curve is also self-similar between the
aggregate utility of wealth and the utility of an individual investment. The difference between
aggregate and per investment utility is the x-axis on the aggregate wealth function U(w) is lower
bound by zero, whereby the x-axis on the investment function U(x) is lower bound by the
5|Page
Figure 1. Utility function consistent with Markowitz Stochastic Dominance
Our function builds on a utility function by Holthausen (1981) by making a few assumptions:
Assumption 1
The first assumption we make is that the investor has performed all of the necessary probability
computations they require to accept their targets. Whether they are ultimately right, yielding an
optimal solution is not of concern. This avoids placing a weight or probability variable to the
function which would only be additive to the inherent specification error, since that weight or
6|Page
Assumption 2
Our second assumption is there is no a priori reason to constrain subjective variance parameters.
One major result derived in the paper is that the t model is congruent
with a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function of the form
( )
() = { (2)
( )
x is the investment, t is the single target from which Holthausen derives both utilities, k is
the loss aversion parameter and is the curvature of the loss function, and is the
1
(, , ) = [ {0, , } ] (4)
=1
where Rx,z represents the returns of the investment x at time z, n is the degree of the LPM, q is the
degree of the UPM, h is the target for computing below target returns, and l is the target for
constant k to generate loss aversion. Rather the ratio of loss aversion exponent n and gain-
seeking exponent q will be able to replicate the loss aversion notion via n > q. With n and q > 1
7|Page
we can also compensate for above-target risk-seeking behavior that eludes Holthausen due to
1. For our model, n < q dictates overall risk seeking while supporting any nonlinear variance
interpretations.
Assumption 3
The third assumption we make is if that target or reference point equals zero, it is a fair bet. In
Markowitzs example of his dual targets, C and D, D C = 0 because they are symmetrical.
In Figure 2 below we have illustrated the complete function using Figure 1, the MSD Reverse-S
function. We have one MSD for gains, centered on an upside target and one MSD for losses,
centered on an acceptable level of loss. This function is for an individual investment, U(x).
In the aggregate utility of wealth U(w), the upside target is the PCS from which a MSD Reverse-
S function will be centered on. In the loss region, the lower target is Roys Safety first level, or
8|Page
U(w) or customary
wealth (dashed y-axis).
MSD Reverse-S
centered on upside
target
LOSSES
Upside target for
investment. PCS level
for aggregate wealth.
MSD Reverse-S
centered on
acceptable level of
loss
Figure 2. Superimposing 2 MSDs onto larger utility axes, revealing final shape of our
function, concave - convex concave convex.
9|Page
SINGLE BENCHMARK UPM / LPM UTILITY
( LPM (n,h,y) + UPM (n,y,x) + U(0)) If LPM (n,h,y) LPM (n,h,x) > 0
(UPM (q,l,x) + UPM (q,a,x) + U(0)) If UPM (q,l,x) UPM (q,l,a) > 0
10 | P a g e
The next section of the paper will place our proposed utility model into the literature. Then we
will explore the implications of the literature for our utility model. A short discussion,
conclusions, and currently observed zero return investor behavior will follow.
It should be noted that a more extensive review of the literature is provided in Appendix A. The
utility formula for an investment U(x) can be represented by the marginal change in wealth it
produces.
One would assume a zero return on an investment should produce no change in the aggregate
utility of wealth.
But, if we do not assume U(0) = 0 and isolate U(0) we have Equation 7 which illustrates that
11 | P a g e
Using Allais paradox (Allais, 1953), we can show that U(0) does not equal zero when there is a
certain outcome and can be zero, negative, or positive when there is no certain outcome.
SITUATION A SITUATION B
$1m with certainty 89% chance of $1m; 10% chance of $5m; 1% chance of nothing
U($0 M) < 0
SITUATION A SITUATION B
89% chance of nothing; 11% chance of $1m 90% chance of nothing; 10% chance of $5m
U($0 M) 0
12 | P a g e
What Allais decision examples isolate is the effect of the certainty equivalence and how it can
rationally distort any expected value calculation. Post et al. (2008) note the Dutch contestants
take a higher discount to expected value when the offer is a larger multiple of their annual
income in an analysis of the gameshow Deal or No Deal. This observed behavior is completely
consistent with risk aversion and a larger upside target of their local MSD for gains utility
decisions.
An examination of the historical utility functions that are compliant with von Neumann and
Morgenstern (1947) as well as Prospect Theory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979) will reveal what
the utility interpretation is for a zero-return situation. Table 2 summarizes these results derived
in Appendix A. One consistency to note is that there is a single target or reference point, and it
This target point (Fishburn, 1977 and Libby and Fishburn, 1977) or reference
point (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979) is often the zero-gain point, as in
Markowitzs (1952) case or in Swalms (1966) data, but it may be in the loss
region (for some wildcatters as in Grayson, 1960) or the gain region (Green,
1963).
13 | P a g e
a. FISHBURN (1977)
where x is the investment, t is the target, k is the loss aversion parameter and is the
curvature of the loss function.
where x0 is the investment, u0 is the utility function in the original data format, t is the
target, k1 and k2 are the gain-seeking parameters, k3 and k4 are the loss aversion
parameters.
c. HOLTHAUSEN (1981)
where x is the investment, t is the target, k is the loss aversion parameter and is the
curvature of the loss function, and is the curvature of the gain function.
14 | P a g e
d. PROSPECT THEORY KAHNEMAN AND TVERSKY (1979)
( )
(|) = {
( ) >
where x is the investment, RP is the reference point, is the loss aversion parameter and
is both the curvature of the loss function and the gain function.
15 | P a g e
III. U(0) INTERPRETATIONS AND FURTHER DEVELOPMENT
One possible explanation for the negative utility generated from a zero return is opportunity cost.
However, isnt the first goal of risk aversion not to lose? Furthermore, if a risk-averse investor's
first goal is to not lose, doesn't a zero return satisfy that goal? Then why would an investor
realize a negative utility from such an event? Opportunity cost would be more aligned with a
risk-seeking investor. A risk-averse investor should exhibit a form of relief or positive utility
from a zero return, consistent with a break-even effect. Markowitz (2010) notes this notion,
Because not buying the ticket has a utility U(0) = 1. The logic behind this observation is
"In general, any outcome can be assigned utility equal to zero, any better outcome
can be assigned utility equal to one. On a utility curve, such as that in Figure 1
for example, the level of return with zero utility and the (higher) level of return
with unit utility can be chosen arbitrarily. The zero and unit of the utility scale,
therefore, is a matter of convention and convenience.
It is shown in the footnote that, once the zero and unit of the utility scale are
chosen, the rest of the utility curve follows from the individual's preferences. No
more points may be arbitrarily selected without affecting the preferences
represented by the curve."
The single target or reference point is one major hindrance in reflecting a level of wealth. By
identifying an acceptable level of loss and an upside target (akin to C and D per Markowitz,
1952, or something as temporal as a stop loss and a limit order investors typically use), we avoid
this hindrance and are able to let the individual preferences of the function generate both
negative and positive levels of utility for a zero return under different wealth benchmark
configurations, rather than arbitrarily set the wealth benchmark at zero or one.
16 | P a g e
1. SYMMETRICAL BENCHMARKS
For a zero return x = 0, this situation would infer that there would be no UPM or LPM.
When
LPM(n,h,x) = 0 and UPM (q,l,x) = 0
Then our utility function reduces to,
U(0) = LPM(n,h,y) + UPM(q,l,a).
If y (acceptable level of loss) = a (upside return target), h (target to compute lower partial
moment from) = l (target to compute upper partial moment from) and n (loss aversion exponent)
= q (risk-seeking exponent) (symmetrical benchmarks from the same target [does not have to be
0 as for nominal gains and losses]; indifference loss exponent ratio) then, U(0) = 0.
80
60
Upside
Target
40
20 Acceptable
level of loss
Lower Partial
UTILITY
Moment
0
Upper Partial
Moment
-20
-40
-60
-80
0
8
-8
-6
-4
-2
LOSSES GAINS
17 | P a g e
The symmetrical inflection points at benchmarks y and a (C and D respectively per Markowitz
1952), intersects the y-axis, utility, at 0. This symmetrical benchmark setup represents a fair bet
The local investment U(0) = 0 or no change in wealth from the investment, will not affect the
aggregate level of overall utility. This makes sense considering a zero return and indifference of
the investor.
18 | P a g e
2. ASYMMETRICAL BENCHMARKS: INCREASED WEALTH
If y > a, h = l and n = q (asymmetrical benchmarks from the same target; indifference loss
The LPM will be larger than the UPM generating a negative utility from a zero return reflecting
the opportunity cost. This is a function of the asymmetrical benchmarks identified with an
No change in wealth from a zero return lowers the aggregate utility of overall wealth due to the
100
80
60
Upside
40
Target
20 Acceptable
Lower Partial
level of loss
UTILITY
Moment
0 Upper Partial
Moment
-20
-40
-60
-80
0
8
-8
-6
-4
-2
LOSSES GAINS
Figure 5. Upside target < acceptable level of loss. Asymmetrical benchmarks reflecting
increased wealth.
19 | P a g e
This opportunity cost can be viewed as the intersection of the y-axis at a negative utility point for
the loss function. The amount of the discontinuity at U(0) equals opportunity cost when the
acceptable level of loss is greater than the upside target. The opportunity cost is also additive, it
20 | P a g e
3. ASYMMETRICAL BENCHMARKS: DECREASED WEALTH
If a > y, h = l, and n = q (asymmetrical benchmarks from the same target; indifference loss
The UPM will be larger than the LPM generating a positive utility from a zero return reflecting
the relief a less wealthy individual experiences from a break-even effect as shown in a decreased
A no change in wealth raises the aggregate utility of overall wealth due to the break-even effect
of that investment.
80
Upside
60 Target
40 Acceptable
level of loss
20
Lower Partial
Moment
UTILITY
0
Upper Partial
Moment
-20
-40
-60
-80
-100
0
8
-8
-6
-4
-2
LOSSES GAINS
Figure 6. Upside target > acceptable level of loss. Asymmetrical benchmarks reflecting
decreased wealth.
21 | P a g e
This break-even effect can be viewed as the intersection of the y-axis at a positive utility point
for the gain function. The amount of the discontinuity at U(0) = break-even effect when the
acceptable level of loss is less than the upside target. The break-even effect is also additive, it is
One need only identify the notion of risk seeking with gains to provide an argument for
convexity of gain functions, originally proposed by Markowitz (1952). In order to not violate
the St. Petersburg Paradox, this convexity was ultimately concave to put a boundary on the y-
axis. We avoid the paradox by putting a boundary on the x-axis, by assuming there is some finite
level of wealth that can be ascribed to an asset. On the upside, the ultimate utility boundary is
the total amount of monetary assets available in circulation, while the downside boundary is zero
wealth or bankruptcy. Since utils are subjective units of measure, convexity of gains is less of a
concern than forcing concavity in a bid to address an absurd prior assumption of infinite
monetary resources.
Concavity of gains is also used to reinforce the notion of risk aversion. However, we are also
able to demonstrate overall risk aversion, not by concavity, but multiple other methods. First, the
ratio of the loss-seeking exponent versus the gain-seeking exponent (n:q) will be greater than one
for a risk-averse investor. Second, the associated benchmarks as described earlier will be shifted
to reflect this aversion, as noted in Figure 7 (in Appendix A) from Viole and Nawrocki (2011).
This flexibility and asymmetry is far superior to the rigidity of historical functions when being
22 | P a g e
Another example of human behavior that confounds historical functions is philanthropy. In this
sense, the utility derived from helping others is intangible. This intangible utility is also better
To the first point, the evidence we reviewed is quite supportive: Happier people
give more and giving makes people happier, such that happiness and giving may
operate in a positive feedback loop (with happier people giving more, getting
happier, and giving even more) (Anik, Aknin, Norton and Dunn, 2009).
We note how the function is discontinuous under any asymmetry of benchmarks. This
continuous curve along the y-axis. To properly reflect a break-even effect (positive utility for a
zero return); the continuous function would have to be shifted upwards to intersect the y-axis at
this positive point. The unintended consequence from this action is positive utility readings from
losses, amplified by the amount of break-even effect and underlying curve characteristics.
Under no circumstances could a nominal loss be viewed as a positive utility generator in our
function. The discontinuity at one specific point, zero, ensures this critical notion is upheld with
our loss function upper bound by zero and our gain function lower bound by zero.
Fishburn and Kochenberger (1979) note a similar discontinuity at U(0) with their two-piece von
Finally, we note that P+ and E+ have a limiting form that is discontinuous at the
origin with U(0) = 0 and U(x) = k for all x > 0. This arises from P+ when a1 = k
and a2 goes to zero, and from E+ when b1 = k and b2 goes to infinity.
23 | P a g e
IV. CONCLUSIONS
How can a zero change in wealth offer different utility values? The intransitive nature of a utility
observation at time t means that even if Xt = Xt-1 they can have wildly different interpretations
due to the shift in either a UPM or LPM benchmark. Post et al. (2008) note this,
The specification of the subjective reference point (or the underlying set of
expectations) and how it varies during the game is crucial for our analysis, as it
determines whether outcomes enter as a gain or a loss in the value function and
with what magnitude.
Fishburn and Kochenberger (1979) also note the influence of a target point,
We have identified how the heterogeneous benchmarks drive U(w) and we have noted how
they are influenced by the individuals subjective wealth interpretation. In a zero return scenario
we can examine how the benchmarks reflect this investment result, either as indifferent, an
One important distinction is that the lower upside benchmark (UPM) / larger acceptable level of
loss (LPM) can capture risk seeking from a less wealthy individual, essentially emulating a
emulating targets and acceptable levels of loss from someone wealthier, forcing them to be
bigger risk seekers than their wealth level would rationally infer. Thus, knowing the initial
wealth level cannot provide the insight to the risk profile that the benchmarks reveal.
24 | P a g e
Only in the instance of a fair bet does U(0) = 0. Under any asymmetry, the utility realized from a
zero return will be negative (representing an opportunity cost) or positive (representing a break-
even effect). This information cannot be derived from a level of wealth (w), it is only under an
inspection of the benchmarks associated with that level of wealth and a zero return that we can
U(wt-1) U(w)
Opportunity Cost
LPM Conditional Values
( LPM (n,h,x) LPM (n,y,x) + U(0)) If LPM (n,h,x) LPM (n,h,y) > 0
( LPM (n,h,y) + UPM (n,y,x) + U(0)) If LPM (n,h,y) LPM (n,h,x) > 0
(UPM (q,l,x) + UPM (q,a,x) + U(0)) If UPM (q,l,x) UPM (q,l,a) > 0
Anecdotally, we are currently witnessing this break-even effect phenomenon with individual
participant cash deposits at banks yielding zero. Furthermore, we are witnessing the same
actions by the banks themselves with their record deposits of excess reserves at the Federal
Reserve yielding zero. Thus it can be inferred that the aggregated target or reference point these
participants are using for this investment is negative, generating a positive utility; since their
actions are clearly maximizing their expected utility. This is fully consistent with a risk-averse,
decreased feeling of wealth for an investment generating the positive utility break-even effect for
25 | P a g e
REFERENCES
Allais, P.M. (1953). Le Comportement de LHomme Rationnel Devant Le Risque: Critique des
Postulats et Axiomes de LEcole Americaine. Econometrica, v21(4), 503-546.
Anik, L., L. Aknin, M. Norton, and E. Dunn. (2009). Feeling Good About Giving: The
Benefits and Costs of Self-Interested Charitable Behavior, Available at SSRN:
http://ssrn.com/abstract=1444831 .
Fishburn, Peter C. (1977). "Mean-Risk Analysis With Risk Associated With Below-Target
Returns." American Economic Review, v67(2), 116-126.
Fishburn, Peter C. and Gary A. Kochenberger. (1979). Two-Piece von Neumann-Morgenstern
Utility Functions. Decision Sciences, v10, 503-518.
Grayson, C.J. (1960). Decisions Under Uncertainty: Drilling Decisions by Oil and Gas
Operators. Cambridge, Mass.: Graduate School of Business, Harvard University.
Green, P.E. (1963). Risk Attitudes and Chemical Investment Decisions. Chemical
Engineering Progress, v59(1) (January 1963), 35-40.
Holthausen, D. M. (1981). "A Risk-Return Model With Risk And Return Measured As
Deviations From a Target Return." American Economic Review, v71(1), 182-188.
Kahneman, D., and A. Tversky. (1979). "Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision Making
under Risk." Econometrica, 47, 263-291.
Levy, Moshe and Haim Levy. (2002). Prospect Theory: Much Ado About Nothing.
Management Science, v48(10), 1334-1349.
Libby, R., and P.C. Fishburn. (1977). Behavioral Models of Risk Taking in Business Decisions:
A Survey and Evaluation. Journal of Accounting Research, v15(Autumn 1977), 272-292.
Lopes, L. L. (1987). Between hope and fear: The psychology of risk. Advances in
Experimental Social Psychology, 20, 255-295.
Markowitz, H. (1952). The Utility of Wealth." Journal of Political Economy, 60, 151-158.
Markowitz, H. (1959). Portfolio Selection: Efficient Diversification of Investments.
Markowitz, H. (2010). Porfolio Theory: As I Still See It. Annual Review of Financial
Economics, v2, 1-41.
Post, T., M. Van den Assem, G. Baltussen, and R. Thaler. (2008). Deal or No Deal? Decision
Making under Risk in a Large-Payoff Game Show. American Economic Review, v98(1),
(March 2008), 38-71.
Roy, A. D. (1952). "Safety-First and the Holding of Assets." Econometrica, 20, 431-449.
26 | P a g e
Swalm, R. D. (1966). Utility Theory Insights into Risk Taking. Harvard Business Review,
v47 (November-December 1966), 123-136.
Viole, Fred, and David Nawrocki . (2011). The Utility of Wealth in an Upper and Lower Partial
Moment Fabric. Journal of Investing, v20(2), (Summer 2011), 58-85.
Von Neumann, J., and O. Morgenstern. (1947). Theory of Games and Economic Behavior,
Second Edition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
27 | P a g e
APPENDIX A: U(0) RESULTS FOR HISTORICAL UTILITY FUNCTIONS
A 0 return will then generate a negative utility with a more negative result for the more risk-
averse investor (higher k). U(0) < 0 for all t > 0.
28 | P a g e
Fishburn 0 Return and a 0 Target
U(x) = x for all x t
U(x) = x k (t x) for all x t
U(0) = 0
If t= 0 and x = 0 then both utilities are valid. Thus U(0) = 0. t = 0 however, infers a fair bet that
would be unusual and probably irrational for the investor.
29 | P a g e
A.2 FISHBURN AND KOCHENBERGER (1979)
U(x0) = u0 + u(k1(x0 t))/k2 for all x0 t
U(x0) = u0 u(k3(t x0))/k4 for all x0 t
Fishburn and Kochenberger (1979) force U(0) = 0 and explain the rationale as follows:
The restriction of U(0) = 0, or U(t) = u0, limits the goodness of fit, since it forces
the function to pass through the indicated point. Better overall fits could be
obtained by not requiring U(0) to equal zero for example, by using cx + d
instead of cx for the linear fits but the U(0) = 0 constraint for all functions above
and below target ensures the continuity of each two-piece utility function at the
target. Continuity at t could also be ensured without forcing u(0) to equal zero,
but best two-piece fits with the forms used here would require a simultaneous
below-above fit. One might also fit a single function through all the data points
(e.g., a function that can have both convex and concave segments). We did not do
this, however, since we felt that the separately fit pieces were adequate to
examine the issues raised in the introduction.
30 | P a g e
A.3 HOLTHAUSEN (1981)
U(x) = (x t) for all x t
U(x) = k(t x) for all x t
A 0 return will then generate a negative utility with a more negative result for the more risk-
averse investor (higher k). U(0) < 0 for all t > 0. This is consistent with Fishburn (1977) and
Holthausens goal of consistency (1981), The purpose of this paper is to present a risk-return
model that has many of the same attributes as Fishburns model, but one in which the utility
function for above-target outcomes need not be linear.
A 0 return will generate a positive utility for all levels of . U(0) > 0 for all t < 0.
31 | P a g e
Holthausen 0 Return and a 0 Target
U(x) = (x t) for all x t
U(x) = k(t x) for all x t
If t= 0 and x = 0 then both utilities are valid. Thus U(0) = 0. t = 0, however, infers a fair bet that
would be unusual and probably irrational for the investor.
Holthausen (1981) handles U(0) only when x = t, not in the context of a U(0) when x t.
One major result derived in the paper is that the t model is congruent
with a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function of the form
( )
() = {
( )
32 | P a g e
A.4 PROSPECT THEORY Kahneman and Tversky (1979)
( )
(|) = {
( ) >
A 0 return will then generate a negative utility with a more negative result for the more risk-
averse investor (higher ). U(0) < 0 for all RP > 0.
Only in the loss function can x = RP = 0. Thus U(0) = 0 under a fair bet scenario for Prospect
Theory as well.
33 | P a g e
WEALTH EFFECT ON SINGULARITY UTILITY
80
60
40
20
0
UTILITY
-20
-40
-60
-80
-100
7
7
6.5
5.5
4.5
3.5
2.5
1.5
0.5
0.5
1.5
2.5
3.5
4.5
5.5
6.5
LOSSES GAINS
Figure 7. Increased wealth effect on singularity utility model
As overall wealth increases (blue function), LPM and UPM will shift left representing an
increased ability / propensity to gamble house money effect, reducing the certainty
equivalence for UPM. Downside tolerances are also increased highlighting the effect of
accumulated wealth on the investor's core subsistence level.
A decreased overall wealth (red function) will shift LPM and UPM to the right, illustrating the
increased effect of any losses to a poorer individual as it is closer to encroaching upon their basic
necessities (Roy's, 1952 subsistence level S) as well as the increased amount to reach personal
consumption satiation (PCS).
34 | P a g e