Koopman Koreanmorphologyjuly 04
Koopman Koreanmorphologyjuly 04
1. Introduction.
In Korean and Japanese Morphology from a lexical perspective, Sells (1995) argues against the
view that complex words in Japanese or Korean like (1b) are derived from the underlying
b. C c. CP
3 3
T C TP C
3 to 3 to
Neg T DP 3
3 katta Mary-ga NegP T
V Neg 3 katta
oyag ana VP Neg
4 ana
oyog
Sells establishes that the complex word in (1b) does not contain any pronounced arguments of V,
and argues against the syntactic view in (1), on the grounds that it leads to expectations that are
not met. In particular, if the inflectional morphemes are heads, they should behave as heads: they
should not be transparent for selection, and they should determine the category of the complex
word. Sells shows that certain inflectional morphemes are transparent for locality of selection,
and that the leftmost element in Korean and Japanese ‘words’ shows head-like behavior in that it
determines the categorical feature of the complex word. Sells concludes that the properties of
these words should not receive a syntactic treatment (as Sells states ‘it is the lack of structural
similarity between the morphology and the syntax that is striking’ (p. 320) ). Sells outlines a
1
lexicalist account for the data which takes the templatic nature of the morphology as basic (in
particular, quite different syntactic elements can occupy the same slot in a template). Strictly
morphological principles regulate the flow of information within the word, a task normally
performed by X-bar theory or the theory of Projection. Sells’ account remains sketchy, and I will
not address it here: rather I will concentrate on Sells’ arguments against the syntactic view that
words are build in the syntax, and develop a syntactic account which yields a parsimonious
account of the properties of “morphological units”: neither templatic morphology nor special
morphological principles are necessary. The properties of morphological words follow from
regular syntactic principles, (the theory of projection, agreement and movement), in conjunction
with (idiosyncratic) phonological properties of the affixes. I will agree with Sells that the
syntactic structure in (1c) does not underly the inflected words, and that the words are not derived
by head movenent: instead, I will pursue the idea that the complex words in question are derived
This reply is organized as follows. Section 2 discusses the basic surface constituency of Korean
(and Japanese) sentences in very general terms. I will make the basic case for phrasal (remnant)
movement, based on the phrasal affix nature of the affixes (Yoon 1994, among others) and
ellipsis (Otani and Whitman 1991), and show how this view reconciles the two mutually
incompatible analyses found in the literature (the V movement approach (Otani and Whitman
1991, Koizumi, 1995, 2000) and the V-in-situ approach (Yoon, 1994, Fukui and Sakai 2003).
This analysis undermines the evidence for an underlying OV order. Section 3 spells out some of
the relevant syntactic assumptions in which this reply is couched, and lays out what we should
expect to find. Section 4 turns to the particular cases Sells discusses, motivates syntactic analyses
for them, going beyond Sells discussions. Section 5 extends the analysis to other problems of
Korean morphosyntax, including the relative ordering of the focus particle man ‘only’, and the
structural case markers, and two types of subject agreement in Korean, honorific agreement and
2
plural agreement. Section 6 turns to a discussion of the interaction between word structure and
2. Surface constituency.
Let us start with a brief discussion of the surface constituency of a Korean (and Japanese)
sentence, paying particular attention to the position of the verb and the behavior of inflectional
morphology. In a simple OV sentence in Korean, the verb does not form a surface constituent
with any of its overt arguments, as Sells shows with phonological arguments. This can also be
shown by the placement of short negation an, which is (minimally) adjoined to VP (Whitman
‘I didn’t drive’
Korean and Japanese are agglutinative languages, with the order of morphemes reflecting the
syntactic hierarchy. These morphemes are phrasal affixes (Yoon 1994), which allow their
None of the arguments given in Chomsky (1970) for a lexical treatment apply, nor is there any
empirical evidence for affix hopping, or Marantz’s PF operation of Merger (Marantz 1988, Halle
and Marantz 1993). Thus, inflectional morphemes spell out the corresponding syntactic head
positions.
3
Since the verb and the inflectional morphemes form a phonological constituent, the question
arises if this surface phonological constituent is formed pre-spell out or not. Some linguists argue
the V remains in-situ in the syntax, and forms a constituent after ‘rebracketing’ or Marantz’s
‘Merger’ in the phonology (Yoon 1994, Fukui and Saka 2003), others argue the V raises overtly
pre spell-out on the basis of ellipsis and coordination (Otani and Whitman 1991, Koizumi 2000).
Otani and Whitman (1991) argue that the null object construction in Japanese and Korean should
be analyzed as VP ellipsis, with the verb outside the elided constituent and therefore pronounced.
Although Hoji (1995) shows that there are problems with this analysis concerning the
interpretation of null objects, elliptical answers to yes-no questions (McCloskey 1991) provide
further independent evidence that V and affixes are outside the elided constituent.
4
(9) Hai, ik-ase-ta
Under the reasonable hypothesis that we are dealing with an elided constituent, it follows that the
verb must be outside the elided constituent when ellipsis applies, i.e. the surface position of the
verb must be the result of pre-spell-out movement, consistent with (1) and Sells arguments.
Furthermore, since the elided constituent can contain high adjuncts, the verb must have raised
high into the clausal structure, at least to the polarity head Sigma (Laka, 1991).
This raises the question how the verb gets there. A head movement account runs into the problem
that inflectional morphemes behave like phrasal affixes: this is unexpected, since adjoined heads
in general do not show phrasal characteristics ((*to [[red]and [white]]en, *[[use] and [destroy]]-
ed 2). We thus need an account that reconciles the phrasal affix nature with overt syntactic
movement, and that is what phrasal movement to Spec achieves, as we can see in English for
example, where phrasal affixes follow their dependents in Spec (John’s brother, I’ll go etc), and
allow their dependents to be coordinated: ([John and Mary]’s brothers, [John and Mary]’ll go.
The verb then must be within a phrasal constituent attracted to the Spec of the affix:
This analysis reconciles the two competing syntactic analyses for Korean and Japanese: the V is
in-situ (Yoon 1995, Fukui and Saka 2003), since it is in the VP. And the V appears to have
moved (Koizumi (1995, 2000), Otani and Whitman (1991)), because the (remnant) phrase that
contains it has undergone movement to Spec, ending up in a Spec position high up in the clause. 3
Note that (10) undermines the basic evidence that Japanese and Korean are head final languages
underlyingly, since this apparent head complement structure is in fact a surface Spec head
5
complements of V must have moved leftward, either individually, or as a remnant constituent
(Whitman 2003, Hagstrom, 2003) regardless of the issue whether the verb is underlying head
final or head initial. The difference between a traditional head final analysis and a Kaynian
antisymmetric one thus becomes minimal. The remaining discussion in this paper is cast in terms
of antisymmetry: as I will show the merged head complement order surfaces in certain instances,
How can the phrasal movement approach explain the properties of complex words in Korean and
Japanese Sells that describes? Let us briefly examine the expectations and predictions of the
3.1. Specifiers
Specifiers are to the left of heads, and attract phrases. Phrases in Spec can be attracted to higher
Spec positions, as is the case with NP-movement, and successive cyclic wh-movement.
(11) a. Johni seems Johni to be Johni likely Johni to Johni become Johni an artist
Given the phrasal movement view, we expect to find similar cases in morphology. Thus, with H1
merged higher than H2 (H1>H2) , we should find cases that result in the linear order XP H1 H2
(12) H1P
3
XP 3
H1 H2P
3
XP 3
H2
linear order: XP H1 H2
6
Importantly, the linear order is the same as the order of merger: H1 is merged higher than H2,
takes H2P as a righthand sister, and precedes H2 at spell-out. Notice that the linear order in this
derivation does not “mirror” the syntactic hierarchy, in the sense that the inner affix is not merged
closer to X than the outer affix. In this sense, the example in (12) violates Baker’s Mirror
Principle (Baker 1985). As I will show, the configuration in (12) surfaces in some cases in
Japanese and Korean, thus revealing the head initial merged structure, even though the
morphology of Korean and Japanese strongly mirrors the syntactic hierarchy in (H1>H2>XP is
3.2. Heads.
Heads, regardless of whether they are functional or lexical, project and determine the category
and properties of their projection. Thus, the category of a tensed verb is T, not V. It is widely
assumed that heads select for their complements, and satisfy selection under first merge. Heads
impose restrictions on their Spec as well, and I refer to this as Spec selection: the EPP feature is a
particular instance of Spec selection. Phrasal affixes can combine an EPP feature with a further
phonological requirement: thus a phrasal affix can attract some particular phrase to its Spec,
where its EPP feature is satisfied. If that phrase undergoes further movement, it can be stranded,
provided the phrasal affix can lean on some element within its phonological phrase. This will
yield the restricted and very local types of movements of (12) above.
Attracted elements in Spec positions find themselves in the canonical pied-piping triggering
7
Koopman (1996) and Koopman and Szabolsci (2000) propose that ‘percolation’ results from
cyclic applications of Spec head agreement4. Agreement copies5 some feature from a Spec onto
the head. If a head H acquires a feature through agreement, the HP will carry that feature, by
If complex words are formed by phrasal movement, similar instances of pied-piping and
agreement are expected: in particular some property of a phrase in an embedded Spec should be
(14) H1P<x>
3
H2P<x> 3
3 H1<x>
XP 3
H2 <x>
linear order: 3 2 1
Pied-piping and agreement will account for Sells’ observation that the leftmost element displays
head like behavior in Japanese and Korean. Section 5 extends agreement and pied-piping to other
In recent work, Sportiche (1998, 2000 class lectures, 2001) has argued for a strict enforcement of
The Principle of Locality of Selection: selection must be satisfied in a strictly local relation.
The wh-phrase is selected by V, but is not in a local configuration with its selector at spell-out.
Local selection of course holds pre-movement, i.e. there is a stage in the derivation in which the
selector and selectee are in a local configuration. Note that the wh-C also “selects” for a +wh
8
phrase. This selection, commonly referred to as the EPP property, is locally satisfied after wh-
movement.
As Sportiche shows, strictly enforcing the principle of locality of selection has far reaching
implications for syntax. For example, if V selects for NP (and not for DP) as Sportiche argues, the
standard view that V merges with DP cannot be correct. Instead V must merge with NP first, in
accordance with locality of selection, and D attracts NP through movement, i.e. D’s selection for
(16) D [V NP]
Sportiche is led to the view in (16) on the basis of reconstruction (Sportiche 1999)6. The Principle
of Locality of selection provides the rationale for why that state of affairs must hold. This view
converges with Kayne’s proposals that many traditional constituents are not constituents, but are
remnants within a larger (remnant) constituent formed by attraction and movement (Kayne 2000,
2003). The Principle of Locality of Selection accounts for Sells’ cases of violations of locality of
selection (section 4). It forces particular analyses, and makes further predictions, that can be
empirically tested.
Sells presents two types of arguments against what he calls the syntactic view of morphology, i.e.
the view that “morphological structures and syntactic structures are governed by the same set of
principles and constraints p. 320”. The first type is based on violations of locality of selection.
Rightmost inflectional affixes in general do not yield violations of locality of selection, and
therefore do not behave as heads are expected to behave. The second type of argument shows that
the leftmost element must be relevant for selection in certain cases, and thus shows unexpected
head-like behavior. Somewhat unrelated to the above, Sells argues against universal hierarchies,
9
4.1. Selection before movement
Sells points out that there is a very general and systematic problem with locality of selection, and
illustrates this with the following general example, where a delimiting particle kkaci and the
focus marker nun intervene between the verb and the dative suffix selected by the verb:
As Sells points out, locality of selection is systematically violated in this type of example, a well-
known problem that arises with the incorporation of functional heads in syntactic structures
(Grimshaw 1991). Sells argues that this problem would not occur if the inflectional particles were
this problem: these particles are heads indeed, but at the point in the derivation where selection is
locally satisfied, they have not been merged yet. They are merged at a later point in the
derivation, and attract the focused constituent to their Spec (Kayne 1998). A simplified derivation
for (17) illustrates how this type of analysis works. Other cases of selection before movement are
discussed in section 4.2. We start the derivation at the point where the arguments have been
merged. The structure is simplified, and only considers the indirect object, V, T, and Topic (nun).
Arguably, selection of V by P is satisfied at the point of merger in (18a). The movements in (18a)
(18c) and (18d) are forced by locality of selection, with selection satisfied after movement
(‘remerge’). The step in (18b) creates the remnant PP necessary for (18e) and looks exactly like
10
Kayne’s (1998, 2000) VP-movement to WP8. Müller (2000) argues that this movement is
motivated by the Principle of Shape Conservation (Williams 2003) (V>O), and hence this step is
not expected to take place in surface OV languages. If the derivation above is on the right track,
however, even in a rigid OV languages this step must be crucially involved in deriving a remnant
constituent that contains PP, so at to allow the “remnant VP ” to raise high into the structure, and
The delimiting particles kkaci ‘even, up to’ and man ‘only’ can either precede or follow the P
(John Whitman, personal communication). Nun must be final, pointing to higher merger of nun.
There are in principle two options for analyzing the variable order in the adopted syntactic
framework. Either the relative order of merger between P and man/kkaci is free, in which case the
two linear orders reflect two different hierarchies, in accordance with the Mirror Principle:
Or the order of merger is fixed man/kkaci> P, and the derivation is responsible for the different
11
choose b. or c:
Coordination supports (21) as the only option. All and only the expected patterns of coordination
are attested given the analysis in (21). The coordination pattern predicted by (20b) is excluded:
This surface string is not derivable from (21), since the DP and kkaci do not form a constituent.
b. [DP&DP] P kkaci
Therefore, the unique hierarchy (21) (kkaci>P) underlies the linear orders. This is in accordance
with general principles of clausal structure, which force modifiers of Ps, or Focus to be merged in
12
a higher region than dative P (hence the principled unavailability of the merged order P>focus).
The fact that P can follow kkaci follows from phrasal movement from the Spec position and
Sells presents complementizer selection as an example where local selection in word structure is
interrupted. Korean has different types of non-tensed verb endings, and their distribution is
determined by selecting verbs. Sells, following Cho and Sells 1995, glosses these as Comp1,
Comp2, Comp3, etc. I will gloss them by their spell-out forms, and return to their distribution in
4.5. I follow Sells and analyze ahn as a negative auxiliary (Sells:305) selecting for a clausal
Inflectional elements can intervene between C and the selecting V, leading to apparent non-local
selection:
read-e-only-FOC try-PAST-DECL
The violation of locality is not an argument against the syntactic account under consideration.
Indeed, the Principle of Locality of Selection forces an account where selection is satisfied
locally before movement to higher merged heads takes place, i.e. local selection of the C by the
verb try must precede merger of man and movement to the specifier of man:
“VP”(read) moves to -e which (spec-selects) for a small constituent that I will simply abbreviate
as “VP” (it is at least as big as VoiceP (see section 4.4. ). -e is locally selected by try. In order to
13
make this derivation precise, and examine further predictions, an additional piece of information
is important. As Sells (1998) shows, VP-e obligatorily forms a complex verb with try. This can
be shown by short negation an which must precede the verbal complex, and negates try (hence
Verbal complexes can become quite big, and resemble Hungarian or West Germanic verbal
complexes, with each verb carrying its own inflectional morphology (Koopman and Szabolcsi
2000):
Verbal nouns do not form a surface complex verb, even though these form a tight unit with the
light verb:
Thus, V-e forms a surface constituent that does not contain the phonological form of its selectee,
i.e. it is either an incorporated head, or, rather, anticipating the fact that it can undergo further
phrasal movement, a phrasal remnant. Koopman and Szabolcsi (2000) propose that there is a
universal set of complex verb formators, which must always enter into a local relation with a
small clause predicate (a constituent slightly larger than VP, called VP+). Complex verb
formation is achieved in the following configuration, which transparently fits the Korean verbal
14
In this configuration ‘try’ checks what it needs for complex verb formation (VP+) , and what it
needs morphologically (-e) under first merge (try > -e) . VP(+) movement to –e is forced, because
of the nature of the phrasal affix –e which is very specific about the category that it needs to
attach to. VP+ will pied-pipe –e to the position where a complex verb with ‘try’ is formed,
(32) VP+try
3
eP 3
3 try
VP+read t
ilk e
eP must be a remnant, i.e. arguments and modifiers of this constituent must precede the short
negation an which modifies try. (see Koopman and Szabolcsi for general discussion of
We are now ready to return to Sells’ observation that man (‘only’) can intervene between
the –e constituent and the selecting verb (26). This follows from the hierarchy man>
VP+> try >-e>read, complex verb formation and phrasal movement of the focused
constituent to man. As the reader can check all selectional relations are locally satisfied
15
(34) manP
3
eP 3
3 man VP+try
VP+read t 3
ilk e eP VP
6 3
ilk-e V
try
4.3. Interactions between Focus (man), short negation (an) and verbal complexes.
Next, we consider further predictions given the hierarchies in (27) and (35b):
As a first step, we establish the relative order of merger between man and an. The following
example shows that man ‘only’ scopes over an (Neg) in simple clausal structures, establishing the
‘I did everything but driving’ ‘It is only driving that I didn’t do’ (only>neg)
‘* It not the case that I did only driving and nothing else’ (*neg>only )
Since the focused predicate ilk-e raises to Spec, man (37), it should precede an, and scope over
negation:
16
read-e only not try-PAST-DECL
These data fall out from the underlying the hierarchy of merger, and phrasal movements.
Complex verb formation is obligatory. Certain inflectional morphemes are allowed within verbal
compounding, because they are locally selected by the complex verb formator, and their
selectional properties are satisfied locally before the complex verb is formed. Other inflectional
morphemes are not allowed within the verbal complex (-man, -nun) because these can only be
merged at a later point in the derivation accordance with universal principles that guide the make-
Finally, scope is determined by the hierarchy of merger, which determines the location of the
Sells second type of argument is based on cases where the leftmost element shows head-like
behavior, and is the element which an outside selector needs access to. Sells illustrates this with
(39) a. tabe- te
eat- GER
17
c. tabe-naku-te (Adjectival gerund)
eat Neg-GER
Only the verbal gerunds (39a, b) can be selected by a V like iota ‘to put/to prepare for some
The category of the gerund must be determined by the V/A that it contains, which is merged
lower than the negative copula. This configuration parallels the well-known case of pied-piping
where a feature embedded in a specifier is able to satisfy an outside selector, i.e. this is a case
where selection is not satisfied at the point of merger, but after movement, through spec head
agreement in category. Agreement in category has a phonological reflex: the spell-out of Neg and
the copula covaries with the A/V features in its Spec, as does the form of the Formal level affix.
This leads minimally to the following structures and derivations, with agreement indicated:
18
b. Adjectival gerund
teP<+A>
3
Neg.cop<+A> t
3 te<+A>
AP 3
2 naku<+A>
4 t
tabe A
Cyclic application of Spec head agreement for category and projection carry the categorical
feature up to the gerund, thus allowing the verb to satisfy its selection of the gerund locally.
Agreement in category has as effect that the leftmost category appears to determine the category
of the constituent.
Sells argues that selection has to look deep into a constituent for the form and ordering of the
inflectional morpheme that indicates speech level in Japanese. Interestingly, this selection is also
The formal speech level desu occurs with A, but not with V:
b. aka-katta-desu
The formal speech level mas- occurs with verbs, but not with As. Furthermore, mas- precedes,
b. *tabe-ta- masi
19
eat- PAST-FORMAL
The dependency of the form of speech level on category (desu with AP, mas with VP), is
analyzable in two ways under the syntactic view: selection is satisfied under first merge, or
The hierarchical order of merger would surface because of Spec extraction, the mirror order
a’ AP katta AP to Spec T
It seems to me there is a strong bias for (46). Formal speech level is in complementary
distribution with Force/mood markers, and restricted to root contexts. This suggests Formal is
located at the root level, higher than T. If correct, it must be explained why VP must extract from
TP in (46a), but AP cannot do so. In Koopman and Szabolcsi 2000, and Koopman 2002 this is
achieved by means of so-called complexity filters, which care about the structure at spell-out.
Only phrases of a certain size, category and phonological shape (i.e. with V spelled out) “ fit” in
20
Spec, masi, where size is determined by the most deeply embedded spelled-out element. This is
(47) Complexity filter on Spec, masi: overt material in V cannot be more deeply embedded
than:
3
3 3
3 masi
V
VP-ta is simply too big to fit into the Spec, masi, as the following structure shows, where TP
(48) 3*
TP 3
3 masi
VP 3
3 ta
3
V
Hence the obligatory stranding of T in (46a). Spec-extraction is a way to keep the representations
that the phonology accesses small. Note that this presupposes that phonological spell out must
directly access the hierarchical syntactic structure. The form of Formal speech level covaries
with the category in Spec: this is an overt reflection of Spec head agreement (in category), as
argued in 3.2.1.13 If this analysis is correct, we have identified another case of Spec extraction
within the Japanese “word”, where the merged order surfaces because of Spec extraction.
Sells argues against the syntactic view in part because it presupposes universal hierarchies, or
principles that determine the underlying order of merger, a view he assumes to be problematic.
The verbal (and nominal) morphology of Korean is usually presented as a template, in which
there are a number of morphological slots available after the verb or the noun. Different non-
21
finite verb endings (his C1, C2, C3, C4)) appear to occupy these slots, even though they have
nothing in common with the other elements that can occupy these slots:
Thus, C1 appears in the same slot as Honorific, and can only follow a verbal root, C2 appears in
the same slot as Tense, and can only be preceded by a Honorific suffix, C3 by Honorific and
Tense, and C4 by Honorific, Tense and Mood, etc. This, Sells argues, is exactly what one expects
under a theoretical approach that includes morphological templates, but not under a view that
includes syntactic hierarchies, since this would not allow a unique location of C. Under a
templatic view, all slots should be able to be filled: elements that fill a particular slot do not have
to form a natural class: there is no reason to find a unique position for C in Korean, nor is there
any a-priori reason to assume C and honorific cannot occupy the same slot.
The syntactic view in fact does not lead one to expect a unique syntactic position for a non-finite
verb ending or a subordinator (i.e. C), as much as we don’t expect English, to, -ing, for, that, etc
to occupy exactly the same syntactic position (i.e. to be merged at the same height), or English –
ing to be mergeable in a unique position in the hierarchy: as is well-known –ing can be merged at
different heights in the hierarchy, leading to different types of –ing clauses, with different
distributional properties. Even if the different Cs were all merged in the same position, the
patterns in (49) would still be precisely what one expects to find under a syntactic view:
individual heads can select for different pieces of the hierarchy, thus C1 selects for VoiceP/VP as
a EPP property, C2 for a constituent that includes Agrhon, C3 for TP etc. Since these Cs are final,
selection must minimally be satisfied after movement to their Spec. This is the only way in which
22
the syntactic view can derive the appearance that elements that do not form natural classes seem
to occupy the same slot. Sells further takes the ordering facts discussed in the previous section as
That different linear orders can be derived from a single underlying hierarchy, is not problematic,
but expected under the syntactic view, as we have shown in the previous sections. Finally,
evidence for underlying hierarchies, or principles that underly clausal hierarchies seems even
stronger now than at the time when Sells published his article (Cinque 1999, Rizzi 1997, 2000,
Pollock and Poletto 2003, Hallman 1998, Koopman and Szabolcsi 2000, Julien 2002, Williams
In order to show that the independently needed syntactic mechanisms introduced so far account
for further properties of Korean morphology. In 5.1, I argue that the surprising position of
structural case markers in Korean is due to very local movement stranding the case markers. In
5.2. and 5.3, I argue that honorific agreement and plural agreement should be analyzed as cases
of agreement triggered under pied-piping, and stranding, in the case of plural agreement..
The structural case markers, i/ka (nom), ul (acc), and uy (genitive), follow man ‘only’, as well as
a number of other particles, (kkaci ‘even’, mace ‘even’, cocha ‘even’, pakkey ‘only’), which are
23
in complementary distribution). Case markers occupy a position quite distinct from Ps, which
The question arises how a structural Case marker can follow DP externally merged material like
focus. The type of analysis that can be provided is clear: either the merged order is
locality of selection. Focus >Nom is expected, given the general layering conception of
hierarchies: nominative belongs to the TP level, and Focus to the CP level. In similar vain, we
expect Focus> Acc>DP14 and Focus> Gen in the DP domain. We illustrate the derivation based
on Focus> Casenom:
A DP is attracted to Spec, Nom satisfying local selection by the Case head, and further extracts
to Spec, Focus, if focused. The resulting phase is send off to phonology, and the nominative head
is incorporated into the phonological phrase and spelled out as i or ka depending on the
phonological properties of the preceding segment. Under this analysis, focus and Case surface in
the merged head initial order, not in the mirrored order. Coordination provides independent
support for Focus>Case. Neither man nor i can be repeated under coordination, but DPs can.
24
c. *Swuni man- i hako/kwa Cheslwu man- i ………..
The hierarchy Nom> Focus (man) > DP also allows a syntactic derivation, provided we find some
way to turn DP-man into a remnant constituent before it moves on to Focus. However, it wrongly
predicts coordination under nominative to be available (52c), and it goes against the idea that
The honorific suffix follows the verbal ‘root’ and precedes Tense. It cooccurs with a structural
subject that is marked [+honorific] and is thus a particular instance of subject agreement.
Under standard approaches to agreement, the constituent triggering honorific agreement is either
in a Spec head relation with the relevant Agr head at some point, or locally c-commanded by it
(under Agree). The discussion in section 4.3. offers another possibility: agreement could be
triggered under pied-piping (as argued for independently in Koopman 2003). This may find
further support by the ability of an honorific possessors to trigger honorific agreement, without
evidence for overt possessor raising. (Sells 1995, fnt. 21, citing Hon 1991:12):
25
(54) [Sensayng-nim-uy son-i ] khu-si-ta
The possessor in Spec, DP agrees with D and hence the entire DP carries the feature [+hon],
allowing Agrhon to agree with the possessor. Under an agreement under pied-piping approach, an
feature, and triggers further agreement under pied-piping. The honorific agreement is checked off
in Spec Agrhon and will therefore not trigger agreement on higher heads. The honorific head
must be merged low, both within the DP, where it precedes plural, and within the clause, where it
precedes tense (and plural agreement as well). It will pied-pipe with the vP to higher merged
(55) AgrhonP
3
vP<+hon> r
3 Agrhon
NP 3 si<+hon>
[+hon] v
<+hon>
There are some mysteries with honorifics which Sells takes as additional strikes against the
syntactic view. The purpose of this section is to show that the syntactic view can in fact make the
relevant distinctions using the available mechanisms, and hence that these data do not form any
The first observation concerns Japanese irregular honorific verb forms. Though a bit redundant,
irregular honorific verb forms may appear in the syntactic honorific construction (Sells and Ida
1991), but the regular verb stem cannot appear in this environment.
26
b. Irregular form: *o-si-ni-naru Æ nasaru ‘honorably do’
Sells points out that double marking seems problematic for a syntactic account since
honorification should have a unique syntactic expression. In light of the preceding section, we can
understand the honorific construction as follows: whenever a V agrees with a honorific subject, it
inherits the feature +honorific. In accordance with the elsewhere principle, the regular verb stem
is blocked in (56b) by the listed honorific form. The listed form can appear by itself, since it
carries the feature +honorific. The listed form can also occur in the syntactic honorific
Sells’ second observation concerns irregular honorific forms in Korean, which ‘fit’ into different
syntactic contexts than regular ones. As shown in (49), C1 cannot cooccur with an overt honorific
suffix. However, C1 can cooccur with an irregular honorific form: (capswusi-e versus *ilk-usi-e)
(Sells:293 (28)):
The irregular honorific form thus has the distribution of a regular verbal root, yet at the same
Suppose that irregular honorific verb forms and regular honorific verb forms have the following
syntactic representations when handed over to the phonology. A zero head cooccurs with a
phonologically specified list of stems. Regular honorifics represent the elsewhere case, with the
27
(58) a. irregular honorifics regular honorific
AgrhonP b. AgrhonP
3 3
VP 3 VP 3
/+list/ [e]hon <+hon> [u)si]hon
<+hon>
These structures express their common distribution, but differ in the distribution of overt/covert
material. The difference in basic syntactic constituency is not without syntactic consequences. VP
extraction in (58a) would strand a silent head but an overt head in (58b). Furthermore, pied-
piping in the latter case would yield the ungrammatical string (59c).
(59a) shows that an irregular honorific verb has the same distribution as a root V, i.e. it can be in
the Spec, CP of this particular C satisfying the selectional requirement of this C. (59b) probably
violates a phonological requirement on the spell-out of the overt honorific–si (i.e. must have a VP
with overt V in its Spec at spell-out); and (59c) probably violates a size requirement on overt
material in Spec –e (the overt V may not be more deeply embedded than vP). The silent honorific
(59a) “escapes” phonological conditions by virtue of being silent, and therefore only (59a) yields
a well-formed surface form. This allows a CP headed by –e to contain an honorific subject, and
Korean has a second kind of subject agreement, resembling complementizer agreement. Plural
subjects optionally trigger plural agreement tul, and do so lavishly. Sells did not include tul in his
article: “The plural marker tul does not appear in the charts above because it shows considerable
28
freedom to where it may attach within the word”. (Sells: 316, footnote 40). In this section, I will
show that the quite challenging distribution of tul can be quite nicely integrated in the syntactic
account . More specifically, I will argue that plural agreement is triggered under pied-piping and
stranding of Agrplural. The differences with honorific agreement follow from the high location of
plural Agreement, which seems to correspond more closely to a very high AgrS.
The data in this section are mostly drawn from Park and Sohn 1993, and references cited
therein.16 Tul is a plural suffix on nouns, and a plural agreement marker optionally co-occurring
with a plural subject17, (optionality is indicated in the examples below by italics); tul can follow
left- INFORMAL-PL
‘ They left’
Tul may also follow any of the embedded Cs (C1 through C3, section 4.2.), if that CP contains a
read-e- PL try-PAST-DECL-PL
29
read-ko –PL want-MODAL-DECL-PL
Tul may not follow any of the mood/force markers however, if the latter are embedded under the
general subordinator ko (Park and Sohn: 1993, p. 201), which Sells (p. 297) describes as
But tul may follow the subordinator ko, if ko itself can be said to have a plural subject (Park and
Park and Sohn (1993) further show that tul cannot occur in relative clauses nor on noun-
Plural tul cannot appear anywhere between Mood/Force and the verb:20
30
(64) ilk- (*tul) usi- (*tul) ess – (*tul) ta – (*tul) ko
Finally, tul can optionally follow adverbs and PPs as long as these are “controlled” by the plural
subject, and occur on the projection line between V and the surface position of the plural subject
Plural agreement is distinct from honorific agreement: it occurs in a different position, and it is
neither in complementary distribution with honorific, nor fused with it (61e). Plural agreement is
spelled out in a somewhat unusual position, after C, which makes it look very similar to
agreement, plural agreement is optional. The linear position suggests it spells out a much higher
Agr projection than honorific agreement, say a very high Agr projection just below the C region,
i.e. C > AgrS, or just above C, i.e. AgrS>C. If plural spells out high AgrS, as in (67a), the only
possibility to derive this order from the underlying hierarchy is by obligatorily stranding AgrS.
Since TP precedes C, it is natural to think of the extracted XP that contains the agreement
31
This derivation accounts for the linear position of plural agreement: it must follow C, and cannot
occur anywhere in the verbal complex between V and C, because AgrS is merged higher than T,
(67) *(pl)T-*(pl)-“C”
Instead of C>Agrpl, it could be argued that Agr is merged higher than C, as Shlonsky (1994)
proposes for similar cases of complementizer agreement in the West Germanic OV languages. If
Park and Sohn (1993) adopt a variant of (68), in which the presence of a higher Agr projection is
only available in root Cs, thus explaining why tul may not appear in non–root contexts. Their
basic generalization seems to be incorrect, however. Plural agreement does occur in non-root
contexts, though not in all non-root contexts. Non-root clausal complements allow for optional
plural agreement when they contain a plural subject with C1, C2 and C3 endings (61).24
Embedding these predicates under a verb like say, does not affect the plural marking on the
embedded C , but only affects tul’s possible co-occurrence before the subordinator ko (64),
showing that this must be related to some property of ko. (section 5.3.3.)
The underlined tul is licensed by a plural DP internal to the embedded complement, i.e. PRO, the
external argument of read. Moreover, tul may appear in embedded contexts, as long as the
subordinator ko is absent25:
32
Since (68) fails to account for tul’s possible appearance in embedded environments, I will
continue to assume that tul spells out AgrS (C>Agr).26 Thus, Korean has a crosslinguistically
Why cannot tul precede the subordinator ko? Consider a representative example (63), repeated
here as (72):
A clausal complement with a plural subject cannot trigger plural agreement, neither after the
question particle, nor following the subordinator ko. Plural agreement can follow ko though , if ko
can be said to have a PRO controlled by the plural DP of the verbs of thinking or speech:
In our paper on logophoricity (Koopman and Sportiche 1989)), certain types of complementizers
node, and taking a CP complement. This proposal directly captures the distribution of plural
agreement following ko, as can be illustrated with the underlying hierarchy, abstracting away
(73) C1 > AgrS1>T>DPpl say> C2 > AgrS2 >T> PROpl> ko> [C3> AgrS3> T > DP3pl
A plural subject in C1 will yield plural agreement following C1, a plural subject in C2, plural
agreement following ko, a plural in C3 plural following C3. In (71), PRO is singular, since its
33
controller is singular; hence ko cannot be followed by tul. (* ko tul). In (72), PRO is plural, since
This leaves the question why tul cannot be triggered on AgrS3 when embedded under ko, yielding
. *C-tul-ko. The derivation underlying this order would contain the following substructure:
(74) 3
CP 3
3 ko
TPpl 3
5 C 3
TP<+pl>3
tul
This configuration contains overt phonological material on a right branch lower than the head C,
and is notorious for yielding ungrammaticality (*a proud of John mother) . I will assume that
whatever explains the ill-formedness of such configurations (see Koopman 2002 for discussion),
will rule out (74) as well. Simply not agreeing, an option that is always available in Korean, will
yield convergence, and removes the phonological problem. Alternatively, making merger of
The plural marker can neither follow nor precede the complementizer in relative clauses or noun-
Relative clauses precede the head of the relative clause, as do clausal complements to the noun.
Kayne (1994) proposes that UG makes a D0 CP structure available for relativization, but prohibits
the mirror image CP D0. Therefore, head final relative clauses must be analyzed as deriving from
34
head initial structures, and involve raising of the head noun to Spec, CP, followed by IP
b. IPj D0 [[ NP ] Co [e]j
Filling in the details in Korean, assuming nun equals D and C is silent yields the following
intermediate structure:
(77) D0 [[ NP ] Co [ Agrpl
nun soldiers
Given this derivation there are two options. either AgrP pied-pipes to the left of D, or Agrpl is
stranded. There is no possible derivation that would result in tul immediately following D*(n)un
tul NP. The prediction of this analysis then is that this form should be invariably excluded across
(78a) poses a similar problem as (77), with tul on a right branch lower than T, preceding nun. If
TP movement in Korean strands plural AgrS, AgrS should be stranded after the head noun, but
never before or after the D. (Note that this results in the same linear order as the plural nominal
affix tul ).
Thus, plural agreement should be triggerable by a plural subject within the relative clause or
complement clause. At this point, this prediction is not borne out (though plural subjects seem to
facilitate the plural following the head noun for many speakers), and further research is necessary,
As I have shown in this section, the syntactic account adopted in this paper yields new insights
into the distribution of tul. The idea that agreement can be triggered under pied-piping plays a
35
crucial role (Koopman 2003). This possibility is expected to exist given what we know about the
play a further filtering role: sometimes derivations are filtered out because a head would be too
deeply embedded at spell-out, sometimes individual heads filter out certain otherwise licit
In this section, we further examine the interaction between scope and word structure. If word
structure is derived in the syntax, and scope is determined by the merger of the heads that
determine scope, word structure should interact with available scope possibilities as a
Lee (2004, in prep) makes exactly this point. She uses word structure to account for scope
interactions in Korean. In a nutshell, she shows that an accusative object that precedes a universal
subject cannot scope over a subject QP, but a preceding PP can either scope over or under the
quantified subject.
Lee proposes that man is an agreement morpheme, that triggers movement of the focus
determined. The silent focus head can be merged at several points in the hierarchy. If
36
ONLY is merged low , universal> focus results, if ONLY is merged higher than the
universal, in the left periphery, the reading is focus>universal. DP-man-acc cannot scope
over universal subjects because the linear order DP-man-acc signals the silent Focus head
must be merged below accusative hence Universal>only is the only available reading.
Lee appeals to the Mirror Principle (“check inner affixes before you check outer
affixes”), to force the low position of the silent Focus head with accusative case. A PP
(81) can scope either over universals, or below universals, because the linear order is
consistent with both high or low merger of ONLY. Lee thus presents an extremely strong
As far as I can tell, these scope facts fall out in very similar ways in the proposal made in
this paper, where man is merged directly as a focus head, higher than accusative,
provided of course that we accept head complement order. The linear string man-acc
shows that man (only) must be merged immediately above accusative, in conjunction
with the universal hierarchy Focus>Case, since this is the only way to form this particular
surface constituent28 Hence DP-man-acc will scope under universal (and preposing to the
left of the universal must be achieved by scrambling). There is no other derivation that
Consider, for example, what outputs would result from merger of man higher than the subject
37
b. *[ DP- ul acc -man [QP every DP-nom [DP acc [
Neither string corresponds to the input strings that native speakers are asked to judge in (81), nor
are they well-formed. It must be explained how these strings are ruled out, and the reason here
does not seem to be syntactic, but phonological. The derivation in (83b) yields overt phonological
material on a right branch, and I will tentatively assume that this is the reason (83b) is out.29 (83c)
results in a stranded accusative –ul. It is likely that this can be excluded by a phonological
condition on ul: it needs to lean on overt phonological material in a specific phonological domain,
and though it can be stranded, it cannot be the sole remnant in that domain. Interestingly, not
pronouncing ul is a way to remove the phonological restriction, and as expected, both high scope
(=high merger) and low scope (=low merger) of man is possible in this case. (Lee, 2004, ex.
(26))30
(i) Everyone loves John and no one else. (very > only)
(ii) John is the only one whom everyone loves. (only > every)
Finally, as in Lee’s account, Case markers must be part of the “narrow” syntax, since they
interact with the derivations in specific ways forcing decisions about the location of scope bearing
heads, and hence making very specific predictions about scope interactions.
7. Conclusion.
In this paper, I have argued in favor of a syntactic view of Korean (and Japanese) morphology,
which derives the surface constituency of “words” from an underling Spec H complement order
by means of local phrasal movements, providing strong support for Kayne (1994). This accounts
38
for the fact that the affixes are phrasal affixes. This view uses underlying hierarchies, movement
from Spec stranding heads, pied-piping, and generalized Spec head agreement under pied-piping.
My primary concern has been to show that syntactic analyses can be motivated, contra Sells
1995, and that the vocabulary necessary to describe word structure is the usual syntactic
vocabulary. Inflected words are derived by phrasal movement, with many, but not all, words
mirroring the syntactic hierarchy of merger. Underlying head complement order surfaces in
particular instances, directly supporting antisymmetry. Furthermore, I argued that certain strings
that the syntax should generate are filtered out by “phonological” properties of individual lexical
items (complexity filters) when phonological material is inserted. Sometimes not inserting
References
Bayer, Josef: 1984 “ COMP in Bavarian syntax,” The Linguistic Review 3, 209-274.
Beghelli, F. and T. Stowell, 1997, Distributivity and negation: the syntax of each and every.
Belletti, Ad (2002), Aspects of the low IP area. in L. Rizzi (ed) The Structure of IP and CP.
Bennis, H. and L. Haegeman. 1984. On the status of agreement and relative clauses in West
Foris. 33-53.
Cecchetto, Carlo. 1999. A comparative analysis of left and right dislocation in Romance.
39
Cho, Young-mee Yu, and Peter Sells. 1995. A lexical account of inflectional suffixes in
Chung-hye Han, Jeffrey Lidz, Julien Musolino (2003) Verb-raising and Grammar
Cinque, G. 2002 ‘A note on mood, modality, tense and aspect affixes in Turkish’ in Eser
Embick R and R. Noyer, 2001 “Movement operations after syntax” Linguistic Inquiry,
Fukui, N and H. Sakai 2003. The Visibility Guideline for Functional Categories:Verb Raising
Halle, Morris and Alec Marantz. 1993. 'Distributed Morphology and the Pieces of
Inflection.' In The View from Building 20, ed. Kenneth Hale and S. Jay Keyser. MIT Press,
Cambridge, 111-176.
Hallman, P. 1997. “Reiterative Syntax”. In Clitics, pronouns, and movement, J. Black and V.
40
Julien, M. (2002) Syntactic heads and Word Formation, Oxford University Press.
New York
Kayne, R.S. 2000. Parameters and Universals. New York.: Oxford University Press.
Koizumi, M., 2000. String vacuous overt verb raising. Journal of East Asian
Koopman, H. 1984 The syntax of Verbs: from Verb movement rules in the Kru languages to
Koopman, H. 1994. Licensing Heads. in N Hornstein and David Lightfoot (ed) Verb
Koopman, H. 2003. Inside the Noun in Syntax at Sunset : Head Movement and Syntactic
Koopman, H. and Szabolcsi A. 2000, Verbal Complexes Current Studies in Linguistics 34,
41
Kornfilt, J. (2002). Agreement and its Placement in Turkic Non-Subject Relative Clauses, ms.
Syracuse University.
Kural, M. 1994 ‘Inf and Comp in Turkish subordinate clauses’, WCCFL 12, p. 339-354.
Kuroda, S,-Y.2003 Complex predicates and predicate raising, Lingua, 113, 447-480.
Laka, I. 1990. Negation in Syntax: On the Nature of Functional Categories and Projections.
Lee, Y. 2004 ‘Only, scope and the Mirror Principle’ to appear in Natural Language
Semantics.
Marantz, A., 1988. Clitics, morphological merger, and the mapping to phonological structure.
Muller, Gereon. 2000. Shape conservation and remnant movement Proceedings of NELS 30
Otani, K. and J. Whitman (1991). V-raising and VP-ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 22, 345-358.
Company.
Poletto C. and Pollock J-Y. 2003. “ On the Left Periphery of some Romance Wh-
42
Rizzi, L. 1997 .“On the fine structure of the left-periphery” in Elements of Grammar.
Rizzi, L. 1999. On the position “Int”(errogative)” in the Left Periphery of the Clause,
msUniversità di Siena.
Schütze, C (2001) 'On Korean "Case stacking": The varied functions of the particles ka and
Sells, P 1995 Korean and Japanese Morphology from a lexical perspective, Linguistic
Sells, P. 1998. “Structural relationships within complex predicates” In Byung-Soo Park and
James Yoon (eds.) Proceedings of ICKL 11. Seoul, International Circle of Korean
Linguistics, 115-147.
Sells. P. and M. Ida 1991. Subject and Object Honorification in Japanese. In Proceedings of
the Seventh Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistic Society, 312-323. Berkeley Linguistic
Sportiche, D. 2001 Structural Bonds and Strict Locality, Tools in Linguistic Theory
Webelhuth,G. 1992. Principles and parameters of syntactic saturation, New York: Oxford
University Press.
43
Whitman, J. (2001) “Kayne 1994: p. 143, fn. 3,” in G. Alexandrova & O. Artunova (eds.),
Kayne (ed s.) Handbook of Comparative Syntax, Oxford University Press, New York.
Texas.
Yoon, J. (1994) "Korean Inflection and Checking Theory," MIT Working Papers in
Linguistics, C. Philip & H. Harley eds., Department of Linguistics, MIT, pp. 251-270
Zwart, C. J.-W 2001. Syntactic and phonological verb movement. Syntax 4.1
Zwart, C. J.-W. 1993. Dutch syntax: a minimalist approach. University of Groningen PhD
thesis.
44
*
I would like to thank Sun-Ah Jun, Seungho Nam, Soyoung Park, Genhee Kim, Chistina Kim,
and Chunmin Lee for their generous help with Korean data. Many thanks to John Whitman for
Richard Kayne, Gugluelmo Cinque, Christina Kim, David Schüller, Greg Kobele, the participants
an indication of the syntactic nature: (Kuroda 2000: 445 (16)) (also Kuroda 1986a: (16); 1993a:
(15))
Hanako NOM Masao DAT house ACC clean or room-rent ACC pay cause that to do
‘Hanako decided to make Masao clean the house or pay room rent’
2
In Koopman and Szabolcsi (2000), we propose all inflectional morphology is derived through
phrasal movement, in which case the different behavior of the different types of affixes need to be
independently explained. The point in the text simply states the fact that Japanese and Korean
constituent to higher functional projections, as indeed must be the case. In Korean, short negation
an precedes the verb, and a subconstituent an [V-X] is formed (Whitman 2002). However, (non-
verbal) dependents of the verb occur to the left of short negation, and some of the elements
(idiomatic parts, small clause predicates, and low adverbs) must remain after ellipsis, showing
they are outside the elided constituent, i.e. they have undergone movement as well. Higher
material (definite DPs, quantified DPS, localitive and temporal adverbials) are part of the elided
45
(i) Mary-ka motun panana-lul eoje jengwon-e [cal [an mek]-ess]-ni
‘She didn’t’
Coordination yields parallel results showing that the low adverb is within the ATB moved
(ii) Mary-ka [[FP motun sakwa-lul ti] kuliko [FP motun panana-lul ti]] cal mek-ess-ta.
Many questions remain about the finer constituent structure of the inflected verb phrase.
However, these go beyond the basic point in this paper and should be examined in the context of
Cinque 1999.
4
For PP pied-piping, see Koopman and Szabolci 2000:p42.
5
I phrase agreement in terms of copying, instead of checking, since I think this better describes
the basic agreement mechanism. Nothing hinges on this particular choice however.
6
For expository reasons, the picture is simplified here. If followed through, all functional
i have lost footnote 8,. and seem to be unable to delete it, or renumber the following notes.
8
This step could perhaps also motivated by the Principle of Locality of Selection. If P selects VP
and merges with VP, there would be no motivation for VP movement. However, suppose that the
verb and the P are actually not in a local relation at the point of merger, but that P merges like a C
(Kayne, 2000). If that is correct, locality of selection must be met after movement, hence both DP
movement and VP movement are obligatory to establish the necessary local configurations.
46
9
These derivations do not show the VP movements, which have been added in (i) below, and
a. move VP VP w [PP DP P ]
b. Merge kkaci,
negation an does not modify the lower predicate but the higher one, and still part of the
complement clause must restructure (as we can see by the fact cal modifies the embedded verb,
yet precedes the high negation). It rather looks like an is a very high clausal head, which attracts
the complex verb to its right, with subsequent movement to its Spec.
47
11
Not all speakers accept the short form negation an with man focus in this context. For those
speakers that do accept this combination, the scope is focus>negation (Many thanks to Chungmin
Lee for extensive multispeaker feedback on this issue). For some speakers, focus can also scope
under negation, but only when an accentual phrase follows the focused constituent. This points to
a hierarchy where man is merged lower than negation, within the clausal complement of try.
phrase, suggesting that the structure underlying this phrasing can only be man>an. (Thanks to
Christina Kim for the pointing out to me that the morphological structure interacts with available
scope readings, and to Sun-Ah Jun and Chungmin Lee for extensive feedback on this issue). It
seems, as so often with verbal complexes and restructuring, that there is considerable speaker
variation in this area (see Koopman and Szabolcsi (2000)). At this point, the variability can be
summed up as follows:
(iii) some speakers allow Negation>focus, but only if man is followed by an intonational
I take the variation in (ii), (iii) to reflect whether individual speakers exceptionally allow focus to
be merged within the –e complement of ‘try’ or not. If they do (iii), low merger must be
consistent with the phonological phrasing/word structure, suggesting this is another instance
where word structure and syntax determine scopal possibilities (Lee 2004 and section 6. As a
final note, all speakers seem to allow focus to be merged within the fully clausal –ci complement
48
(i) selection satisfied after movement though Spec head agreement for desu:
strand. This can be achieved if katta must have overt material in its Spec at spell-out. In
‘substandard’ Japanese –desu can also precede ta, but this requires a different morphology on A
This suggests that Spec extraction might also be available for APs in substandard Japanese,
the left periphery in lower regions of the sentence, see Hallman 1996, Sportiche 1996, Cecchetto
hokun ‘or’.
“Only students who are present everyday or only students who submit all the reports
Notice that this example is considerably more complex than the example in the text. In particular,
the DPs contain relative clauses. It may be the case that the more complex derivation here creates
49
17
Tul on non-subjects is claimed to force a distributive reading. (see Park and Sohn (1993) and
H.-K Lee (1991) for some discussion). I will have to ignore questions of interpretation.
18
Some Korean speakers find the sequence ta-tul acceptable, but slightly uncomfortable.
19
man can further attach to the CP (ilk-e-tul man), suggesting (remnant) CP extraction to Focus
As an anonymous reviewer points out, the order ilk-e man-tul is also acceptable, though generally
less preferred. This might suggest the presence of an additional Agr position just below man, and
CP recursion, with VP-e moving through AgrS and triggering plural agreement under pied-
piping:
This analysis predicts that man must have scope over an(negation) given this particular linear
string, though not in the other order. (Note that this only holds for speakers who allow man to be
merged within the complement clause to start with) (see footnote 11) At this point, judgments
here are very difficult and not very secure., though they seem to go in the right direction.
20
The contrast between (61) and (64) is quite problematic for a templatic view of morphology. If
–tul can attach to C1 etc, and if C1 occurs in slot 1,why then cannot it attach to other elements in
slot 1?
21
As expected, ECM accusatives behave like subjects:
50
22
Kornfilt (2002) shows that in certain Turkic languages a post-nominal agreement morpheme
agrees with the subject of a pre-nominal relative, and analyzes these in terms of AgrS stranding.
Turkish data presented by Kural (1994) initially inspired me to pursue this type of analysis.
adverbs that occur on the main projection line between V and C. It is tempting to assume that in
all these cases, the same configuration holds, i.e. each time tul shows the presence of C>Agr,
honorifics can occur (see (59). In section 4.2.1. I took this to show that these complements can in
fact contain Agrhon.. (61a) shows that these complements can also contain a high AgrS, further
confirming Koopman & Szabolcsi’s (2000) idea that complements of restructuring predicates are
always dominated by full CPs , which are made to look small when part of the CP, which is
Case.
26
This suggests that all cases of complementizer agreement should be analyzed as being triggered
under TP movement stranding agreement. It is suggestive here that only the SOV Germanic
languages have complementizer agreement, and that complementizer agreement is only possible
51
in clauses that have an OV order: embedded verb second is incompatible with complementizer
agreement ( cf. Shlonsky 1994, Kayne 1994: p.56, Zwart 1997, Bennis and Haegeman, 1983,
dialects of Korean.
28
The surface constituent: DP-man-ul is formed by further VP movement to the left of man .
29
The low interpretation shows that [DP-ul-][man has to be excluded independently.
30
For other cases where not inserting phonological material removes the phonological restriction,
see (4.3.2, 5.2.1, 5.3.3.). This account should extend to other cases where topic and focus markers
52