MODULE-LOGIC-AND-CRITICAL-THINKING
MODULE-LOGIC-AND-CRITICAL-THINKING
After the successful completion of this chapter, you will be able to:
Lesson Overview
______________________________________________________________________________
______________________________________________________________________________
____________
Philosophy deals primarily with issues. What contents philosophy has are not
the specific subject matters, but issues, which are universal in nature.
However, this should not lead us into thinking that philosophy is
incomprehensible. It is only to say that whenever you want to understand
philosophy, it is better to read different thoughts of philosophers, consciously
see its salient features by yourself, participate in it, and do it.
Etymologically, the word “philosophy” comes from two Greek words: “philo”
and “sophia”, which mean “love” and “wisdom”, respectively. Thus, the
literal definition of philosophy is “love of wisdom”. The ancient Greek thinker
Pythagoras was the first to use the word “philosopher” to call a person who
clearly shows a marked curiosity in the things he experiences. Anyone who
raises questions, such as Does God exists? What is reality? What is the
ultimate source of Being? What is knowledge? What does it mean to know?
How do we come to know? What is value?, and the like, is really showing a
curiosity that can be described as a vital concern for becoming wise about
the phenomena of the world and the human experiences. Therefore, seeking
wisdom is among the various essences of philosophy that it has got from its
etymological definition. Nevertheless, this is not sufficient by itself to
understand philosophy, for not all wisdoms are philosophy.
______________________________________________________________________________
______________________________________________________________________________
____________
The wisdom that philosophers seek is not the wisdom of the expertise or
technical skills of professionals. Someone may be encyclopedic, and thus
seemingly intelligent, but he may actually be foolish when it comes to
understanding the meaning and significance of what he knows. According to
Socrates, wisdom consists of a critical habit and eternal vigilance about all
things and a reverence for truth, whatever its form, and wherever its place.
Based on the Socratic understanding of wisdom, philosophy, as a pursuit of
wisdom, is, thus, the development of critical habits, the continuous search
for truth, and the questioning of the apparent.
1) Philosophy is a set of views or beliefs about life and the universe, which
are often held uncritically.
We refer to this meaning as the informal sense of philosophy or
“having” a philosophy. Usually when a person says “my philosophy is,”
he or she is referring to an informal personal attitude to whatever topic
is being discussed.
2) Philosophy is a process of reflecting on and criticizing our most deeply
held conceptions and beliefs.
This is the formal sense of “doing” philosophy. These two senses of
philosophy-”having” and “doing”- cannot be treated entirely
independent of each other, if we did not have a philosophy in the
formal, personal sense, then we could not do a philosophy in the
critical, reflective sense. However, having a philosophy is not sufficient
for doing philosophy. A genuine philosophical attitude is searching and
critical; it is open-minded and tolerant- willing to look at all sides of an
issue without prejudice. To philosophize is not merely to read and know
philosophy; there are skills of argumentation to be mastered,
techniques of analysis to be employed, and a body of material to be
appropriated such that we become able to think philosophically. To
philosophize also means to generalize. Philosophers are reflective and
critical. They take a second look at the material presented by common
sense. They attempt to think through a variety of life’s problems and to
face all the facts involved impartially. The accumulation of knowledge
does not by itself lead to understanding, because it does not
necessarily teach the mind to make a critical evaluation of facts that
entail consistent and coherent judgment. Critical evaluations often
differ. Philosophers, theologians, scientists, and others disagree, first
because they view things from different points of view and with
different assumptions. Their personal experiences, cultural
backgrounds, and training may vary widely. This is especially true of
people living at different times and in different places. A second reason
philosophers disagree is that they live in a changing universe. People
change, society changes, and nature changes. Some people are
responsive and sensitive to change; others cling to tradition and the
status quo, to systems that were formulated some time ago and that
were declared to be authoritative and final. A third reason philosophers
disagree is that they deal with an area of human experience in which
the evidence is not complete. Different people may interpret the
evidence we do have in various ways. Despite these disagreements,
however, philosophers continue to probe, examine, and evaluate the
material with the hope of presenting consistent principles by which we
can live.
3) Philosophy is a rational attempt to look at the world as a whole.
Philosophy seeks to combine the conclusions of the various sciences and
human experience into some kind of consistent worldview. Philosophers
wish to see life, not with the specialized slant of the scientist or the
businessperson or the artist, but with the overall view of someone
cognizant of life as a totality. Although there are difficulties and dangers
in setting forth any worldview, there also are dangers in confining
attention to fragments of human experience. Philosophy’s task is to give
a view of the whole, a life and a worldview, and to integrate the
knowledge of the sciences with that of other disciplines to achieve a
consistent whole. Philosophy, according to this view, attempts to bring
the results of human inquiry- religious, historical, and scientific into some
meaningful interpretation that provides knowledge and insight for our
lives.
4) Philosophy is the logical analysis of language and the clarification of the
meaning of words and concepts.
Certainly, this is one function of philosophy. In fact, nearly all
philosophers have used methods of analysis and have sought to clarify
the meaning of terms and the use of language. Some philosophers see
this as the main task of philosophy, and a few claim this is the only
legitimate function of philosophy. Such persons consider philosophy a
specialized field serving the sciences and aiding in the clarification of
language rather than a broad field reflecting on all of life’s experiences.
This outlook has gained considerable support during the twentieth
century. It would limit what we call knowledge to statements about
observable facts and their interrelations i.e., to the business of the
various sciences. Not all linguistic analysts, however, define knowledge
so narrowly. Although they do reject and try to “clean up” many non-
scientific assertions, many of them think that we can have knowledge of
ethical principles and the like, although this knowledge is also
experientially derived. Those who take the narrower view neglect, when
they do not deny, all generalized worldviews and life views, as well as
traditional moral philosophy and theology. From this narrower point of
view, the aim of philosophy is to expose confusion and nonsense and to
clarify the meaning and use of terms in science and everyday affairs.
5) Philosophy is a group of perennial problems that interest people and for
which philosophers always have sought answers.
Philosophy presses its inquiry into the deepest problems of human
existence. Some of the philosophical questions raised in the past have
been answered in a manner satisfactory to the majority of philosophers.
Many questions, however, have been answered only tentatively, and
many problems remain unsolved. What are philosophical questions? The
question “Did Ram make a false statement on his income tax return?” is
merely a question of fact. However, the questions “What is truth?” and
“What is the distinction between right and wrong?” have philosophical
importance. Sometimes we think seriously about fundamental life issues:
What is life and why am I here? Why is there anything at all? What is the
place of life in this great universe? Is the universe friendly or unfriendly?
Do things operate by chance or through sheer mechanism, or is there
some plan, purpose, or intelligence at the heart of things? Is my life
controlled by outside forces, or do I have a determining or even a partial
degree of control? Why do people struggle and strive for their rights, for
justice, for better things in the future? What do concepts like “right” and
“justice” means, and what are the marks of a good society? Often men
and women have been asked to sacrifice their lives, if need be, for
certain values and ideals. What are the genuine values of life and how
can it attained? Is there really a fundamental distinction between right
and wrong, or is it just a matter of one’s own opinions? What is beauty?
Should religion count in a person’s life? Is it intellectually valid to believe
in God? Is there a possibility of a “life after death?” Is there any way we
can get an answer to these and many related questions? Where does
knowledge come from, and can we have any assurances that anything is
true?
The above questions are all philosophical. The attempt to seek answers
or solutions to them has given rise to theories and systems of thought,
such as idealism, realism, pragmatism, analytic philosophy,
existentialism, phenomenology, and process philosophy. Philosophy also
means the various theories or systems of thought developed by the
great philosophers, such as Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, Augustine,
Aquinas, Descartes, Spinoza, Locke, Berkeley, Kant, Hegel, Nietzsche,
Royce, James, Dewey, Whitehead, and others. Without these people and
their thoughts, philosophy would not have the rich content it has today.
Even though we may be unconscious of the fact, we are constantly
influenced by ideas that have come down to us in the traditions of
society.
Metaphysics
Here are some of the questions that Metaphysics primarily deals with:
What is reality?
What is the ultimately real?
What is the nature of the ultimate reality?
Is it one thing or is it many different things?
Can reality be grasped by the senses, or it is transcendent?
What makes reality different from a mere appearance?
What is mind, and what is its relation to the body?
Is there a cause and effect relationship between reality and
appearance?
Does God exist, and if so, can we prove it?
Are human actions free, or predetermined by a supernatural force?
What is human being? A thinking mind? A perishable body? Or a
combination of both?
What is time?
What is the meaning of life?
Metaphysical questions are the most basic to ask because they provide the
foundation upon which all subsequent inquiry is based. Metaphysical
questions may be divided into four subsets or aspects.
Epistemology
Epistemology is the other field of philosophy that studies about the nature,
scope, meaning, and possibility of knowledge. It deals with issues of
knowledge, opinion, truth, falsity, reason, experience, and faith.
Epistemology is also referred to as “theory of knowledge”.
Etymologically, the word epistemology has been derived from the Greek
words episteme, meaning “knowledge, understanding”, and logos, meaning
“study of”. In other words, we can say that Epistemology is the study of the
nature, source, and validity of knowledge. It seeks to answer of the basic
questions as “What is true?” and “How do we know?” Thus, epistemology
covers two areas: the content of thought and thought itself. The study of
epistemology deals with issues related to the dependability of knowledge
and the validity of the sources through which we gain information.
Axiology
Axiology is the study or theory of value. The term Axiology stems from two
Greek words- “Axios”, meaning “value, worth”, and “logos”, meaning
“reason/ theory/ symbol / science/study of”. Hence, Axiology is the
philosophical study of value, which originally meant the worth of something.
Axiology asks the philosophical questions of values that deal with notions of
what a person or a society regards as good or preferable, such as:
What is a value?
Where do values come from?
How do we justify our values?
How do we know what is valuable?
What is the relationship between values and knowledge?
What kinds of values exist?
Can it be demonstrated that one value is better than another? Who
benefits from values?
Axiology deals with the above and related issues of value in three areas,
namely Ethics, Aesthetics, and Social/Political Philosophy.
Ethics
Ethics, which is also known as Moral Philosophy, is a science that deals with
the philosophical study of moral principles, values, codes, and rules, which
may be used as standards for determining what kind of human
conduct/action is said to be good or bad, right or wrong.
Ethics has three main branches: meta-ethics, normative ethics, and applied
ethics. Ethics raises various questions including:
What is good/bad?
What is right/wrong?
Is it the Right Principle or the Good End that makes human
action/conduct moral?
Is an action right because of its good end, or it is good because of its
right principle?
Are moral principles universal, objective, and unconditional, or relative,
subjective and conditional?
What is the ultimate foundation of moral principles? The supernatural
God? Human reason? Mutual social contract? Social custom?
Does God exist? If so, is He Benevolent and Omnipotent?
Aesthetics
Aesthetics is the theory of beauty. It studies about the particular value of our
artistic and aesthetic experiences. It deals with beauty, art, enjoyment,
sensory/emotional values, perception, and matters of taste and sentiment.
What is art?
What is beauty?
What is the relation between art and beauty?
What is the connection between art, beauty, and truth?
Can there be any objective standard by which we may judge the
beauty of artistic works, or beauty is subjective?
What is artistic creativity and how does it differ from scientific
creativity?
Why works of art are valuable?
Can artistic works communicate? If so, what do they communicate?
Does art have any moral value, and obligations or constraints?
Are there standards of quality in Art?
Lesson Objectives:
The word logic comes from Greek word logos, which means sentence,
discourse, reason, truth and rule. Logic in its broader meaning is the science,
which evaluates arguments and the study of correct reasoning. It could be
also defined as the study of methods and principles of correct reasoning or
the art of correct reasoning.
Logic can be defined in different ways. Here below are some definitions of
logic:
What is an Argument?
The word ‘argument’ may not be a new word to all of us. For all of us
encounter arguments in our day-to-day experience. We read them in
books and newspapers, hear them on television, and formulate them
when communicating with friends and associates. If you look back at the
above different definitions of logic and characterizations, you will certainly
find one thing in common: argument. Moreover, we have said that of the
various benefits of studying logic, identifying, analyzing and evaluating
arguments is the most important one. It follows that argument the
primary subject matter of logic. What is an argument then?
Argument is a technical term and the chief concern of logic. Argument
might have defined and described in different ways. When we define an
arguments from logical point of view, it is a group of statements, one or
more of which (the premise) are claimed to provide support for, or reason
to believe, one of the other, the (conclusion). As is apparent from the
above definition, the term ‘‘argument’’ has a very specific meaning in
logic. It does not mean, for example, a mere verbal fight, as one might
have with one’s parent, spouse, or friend. Let us examine the features of
this definition in detail.
Statement (a) and (b) are true, because they describe things as they are,
or assert what really is the case. Hence, ‘Truth’ is their truth-value.
Whereas statement (c) is false because it asserts what is not, and ‘Falsity’
its truth-value.
However, there are sentences that are not statements, and hence should
be used to construct an argument.
Examples:
Argument always attempts to justify a claim. The claim that the statement
attempts to justify is known as a conclusion of an argument; and the
statement or statements that supposedly justify the claim is/are known as
the premises of the argument. Therefore, a premise is a statement that
set forth the reason or evidence, which is given for accepting the
conclusion of an argument. It is claimed evidence; and a conclusion is a
statement, which is claimed to follow from the given evidence (premise).
In other words, the conclusion is the claim that an argument is trying to
establish.
Example-1:
Example-2:
In both arguments, the first two statements are premises, because they are
claimed to provide evidence for the third statement, whereas the third
statement is a conclusion because it is claimed to follow from the given
evidences. The claim that the premises support the conclusion, (and/or that
the conclusion follow from the premises), is indicated by the word
‘‘therefore.’’
All arguments may be placed in one of two basic groups: those in which the
premises really do support the conclusion and those in which they do not,
even though they are claimed to. The former are said to be good (well-
supported) arguments, the latter bad (poorly-supported) arguments. For
example, compare the above two examples. In the first argument, the
premises really do support the conclusion, they give good reason for
believing that the conclusion is true, and therefore, the argument is a good
one. But the premises of the second argument fail to support the conclusion
adequately. Even if they may be true, they do not provide good reason to
believe that the conclusion is true. Therefore, it is bad argument, but it is still
an argument.
Despite the purpose of logic, as the science that evaluates and analyses
arguments, is to develop methods and techniques that allow us to
distinguish good arguments from bad, one of the most important tasks in the
analysis of arguments is to distinguish premises from conclusion and vice
versa. Sometimes identifying a conclusion from premises is very tough.
Premises and conclusions are difficult to identify for a number of reasons.
Even though all arguments are ideally presumed to be composed of premises
and a conclusion, in reality, sometimes arguments may contain other
sentences as elements. Moreover, even though it is assumed, for the sake of
argument, that all arguments are composed of premises and conclusion,
identifying conclusion from argument is very difficult. Since it is impossible to
analyze arguments without identifying a conclusion from premises, we need
techniques that can help us to identify premises from a conclusion and vice
versa.
The first technique that can be used to identify premises from a conclusion
and vice versa is looking at an indicator word. Frequently, arguments contain
certain indicator words that provide clues in identifying premises and
conclusion.
It implies that So
Example:
Conditional Statements
A conditional statement is an “if . . . then . . .” statement.
Example: If you study hard, then you will score ‘A’ grade.
Every conditional statement is made up of two component statements. The
component statement immediately following the “if” is called the antecedent
(if-clause), and the one following the “then” is called the consequent (then-
clause). However, there is an occasion that the order of antecedent and
consequent is reversed. That is, when occasionally the word ‘‘then’’ is left
out, the order of antecedent and consequent is reversed.
For example: if we left out “then” from the above example the antecedent
and consequent is reversed: You will score ‘A’ grade if you study hard.
In the above example, the antecedent is “You study hard,” and the
consequent is “You will score ‘A’ grade.” In this example, there is a
meaningful relationship between antecedent and consequent. However, such
a relationship need not exist for a statement to count as conditional. The
statement “If Getaneh Kebede is a singer, then Hawassa is in Mekelle” is just
as much a conditional statement as that in the above example.
Conditional statements are not arguments, because they fail to meet the
criteria given earlier. In an argument, at least one statement must claim to
present evidence, and there must be a claim that this evidence implies
something. In a conditional statement, there is no claim that either the
antecedent or the consequent presents evidence. In other words, there is no
assertion that either the antecedent or the consequent is true. Rather, there
is only the assertion that if the antecedent is true, then so is the consequent.
For example, the above example merely asserts that if you study hard, then
you will score ‘A’. It does not assert that you study hard. Nor does it assert
you scored ‘A’.
Of course, a conditional statement as a whole may present evidence because
it asserts a relationship between statements. Yet when conditional
statements are taken in this sense, there is still no argument, because there
is then no separate claim that this evidence implies anything. Therefore, a
single conditional statement is not an argument. The fact that a statement
begin with “if” makes it the idea conditional and not a final reasonable
assertion. That is why also conditional statements are not evaluated as true
or false without separately evaluating the antecedent and the consequent.
They only claim that if the antecedent is true then so is the consequent.
However, some conditional statements are similar to arguments in that they
express the outcome of a reasoning process. As such, they may be said to
have a certain inferential content. Consider the following example:
If destroying a political competitor gives you joy, then you have a low sense
of morality.
The link between the antecedent and consequent resembles the inferential
link between the premises and conclusion of an argument. Yet there is a
difference because the premises of an argument are claimed to be true,
whereas no such claim is made for the antecedent of a conditional
statement. Accordingly, conditional statements are not arguments. Yet,
although taken by themselves are not arguments, their inferential content,
(the inferential content between the antecedent and the consequent), may
be re-expressed to form arguments. For example, the conditional statement
can be re-expressed to form an argument as follows:
Destroying a political competitor gives you joy. Therefore, you have a low
sense of morality.
Here, we clearly have a premise and conclusion structure, and the conclusion
is asserted on the basis of the premise. Therefore, it is argument.
Finally, while no single conditional statement is an argument, a conditional
statement may serve as either the premise or the conclusion (or both) of an
argument. Observe the following examples:
If he is selling our national secretes to enemies, then he is a traitor. He is
selling our national secretes to enemies.
Therefore, he is a traitor.
If he is selling our national secretes to enemies, then he is a traitor.
If he is a traitor, then he must be punished by death.
Therefore, If he is selling our national secretes to enemies, then he must be
punished by death.
The relation between conditional statements and arguments may now be
summarized as follows:
1) A single conditional statement is not an argument.
2) A conditional statement may serve as either the premise or the
conclusion (or both) of an argument.
3) The inferential content of a conditional statement may be re-expressed
to form an argument.
The first two rules are especially pertinent to the recognition of arguments.
According to the first rule, if a passage consists of a single conditional
statement, it is not an argument. But if it consists of a conditional statement
together with some other statement, then, by the second rule, it may be an
argument, depending on such factors as the presence of indicator words and
an inferential relationship between the statements.
Conditional statements are especially important in logic (and many other
fields) because they express the relationship between necessary and
sufficient conditions. A is said to be a sufficient condition for B whenever the
occurrence of A is all that is needed for the occurrence of B. For example,
being a dog is a sufficient condition for being an animal. On the other hand,
B is said to be a necessary condition for A whenever A cannot occur without
the occurrence of B. Thus, being an animal is a necessary condition for being
a dog.
On the other hand, suppose you are told that whatever might be in the box,
it is not an animal. Then you know for certain there is no dog in the box. The
reason you can draw this conclusion is that being an animal is necessary for
being a dog. If there is no animal, there is no dog. However, being an animal
is not sufficient for being a dog, because if you are told that the box contains
an animal, you cannot, from this information alone, conclude that it contains
a dog. It might contain a cat, a mouse, a squirrel, and so on. These ideas are
expressed in the following conditional statements:
If X is a dog, then X is an animal.
If X is not an animal, then X is not a dog.
The first statement says that being a dog is a sufficient condition for being
an animal, and the second that being an animal is a necessary condition for
being a dog. However, a little reflection reveals that these two statements
say exactly the same thing. Thus, each expresses in one way a necessary
condition and in another way a sufficient condition.
But remember that the mere occurrence of an indicator word does not
guarantee the presence of an argument. You must check to see that the
statement identified as the conclusion is claimed to be supported by one or
more of the other statements. Also keep in mind that in many arguments
that lack indicator words, the conclusion is the first statement. Furthermore,
it helps to mentally insert the word “therefore” before the various
statements before deciding that a statement should be interpreted as a
conclusion.
Inductive Arguments
However, this does not mean that the conclusion is wrong or unacceptable,
where as it could be correct or acceptable but only based on probability.
Thus, inductive arguments are those that involve probabilistic reasoning.
Example-1:
Example-2:
Both of the above arguments are inductive. In both of them, the conclusion
does not follow from the premises with strict necessity, but it does follow
with some degree of probability. That is, the conclusion is claimed to follow
from the premises only probably; or the premises are claimed to support
their corresponding conclusion with a probability. In other words, if we
assume that the premises are true, then based on that assumption it is
probable that the conclusion is true. If we, for example, assume that most
African leaders were blacks and that Mandela was an African leader, then it is
improbable that Mandela not been a black, or it is probable that Mandela was
black. But it is not impossible that Mandela not been a black. Similarly, if we
assume that almost all women are mammals and that Hanan is a woman,
then it is improbable that Hanan not be a mammal, or it is probable that
Hanan is a mammal. But it is not impossible that Hanan not be a mammal.
Thus, the above arguments are best interpreted as inductive.
There are three factors that influence the decision about the deductiveness
or inductiveness of an argument’s inferential claim. These are:
The first factor that influences our decision about a certain inferential claim
is the occurrence of special indicator words. There are different sort of
indicator words that indicate or mark the type of a certain argument.
Arguments may contain some words that indicate the arguer’s certainty and
confidence, or the arguer’s uncertainty or doubt, about the truth of his/her
conclusion. Words like “certainly,’’ “necessarily,” ‘‘absolutely,’’ and
‘‘definitely’’ indicate that the argument should be taken as deductive,
whereas words like, “probable” ‘‘improbable,’’ ‘‘plausible,’’ ‘‘implausible,’’
‘‘likely,’’ ‘‘unlikely,’’ and ‘‘reasonable to conclude” suggest that an argument
is inductive. The point is that if an argument draws its conclusion, using
either of the deductive indicator words, it is usually best to interpret it as
deductive, but if it draws its conclusion, using either of the inductive
indicator words, it is usually best to interpret it as inductive. (Note that the
phrase ‘‘it must be the case that’’ is ambiguous; ‘‘must’’ can indicate either
probability or necessity).
Example-1:
Example-2:
In the first example, the conclusion follows with strict necessity from the
premises. If we assume that all Ethiopian people love their country and that
Debebe is an Ethiopian, then it is impossible that Debebe not love his
country. Thus, we should interpret this argument as deductive. In the second
example, the conclusion does not follow from the premises with strict
necessity, but it does follow with some degree of probability. If we assume
that the premises are true, then based on that assumption it is probable that
the conclusion is true. Thus, it is best to interpret the second argument as
inductive.
Many arguments have a distinctive character or form that indicates that the
premises are supposed to provide absolute support for the conclusion. Five
examples of such forms or kinds of argumentation are arguments based on
mathematics, arguments from definition, and syllogisms: categorical,
hypothetical, and disjunctive syllogisms.
For example, you can put two orange and three bananas in a bag and
conclude that the bag contains five fruits. Or again you can measure a
square pieces of land and after determining it is ten meter on each side
conclude that its area is a hundred square meter. Since all arguments in pure
mathematics are deductive, we can usually consider arguments that depend
on mathematics to be deductive as well. A noteworthy exception, however, is
arguments that depend on statistics are usually best interpreted as
inductive.
For example, one may argue that Angel is honest; it is follows that Angel tells
the truth. Or again, Kebede is a physician; therefore, he is a doctor. These
arguments are deductive because their conclusions follow with necessity
from the definitions “honest” and “physician”.
Example:
Example:
Rewina is either Ethiopian or Eritrean.
Rewina is not Eritrean.
Therefore, Rewina is Ethiopian.
In general, inductive arguments are such that the content of the conclusion
is in some way intended to “go beyond” the content of the premises. The
premises of such an argument typically deal with some subject that is
relatively familiar, and the conclusion then moves beyond this to a subject
that is less familiar or that little is known about. Such an argument may take
any of several forms: predictions about the future, arguments from analogy,
inductive generalizations, arguments from authority, arguments based on
signs, and causal inferences, to name just a few.
Prediction: in a prediction the premises deals with some known event in the
present or the past and the conclusions moves beyond this event to some
event to relative future. For example, one may argue that because certain
clouds develop in the center of the highland, a rain will fall within twenty-four
hours. Nearly everyone realizes that the future cannot be known with
certainty. Thus, whenever an argument makes a prediction about the future
one is usually justified considering the argument inductive.
For example;
All birds are mammals.
A crocodile is a bird.
Therefore, the crocodile is a mammal.
The first is that, there is no middle ground between valid and invalid
argument. That means there are no arguments that are “almost” valid and
“almost” invalid. If the conclusion follows with strict necessity from the
premises, the argument is valid, if not, it is invalid.
To see this argument is valid one must ignore the fact that the premises are
false and attempt to determine that would be true, if the premises were true.
Clearly, if the premises were true, it would follow necessarily that NOKIA is a
computer manufacturer. Thus, the argument is valid.
Just the occurrence of false premises and a false conclusion does not prevent
an argument from being valid, so the occurrence of true premises and a true
conclusion does not guarantee validity.
Note that the truth and falsity of premises and conclusion is irrelevant to the
question of validity except in the case of true premises and a false
conclusion. Any deductive argument having true premises and a false
conclusion is necessarily invalid. This is perhaps the most important fact in
all of deductive logic. The entire system of deductive logic would be quite
useless if it accepted as valid any inferential process by which a person could
start with truth in the premises and arrive at falsity in the conclusion.
A Sound Argument is a deductive argument that is valid and has all true
premises. Both conditions must be met for an argument to be sound, and if
either is missing the argument is unsound.
For example:
All trees are plants.
Acacia is a tree.
Therefore, acacia is a plant.
Examples:
1) This mini-library contains over 10,000 books. 50 books selected at
random were found to be written on philosophy. Thus, it is likely that all
of the books in the minilibrary are books written on philosophy. (Weak
Inductive Argument)
2) This mini-library contains over 10,000 books. 1000 books selected at
random were found to be written on philosophy. Thus, it is likely that all
of the books in the minilibrary are books written on philosophy.
(Strong Inductive Argument)
While Edward Glaser defined critical thinking as: (1) an attitude of being
disposed to consider in a thoughtful way the problems and subjects that
come within the range of one’s experience; (2) knowledge of the methods of
logical enquiry and reasoning; and (3) some skill in applying those methods.
Richard Paul also defines as: Critical thinking is that mode of thinking – about
any subject, content or problem – in which the thinker improves the quality
of his or her thinking by skillfully taking charge of the structures inherent in
thinking and imposing intellectual standards upon them.
1) Clarity
2) Precision
3) Accuracy
5) Consistency
6) Logical Correctness
7) Completeness
In most contexts, we rightly prefer deep and complete thinking to
shallow and superficial thinking. Of course, there are times when it is
impossible or inappropriate to discuss an issue in depth; no one would
expect, for example, a thorough and wide-ranging discussion of the
ethics of the right to selfdetermination in a short newspaper editorial.
However, thinking is better when it is deep rather than shallow,
thorough rather than superficial.
8) Fairness
Critical thinking demands that our thinking be fair - that is, open
minded, impartial, and free of distorting biases and preconceptions.
That can be very difficult to achieve. Even the most superficial
acquaintance with history and the social sciences tells us that people
are often strongly disposed to resist unfamiliar ideas, to prejudge
issues, to stereotype outsiders, and to identify truth with their own self-
interest or the interests of their nation or group. It is probably
unrealistic to suppose that our thinking could ever be completely free
of biases and preconceptions; to some extent, we all perceive reality in
ways that are powerfully shaped by our individual life experiences and
cultural backgrounds. But as difficult as it may be to achieve, basic
fairmindedness is clearly an essential attribute of a critical thinker.
Critical thinkers:
Are honest with themselves, acknowledging what they don't know,
recognizing their limitations, and being watchful of their own errors.
Regard problems and controversial issues as exciting challenges.
Strive for understanding, keep curiosity alive, remain patient with
complexity, and are ready to invest time to overcome confusion.
Base judgments on evidence rather than personal preferences,
deferring judgment whenever evidence is insufficient. They revise
judgments when new evidence reveals error.
Are interested in other people's ideas and so are willing to read and
listen attentively, even when they tend to disagree with the other
person.
Recognize that extreme views (whether conservative or liberal) are
seldom correct, so they avoid them, practice fair-mindedness, and seek
a balance view.
Practice restraint, controlling their feelings rather than being controlled
by them, and thinking before acting.
Uncritical thinkers:
Pretend they know more than they do, ignore their limitations, and
assume their views are error-free.
Regard problems and controversial issues as nuisances or threats to
their ego.
Are inpatient with complexity and thus would rather remain confused
than make the effort to understand.
Base judgments on first impressions and gut reactions. They are
unconcerned about the amount or quality of evidence and cling to their
views steadfastly.
Are preoccupied with themselves and their own opinions, and so are
unwilling to pay attention to others' views. At the first sign of
disagreement, they tend to think, "How can I refute this?"
Ignore the need for balance and give preference to views that support
their established views.
Tend to follow their feelings and act impulsively.
There are many factors that impede critical thinking. Let us examine in detail
five of these impediments that play an especially powerful role in hindering
critical thinking: egocentrism, sociocentrism, unwarranted assumptions,
relativistic thinking, and wishful thinking.
1) Egocentrism
2) Sociocentrism
The second powerful barrier that paralyze the critical thinking ability of
most people including intellectuals is sociocentrism. It is group-
centered thinking. Just as egocentrism can hinder rational thinking by
focusing excessively on the self, so sociocentrism can hinder rational
thinking by focusing excessively on the group. Sociocentrism can
distort critical thinking in many ways. Two of the most important are
group bias and conformism.
Group bias is the tendency to see one’s own group (nation, tribe, sect,
peer group, and the like) as being inherently better than others. Social
scientists tell us that such thinking is extremely common throughout
human history and across cultures.
3) Unwarranted
4) Relativistic Thinking
5) Wishful Thinking
Being a critical person in general and critical thinking in particular has many
benefits. In this lesson, we will discuss some benefits of critical thinking.
Critical thinking teaches you how to raise and identify fundamental questions
and problems in the community. It will teach you to reformulate these
problems clearly and precisely. It will teach you how to gather and assess
relevant information, develop reasoned conclusions and solutions, testing
them against relevant criterion and standards. It teaches you how to be open
minded to alternative system of thought, recognize and assess your own
assumptions, implications and practical consequences, how to communicate
effectively with others in figuring out solutions to complex problems. Critical
thinking is what university is all about.
University is not only about teaching students with facts. It’s about teaching
students to think- think critically.