Preview-9781009276603 A47730773
Preview-9781009276603 A47730773
Facing global climate crisis, Marx’s ecological critique of capitalism more clearly
demonstrates its importance than ever. Marx in the Anthropocene explains why
Marx’s ecology had to be marginalized, and even suppressed by Marxists after
his death, throughout the 20th century. Marx’s ecological critique of capitalism,
however, revives in the Anthropocene against dominant productivism and monism.
Investigating new materials published in the complete works of Marx and Engels
(Marx-Engels-Gesamtausgabe), Kohei Saito offers a wholly novel idea of Marx’s
alternative to capitalism that should be adequately characterized as degrowth
communism. This provocative interpretation of the late Marx sheds new light on
recent debates on the relationship between society and nature and invites readers
to envision a post-capitalist society without repeating the failure of the actually
existing socialism of the 20th century.
Kohei Saito
University Printing House, Cambridge CB2 8BS, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, vic 3207, Australia
314 to 321, 3rd Floor, Plot No.3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre, New Delhi 110025, India
103 Penang Road, #05–06/07, Visioncrest Commercial, Singapore 238467
Cambridge University Press is part of the University of Cambridge.
It furthers the University’s mission by disseminating knowledge in the pursuit of
education, learning and research at the highest international levels of excellence.
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781108844154
© Kohei Saito 2022
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without the written
permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published 2022
Printed in India
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library
ISBN 978-1-108-84415-4 Hardback
ISBN 978-1-009-36618-2 Paperback
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy
of URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication,
and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain,
accurate or appropriate.
For Teinosuke Otani
My teacher, devoted friend
Contents
Acknowledgements ix
List of Abbreviations xiii
Introduction 1
Conclusion 245
References 251
Index 268
Acknowledgements
While working towards the completion of this project since 2017, I have received
generous assistance in various ways from scholars and friends all over the world.
My approach to Marx’s writings benefited immensely from my direct engagement
with an ongoing project of new complete works of Marx and Engels, the
Marx-Engels-Gesamtausgabe. I owe a great deal to my colleagues from the Marx-
Engels-Gesamtausgabe, in particular Gerald Hubmann, Timm Graßmann, Regina
Roth, Claudia Reichel, Jürgen Herres, Rolf Hecker and Carl-Erich Vollgraf in
Berlin, Germany.
I also benefited from the JSPS Overseas Research Fellowship (2016–17),
which enabled me to stay at the Department of Sociology at the University of
California–Santa Barbara to conduct research with Kevin Anderson. His Marx at
the Margins gave me indispensable inspiration for starting this book project. Ryuji
Sasaki and Soichiro Sumida from Japan read and commented upon the entire
manuscript. This time, again, they helped improve the logical consistency and
clarity of the text. In addition, I have frequently discussed this project with my close
colleagues Tomonaga Tairako, Makoto Itoh, Hideto Akashi, Kengo Nakamura and
Midori Wakamori, who always provided me with immense encouragement and
important suggestions. Patrick Eiden-Offe, Judith Dellheim and Terrell Carver
also read and gave me invaluable comments on parts of the manuscript. Others
offered comments in response to talks and papers presented at various conferences
and lectures, especially Michael Heinrich, Frieder Otto Wolf, Christian Zeller,
Bob Jessop, Babak Amini, Bini Adamczak, Kaan Kangal, Paula Rauhala, Joel
Wainwright, Martin Wagner, Yibing Zhang, Ingo Stützle, Michael Löwy, Nick
Srnicek, Michael Hardt, Paul Mason, Paul Burkett and John Bellamy Foster.
During the research, I had precious opportunities to attend various
international conferences and seminars. Earlier versions of parts of this book have
x | Acknowledgements
• C
hapter 1, ‘Marx’s Theory of Metabolism in the Age of Global Ecological
Crisis’, Historical Materialism 28, no 2 (2020): 3–24.
• C hapter 2, ‘Marx & Engels: The Intellectual Relationship Revisited
from an Ecological Perspective’, in Marx’s Capital after 150 Years Critique
and Alternative to Capitalism, ed. Marcello Musto (London: Routledge,
2020), 167–83.
• Chapter 7, ‘Primitive Accumulation as the Cause of Economic and
Ecological Disaster’, in Rethinking Alternatives with Marx, ed. Marcello
Musto (New York: Palgrave, 2021), 93–112.
Finally, it would have been impossible to complete the project without my family,
Mao, Lichto and Lisa, who always supported and encouraged this project and
gave me the passion to envision a better world in this dark time.
Abbreviations
The world is on fire. We are experiencing ‘the end of the end of history’
(Hochuli, Hoare and Cunliffe 2021). With the rapid deepening of the
global ecological crisis in various forms such as climate change, oxidation of
the ocean, disruption of the nitrogen cycle, desertification, soil erosion and
loss of biodiversity, Francis Fukuyama’s declaration of ‘the end of history’
after the collapse of the USSR (Union of Soviet Socialist Republics)
(Fukuyama 1992) is approaching a totally unexpected dead end today, namely
the end of human history. In fact, the triumph of neoliberal globalization only
accelerated the rapid increase in environmental impacts upon the earth by
human activities since the end of the Second World War – the so called ‘Great
Acceleration’, the age in which all major socio-economic and Earth system
trends record a hockey stick pattern of increase (McNeil and Engelke 2016)
– and ultimately destabilized the foundation of human civilization. Pandemic,
war and climate breakdown are all symptomatic of ‘the end of history’, putting
democracy, capitalism and ecological systems into chronic crisis.
Many people are well aware of the fact that the current mode of living
is heading towards catastrophe, but the capitalist system does not offer an
alternative to the juggernaut of overproduction and overconsumption. Nor
is there any compelling reason to believe that it will soon do so because
capitalism’s systemic compulsion continues to employ fossil fuel consumption
despite consistent warnings, knowledge and opposition. Considering the fact
that rapid, deep decarbonization that could meet the 1.5-degree-Celsius
target of the Paris Agreement requires thorough transformative changes in
virtually every sphere of society, more radical social movements embracing
direct action have emerged, demanding to uproot the capitalist system
2 | Marx in the Anthropocene
York 2005; Longo, Clausen and Clark 2015; Holleman 2018).4 Part I of the
current book develops the metabolic rift approach further as the theoretical
and methodological foundation of Marxian political ecology. In addition to
Marx, Part I enriches Marxian ecology by dealing with Friedrich Engels, Rosa
Luxemburg, Lukács György and István Mészáros, because their texts help
comprehend the theoretical scope of the marginalized concept of ‘metabolism’
in Marxism.
However, this project is not simply about how to understand Marx’s
concept of metabolism more correctly. The task of developing Marxian ecology
based on the concept of metabolic rift is worth carrying out as it has a practical
relevance: different approaches to the ecological crisis will provide different
solutions to it. In this context, it is noteworthy that ‘post-Marxist’ attempts
to conceptualize the human–nature relationship in the Anthropocene
against the concept of ‘metabolic rift’ have emerged. They are committed to
philosophical monism. The proponents of the monist view problematize an
‘ontological dualism’ of Marxism (Castree 2013: 177) that they claim fails to
adequately understand the ontological status of nature in the Anthropocene.
Since capitalism thoroughly reconstructs the entire environment, nature as
such does not exist, but is ‘produced’ through capitalist development. Monists,
transcending ontological binarism, insist on replacing it with relational
thinking: everything is a ‘hybrid’ of nature and society. Jason W. Moore
(2015) in particular directs this critique against the concept of ‘metabolic rift’,
claiming that it falls into the Cartesian dualism of ‘Society’ and ‘Nature’. He
instead puts forward a relational understanding of human–nature metabolism.
Yet monism once again revives a failed Prometheanism for the
Anthropocene, justifying the ever-increasing intervention in nature. Such a
‘geo-constructivist’ approach maintains that there is already too much human
intervention in nature in the Anthropocene (Neyrat 2019). Therefore, any
attempt to stop the intervention in fear of environmental destruction is
irresponsible and disastrous because the process is irreversible. According to
the geo-constructivist approach, the only way forward is ‘stewardship’ of the
earth by remaking the whole planet in order to secure human existence in the
future, if not human emancipation. This revival of the Promethean project is
sneaking into Marxist efforts to renew their vision of a post-capitalist future
(Mason 2015; Srnicek and Williams 2016; Bastani 2019). In this context, Part
II of this book offers a reply to various monist and Promethean currents in the
Anthropocene through the lens of Marx’s methodological dualism.
After critically examining the theoretical limitations of both monist and
Promethean views, Part III elaborates on Marx’s ecological vision of a post-
capitalist society in a non-productivist manner. Using the new insights offered
by the MEGA, it demonstrates that through interdisciplinary research in the
6 | Marx in the Anthropocene
natural sciences, humanities and social sciences, the late Marx experienced a
theoretical breakthrough – coupure épistémologique in an Althusserian sense
(Althusser 2005) – after 1868. His last vision of post-capitalism in the 1880s
went beyond ecosocialism, and it can be more adequately characterized as
degrowth communism. This previously unknown idea of degrowth communism
begets useful insights to transcend persistent ‘capitalist realism’. While there
is growing interest in radical approaches today, it is not sufficient simply to
develop an ecosocialist critique of contemporary capitalism. Only by going
back to Marx’s own texts is it possible to offer a positive vision of a future
society for the Anthropocene. Such a radical transformation must be the new
beginning of history as the age of degrowth communism.
However, if Marx really did propose degrowth communism, why has no one
pointed it out in the past, and why did Marxism endorse productivist socialism?
One simple reason is that Marx’s ecology was ignored for a long time. It is thus
first necessary to trace back the moment of its suppression. This genealogy of
(suppressed) Marxian ecology starts with Marx himself. Referring to Marx’s
notebooks on the natural sciences that are published in the MEGA, Chapter
1 establishes Marx’s concept of ‘metabolic rift’ by highlighting the three
dimensions of the ecological rifts and their spatiotemporal ‘shifts’ mediated
by technologies on a global scale. This original insight into capital’s constant
expropriation of nature as the root cause of the metabolic rift was deepened
by Rosa Luxemburg in The Accumulation of Capital, which problematized
the main ‘contradiction’ of capitalism due to its destructive impacts upon the
people and environment in non-capitalist peripheries.
Although she employed the concept of ‘metabolism’, Luxemburg
formulated it as a critique of Marx’s narrow view of capital accumulation.
Her critique implies that Marx’s concept of metabolism was not properly
understood even at that time. This misunderstanding was inevitable because
many of Marx’s writings were unpublished and unavailable to Luxemburg.
Yet this problem also originates in Engels’s attempt to establish ‘Marxism’
as a systematic worldview for the proletariat. In order to trace the original
deformation of Marx’s concept of metabolism, Chapter 2 reconstructs Engels’s
reception of Marx’s theory of metabolism by carefully comparing Engels’s
editorial work on Capital with Marx’s original economic manuscripts as well
as their notebooks published in the MEGA. This investigation reveals subtle
but decisive theoretical differences between Marx and Engels, especially in
terms of their treatment of metabolism. These differences prevented Engels
from adequately appreciating Marx’s theory of metabolic rift, so the concept
of metabolism came to be marginalized in Marxism.
This marginalization is clearly documented in the historical formation
and development of Western Marxism in the 1920s, which further diverged
Introduction | 7
from Marx’s original insight into metabolism and his methodology. Here the
problem of the intellectual relationship between Marx and Engels came to have
a significant influence because it determined the entire paradigm of Western
Marxism. Famously enough, Western Marxism highlighted the rigorous
differentiation of Marx and Engels, accusing the latter’s illegitimate extension
of dialectics to the sphere of nature as a cause of Soviet Marxism’s mechanistic
social analysis. However, despite their harsh critique of Engels, Western
Marxists shared the fundamental assumption with Soviet orthodox Marxism
that Marx had little to say about nature, thereby neglecting the importance of
his concept of metabolism and his ecological critique of capitalism.
As discussed in Chapter 3, the founder of Western Marxism,
Lukács György, is an exceptional figure in that he clearly paid attention to
this concept of metabolism. Although his critique of Engels’s treatment of
nature in History and Class Consciousness had an immense impact on Western
Marxism, he actually had a different approach to the problem of nature
that was formulated as part of his theory of metabolism in his unpublished
manuscript of 1925–6 titled Tailism and the Dialectic. This manuscript
was unknown for a long time, so Lukács’s intention in History and Class
Consciousness was not properly understood, and he was repeatedly criticized
for various theoretical inconsistencies and ambivalences. However, looking at
Tailism and the Dialectic, it becomes clear that his treatment of the relationship
between humans and nature shows a continuity with Marx’s own dualist
methodology that analytically distinguished between the social and the
natural. With this methodology, Lukács’s theory of metabolism provides a
way of developing Marx’s ‘non-Cartesian’ dualism of Form and Matter as a
critique of modern capitalist production. Nevertheless, his unique insight was
suppressed by both orthodox Marxism and Western Marxism, leading to the
marginalization of Marxian ecology throughout the 20th century.
Since Marx’s dualist method is not correctly understood, the concept of
metabolic rift continues to be exposed to various criticisms. Chapter 4 deals
with Marxist versions of the monist view represented by Jason W. Moore’s
‘world ecology’ as well as by Neil Smith’s and Noel Castree’s ‘production
of nature’. Despite their obvious theoretical differences, their monist
understanding of capitalism shows how misunderstanding Marx’s method
generates problematic consequences that have practical relevancy.
As discussed in Chapter 5, the failure to understand Marx’s method
also results in the recent revival of the Promethean idea among Marxists.
These utopian Marxists draw upon Marx’s Grundrisse and argue that a third
industrial revolution based on information technology (for example, artificial
intelligence [AI], sharing economy and Internet of things [IoT]) combined
with full automation could liberate humans from the drudgery of work and
8 | Marx in the Anthropocene
Notes
1 Bill McKibben does not necessarily deny that pristine nature did not exist even
before the 1990s. He instead highlights that the ‘idea’ of nature as independent
from human intervention can no longer be accepted as a valid conceptual tool
due to the increasing human impacts upon nature. This situation has to do with
the recent popularity of monist approaches, as discussed in Chapter 4, although
McKibben does not participate in these debates.
2 Eugene F. Stoermer already used the term ‘Anthropocene’ in the 1980s, although
he employed it in a different sense. A Russian geochemist, Vladimir I. Vernadsky
developed the concept of ‘biosphere’ in the 1920s in order to highlight human
impacts upon the biological life on a planetary scale, which has relevance to
today’s discussion of the Anthropocene (Vernadsky [1926] 1997; Steffen et al.
2011: 844).
3 Naomi Klein (2020) continues to argue for ‘democratic socialism’ in her more
recent book too. Thomas Piketty (2020) also advocates for ‘participatory
socialism’ not only for the sake of social equality but also for sustainability in the
face of climate change. Their endorsement of ‘socialism’ represents a major shift
in the general political tone towards the left.
4 Other recent literature on the metabolic rift approach includes Moore (2000,
2002), Mancus (2007), McMichael (2008), Gunderson (2011) and Weston
(2014).
Part I
Marx’s Ecological Critique of
Capitalism and Its Oblivion
1
Marx’s Theory of Metabolism in the
Age of Global Ecological Crisis*
For quite a long time, Marx’s interest in ecological issues was neglected even
among serious Marxist scholars. Marx’s socialism was said to be characterized
by a ‘Promethean’ (pro-technological, anti-ecological) advocacy for the
domination of nature. Marxists, on the one hand, reinforced this impression by
negatively reacting to environmentalism, which they believed to be inherently
anti-working class and only functioning as an ideology of the upper middle
class. On the other hand, the environmental catastrophe in the USSR –
most notably represented by the ecological collapse of the Aral Sea and the
Chernobyl disaster – reinforced the conviction among environmentalists
that socialism cannot establish a sustainable society. As a consequence, there
emerged a long-standing antagonism between the Red and the Green in the
second half of the 20th century.
The situation is changing in the 21st century. No matter how devastating
actually existing socialism was to the environment, its collapse and the
triumph of capitalism has only contributed to further ecological degradation
under neoliberal globalization in the last few decades. The ineffectiveness of
conventional market-based solutions to ecological issues resulted in a renewed
interest in more heterodox approaches including Marxian economics (Burkett
2006). At the same time, the collapse of the USSR and the declining influence
*
This chapter draws on material from ‘Marx’s Theory of Metabolism in the Age of
Global Ecological Crisis’, Historical Materialism 28, no. 2 (2020): 3–24. Published
with permission. The content is significantly modified, enlarged and updated for the
current book.
14 | Marx in the Anthropocene
I
The Suppression of Marx’s Idea of Ecosocialism
Since the 1970s, Marx was repeatedly accused of a naïve ‘Promethean attitude’
(Giddens 1981: 60): ‘Marx’s attitude toward the world always retained
that Promethean thrust, glorifying the human conquest of nature’ (Ferkiss
1993: 108). Even self-proclaimed Marxists admitted this flaw. For instance,
Leszek Kołakowski (1978: 412) maintained that ‘a typical feature of Marx’s
Prometheanism is his lack of interest in the natural’. According to critics,
Marx’s productivist view ignored the problem of natural limits and naively
praised the free manipulation of nature: Marx was ‘largely uncritical of the
industrial system of technology and the project of human domination of nature’
( J. Clark 1984: 27).They problematized Marx’s optimistic assumption, inherent
to his ‘historical materialism’, that the development of the productive forces
under capitalism should be sufficient to provide a material basis for human
emancipation. Due to the environmental degradation that occurred under
actually existing socialism, environmentalists felt justified in denouncing that