The Sound Shape of Language 3rd ed., with a new preface Edition Linda R. Waugh - Get instant access to the full ebook with detailed content
The Sound Shape of Language 3rd ed., with a new preface Edition Linda R. Waugh - Get instant access to the full ebook with detailed content
com
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-sound-shape-of-
language-3rd-ed-with-a-new-preface-edition-linda-r-waugh/
OR CLICK BUTTON
DOWLOAD EBOOK
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-sound-shape-of-language-3rd-ed-with-
a-new-preface-edition-roman-jakobson/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/prosodic-phonology-with-a-new-
foreword-2nd-ed-with-a-new-preface-edition-marina-nespor/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-power-of-identity-2nd-edition-with-
a-new-preface-edition-manuel-castells/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/mabel-mckay-weaving-the-dream-first-
edition-with-a-new-preface-edition-greg-sarris/
ebookgate.com
The Shape of the Liturgy New Edition Dix
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-shape-of-the-liturgy-new-edition-
dix/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/politics-culture-and-class-in-the-
french-revolution-twentieth-anniversary-edition-with-a-new-preface-
lynn-hunt/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/khubilai-khan-his-life-and-times-20th-
anniversary-edition-with-a-new-preface-morris-rossabi/
ebookgate.com
Mouton de Gruyter
Berlin · New York 2002
Mouton de Gruyter (formerly Mouton, The Hague)
is a Division of Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co. KG, Berlin.
Second Edition: 1987.
This work was originally published in 1979
by Indiana University Press, Bloomington and London.
Jakobson, Roman:
The sound shape of language / Roman Jakobson ; Linda R.Waugh.
Assisted by Martha Taylor. - Berlin ; New York : Mouton de Gruy-
ter, 2002
ISBN 3-11-017285-2
© Copyright 2002 by Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co. KG, 10785 Berlin.
All rights reserved, including those of translation into foreign languages. No part of this
book may be reproduced in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including
photocopy, recording, or any information storage and retrieval system, without permission
in writing from the publisher.
Typesetting: Georg Appl, Wemding.
Printing and binding: Werner Hildebrand, Berlin.
Cover design: Sigurd Wendland, Berlin.
Printed in Germany.
What fetters the mind and benumbs the spirit
is ever the dogged acceptance of absolutes.
Edward Sapir, 1924
The Grammarian and His
Language
CONTENTS
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS XI
NOTE ON TRANSCRIPTION XII
PREFACE TO THE THIRD EDITION (Linda R. Waugh) XIII
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION (Linda R. Waugh) 1
Chapter One
Speech Sounds and Their Tasks 7
I. Spoonerisms 7
II. Sense Discrimination 8
III. Homonymy 9
IV. Doublets 12
V. Early Search 13
VI. Invariance and Relativity 17
VII. Quest for Oppositions 22
VIII. Features and Phonemes 29
IX. Speech Sounds and the Brain 32
X. Redundancy 39
XI. Configurative Features 41
XII. Stylistic Variations 43
XIII. Physiognomic Indices 45
XIV. The Distinctive Features in Relation to the Other
Components of the Speech Sound 46
XV. The Identification of Distinctive Features 53
XVI. Sense Discrimination and Sense Determination 57
XVII. Autonomy and Integration 59
XVIII. Universals 60
XIX. Speech Perception 64
XX. Life and Language 67
XXI. Role of Learning 73
XXII. Speech and Visualized Language 74
XXIII. Multiformity and Conformism 77
XXIV. Inner Speech 81
VIII
Chapter Two
Quest for the Ultimate Constituents 83
I. To the Memory of Pierre Delattre 83
II. Vowel ~ Consonant 87
III. Syllabicity 89
IV. Markedness 92
V. Grave ~ Acute 95
VI. Production and Decoding 98
VII. Compact-Diffuse 101
VIII. Sharpness and Flatness 113
IX. Interrelation of Tonality Features 119
X. And What Now? 123
Chapter Three
The Network of Distinctive Features 125
I. Significance of the Distinctive Features 125
II. The Two Axes 128
III. Nasality 134
IV. Voiced ~ Voiceless and Tense ~ Lax 138
V. Strident- Mellow 142
VI. Consonantal Correspondences to the Prosodic Features . 145
VII. Vowel Harmony 149
VIII. Glides 153
IX. The Nascent Sound Shape 156
X. Dynamic Synchrony 168
XI. Vistas 176
Chapter Four
The Spell of Speech Sounds 181
I. Sound Symbolism 181
II. Synesthesia 191
III. Word Affinities 198
IV. Sound-Symbolic Ablaut 203
V. Speech Sounds in Mythopoeic Usage 208
VI. Verbal Taboo 211
VII. Glossolalia 214
VIII. Sound as the Basis of Verse 218
IX
AFTERWORD 235
APPENDIX ONE
The Role of Phonic Elements in Speech Perception 241
APPENDIX TWO
On the Sound Shape of Language: Mediacy and Immediacy
by Linda R. Waugh 255
REFERENCES 273
ILLUSTRATIONS
1. Magic runes from Bryggen 16
2. Neuroanatomical schema for the auditory asymmetries . . . . 35
3. Delattre's spectrographic pattern of French consonants . . . . 97
4. Spectrograms of American English ba,da, and ga 103
5. X-ray photographs of Czech vowels and consonants 106
6. Title page of C. F. Hellwag's dissertation of 1781 129
7. The vowel triangle in C.F. Hell wag's dissertation 130
8. A cubic graph of the Turkish vowel system 151
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
For support of our work on this book, we thank the Ford Foundation
and its director, McGeorge Bundy.
For gracious assistance in the preparation of our study, thanks are
due to the Massachusetts Institute of Technology; Cornell University;
Ossabaw Island Project and its president, Eleanor Torrey West; Per-
ception Technology Corporation and its director, Hussein Yilmaz; the
Bryggen Museum in Bergen, its director, curator Asbjörn Herteig, and
Aslak Liestol, curator of the Universitetets Oldsaksamling in Oslo; the
Department of Indo-Pacific Languages at the University of Hawaii;
Stanford University Phonology Archives; Harvard University Interli-
brary Loan; and the National Library of Medicine, Bethesda, Mary-
land.
For valuable advice and suggestions we are gratefully indebted to
our friends and colleagues: Milada Blekastad, Sheila Blumstein, Ro-
bert Blust, Dwight Bolinger, the late Jacob Bronowski, Noam Chom-
sky, George N. Clements, Helge Dyvik, Samuel Elbert, Donna Erick-
son, Rachel Erlich, Sigurd Fasting, Charles Ferguson, Eli Fi-
scher-Jorgensen, Ivan Fonagy, Joseph Greenberg, Morris Halle, Einar
Haugen, Charles Hockett, Marcia Howden, Andrew Kerek, Michael
Krauss, Peter Ladefoged, Alvin Libermann, Björn Lindblom, Andre
Malecot, Robert H. Maurer, Sven Öhman, Colin Painter, Donald Pre-
ziosi, Ronald Scollon, Michael Silverstein, Edward Stankiewicz, Ken-
neth Stevens, Michael Studdert-Kennedy, William S.-Y. Wang, Calvert
Watkins, David Waugh, Roger Wescott, Dean S. Worth, and in partic-
ular Gunnar Fant and the late Pierre Delattre. Permission to reproduce
illustrations and texts was kindly granted by Doreen Kimura and Cor-
tex, by S. Blumstein and K. Stevens, by Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, by
Granada Publishing Limited, and by Chappell Music Company.
NOTE ON TRANSCRIPTION
For the vowels we use the official IPA system, except that «(and not y)
designates the high front rounded vowel corresponding to /'. Long
vowels are noted by a macron (e.g., ä), nasal vowels by a tilde (ä).
For the consonants we use the symbols t, d for dental or dentialveo-
lar stops where there is no further distinction. If there is a difference, t
and d are usable for the dental stop, and t° and d° for the alveolar. For
the palatal consonants - stops, fricatives, nasals - we use the principle
used by Slavistic literature and going back to the spelling system estab-
lished by Jan Hus for Czech: a v is placed over or at the top right of the
corresponding dental: , d~ s, , n, c, and j". The last two are palatal af-
fricates corresponding to the dental affricates c and z. (In some sys-
tems of transcription quoted here s and z are rendered as J and 3.) f is a
strident r (as in Czech), and ö are the tense (voiceless) and lax
(voiced) interdental nonstrident continuants. Secondary modifications
of consonants are noted in the following manner: palatalization by '
(e.g., t'); rounding, velarization, or pharyngealization by ° (e.g., t°); ret-
roflexion by. (e.g., t); aspiration by h (e.g., th); glottalization by ? (e.g.,
t?); devoicing by 0 (e.g., d); syllabicity by , (e.g., r).
PREFACE TO THE THIRD EDITION
Linda R. Waugh
Tucson, Arizona
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION
1
Published in 1979 by Indiana University Press and prepared with the assis-
tance of Martha Taylor.
2 PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION
Linda R. Waugh
CHAPTER ONE
I. SPOONERISMS
III. HOMONYMY
IV. DOUBLETS
V. EARLY SEARCH
_L
Figure 1.
Magic runes from Bryggen (Bergen, Norway),
mtpkrgb iiiiiiissssssstttttttiiiiiiilllllll
"mark the long ones with a stroke to distinguish them from the short
ones", and again minimal pairs and illustrative sentences follow: "far
['vessel'] is a kind of ship, but far ['danger'] is a kind of distress". In this
way, as the author states, all thirty-six distinctive vowels of the Icelan-
dic language are taken care of in a new "alphabet for us Icelanders".
On the other hand, the treatise makes use of one and the same letter for
cognate sounds without distinctive capacity, e.g. for the voiced and
voiceless interdentale.
Many remarkable theoretical and empirical assertions of the past,
after suffering long-term disregard and oblivion, reappear, often with
no reference to the original model, and turn into new, effective propo-
sitions. Such was, for instance, the historical destiny of the 2000-year-
old Stoic thesis which treated the sign, SEMEION, as an entity constitut-
ed by the two correlatives: the SEMAINON ('the signifier') and the sE-
MAINOMENON ('the signified'). In the last semester of his series of
courses in linguistic theory, Saussure took over and emphatically rec-
ommended this formula - "le signifiant et le signifie sont les deux ele-
ments composant le signe" (1916: 152; cf. Golebiewski) - and it en-
tered into his posthumous Cours de linguistique generate, compiled by
Saussure's disciples Charles Bally (1865-1947) and Albert Sechehaye
(1870-1946) and published in 1916. This thesis, often mistakenly
viewed as an invention of the Genevan, is unsurpassed because of its
clear ascertainment of the two semiotic constituents, one (SEMAINON,
'signans', signifiant) directly given and the other (SEMAINOMENON,
'signatum', signifie) prompted by the first. Both abstract and concrete
questions of the relationship between signans and signatum in the
realm of signs (signa) and especially in the various aspects of language
belong to the continuously increasing penetrations into the cultural life
of humanity which engender ever-new solutions and ever-new puzzles.
of structure "it is not things that matter but the relations between
them", an idea which found a manifold expression in contemporane-
ous sciences and arts, was a main guide for the exponents of the
Prague Linguistic Circle, founded in 1926. They endeavored to derive
the characteristics of phonemes from the interrelations of these units
and in the "Project of Standardized Phonological Terminology" of
1930 they defined a 'phonological unit' as a term of an opposition. The
concept of Opposition' took on fundamental importance for the inqui-
ry into sound differences able to serve in a given language for the dif-
ferentiation of cognitive meanings. The question of the relationship
between the sense-discriminative units became the necessary require-
ment for any delineation of functional sound systems.
146ff.), and the principle of basing such an analysis upon a relative ap-
proach met with his express approval.
Saussure's basic definition of differential units as "negative, relative
and oppositive" has been seminal. The idea of opposition as the pri-
mary logical operation universally arising in humans from the first
glimmerings of consciousness in infants and from youngsters' initial
steps in the buildup of language was viewed as the natural key to the
inquiry into verbal structure from its highest to its lowest levels. The in-
alienable property of opposition which separates it from all other, con-
tingent differences is, when we are dealing with one opposite, the obli-
gatory copresence of the other one in our minds, or in other words, the
impossibility of evoking long without a simultaneous, latent idea of
short, or expensive without cheap, 'voiced' without 'voiceless', and vice
versa, as was for the first time (1938,1939) brought to light and lucidly
demonstrated by the Dutch theoretician of language Hendrik Pos (cf.
below pp. 176 f.). When contending in the 1930s with the idea of oppo-
sition, linguists were unacquainted with Charles Sanders Peirce's
(1839-1914) writings, which offer an astute insight into the "particular
features of language" and into the concept of opposition: "The natural
classification takes place by dichotomies" (Peirce 1.437); "A dyad con-
sists of two subjects brought into oneness" (1.326); "Essential dyadic
relation: existence lies in opposition merely" (1.457). In Peirce's par-
lance "a dual relative term, such as 'lover', 'benefactor', 'servant' is a
common name signifying a pair of objects". Every "relative has also a
converse, produced by reversing the order of the members of the pair.
Thus the converse of 'lover' is 'loved' " (III.238 & 330).
Curiously enough, some American linguists insisted on the replace-
ment of the allegedly un-American term Opposition' by the less telling
and more ambiguous label 'contrast', despite the remarkable commen-
tary on opposition given by this most prominent American thinker. It
becomes a fundamental, operational concept not only for language (cf.
Ivanov 1974), but also for social structure in general (cf. Lorrain 1975;
Levi-Strauss 1958: 37 ff., 93 ff., 257 ff., 1963, and 1971: 240 ff., 498 ff.,
539f.; Parsons & Bales 1955; Blanche 1966; Fox 1974, 1975, 1977).
Franfois Lorrain opens his research on social systems by arguing for
"the privileged place of binary oppositions in the human mind" (p. 17).
In his dense essay on intellectual structures, R. Blanche (p.15) insists
on the importance of such oppositional structures: they should not be
underestimated, and in particular the organization of concepts by ad-
versative couples appears to be an original, permanent form of thought
SPEECH SOUNDS AND THEIR TASKS 25
and the Dutch shift to [xt] from [ft] with achter for after (Kaiser 1929:
119); or - for stops - the Celtic change of vesper into fescor; or the in-
terchange between [fj and [x] in various Slavic dialects, for instance in
Polish na ftorym, xtorek and Slovenian kozuch> kozuf, chruska>
fruska, krxka> krfka, plexko> plefko, and the reverse Czech substitu-
tion of the labial preposition by a velar one, [x] before voiceless obstru-
ents: ch Tumove, chpravit, ch Cechach and [y] before voiced ones: hbeh-
nou, h Vysokym, h Jablonci, or Russian dialectal forms with velars in-
stead of labials: dexka, verexka, xlex kuzox, x cerkox (v cerkov), krox,
oxtomik, and a corresponding change of [v] into [γ]: y lese, γ wy/ιί (v ug-
lu), ynuk, ydovec, y dom, as well as reverse changes of velars into la-
bials \fto, lefko, if,fodit',fajat'. The Russian dialectal changes of [g] or [γ]
into [v] may be exemplified by the masculine genitive ending of adjec-
tives and pronouns, -ovo, and also by such forms as povost from pogost
or mnovo from mnogo, as well as the exchange between [x] and [fj in
words of foreign origin, such as kufarka instead of kuxarka, xrancus in-
stead offrancus, and xrukt instead offrukt. In some Indonesian (name-
ly Eastern Toba-Batak) dialects, [p] in general changes into [k]: for in-
stance piso 'knife' > kiso (see Meillet & Cohen 1924: 418 f.). Also typi-
cal are the Czech dialectal variant kafez instead ofparezand such chil-
dren's oscillations between velars and labials as Czech telefon and vou-
sy changed into exon and xosi or in Peking Chinese xurj from fug (see
Ohnesorg 1959: 30,44).
It was especially in this and similar connections that the question of
a property joining labials with velars in opposition to the common fea-
ture of dentals and palatals, as well as the question of the feature com-
mon to labials and dentals in contradistinction to that of velars and
palatals, was brought into consideration, especially since each of these
paired groups displays characteristic interchanges in the history of
world languages. The preliminary solution to this complex of ques-
tions and to the problem of interconnections between the consonantal
and vocalic patterns was presented for discussion at the Third Interna-
tional Congress of Phonetic Sciences in Ghent in 1938 (See RJ I:
272 ff.), on the eve of the world events which put an end to the Prague
phonological deliberations and in general radically changed the to-
pography of international scientific activities.
Any notion of opposites is inseparable from the notion of opposi-
tion as such and neither of the two opposites can function in the neigh-
borhood of other concurrent or successive features if such a neighbor-
hood excludes the appearance of the other opposite. If instead of the
SPEECH SOUNDS AND THEIR TASKS 27
This however does not end the evidence of the Argive Heraeum.
Some thirty years ago the site was excavated by the American School
of Archaeology at Athens. Among the finds was a bundle of iron spits
or rods about four feet long (fig. 21) which Svoronos[837] has plausibly
associated with the ὀβελίσκοι of the Etymologicum Magnum.
The Americans ascribed the foundation of the Heraeum to the
Mycenaean period, so that the dedication of the spits could be put
anywhere in the three centuries that form the limit of controversy as
to Pheidon’s date. But more recently this dating has been shown to
be mistaken by the Germans who excavated Tiryns. Whole series of
miniature vessels which the Argive Heraeum excavators had
regarded as Mycenaean were shown by the Tiryns excavators to be
seventh century or later, and when one of them, Frickenhaus, visited
the Argive Heraeum, he found fragments of Geometric and proto-
Corinthian pottery in positions which proved the sherds to be older
than the temple foundations. From this fact he argues conclusively
that the abundant series of dedications at the Heraeum begin in the
seventh century. Pheidon’s ὀβελίσκοι cannot therefore go further
back than that[838]. The Mycenaean objects from the Argive Heraeum
site must all come from a small secular settlement that preceded the
temple. The latter becomes possibly contemporary with Pheidon
himself.
This is a fact of possible significance. It suggests that the Heraeum
may have been the religious centre of Pheidon’s imperial policy, a
sort of religious federal capital carefully placed away from the chief
cities of the Argolid much as the federal capital of Australia has been
placed away from the capitals of the various Australian states. It
looks indeed as though the analogy may have been closer still, and
that Pheidon was the builder of his federal capital. If so his date was
some time, probably early, in the seventh century.
This ends the evidence of the Heraeum B. Fresh
and brings me to the most important evidence from
section of my argument. We have just seen Herodotus.
how little need there is to mistrust Ephorus simply because he does
not exactly reproduce Herodotus. All the same the earlier writer is of
course by far the more reliable. The account of Pheidon’s coinage in
Aegina would gain enormously in credibility if any evidence for it
could be found in the pages of Herodotus. Modern writers without
exception have taken it for granted that no such evidence is to be
found. In this I believe them to have been mistaken. There is a
passage in the fifth book which, though it does not mention
Pheidon’s name, I believe to describe the conquest by him of Aegina
and the institution as a result of that conquest of the weight standard
on which the earliest Aeginetan coins were struck. If my explanation
has not been anticipated, there is no reason for surprise. The passage
contains references to pottery, ships, dress, and jewellery, and my
interpretation of it is based on archaeological evidence much of
which has only quite recently become available.
In the passage of the fifth book which we Herodotus, V. 82
[839]
are now to examine Herodotus is f. describes an
explaining the origin of the hatred that Argive
intervention in
existed between Athens and Aegina in 500 Aegina,
B.C. Aegina had once been subject to
Epidaurus[840]. Then the Aeginetans, having built triremes and made
themselves masters of the sea[841], revolted. Through their revolt they
got embroiled with the Athenians, who had at that time very close
relations with Epidaurus. At the suggestion of the Epidaurians, the
Athenians sailed against Aegina. The Aeginetans appealed to Argos,
and with the help of an Argive force that crossed undetected from
Epidaurus, utterly defeated the Athenians in a land battle on the
island. The various measures[842] taken in common by the Aeginetans
and the Argives immediately after the war suggest that Aegina, when
she had revolted from Epidaurus, became in some sort a confederate,
or possibly a subject, of Argos[843]. We may assume too that Argos
secured some sort of control over Epidaurus in the course of the war.
Otherwise it is inconceivable that an Argive force should have set out
from Epidaurus with the double purpose of aiding Epidaurus’
revolted subjects and attacking those very Athenians, whose
expedition against the island had been suggested by the Epidaurians
themselves[844]. The crushing defeat that the Athenians sustained
may have been due to the collapse of her Epidaurian allies.
One further point about Herodotus’ narrative should be noticed.
There is nothing in it to suggest that at the time when the Aeginetans
revolted from the Epidaurians, either of them was dependent on
Argos. The narrative points rather to a previous confederation or
dominion in which the chief cities were Epidaurus, Aegina, and not
Argos but Athens. Are there any indications as to when all this
occurred?
The reference is to a time considerably[845] previous to 500 B.C.
Macan thinks that the most probable date for the expedition to
Aegina is somewhere in the lifetime of Solon or Peisistratus[846]. He
points to various circumstances that generally
certainly might well have led to a collision ascribed to the
between Athens and Aegina during that first half of the
sixth century,
period[847]. All the same it is difficult to
accept a date within those limits. The Aeginetans are not likely[848] to
have been dependent on Epidaurus after it was conquered by
Periander, about 600 B.C.[849] If therefore the revolt from Epidaurus
and the Athenian invasion are incidents in one and the same
struggle, both must go into the seventh century. Macan prefers to
assume a long interval between these two events. But Herodotus
gives no hint of one. On the contrary, his narrative hangs excellently
together as a description of successive and correlated incidents in a
single struggle. Not only so, but even if the invasion be separated
from the revolt, it is difficult to believe that it occurred after 590. So
crushing a defeat for the Athenians, who themselves admitted that
only one of their number got back to Attica[850], could hardly have
taken place in the time of Solon or Peisistratus without being
associated with their names. After all, a fair amount is known about
sixth century Athens. There are no traces of any such overwhelming
disaster, or of the inevitable set back that would have followed it. The
relations of Athens to Argos during the period seem to have been
friendly rather than the reverse. Peisistratus had Argive mercenaries,
not to speak of an Argive wife[851]. Argive support of Peisistratus is of
course quite consistent with hostility to the government that
Peisistratus overthrew. It has indeed been suggested[852] that the
Aeginetan expedition took place while Peisistratus was in exile. But,
apart from the entire absence of evidence, and all the other
difficulties involved by a sixth century date, this suggestion means
that Peisistratus sought a bodyguard and wife in the most unpopular
quarter imaginable, hardly a probable proceeding on the part of a
ruler so tactful and popular as Peisistratus must have been.
A date late in the seventh century is rendered unlikely by what is
known of Procles of Epidaurus[853], the father-in-law of Periander,
who ruled Epidaurus during the last part of the seventh century[854],
apparently as a dependent of the Corinthian tyrant, by whom he was
eventually deposed. C. Mueller indeed[855] claims Aegina for Procles,
but only on the more than dubious evidence of a more than dubious
story of Plutarch’s, which tells how Procles once used an “Aeginetan
stranger” to get rid of the corpse of a man whom he had murdered
for his money[856].
On the whole the narrative seems to fall but more
best into the first half of the seventh probably to be
century. That is the time that best suits the dated early in the
seventh, as
naval situation during the war, and the shown by
effect that it is said to have had upon archaeological
costume, ornament, and pottery. As the evidence on
archaeological evidence for all these points allusions in the
is based largely on the evidence of the narrative to:
pottery, it will be best to take the pottery
first.
In the temple of Damia and Auxesia on (i) pottery,
Aegina it became the practice (νόμος) after
the war “to introduce into the temple neither anything else Attic nor
pottery, but to drink there henceforth only out of native jars[857].”
Herodotus mentions this embargo on Attic pottery only as applied to
the one temple on Aegina[858]. But he states that it was observed by
Argives as well as by Aeginetans, which points to the possibility that
the practice prevailed in Argos as well as Aegina. Macan goes as far
as to suggest that it is an “understatement and pseudo-explanation of
a measure or custom for the protection of native ware from Attic
competition[859].” The other measures recorded in this connexion, the
changes in Attic dress and in Peloponnesian brooches, support
Macan’s suggestion. But in the matter of dating he follows earlier
writers who, using very inadequate material, came to conclusions
which can now be shown to be improbable. They date this embargo
in the middle of the sixth century. But in Aegina at any rate Attic
pottery continued to be imported throughout the second half of the
sixth century, while in Argos, where the evidence is less decisive and
abundant, there is no sign of a cessation of Attic imports about 550
B.C. On the other hand both in Argos and Aegina there does appear
to be an abrupt cessation of Attic imports early in the seventh
century. As, further, the general history of Greek pottery shows that
an Argive-Aeginetan embargo on Attic pottery would have had a
strong commercial motive early in the seventh century and none in
the middle of the sixth, there is a strong presumption that the date of
the embargo was not the middle of the sixth century but somewhere
about the beginning of the seventh. To examine the archaeological
evidence here in detail would take us too far from our main enquiry.
It will be found presented in full in an appendix[860].
The war was a great disaster for Athenian (ii) sea-power
naval power. Now the period of greatest and ships,
eclipse for Athens from this point of view was the seventh century.
Throughout it there is no indication whatever of naval activity at
Athens, except a possible war against Mitylene. Even that must be
put at the earliest close on the year 600 B.C., and is to be regarded as
announcing the beginning of the new epoch of activity in the sixth
century[861]; and against it must be set the failure in the struggle with
Megara for Salamis[862]. This had not been the naval position of
Athens earlier. During the dark ages she appears to have been a
considerable naval power. A tradition preserved by Plutarch makes
Athens succeed Crete in the command of the sea[863]: naval power is
implied in Theseus’ expedition to Crete; a poem of Bacchylides[864],
which is illustrated by a vase painting of Euphronios[865], tells how
Theseus went to the depths of the sea to fetch up the ring of Minos,
and the story has been brought by S. Reinach into connexion with
rings such as those of Polycrates and the doges of Venice, and
explained as symbolizing the winning by Theseus of the sea which
had been previously the bride of Minos[866].
The date of these events must not be pressed. The period of this
sea-power is plainly the dark age that followed the breaking up of the
Cretan and Mycenaean civilization. It is the period of the pottery
known as Geometric, and the Athenian Geometric, the Dipylon ware,
again and again shows pictures of ships. Thirty-nine examples are
quoted by Torr[867], enough, as pointed out by Helbig[868], to prove the
important rôle played by the Athenian navy in the life of Athens of
that age. The Dipylon ships, as remarked twenty years ago by
Helbig[869], show that already in the eighth century Athens was
preparing to found her power on her navy. It requires some such
catastrophic explanation as has just been offered to account for her
complete set back in the seventh.
One result in Athens of the reverse in (iii) dress.
Aegina, so Herodotus declares, was a
revolution in the dress of the Athenian women, who gave up the
Doric costume, which was made of wool and fastened with pins, and
adopted in its place the Ionic, which consisted of sewn garments
made of linen. The passage is a locus classicus among writers on
Greek dress, and it must be at once admitted that nearly all of them
accept a date late in the first half of the sixth century[870]. So late a
date seems to me to be untenable. It can be reconciled neither with
the statements of Thucydides on the subject of Athenian dress[871],
nor with the evidence of extant monuments[872]. The sumptuary laws
on women’s dress passed by Solon in 594 B.C.[873] were plainly
directed against the Ionian costume. They show that it must have
reached Athens by about 600 B.C. and offer no evidence that it had
not done so considerably earlier. Bury dates the introduction of
Ionian dress into Athens “c. 650 (?)[874].”
Among the Aeginetans and Argives as a After the war the
result of their victory over Athens a change Argives and
was introduced in what Herodotus calls the Aeginetans make
their brooches
“measure” (μέτρον) of Aeginetan and Argive “half as big
brooches (περόναι). Herodotus states that again.”
this change affected both the dedications at
the temple of Damia and Auxesia[875], and also the general
manufacture and use. The way he tells the story explains why he goes
beyond the temple when speaking of the pins, but does not do so in
the case of the pottery. The exclusion of Attic pottery from the
Aeginetan temple, or rather the exclusive use for temple purposes of
local ware, was in Herodotus’ days a ritualistic survival. The large
brooches on the other hand had continued in general use. “Now the
women of Argos and Aegina even to my own days wore brooches of
increased size.” Very possibly Herodotus had himself noticed them.
It is the account of this change in the “measure” of the Aeginetan and
Argive brooches that confirms the connexion of Pheidon with the
origin of the Aeginetan coinage.
The new practice was in Herodotus’ own words: “to make the
brooches half as big again as the then established measure.” It is
probably significant that, both before and after the change, the
brooches have a standard “measure.” The tendency of articles of
jewellery in early periods to be of a fixed weight is a familiar one.
Numerous instances are quoted in Ridgeway’s Origin of Metallic
Currency[876]. Not only so, but these fixed weights are repeatedly
found corresponding with or anticipating the coin standards of the
places they belong to.
It may be objected that the word μέτρον does not mean weight.
This is so when it is contrasted with σταθμός[877]; but it appears to
have been used also in a more comprehensive sense[878]. The
Athenian μετρονόμοι[879] must have inspected weights as well as
measures. μέτρον is presumably applied to both, and to a fifth
century Greek there would be no question of its referring to anything
but weight when applied to jewellery[880].
The change introduced by the Argives and The Aeginetan
Aeginetans after driving the Athenians from drachma was
Aegina was to make the “measure” of their half as big again
as the Attic.
brooches half as big again as what it had
previously been. Now this is approximately the relationship in weight
of the earliest Aeginetan drachmae to the earliest drachmae struck
on the Euboeic standard. Later, in Herodotus’ own times, the relative
weights were four to three. But the earliest Aeginetan drachmae
weighed a little more than those of later issues[881]. On the other
hand, as stated by Percy Gardner[882] in discussing Solon’s
“augmentation” of the Athenian coins, the earliest Attic or rather
Euboeic drachma[883] weighed less than those of post-Solonian times.
The weight of the Aeginetan drachma as determined from the early
didrachms quoted above (p. 171, n. 6) is just over six grammes, as
compared with the 5·85 grammes of later issues, while that of the
earliest Attic Euboeic drachma as determined from the coins of p.
171, n. 8 is just over four grammes, as compared with the 4·26
grammes of later issues[884].
Thus the original Aeginetan drachma seems to have been just half
as heavy again as the earliest Attic[885]. This ratio is accepted by
Ridgeway[886], who regards it as invented to make ten silver pieces
worth one gold when gold was fifteen times as precious as silver,
while later, when silver rose to be worth 3/40 of its weight in gold,
the silver pieces were slightly diminished in weight, in order that ten
of them might still be the equivalent of one of gold[887].
Let us now return to the one passage of Summary of the
Herodotus, in which he refers by name to evidence of
the Argive tyrant. Herodotus.
In that passage he speaks of Pheidon as “the man who made their
measures for the Peloponnesians[888].” The force of the definite
article that precedes the Greek μέτρα has not always been sufficiently
stressed. More than one recent writer begins his discussion of the
passage by translating τὰ μέτρα “a system of measures.” The
subsequent argument has naturally suffered. τὰ μέτρα can be no
other measures than those associated with the Peloponnesus in
Herodotus’ own days, namely those of the famous Aeginetan
standard, employed in particular for the coinage of the island[889].
Other scholars have regarded the statement that Pheidon struck the
first coins in Aegina as merely an amplification by later writers of
these very words. They argue that “the measures” plainly meant the
Aeginetan standard, and so suggested the famous Aeginetan coinage.
This latter view assumes of course that the amplifications of Ephorus
are not to be found in Herodotus himself. But what are the facts? The
establishment of Aeginetan measures in the Peloponnesus are
alluded to by Herodotus not only in the passage about the Argive
tyrant in Book VI but also very possibly in the passage in Book V that
describes the early Argive expedition to Aegina. In this latter passage
the measures are said to have been the result of the expedition. Both
expedition and tyrant are probably to be dated early in the seventh
century. That is also the date to which numismatists generally assign
the first drachmae struck in Aegina, struck too on a standard that,
like that of our brooches, was half again as great as that previously in
use.
It is hard to avoid the inference that when the fourth century
writers say that Pheidon coined in Aegina, they are faithfully
reporting a genuine tradition.
It has indeed been maintained that the Sceptical views
whole Herodotean account of the early on these
relations of Argos, Aegina, and Athens is chapters of
Herodotus stated
unhistorical[890]. The arguments brought and answered.
forward to support this destructive view
are: (i) that the episode is timeless and its timelessness must be due
to its unhistorical character, (ii) that it must be unhistorical because
it cannot, as alleged by Herodotus, have been the cause of the war of
487 B.C., which must have been due to the natural rivalry of the two
neighbouring states. As regards the first of these two arguments, the
preceding pages have, it is hoped, shown that the episode is not
timeless: as regards the second, it is enough to point out that it
assumes that war cannot breed war, that no war can be due to two
causes, and that an incident cannot be historical if it is alleged as
leading to results that it cannot have in fact produced. The fact that
arguments such as these were accepted for publication in a periodical
of high repute less than a generation back shows how much the
whole world of scholarship was infected by the spirit of uncritical
scepticism that has left its mark in some quarters on that of the
present age.
Others again like Wilamowitz[891] regard the narrative of
Herodotus V. 82–88 as simply a reflexion backwards of the state of
affairs existing in 487 B.C.[892], when Athens attacked Aegina, and the
Aeginetans “called to their aid the same people as before, the
Argives[893].” They argue that (i) the story is our only evidence for
hatred between Athens and Aegina much before 506 B.C., (ii) the
Argive-Aeginetan brooches as compared with the broochless
Athenian costume[894], the embargo on Attic pottery at the Aeginetan
temple, and the posture of the kneeling statues (pleading before the
Athenian invaders) may all have been referred in Herodotus’ days to
the existing hatred and recent wars between Athens and Aegina, (iii)
Herodotus puts back the Athenian disaster into the timeless period
because the miracle and the change of costume required an early
date, and the story does not fit the war of 487 B.C., since the famous
Sophanes[895], who fought in it, lived till 464. Herodotus, they say,
gives no account of a disaster to the Athenian fleet in 487 because he
had used it up for this early reflexion.
Of these points (i) is answered by the whole of this chapter, (ii) and
(iii) fall with (i), besides which (ii) contains many improbabilities,
e.g. that the pottery in an Aeginetan temple should without historic
reason have suggested to any fifth century Greek an early war with
Athens, while (iii) assumes an Athenian disaster in 487 B.C., whereas
Thucydides declares that Athens was successful in that war[896].
There is nothing suspicious in the Aeginetans having twice in two
hundred years attained some sort of thalassocracy, and having on
both occasions come as a result into collision with Athens. It is
perfectly natural for the Aeginetans on a second occasion to appeal to
allies who had previously helped them so effectively and with such
profit to themselves. Macan[897] observes that the Herodotean
account of the feud between Athens and Aegina is remarkably
uninfluenced by contemporary politics and interests. He suggests[898]
dating the subjection of Aegina to Epidaurus to the reign of Pheidon,
and the revolt of the island from Epidaurus to the time of Pheidon’s
fall. But why in that case does the account speak of a revolt from
Epidaurus, if it was really a revolt from the famous Argive tyranny?
The whole narrative finds a more appropriate setting if regarded as
one chapter in the history of Pheidon himself.
Only, why in this case is the name of Why Pheidon is
Pheidon nowhere mentioned? It is one not mentioned in
thing to omit details in a biography four them.
lines in length. It is quite another to omit so prominent a name in a
narrative that runs to seven whole chapters. But the omission,
though at first sight surprising, is capable of explanation. The
Herodotean story appears to have been derived from the temple of
Damia and Auxesia[899]. It was told Herodotus not in connexion with
any royal monument, but to explain certain offerings of pottery and
jewellery that he saw in the temple. Not a single personal name
occurs in the whole narrative, and there is no particular reason why
there should. There may actually have been motives for not
introducing them. The account of the events given to Herodotus in
the Aeginetan temple of Damia and Auxesia would naturally not
emphasize the part played by the Argive tyrant. The Athenian
version, to which also Herodotus alludes, would have still better
reason for trying to forget the name of Pheidon. If my whole
interpretation of these events is not entirely wrong, Pheidon dealt
the Athenians what was probably the most crushing blow they had
ever received down to the days when Herodotus wrote his history.
The personal name may be omitted from the same motive that made
the Athenians speak of the Aeginetan drachma as the “fat” drachma,
which they are said to have done, “refusing to call it Aeginetan out of
hatred of the Aeginetans[900].” Sparta again had taken sides against
Pheidon at Olympia[901], and would have had no interest in
perpetuating the name of the man who had almost barred their way
to the hegemony of the Peloponnese.
Ephorus’ account of Pheidon’s conquests and inventions is derived
neither from Attic nor from Aeginetan sources. As seen already[902]
the source of his statement about Pheidon coining in Aegina was
most probably the Argive Heraeum. Herodotus claims to use Argive
sources, but for him the war is primarily a matter between the
Athenians and the Aeginetans, whose subsequent hatred of one
another it is intended to explain. Thus we appear to have three rival
or even hostile traditions confirming one another, so that the variety
of sources adds in a real way to the credibility of the resultant
narrative.
The notices about the coinage are not the Pheidon and
only evidence for associating Pheidon with Aegina, further
Aegina. According to Ephorus “he evidence from
Ephorus:
completely recovered the lot of Temenos, Pheidon
which had previously been split into several recovered the lot
parts[903].” Temenos appears in the of Temenos,
genealogies as great great grandson of which included
Heracles, and founder of the Dorian Aegina.
dynasty at Argos[904]. He and his sons and his son-in-law between
them are represented as securing the greater part of the North-east
Peloponnese. Aegina fell to his son-in-law Deiophontes, who went to
the island from Epidaurus[905].
The operations described in Herodotus V. 82–88, by which the
Argives crossed from Epidaurus and drove the Athenians out of
Aegina and put an end to the Epidaurians being tributary to
Athens[906], are almost beyond doubt to be identified with the
recovery by Argos of the portion of the lot of Temenos that had been
secured by Deiophontes.
It is true that this account of the recovery Traces of this
of the lot of Temenos is first certainly met recovery in other
with in Strabo, whose authority is only the passages of
Herodotus.
fourth century Ephorus. But there are hints
that Ephorus is here to be trusted. There is the evidence of
Herodotus that from an unspecified earlier date down to about 550
B.C. the Argives had possessed the whole east coast of the
Peloponnesus and “the island of Cythera and the rest of the
islands[907].” The most likely period for Argos to have acquired this
territory is the reign of Pheidon. Pheidon according to Strabo[908]
“had deprived the Spartans of the hegemony of the Peloponnese,”
and it is the Spartans who shortly before Croesus asked for their
help, had wrested from the Argives “Cythera and the rest of the
islands.” About 668 B.C., i.e. probably in Pheidon’s reign, the Argives
had beaten the Spartans in the battle of Hysiae, which decided the
possession of the strip of coast land south of the Argolid[909].
Aegina is not mentioned in these proceedings, but C. Mueller may
be right in including it among “the rest of the islands[910].” The Hysiae
campaign is roughly contemporary with the second Messenian war,
in which Argos took part against the Spartans[911], and of which
indeed it may have been an incident. Now in that war the Samians
took part by sea against the Argives[912], and it is natural to connect
this action of theirs with their repeated attacks on Aegina in the days
of the Samian King Amphikrates, at some period indefinitely before
the reign of Polycrates. The Samians were certainly a naval power in
the first half of the seventh century. The four triremes built for them
in 704 B.C. marked for Thucydides an epoch in naval history[913].
About 668 B.C. Kolaios the Samian made his famous voyage beyond
the Straits of Gibraltar to the Spanish seaport of Tartessus, a voyage
that implies much previous naval enterprise on the Samians’ part.
The rivalry with Aegina was probably commercial. Kolaios and his
crew returned from the “silver rooted streams” of the Tartessus
river[914], having “made the greatest profits from cargoes of all Greeks
of whom we have accurate information, excepting Sostratos the
Aeginetan: for it is impossible for anyone else to rival him[915].”
Samian attacks on Aegina are thus particularly likely to have
happened about the time of the second Messenian war.
A century ago C. Mueller[916] argued that some event or other
connecting Samos with Aegina must have been closely connected
with the revolt of Aegina from Epidaurus, since the revolt was
described in the History of Samos of the Samian historian Duris
(born about 340 B.C.)[917]. From this he proceeds to advocate a date
for the revolt not very long before the war between Samos and
Aegina of 520 B.C. Arguments based on the laws of digression
observed by a writer whose works are known to us only in a few
fragments need to be used with caution. If Duris is any indication
whatever for the date of the revolt, he leaves an open choice between
the time of the war of 520 B.C. and that of the days of King
Amphikrates; and as between these two the evidence shows that the
earlier is probable while the latter is almost impossible.
As independent evidence these hints would be of scarcely any
value. As confirmation of a definite but disputable statement their
value is considerable.
The recovery of ancestral domains is a Summary of
favourite euphemism among military Pheidon’s
conquerors for their policy of annexation. activities
according to
The chronology, both relative and absolute,
Strabo (=
of Strabo’s summary of Pheidon’s career Ephorus).
has every appearance of authenticity.
Pheidon first recovers the lot of Temenos, then “invents” his
measures and coinage, and after that attempts to expand eastwards
and southwards to secure the whole inheritance of Heracles, or in
other words aims at the suzerainty of the whole Peloponnese, and to
that end celebrates the Olympian games. This last event is probably
to be dated 668 B.C. The coinage must be put indefinitely earlier in
his reign, a perfectly reasonable date on numismatic and historical
grounds, and the recovery of the lot of Temenos a few years earlier
still.
The date thus reached is confirmed by the histories of the two
other leading cities of this part of the Peloponnese, Sicyon and
Corinth.
Sicyon formed part of the lot of Temenos, Pheidon and
[918]
and was held by his son Phalkes . About other parts of the
670 B.C. the city fell under the tyranny of lot of Temenos:
(i) Sicyon.
the able and powerful family of Orthagoras,
whose policy was marked by extreme hostility to Argos[919]. Pheidon
plainly can have had no footing in Sicyon during the rule of the
Orthagorids. But the unusual stability and popularity of the tyranny
at Sicyon have often been explained, not without reason, as due to its
popular anti-Dorian policy. During the second Messenian war, which
Pausanias dates 686–668 B.C.[920], so that the rise of Orthagoras
coincides with its conclusion, the Sicyonians appear to have acted in
close co-operation with the Argives[921]. The position and policy of the
Sicyonian tyrants becomes particularly comprehensible if they had
risen to power as leaders of a racial uprising that put an end in the
city to a Dorian ascendancy that dated originally from the days of
Temenos[922] and had been revived by Pheidon[923].
Whether Corinth formed part of the lot of (ii) Corinth.
Temenos is uncertain. Probably it did.
Strabo and Ptolemy exclude the city from the Argolid[924]. But on the
other hand Homer speaks of it as being “in a corner of horse rearing
Argos[925],” and Pausanias states that “the district of Corinth is part of
Argolis[926],” and that he believes it to have been so in Homeric
times[927]. The conflicting statements of these excellent authorities
are best reconciled by supposing them to be referring to different
periods. If this is so, and if, as well might be, all the domains of
Homeric Argos passed to its first Dorian lord, then Corinth formed
part of the lot of Temenos. A Temenid Corinth is perhaps implied in
Apollodorus[928], where Temenos, the two sons of Aristodemus, and
Kresphontes “when they had conquered the Peloponnese, set up
three altars of Zeus Patroos and sacrificed on them and drew lots for
the cities. The first lot was Argos, the second Sparta, the third
Messene.”
For connexions between Pheidon and Corinth we have only a story
told by Plutarch and a Scholiast on Apollonius Rhodius[929] of which
the salient points are that (a) Pheidon tries to annex Corinth; (b) the
Bacchiads and Archias are the pro-Argive party; (c) the fall of the
Bacchiads (which led to the rise of the tyrant Cypselus) meant the
overthrow of Argive influence.
So far the story is all of a piece, and supports the view that the
simultaneous establishment of Cypselus in Corinth and Orthagoras
in Sicyon may have been part cause and part result of the fall of
Pheidon and the breaking up again of the lot of Temenos. Such a
suggestion harmonizes well with the friendship that existed between
the Corinthian and Sicyon tyrants[930].
There are however chronological difficulties in this interpretation
of the Pheidon Archias story. In the story (i) the fall of the Bacchiads
is made contemporary with the foundation of Syracuse, i.e. it must
presumably be dated about 734 B.C.[931]; (ii) Pheidon is put some
time before this event, his contemporary Habron being grandfather
of Archias’ favourite Actaeon: the Marmor Parium enters Pheidon
before Archias.
In a highly romantic narrative like that of Archias and Actaeon the
last thing to be looked for is a reliable and exact chronology.
Impossible dates may mean impossible statements; but on the other
hand they may mean merely a confusion of facts of different dates, or
again, the facts may be coherent, and the dates just simply wrong.
In the present case, except for the relative dating of Archias and
Pheidon, the historic background is perfectly coherent, if the events
are put early in the seventh century. To accept the 750 date for
Pheidon sets him right in relation to Archias, but leaves the rest of
the story in the air. There is indeed always the refuge of assuming a
double banishment of the Bacchiads. But the idea of a double
banishment, traces of which might easily be discovered by the
reduplicating school of historians, is deservedly suspect, and may
have arisen from a double dating due to double dating of Pheidon. If
there really were two banishments, the story better suits the second.
Neither Plutarch nor the Scholiast on Apollonius gives any
absolute dates; and those of the Parian Marble, which does, are
impossible. The Marble dates Pheidon 895 B.C. and Archias 758.
Pheidon is also indeed made contemporary with an Athenian who
according to Castor held the office of king from 864 to 846 B.C.[932]
From 846 to 758 is a possible, though improbably long interval
between Pheidon and Archias, if as the story tells us, the latter had as
favourite the grandson of one of Pheidon’s contemporaries; but even
so the dating is so unsatisfactory, that the latest editor of the Parian
Marble[933] has suggested transposing Archias and Pheidon. But,
apart from other difficulties, the resultant early date for Archias is
altogether against the evidence. There is no need to put him back
into the ninth century merely because it is not unlikely that Greeks at
that period were already making their way to Sicily. The antedating
of Pheidon has already been accounted for, and he appears to have
taken back Archias with him part of the way.
The date of Archias is a problem any way. But it is not difficult to
suggest a possible chronology. Pheidon’s fall[934] was probably rapid
(a proof of his hubris). His rise was probably slow. Being a hereditary
monarch, he may well have ruled for fifty years, from about 715 to
665 B.C. It was early in his career that he began to carry out his
designs on Corinth. Archias, who had founded Syracuse in 734, gave
him support. We are told no details, but the alliances of the period of
the second Messenian war and the naval struggle in the Saronic Gulf
must have supplied abundant motives and inducements. Bacchiad
government under Argive protection continued till Pheidon fell,
which meant also the fall of the Bacchiads themselves. They
withdrew to the far west. Demaratus penetrated as far as Tarquinii.
Large numbers doubtless settled at Syracuse. The order of events just
outlined coincides entirely with the extant narratives, except in the
one matter of Syracuse, and there the divergence is very
comprehensible. The founder of Syracuse had supported Pheidon.
Pheidon’s fall had led to a great influx of pro-Argive Corinthians into
Syracuse, and threw Archias back entirely onto his Sicilian colony. If
this is what really happened, it would not be surprising if the fall of
Pheidon came to be regarded as having led to the original foundation
of Syracuse.
The chief doubt however as to the Pheidon of
historical truth of the Argive tyrant’s Corinth: is he
interference in Corinth is caused by certain identical with the
Argive?
references to a Corinthian Pheidon,
described by Aristotle as “one of the earliest lawgivers[935].” When an
Argive Pheidon is reported as making his appearance in Corinthian
history, is it a mistake due to the confusing of two separate
personalities? If two existed, they were unquestionably confused. A
Pindar Scholiast says that “a certain Pheidon, a man of Corinth,
invented measures and weights[936].”
But there is an alternative possibility. The Corinthian Pheidon may
be only one aspect of the Argive: this is suggested by the Pindar
Scholiast later in the same ode, where he says that “the Pheidon who
first struck their measures (κόψας τὸ μέτρον) for the Corinthians
was an Argive[937].” Too much stress must not be laid on such very
confused statements[938]. At best they can only corroborate other and
better evidence. This however is not altogether lacking. When
Karanos, the kinsman of Pheidon, went to Macedonia and occupied
Edessa and the lands of the Argeadae[939], Bacchiads from Corinth
settled near by among the Lynkestai[940].
A lawgiver who was “one of the earliest” can have arisen in Corinth
only before the establishment of the tyranny in 657 B.C. On the other
hand lawgivers seem to have been mainly a seventh century
phenomenon in Greece, and the most natural time for one to have
been appointed in Corinth is when the Bacchiad nobility was losing
its ascendancy, a process which may be imagined as beginning early
in the seventh century or at the end of the eighth. Plutarch describes
Pheidon’s designs on Corinth as formed at the beginning of his
career. Everything points to the Argive tyrant having had a long
reign. There is nothing improbable in the supposition that the rival
factions in Corinth invited to act as their lawgiver a young sovereign
of unusual ability who ruled a city of great traditions but not at the
time particularly powerful[941]. I have already suggested the course
taken by events in Corinth after Pheidon had once secured a position
in the city. One passage remains to be quoted that makes it still more
probable both that the Corinthian lawgiver was the Argive tyrant,
and that events in Corinth took something like the course that I have
suggested. According to Nicholas of Damascus[942] Pheidon out of
friendship went to the help of the Corinthians during a civil war: an
attack was made by his supporters, and he was killed[943]. An intimate
connexion from the beginning of his career with the great trading
and manufacturing city of the Isthmus would go far to explain the
commercial and financial inventiveness that was the distinguishing
feature of this royal tyrant[944].
Chapter VII. Corinth
ebookgate.com