17676
17676
_____ Follow the link below to get your download now _____
https://testbankdeal.com/product/microeconomics-9th-edition-
colander-solutions-manual/
https://testbankdeal.com/product/microeconomics-9th-edition-colander-
test-bank/
https://testbankdeal.com/product/microeconomics-10th-edition-colander-
solutions-manual/
https://testbankdeal.com/product/economics-9th-edition-colander-
solutions-manual/
https://testbankdeal.com/product/economics-of-money-banking-and-
financial-markets-global-11th-edition-mishkin-solutions-manual/
Calculus Concepts and Contexts Enhanced Edition 4th
Edition Stewart Test Bank
https://testbankdeal.com/product/calculus-concepts-and-contexts-
enhanced-edition-4th-edition-stewart-test-bank/
https://testbankdeal.com/product/international-business-competing-in-
the-global-marketplace-9th-edition-hill-solutions-manual/
https://testbankdeal.com/product/chemistry-a-molecular-approach-with-
masteringchemistry-2nd-edition-tro-test-bank/
https://testbankdeal.com/product/introduction-to-international-
economics-3rd-edition-salvatore-test-bank/
https://testbankdeal.com/product/hands-on-ethical-hacking-and-network-
defense-2nd-edition-simpson-test-bank/
Biochemistry 8th Edition Berg Test Bank
https://testbankdeal.com/product/biochemistry-8th-edition-berg-test-
bank/
Chapter 08: Market Failure versus Government Failure
2. The marginal social benefit of a good that exhibits positive externalities is greater
than the private social benefit because the trade results in a benefit to people
outside the trade.
3. An economist might argue about the word acceptable. Although not many people
would argue that any pollution is good, an economist who realizes that
eliminating pollution completely is probably an impossibly costly goal would find
pollution acceptable if it could be reduced to a cost-efficient level.
4. This oil tax is an example of a tax incentive program that attempts to make the
price of oil reflect the negative externality. If it works, it should provide an
incentive for the users with the lowest cost of reduction to decrease their
consumption of oil. If those with the lowest costs are significant users, there will
be a significant reduction. The effect depends on how high the tax is and the
alternatives available to oil consumers.
5. a. Assuming perfect competition, the price and quantity will be set where demand
crosses marginal cost with equilibrium price, P1, and equilibrium quantity, Q1.
b. The socially efficient price and quantity would be where demand crosses marginal
social cost, a higher price and a smaller output (P0, Q0).
8. a. The price of getting rid of garbage rose, but the price of getting rid of recyclables
did not. People substituted recycling for disposing.
b. The weight of garbage fell less than did volume because the fee was based on
volume; people stuffed the bags fuller, placing more garbage into a 32-gallon bag.
c. With a flat fee, the marginal cost of disposing more garbage was essentially zero,
and so in the accompanying graph, Q0 garbage pickup was demanded. With
volume pricing, the price rose to P1 and quantity demanded fell to Q1. See the
accompanying graph.
9. (1) The public aspect of safety is that if safety provides a safe environment, it is
provided for all people and one person enjoying safety does not preclude others
from benefiting from that safety. (2) Naming streets allows people to orient
themselves in towns and facilitates communication. Once a street is named, it
benefits all people. No one can be excluded from referring to that name. In
addition, one person using that street name does not preclude others from
referring to that street by its name. Before the street is named, however, if a
particular name is used to refer to more than one street, the value of that name in
providing geographic orientation will be diminished. (3) A steak dinner has no
public good aspects, since it is both rival and excludable.
10. Nonexcludability and nonrivalry both increase the ability of free riders to enjoy
the benefit of the product without paying for it.
8-2
© 2013 by McGraw-Hill Education. This is proprietary material solely for authorized instructor use. Not authorized for sale or
distribution in any manner. This document may not be copied, scanned, duplicated, forwarded, distributed, or posted on a website, in
whole or part.
Chapter 08: Market Failure versus Government Failure
11. City parks are examples of public goods. Use by one person does not deplete their
use by others, and they are nonexcludable. Asking for voluntary contributions to
sustain city parks will result in too few parks because of the free rider problem.
Once a park was built, it would be difficult to exclude the people who did not
voluntarily contribute to its building from using it; thus, individuals do not have a
monetary incentive to be the ones to pay for it. (They may have nonmonetary
incentives such as wanting to support green spaces in their neighborhoods.)
12. a. The market demand curve is shown in the accompanying graph. The market curve
and the demand curve for A are the same from quantity 4 and up. Remember that
with public goods, the market demand curve is created by summing the individual
demand curves vertically.
b. Because people do not actually purchase public goods, their true preferences are
not revealed. Since people will not pay directly for those goods, they will tend to
overstate the value they receive from public goods.
c. The socially optimal amount of the public good at a price of $2 is four units.
d. Given the free rider problem, the answer to c is most likely an overestimate.
13. You might offer the average, $600. If sellers of cherries want $700, your $600
would buy you only lemons. If you had this information, you'd know that you had
no chance of buying a cherry. The problem is that even though all cherries are
priced higher than $700, there are also lemons priced higher than $700. You
probably would lower your asking price to reflect the fact that there are only
lemons available in the market.
14. Three examples of signaling are (1) car warrantees, (2) 90-day return policies, and
(3) academic credentials. (Other answers are possible.)
8-3
© 2013 by McGraw-Hill Education. This is proprietary material solely for authorized instructor use. Not authorized for sale or
distribution in any manner. This document may not be copied, scanned, duplicated, forwarded, distributed, or posted on a website, in
whole or part.
Chapter 08: Market Failure versus Government Failure
probability of getting in an accident. People who are more likely to expect to get
in an accident will chose the low deductible.
16. In a market in which buyers and sellers have different amounts of information
about the good for sale, a problem occurs that is called the adverse selection
problem. The problem is that the market for quality products disappears.
Although the question doesn't ask for an example, here's one: In commercial
dating services, the seller certainly has more information about the negative (and
positive) aspects of the product than does the buyer. We suspect that the market
has fewer “acceptable” dates than the general population.
17. Neither buyers nor sellers would have any information about the quality of the
cars, and so the mix would become a potluck and the distribution of problems
would reflect the quality and natural aging of cars.
19. The advanced degree serves the same purpose as a license. It reduces the supply
and increases the wage of the one with the license.
21. The moral hazard problem in insurance will lead to higher premiums because
those who are covered will be less careful with whatever behavior is being
covered and behave in a way that is more risky. Both raise the cost of providing
insurance for the provider. Although the question does not ask for an example,
here is one: The problem will lead to higher health insurance premiums because
those who are covered will be less careful about maintaining their health and seek
medical care more frequently. Both raise the cost of providing health insurance.
22. a. No. The right number of regulations is a normative issue. One could argue that the
right number of regulations is the number that equates the marginal cost to the
marginal benefit of those regulations. Since we don't know the marginal benefit of
the regulations, just the total, we can't tell whether these regulations are optimal.
b. To the extent that the marginal costs and marginal benefits of regulations are
known, economists would use a cost/benefit analysis to decide about each
8-4
© 2013 by McGraw-Hill Education. This is proprietary material solely for authorized instructor use. Not authorized for sale or
distribution in any manner. This document may not be copied, scanned, duplicated, forwarded, distributed, or posted on a website, in
whole or part.
Chapter 08: Market Failure versus Government Failure
regulation.
23. Whether government ought to forbid Ben from wearing a red shirt depends on
how much you support a free market and whether you believe government should
correct all externalities. One opinion is that even though Sally might dislike the
color red, she is not physically harmed in any way. Besides, Ben should also have
the freedom to wear the clothes that he wants as a freedom of expression.
24. There is no one correct answer to this question. The best answer is that it depends
on one's view of government's role in the market. Most economists consider
externalities to be one of the problems where government may have a role, though
some believe that a market will develop to address those externalities. If one does
believe that there is a role for government, tax incentive policies allow the
invisible hand to guide the trade to equate marginal social cost with marginal
social benefit. Those who can reduce their use of fossil fuel most easily will
reduce consumption the most. The opposite is true for those who face a higher
cost of reducing consumption. In this way, the tax is better than direct regulation.
A market incentive plan is another program that uses the invisible hand to lead to
the optimal use. There are other issues to consider, such as whether fossil fuels
do in fact lead to global warming and whether global warming is, on average, bad
for society.
1. Austrian
a. Yes, it could.
2. Religious
a. There is some truth to this saying; if people were only selfish, they would lose
much that makes them human.
b. Yes, there is a conflict, although how strong the conflict is, is a matter of debate.
c. No probably not, although, again, the answer is debatable. Markets would not
work well if people were purely selfless. In many ways, the society would simply
not need markets.
3. Institutionalist
4. Post-Keynesian
b. The seller of the car could offer a warranty for the car. (There are other
possibilities.)
c. It could, since there are no barriers to entry, but it seems to be very expensive for
small firms to create such warranties, leaving a potential for government action.
5. Radical
a. Providing safe drinking water has public goods aspects to it; it benefits the entire
community, not just the individual, and many of the costs are joint.
c. From a radical perspective, public provisioning of basic services makes the most
sense.
8-6
© 2013 by McGraw-Hill Education. This is proprietary material solely for authorized instructor use. Not authorized for sale or
distribution in any manner. This document may not be copied, scanned, duplicated, forwarded, distributed, or posted on a website, in
whole or part.
Chapter 08: Market Failure versus Government Failure
Issues to Ponder
2. a. One advantage of such fees is that they reduce the quantity of animal trophies
demanded (assuming poaching can be prevented). This reduces the damage to the
stock of animals. Further, the revenue could be used to raise more animals or meet
other needs of African nations. This also provides an incentive for the local
people to preserve sufficient big game to meet the demand for the permits.
b. One argument against it is that condoning such slaughter at any price is immoral
and removing the stigma of illegal killing may even result in a greater demand for
animal trophies. A second argument is that by the time the optimal price is found,
the animals may well be extinct.
3. a. Most likely the price of all cars will rise; air quality probably would rise as well.
b. This law could possibly increase pollution if consumers hold on to their older, less
efficient but lower-cost, higher-performance gas cars and delay the purchase of an
electric car. This would increase the average age of cars on the road, increasing
pollution. Furthermore, if electric cars (the most likely candidates) were designed
to meet the no-pollution requirement, it could be that the process of generating
sufficient electricity to run the cars would produce even more pollution, at which
point even more regulation might be imposed.
c. Economists generally favor market incentive programs over direct regulation. A
market incentive program that reduces pollution by a certain percent might be to
tax drivers of older, high-pollution cars and use the tax revenue to subsidize those
who purchase the new no-pollution cars. This approach will be more likely to
equate marginal cost with marginal benefit. Another market incentive program
would be to increase taxes on gasoline, causing the demand for gasoline to
decrease as people switched to more efficient vehicles.
4. Three market failures that possibly justify national parks are as follows: (1)
National parks are possibly public goods. Use by one does not deplete their use by
others, and it is difficult to exclude people from using them. National parks are
not pure public goods because they can be gated with tollbooths at their entrances,
requiring fees to enter. However, one aspect of national parks—existence value—
is not excludable. Existence value is the value a citizen of a country derives from
the knowledge that the country has national parks. National parks create national
pride and identity. This value is both nonrival and nonexcludable, leading to
underproduction of national parks by the private market. (2) National parks create
positive externalities. People who visit national parks learn about taking care of
the environment, our national heritage, and the complexity of nature—education
that can be brought into other parts of economic life. Another positive externality
8-7
© 2013 by McGraw-Hill Education. This is proprietary material solely for authorized instructor use. Not authorized for sale or
distribution in any manner. This document may not be copied, scanned, duplicated, forwarded, distributed, or posted on a website, in
whole or part.
Chapter 08: Market Failure versus Government Failure
is that they provide resources for a variety of research that provides benefits to
society. (3) National parks may experience increasing returns to scale. That is, the
larger the park, the lower the per-unit cost of maintaining it. Thus, national parks
can be seen as a natural monopoly of sorts, justifying government intervention.
(Source: “Market Failures and the Rationale for National Parks,” Journal of
Economic Education, Fall 2002.) (Natural monopolies are covered in Chapter 14
but can be introduced by the instructor to facilitate the class discussion.)
6. Although there are benefits of licensing, it is often used as a way to restrict entry
into the profession and thwart competition. Thus, although some type of
certification program may be warranted, licensing is probably not warranted.
7. Pro: People should undergo testing before getting life insurance because a person
who is more likely to seek thrills is a greater risk to the insurance company, and
they should bear these higher costs themselves rather than having them passed on
to non-risk seekers.
Con: People should not undergo testing before getting life insurance because
whether a person is a greater risk depends on revealed behavior rather than
proclivity toward a particular behavior. We, not our genes, decide our behavior.
Undergoing such testing would result in people who have the gene but who avoid
such behavior having to unnecessarily pay a higher premium.
8. Many answers are possible, beginning with (1) the label on breakfast cereal, (2)
the roads used to get to school, (3) either the school they go to (if it is public) or
the federal funds their school receives (if it is private), (4) the taxes paid on the
snack at the snack bar, and (5) the laws that are enforced on the roadways. The
benefits of labeling are that consumers can better plan nutritional balance and are
better informed about the product they are buying. Whether this is justified is
unclear. If consumers wanted such labeling, there would be market pressure to
include that information on cereal boxes. Some labeling, such as whether the
product contains genetically modified food, could unnecessarily alarm consumers.
This would hurt companies that use genetically modified food and help
companies that don’t. Whether genetically modified food is harmful is still up for
debate.
9. The tax on oil will probably affect the pollution coming from oil, but it is possible
that users could switch to other fuel sources that result in other and greater forms
of pollution. Moreover, some types of pollution would be unaffected. Thus, the
net impact on the environment is difficult to predict.
8-8
© 2013 by McGraw-Hill Education. This is proprietary material solely for authorized instructor use. Not authorized for sale or
distribution in any manner. This document may not be copied, scanned, duplicated, forwarded, distributed, or posted on a website, in
whole or part.
Chapter 08: Market Failure versus Government Failure
10. a. Some dairy farmers probably would argue that labeling is unnecessary since the
drugs they administer have been certified by the FDA. Dairy farmers who do not
use BST would support BST labeling because consumers may perceive their milk
as better for their health.
b. If BST were to be listed on milk containers, one could argue that all drugs and
antibiotics should be listed. However, such listing (without more information)
might cause unnecessary consumer concern. To support BST labeling but not
other labeling, one must argue that BST is different.
c. One would suspect that dairy farmers who support BST labeling would not
support the broader law that might include drugs that they do use. Only those few
farmers who use wholly organic farming would support full labeling.
8-9
© 2013 by McGraw-Hill Education. This is proprietary material solely for authorized instructor use. Not authorized for sale or
distribution in any manner. This document may not be copied, scanned, duplicated, forwarded, distributed, or posted on a website, in
whole or part.
Other documents randomly have
different content
edge of a curtain is seen the foot of the approaching husband,
bringing his vengeance and the lovers’ doom. The same subject has
been more elaborately and completely treated by Mr. G.F. Watts,
whose picture shows Francesca telling her sad tale to Dante and
Virgil as they pass; and the poet who is said to have known her on
earth, and to have written the record quoted from the “Inferno” in
the house at Rimini in which she was born, is depicted sinking in a
swoon before her, overcome with pity and with awe.
Again, and in a widely different field of dramatic narrative, does
Rossetti bring this passionate sense of retribution into play. His
drawing for the never-finished picture, “The Death of Lady Macbeth,”
is full of the same half-pitiful and half-triumphant spirit of righteous
vengeance, and the same perception of inexorable penalty. The aged
and dying woman crouching on her bed has once been comely and
of commanding countenance; and in her last hour the remembered
beauty of her face, the lingering majesty of her figure, seem to
overawe her attendants, one of whom presses a sponge to her head.
In that changed face the conflict between remorse and pride,
ambition and terror, is still fierce and strong; but she is dying utterly
alone: there is no love, no tenderness, in the ministry of those who
gather round the murderess.
Still more clearly and resolutely is this perception of moral issues
sustained by the Pre-Raphaelites when they pass from history and
legend to classic mythology, to allegorical type, or to the dramatic
presentation of modern life. In the “Awakening Conscience” of
Holman Hunt, in the exquisitely pathetic “Psyche” of G.F. Watts, in
the “Hesterna Rosa,” “Gate of Memory,” and “Found” of Rossetti, the
bitter cost of sin is realized with unfaltering consistency. Rossetti’s
long-laboured and yet uncompleted “Found” may be taken as the
companion, if not the sequel, to his poem, “Jenny.” It shows us the
last humiliation of a ruined girl who is “found”—dying on the streets
of London—by the lover of her youth,—a countryman who has
driven in with his milk-cart through the chill light of a London dawn.
All the pride and struggle of the past is written on her once lovely
face, and she shrinks in shame and terror from his touch.
“Ah! gave not these two hearts their mutual pledge,
Under one mantle sheltered ’neath the hedge
In gloaming courtship? And, O God! to-day
He only knows he holds her;—but what part
Can life now take? She cries in her locked heart,—
‘Leave me—I do not know you—go away!’”[11]
It might almost be the same sad girl that stands at “The Gate of
Memory,” watching a group of young and innocent maidens at play
beside a well.
All the depth, all the tenderness, all the heroic strength of a divine
sorrow that sees the end of sorrow, shines in this full-souled face. It
is the ideal of the highest womanhood, and indeed of the highest
humanity; of the love that has attained to be godlike, redeeming the
world by infinite compassion; a love that “hopeth all things and
endureth all things,” and in whose steadfast courage lies the
conquering principle of the life to be. It is the companion picture—
and in some respects it is a nobler, healthier version—of “The
Blessed Damozel,” leaning from the bar of heaven to console the
mourner on the earth below. The love that can so take hold of
immortality, bring comfort even from the gates of death, and bridge
over, by the sweet persistence of its ministry, by the passionate
reality of its inspiration, the gulf between the physical and the
spiritual world, is the love which of old was the source of the “Vita
Nuova,” and which springs anew in our own age through “Our Lady
of Pity” and “The Blessed Damozel.” In such designs Rossetti has
restored to us all that was best in the mediæval thought of
womanhood,—adding the “ever-motherly” to the “ever-womanly” of
the Hellenic model, and the Divine Motherhood to the Divine
Fatherhood of the Christian ideal; and enriched it with the whole
wealth of psycho-sensuous beauty brought over from the region of
romance. And in this consummation is justified the verdict of Ruskin:
that “Rossetti was the chief intellectual force in the establishment of
the modern romantic school in England.”
CHAPTER VIII.
THE POETRY OF DANTE ROSSETTI.
The poetry of Dante Gabriel Rossetti lies apart from the main
current of contemporary verse, both in its highly specialized quality
of thought and language, and in the conditions and circumstances of
its production. Inasmuch as he followed openly the profession of a
painter, pursuing poetry, for the most part, as a recreative rather
than a principal study (though never with less seriousness than his
accepted vocation), and publishing his first volume of original poems
in his forty-second year, he is exempt to some extent from the
standards of criticism applied to him whose creative energies are
concentrated in the field of literature. Whether Rossetti’s genius, as
he himself believed, found its highest and most perfect embodiment
in poetry rather than in painting,—whether the essential qualities of
his art will be more evident to posterity in the modest volume of his
collected poems than in the pictures now dispersed through England
and America—is still an open question. It may, however, be admitted
that his mastery of the verbal medium was almost always more
complete, his discipline in metrical structure more thorough, and his
natural habit of diction more facile, than any skill which he attained
in brush and pencil. To estimate his final influence upon
contemporary thought in the one realm as against the other is yet
more difficult than to assess the relative merit of his actual work in
either sphere: so intimately was the poet incarnate in the painter; so
largely did the painter’s vision inspire and dominate the poet.
But it would be a poor analysis that should divide too finely the
interwoven threads of a radiant and many-coloured genius. In an
age of intellectual re-birth, of artistic and social revolution, the re-
adjustment of forces and functions in the ethical and æsthetical
realms is apt to produce a strange complexity of talent, not always
beneficial to a single art, not always well for the diversely endowed
artist, but often tending to the unification of many activities into one
effective stream of purpose, moved by the impulse that infused the
nation with a Time-Spirit potent for immortal things. Such a
combination of talent in single personalities, in a period of rare
national fertility in scholarship and creative power, reveals at the
same time the basic unity of the æsthetic life and its inseparable
interdependence with the moral ideal. Michaelangelo, at the zenith
of the Italian Renaissance, standing at the parting of the ways,
gathered up, as it seemed, the several arts into his representative
genius, and left to the land that was soon to swamp the æsthetic
spirit in the mire of a materialistic decadence the threefold heritage
of his painting, his sculpture, and his song. Rossetti, at the zenith of
the English Renaissance, drew a twofold inspiration from the
struggle of the modern world, and left the double dower of painting
and of poetry, to urge the coming generation to the higher issues of
fine art, or to stand, the witness of rejected ideals to ages
recalcitrant to the vision and the impulse of to-day.
For the first greatness of Rossetti’s poetry is that it assumes for
ever the reality and the immanence of a spiritual—and more—a
moral world. Not that he ever misuses the vehicles of art as tools of
philosophy, or stoops to a didactic application of æsthetic truth. But
his art is all moral (as Mr. Ruskin would put it) because it is all fine
art. And the moral purpose of art is the better secured when art is
trusted to effect that purpose in its own way. The consciously
didactic poet is less sure to mould the will and character of a people,
than he the form and substance of whose utterance are so perfected
in truth and virility of thought, in majesty and grace of speech, as to
be a fit oblation to his own ideal. Not “how can I best teach others
and influence them aright?” but “how can I best express the highest
things I know and feel?” is the self-examination of the true artist.
Rossetti’s poetry is self-expressive, self-revealing to the very heart’s
core. The ultimate test of poetry is not “what did this man intend to
teach us?” but “of what sort is the manhood here revealed? what are
the visions by which it lived? what the ideals in which it grew? Is
such a soul’s experience wide, deep, typical, and profitable to the
rest of mankind?”
In applying such a test to the writings of Rossetti, it is necessary
to distinguish between what may be roughly termed the “personal”
and the “impersonal” poems. In the one class, supremely
exemplified by the “House of Life” sonnets, but including also “Dante
at Verona,” “The Stream’s Secret,” “The Portrait,” and many of the
shorter lyrics, the personal note of love or grief, of memory or hope,
is wholly dominant; the poet’s soul is absorbed with its individual
being, and sees in all the life around him the illustration and
interpretation of his own. In the other class, in the great romantic
ballads, in “Rose Mary” and “The Blessed Damozel,” in “The White
Ship” and “The King’s Tragedy,” in “The Bride’s Prelude” and “Sister
Helen,” the imagination takes a higher and a larger range; the one
soul interprets others, waiting not to be interpreted. The art
becomes impersonal in this sense only—that the thought of self is
merged in the full and immense life of humanity, laying hold of the
universal consciousness through its own initiative experience; the
heart beats with the world’s heart, shares its eternal struggles,
contributes to its eternal growth; and the spirit knows itself one
fragment of an infinite whole. In such a sphere the art remains the
more vitally personal, in that the poet brings the mysteries of
existence, the abiding problems and realities of the conscious world,
to the touchstone, as it were, of his own spirit, and submits himself
thereby to the more crucial test,—of how he can interpret humanity
to man, and make more clear the knowledge, more possible the
realization, of his highest ideals.
With this general division of the subject-matter of Rossetti’s
poetry, the classification of its metrical cast and forms of diction will
be singularly parallel. Most of his finest compositions might be
distinguished as purely Saxon or pre-eminently Latin poems; and it is
notable that the more intimately subjective and analytic the thought
within, the more persistently does it assume the Latin garb; while as
the imagination ranges from the introspection of the hyper-conscious
self, and finds, on the heights of common human feeling and
aspiration, a larger and a freer air, the mode passes into the more
keen and rarified Saxon speech. No other English poet has resolved
the breadth and simplicity of the Gothic, and the depth and intensity
of the Italian habit of expression, into such distinctive poetic
vehicles. But at the same time few have blended the diverse
elements of the modern English tongue into the harmony and
sonority with which Rossetti’s music thrills when he tempers the
sharper Saxon with a deep undertone of polysyllabic song; or stirs
the languorous pulses of a sonnet with some swift cadence of
familiar words. He had the finest perception of national and racial
properties of form and rhythm; and discerning the characteristics of
the poetry of action in the literature of the north, and the poetry of
reflection in the literature of the south, he cast his great historical
lyrics in the highest narrative—that is to say, the ballad form; and
chose the sonnet—the most remote, chastened, and exclusive
vehicle—for the meditative, and yet sensuous, self-delineative love-
poetry.
These broad generalizations, however, cannot be closely pressed
upon the entire sequence of Rossetti’s poems. The exigencies of the
English language alone elude their literal application. They will rather
serve to illustrate the duality of his endowments, and the singular
power of his genius both to conserve and specialize the
characteristics of his Italian heritage, and also to waive them in the
Saxon mode as utterly as though the latter were more native to his
tongue.
Nor does such a superficial distinction affect the spiritual qualities
which pervade Rossetti’s poetry as a whole. From first to last, in
dramatic description or narrative, in sonnet-argument or meditative
questioning, his verse remains full-charged with the very essence of
romance. As a poet, he is neither less nor more Pre-Raphaelite than
as a painter. The vivid and intense simplicity of his Saxon diction, the
verbal lightnings of his ballad-style, seem to correspond with the
tone and method of his water-colour painting, and the more
laboured splendour of the sonnets with the properties of his work in
oils. Nor is it difficult to detect an analogy between that stage of his
painting in which the pristine lucidity of expression was partially lost
in the painful tension of his later thought, and the tendency of some
few of his sonnets towards decadence into the over-laborious and
the obscure. Yet if by “Pre-Raphaelite” we understand that fusion of
the naïve mysticism of romance with austere Platonic Hellenism
which we discern in the best Renaissance art, Rossetti never falls in
spirit from that standard of beauty and truth; and rarely lapses,
through the very richness and fecundity of the language at his
command, into the redundant verbiage towards which his sensuous
imagery was easily led. It has remained for a brother-poet of the
romantic revival to cultivate a more marvellous dexterity of rhyme
and rhythm, and to develop the technical resources of our language
to the utmost limits of intelligible song. The lyrics of Mr. Swinburne,
like the superb decorative extravagances of the later Renaissance,
represent that culmination of mastery over the forms of expression
wherein to-day, as of yore, the purity of the thought is lost in the
splendour of the setting, and poetic power wastes itself in a magic
facility of verse.
The poetry of Rossetti, modern as it is in its passionate grasp of
human interests, its deep insight into present and perpetual things,
links itself nevertheless to an English past; takes up, as it were, the
dropped threads of Elizabethan glory; re-inspires the circling breath
of life which passed round Europe in the fifteenth century, kindling
England from the fires of re-awakened Italy in the golden age of
song. It has already been pointed out by one of Rossetti’s
biographers that “the malign influence over our literature in post-
Shakespearean times has been French.” It was reserved for a second
Renaissance, heralded by Chatterton and Blake, led by Shelley,
Keats, and Coleridge, and culminated by Dante Rossetti, to blot out
two centuries of foreign tradition and control, and take us back to
the broad simplicity and dignity of Shakespeare’s England.
Our reiteration, therefore, of the term “Pre-Raphaelite” in
approaching Rossetti’s work as a poet, leads us to expect, not
mysticism merely, but a certain robust sensuousness, as of Pagan
origin, in his interpretation of life and destiny. The romantic temper
in its highest manifestations, absorbing and transfiguring, rather
than conflicting with, the classic ideals, implies much more than
receptivity to newer beauty and truth. It has a moral basis and an
intellectual range: it apprehends the spiritual world as something
closely bound up with familiar things: it finds the human soul striving
for expression through material forms: it recognizes the divine
possibilities of individual and social life, the force and responsibility
of personal character, and the solemnity of the choice between good
and evil daily made by man.
But the controversy excited by Rossetti’s pictures has been neither
more intemperate nor more significant than that which has raged
around his poems;—interpreted by one section of his critics as a
pæan of sensuality and materialism, by another as the most spiritual
and chastened love-poetry of the age. The laureate of the Pre-
Raphaelite Brotherhood indeed summed up, in what now affords but
one volume of original verse, the inmost vicissitudes of a spirit so
rare and rich of vision as to transcend at once the canons of
conventional experience. But the personal note, in the self-
delineative poems, is struck with a peculiar dignity of reserve; and
even while the most sacred depths of individual consciousness are
laid bare, the actual ego is never intruded upon the surface of the
speech,—never portrays directly its own character, seldom describes
its own sensations as Byron or Shelley would; but veils itself, even in
the profusion of luminous imagery and searching analysis of thought
and sense.
The eternal mysteries and sanctities of sexual love, conceived in
its highest aspects and known as a revelation and a sacrament,
afford the theme of nearly all Rossetti’s autobiographic poetry. The
conditions of its production were ordained by the stern fate that
linked him afar off to Dante among his countrymen, and near at
hand to two brother-mourners among minor English bards—James
Thomson and Philip Bourke Marston—in the sad fraternity of poets
whom death has prematurely robbed of the beloved object that once
inspired their song. The exalted spirituality which marks Rossetti’s
treatment of this theme was doubtless largely due to the influence
of Dante, and especially to the fruitful inspiration and discipline of
the great literary task of his youth—the translation of the “Vita
Nuova” and kindred examples of the early Italian poets—than which
Rossetti could have hardly found a better preparation for his work
that was to come.
Into his great sonnet-sequence, “The House of Life,” Rossetti
poured the full passion of his mystic love,—partially inherent in his
own sensuous, imaginative, and introspective nature, partially
instilled at the feet of Dante; and learned—a bitter and a costly
lesson—at the school of experience also; fraught with inestimable
joy and sorrow to his own soul. “At an age,” says one writing of that
hard probation, “when most men have outlived the romances of
their youth, Rossetti was laying, in ‘The House of Life,’ the
foundations of a new school of love-poetry.” He was in fact re-
creating the æsthetic life of a nation; restoring to it, through the
alembic of mediæval and Renaissance thought, the lost glory of all
that was abidingly precious in the Platonic world. For in this
wondrous cycle of sonnets is re-coined the whole language of ideal
love. From the last echo of the “Vita Nuova” it takes up the same
pure strain, and sings again the song of Dante for the Blessed
Beatrice; hymning the very apotheosis of spiritual passion, and
harmonizing once more in English poetry the intellectual with the
sensuous world. Never, in the superb visions of “The House of
Life”—in which the soul of man is pictured sojourning awhile during
its solemn and fateful passage through eternity—never does the
physical love become the stumbling-block to the spiritual, but always
the key to it. The “body’s beauty” is only precious as the witness of
the “soul’s beauty;” the physical bond is nothing if not the symbol of
a spiritual affinity, a sacred kinship, fore-ordained, if not eternal,
sealed in Heaven and consecrated to the divinest purposes; the
sensuous rapture is but a symbolic worship,—“the outward and
visible sign of an inward and spiritual grace” which to reject or
betray is to profane the inmost sanctuary of the God of Love:
“What of her glass without her?” he cries again after the great
bereavement which has removed the visible presence of the
beloved:
And with what fine insight does Rossetti pierce the tender
subtleties of the woman’s responsive heart! Has any other English
poet discerned so well that retrospective instinct which clings to the
early semblances of pure and non-sexual love?
testbankdeal.com