(Ebook) Understanding Quantum Raffles: Quantum Mechanics on an Informational Approach: Structure and Interpretation by Michael Janas, Michael E. Cuffaro, Michel Janssen ISBN 9783030859381, 9783030859398, 303085938X, 3030859398 - Download the ebook and explore the most detailed content
(Ebook) Understanding Quantum Raffles: Quantum Mechanics on an Informational Approach: Structure and Interpretation by Michael Janas, Michael E. Cuffaro, Michel Janssen ISBN 9783030859381, 9783030859398, 303085938X, 3030859398 - Download the ebook and explore the most detailed content
com
OR CLICK BUTTON
DOWLOAD EBOOK
(Ebook) Biota Grow 2C gather 2C cook by Loucas, Jason; Viles, James ISBN
9781459699816, 9781743365571, 9781925268492, 1459699815, 1743365578, 1925268497
https://ebooknice.com/product/biota-grow-2c-gather-2c-cook-6661374
ebooknice.com
(Ebook) Matematik 5000+ Kurs 2c Lärobok by Lena Alfredsson, Hans Heikne, Sanna
Bodemyr ISBN 9789127456600, 9127456609
https://ebooknice.com/product/matematik-5000-kurs-2c-larobok-23848312
ebooknice.com
(Ebook) SAT II Success MATH 1C and 2C 2002 (Peterson's SAT II Success) by Peterson's
ISBN 9780768906677, 0768906679
https://ebooknice.com/product/sat-ii-success-math-1c-and-2c-2002-peterson-s-sat-
ii-success-1722018
ebooknice.com
(Ebook) Master SAT II Math 1c and 2c 4th ed (Arco Master the SAT Subject Test: Math
Levels 1 & 2) by Arco ISBN 9780768923049, 0768923042
https://ebooknice.com/product/master-sat-ii-math-1c-and-2c-4th-ed-arco-master-
the-sat-subject-test-math-levels-1-2-2326094
ebooknice.com
(Ebook) Cambridge IGCSE and O Level History Workbook 2C - Depth Study: the United
States, 1919-41 2nd Edition by Benjamin Harrison ISBN 9781398375147, 9781398375048,
1398375144, 1398375047
https://ebooknice.com/product/cambridge-igcse-and-o-level-history-
workbook-2c-depth-study-the-united-states-1919-41-2nd-edition-53538044
ebooknice.com
https://ebooknice.com/product/constructing-quantum-mechanics-53653496
ebooknice.com
https://ebooknice.com/product/the-interpretation-of-quantum-mechanics-57020188
ebooknice.com
https://ebooknice.com/product/constructing-quantum-mechanics-volume-one-the-
scaffold-19001923-10671146
ebooknice.com
https://ebooknice.com/product/quantum-mechanics-mathematical-structure-and-
physical-structure-part-i-34493418
ebooknice.com
Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science 340
Michael Janas
Michael E. Cuffaro
Michel Janssen
Understanding
Quantum
Raffles
Quantum Mechanics on an
Informational Approach:
Structure and Interpretation
With a Foreword by Jeffrey Bub
Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History
of Science
Volume 340
Editors
Alisa Bokulich, Boston University
Jürgen Renn, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science
Managing Editor
Lindy Divarci, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science
Editorial Board
Theodore Arabatzis, University of Athens
Heather E. Douglas, University of Waterloo
Jean Gayon, Université Paris 1
Thomas F. Glick, Boston University
Hubert Goenner, University of Goettingen
John Heilbron, University of California, Berkeley
Diana Kormos-Buchwald, California Institute of Technology
Christoph Lehner, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science
Peter McLaughlin, Universität Heidelberg
Agustí Nieto-Galan, Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona
Nuccio Ordine, Universitá della Calabria
Sylvan S. Schweber, Harvard University
Ana Simões, Universidade de Lisboa
John J. Stachel, Boston University
Baichun Zhang, Chinese Academy of Science
Kostas Gavroglu, National and Kapodistrian University of Athens
The series Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science was
conceived in the broadest framework of interdisciplinary and international
concerns. Natural scientists, mathematicians, social scientists and philoso-
phers have contributed to the series, as have historians and sociologists of
science, linguists, psychologists, physicians, and literary critics.
The series has been able to include works by authors from many other
countries around the world.
The editors believe that the history and philosophy of science should itself
be scientific, self-consciously critical, humane as well as rational, sceptical
and undogmatic while also receptive to discussion of first principles. One of
the aims of Boston Studies, therefore, is to develop collaboration among
scientists, historians and philosophers.
Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science looks into and
reflects on interactions between epistemological and historical dimensions in
an effort to understand the scientific enterprise from every viewpoint.
Understanding
Quantum Raffles
Quantum Mechanics on an Informational
Approach: Structure and Interpretation
123
Michael Janas Michael E. Cuffaro
School of Physics and Astronomy Fakultät für Philosophie
University of Minnesota Ludwig Maximilian
Minneapolis, MN, USA University of Munich
München, Bayern, Germany
Michel Janssen
School of Physics and Astronomy
University of Minnesota
Minneapolis, MN, USA
© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature
Switzerland AG 2022
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher,
whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation,
reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any
other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation,
computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this
publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are
exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors, and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in
this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor
the authors or the editors give a warranty, expressed or implied, with respect to the material
contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains
neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
This Springer imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
We dedicate this volume to the memory of Itamar
Pitowsky (1950–2010) and William Demopoulos
(1943–2017).
vii
viii Foreword
1 I. Pitowsky, ‘On the geometry of quantum correlations,’ Physical Review A 77, 062109
(2008).
Foreword ix
constraint follows quite generally, without assuming the Born rule for quantum
probabilities.
The Mermin inequality refers to spin-1/2 particles in the singlet state.
Remarkably, it turns out that singlet state quantum correlations are confined
to the elliptope even for higher spin values, while the tetrahedron for local
classical correlations is replaced by a succession of polyhedra with more and
more facets for higher spins, approaching the elliptope in the limit of infinite
spin. All this is beautifully illustrated in 3-dimensional visualizations. The
analysis is particularly impressive because it shows clearly and precisely how
classical and quantum correlations are related in this particular case.
This is certainly the first book in which the word ‘Bubism’ appears. The
three Mikes use the term to refer to ‘an interpretation of quantum mechanics
along the lines of Bananaworld, belonging to the same lineage, or so we will
argue, as the much-maligned Copenhagen interpretation.’ Bananaworld began
as a discussion of entanglement, but as I wrote the book it evolved into a way
of thinking about the transition from classical to quantum mechanics. The
three Mikes have taken this perspective and articulated and developed it into
an interpretation that I fully endorse but which owes as much to their careful
analysis of the conceptual issues as my own thinking.
I added the last chapter to Bananaworld, ‘Making Sense of it All,’ because
I thought I should say something about the measurement problem of quantum
mechanics as it is usually understood, and how various interpretations propose
to solve the problem. But the chapter doesn’t fit well with the rest of the book,
which, taken as a whole, was already an attempt to make sense of it all. The
revised version in the paperback edition is an improvement, but not entirely
satisfactory. Chapter 6 of Understanding Quantum Raffles, on interpreting
quantum mechanics, nails it.
Here, following the account by the three Mikes, is how I now see the view
they call Bubism. Quantum mechanics began with Heisenberg’s unprecedented
move to ‘reinterpret’ classical quantities like position and momentum as non-
commutative. In a commutative algebra, the 2-valued quantities, representing
propositions that can be true or false, form a Boolean algebra. A Boolean
algebra is isomorphic to a set of subsets of a set, with the Boolean opera-
tions corresponding to the union, intersection, and complement of sets. The
conceptual significance of Heisenberg’s proposal lies in replacing the Boolean
algebra of subsets of classical phase space, where the points represent classical
states and subsets represent ranges of values of dynamical variables, with a
non-Boolean algebra. Later, following the Born-Heisenberg-Jordan Dreimän-
nerarbeit and further developments by Dirac, Jordan, and von Neumann, this
x Foreword
6 Von Neumann evidently meant to say that the transition probability is the square of the
(absolute value of) the inner product, which is the square of the cosine of the angle between
them.
7 J.S. Bell, ‘Against measurement,’ in Physics World 8, 33–40 (1990). The comment is on
p. 34.
xii Foreword
8 M. Born, The Born-Einstein Correspondence (Walker and Co., London, 1971). Pauli talks
about the classical ideal of the ‘detached observer’ in a letter to Born dated March 30, 1954
on p. 218.
9 ‘Die gegenwärtige Situation in der Quantenmechanik,’ Die Naturwissenschaften 48, 807–
812; 49, 823–828, 844–849 (1935). The quotation is from p. 826. The translation is by John
Trimmer, Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 124, 323—338 (1980).
Foreword xiii
Schrödinger calls the measurement problem ‘the most difficult and most
interesting point of the theory.’10 As the three Mikes aptly put it, the measure-
ment problem is a feature of quantum mechanics as a non-Boolean theory, not
a bug.
Interpretations of quantum mechanics that oppose the Copenhagen inter-
pretation begin with Schrödinger’s wave theory as conceptually fundamental,
rather than Heisenberg’s algebraic formulation of quantum mechanics, and
propose dynamical solutions to what then seems to be a problem: how does
what we do when we perform a measurement by manipulating some hardware
in a laboratory select a Boolean frame in Hilbert space, a basis of observables
that have definite values, and what explains the particular assignment of truth
values to the elements in the Boolean frame, or the particular assignment of
values to observables.
Bohm’s theory tells a one-world Boolean story: position in configuration
space is always definite, associated with a Boolean algebra, and other quan-
tities become definite through correlation with position via the measurement
dynamics. The problem here, as Bell showed, is that Bohm’s theory is nonlo-
cal in configuration space, allowing instantaneous action at a distance, which
Einstein regarded as ‘spooky’11 and so non-physical (although averaging over
the Born distribution hides the nonlocality). I suspect that it was for this rea-
son that Einstein dismissed Bohm’s theory as ‘too cheap for me’ in a letter to
Born.12
The Everett interpretation tells a multi-world Boolean story in which every-
thing that can happen does happen in some Boolean world. This avoids having
to explain why this measurement outcome rather than that measurement out-
come, since every possible outcome actually occurs in some world. The trick is
to show how this fits Schrödinger’s wave theory of quantum mechanics. There
is no spooky action at a distance in the Everettian interpretation, but the mea-
surement problem appears as the basis problem: how to explain the selection of
a particular basis with respect to which the multiplicity associated with ‘split-
ting into many worlds’ occurs in a measurement process. Everettians solve the
basis problem by appealing to the dynamics of environmental decoherence:
as the environment becomes increasingly entangled with the measuring ap-
10 ibid., p. 826.
11 M. Born, op. cit.. The term is used in a letter from Einstein to Born dated March 3, 1947
on p. 158.
12 M. Born, op. cit. The comment is on p. 192 in a letter from Einstein to Born dated May
12, 1952.
xiv Foreword
paratus, it becomes more and more difficult, but not in principle impossible,
to distinguish an entangled state from the corresponding mixture with respect
to a particular coarse-grained basis. Quantum probabilities with respect to
the elements of this basis are explained in terms of the decision theory of an
agent-in-a-world about to make a measurement. Even granting decoherence as
an effective solution to the basis problem, it seems contrived to interpret the
‘perfectly new and sui generis aspects of physical reality,’ the Hilbert space
probabilities that are ‘uniquely given from the start,’ in this way.
Understanding Quantum Raffles is likely to be a classic in the foundational
literature on quantum mechanics. The three Mikes have produced an exception-
ally lucid book on quantum foundations that is also suitable for readers, with
some tolerance for basic algebra and geometry, who are looking for answers
to conceptual questions that are typically glossed over in standard courses on
quantum mechanics.
Jeffrey Bub
Philosophy Department
Institute for Physical Science and Technology
Joint Center for Quantum Information and Computer Science
University of Maryland, College Park
Preface
The volume you just got yourself entangled with was inspired by Jeffrey Bub’s
(2016) Bananaworld: Quantum Mechanics for Primates. Our original plan
had been to contribute an article to a special issue of the journal Studies in
History and Philosophy of Modern Physics devoted to Jeff’s book. That article
eventually grew and morphed into this monograph, which we feel can now
stand on its own feet. We are proud to present it as a volume in the series
Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science. In this volume,
on the basis of some novel technical results (Chapters 2–5), we present and
defend an informational interpretation of the basic framework of quantum
mechanics (Chapters 1, 6–7). Our primary target audience for this book is
physicists, philosophers of physics and students in these areas interested in
the foundations of quantum mechanics. However, in the spirit of Bananaworld
and its sequel, the graphic novel Totally Random: Why Nobody Understands
Quantum Mechanics written by Jeff and his daughter Tanya (Bub & Bub,
2018), we wrote parts of our book (especially Chapter 2 and Sections 3.1–3.2)
with the idea that they could be used as the basis for courses introducing
non-physics majors to quantum mechanics, or for self-study by those outside
of a university setting with an interest in quantum mechanics. Such readers,
however, should be prepared to brush up on some high-school mathematics
along the way (basic algebra and geometry; sines and cosines; vectors, matrices
and determinants—but absolutely no calculus).13 We hope that all readers,
even those who disagree with us on the basic issue of how their entanglement
with our book results in them forming a definite view of its contents, will find
something of value between its covers. This preface serves two purposes. First,
we will briefly describe the contents of this volume. Second, we will give a
brief history of how we came to write it, which will also give us an opportunity
to thank the many people who helped us along the way.
Let us begin then by laying out the overall argumentative strategy of our
book (which is in broad outline the same as it was in our original plan for a
paper). We use correlation arrays, the workhorse of Bananaworld, to analyze
the correlations found in an experimental setup due to David Mermin (1981)
for measurements on pairs of spin- 21 particles in the singlet state. Adopting
an approach pioneered by Itamar Pitowsky (1989b) and promoted in Banana-
13 See Section 2.6.2, note 28, for some recommendations for non-expert readers looking for
introductions to the basic formalism of quantum mechanics.
xv
xvi Preface
mentioned above and chapters from David Albert’s Quantum Mechanics and
Experience (Albert, 1992) to introduce quantum mechanics to non-physics
majors in college and in high-school physics classes. Over the past few years,
Janssen (assisted by Janas) has been developing a different approach, informed
by and informing the material presented in this book. Like Albert (1992, Ch.
1, pp. 1–16, “Superposition”), we start, in Chapter 2, with certain stochastic
experiments and show that classical theory (more precisely: local hidden-
variable theories) cannot account for the statistics found in these experiments.
Following Mermin rather than Albert, however, we choose (variations on) an
experiment highlighting entanglement rather than superposition as the key
feature that distinguishes quantum theory from classical theory (cf. Chapter
2, note 2 and Chapter 6, note 44). Albert (1992, Ch. 2, pp. 17–60) proceeds
to give a concise and elementary exposition of the formalism of quantum
mechanics (which we highly recommend to readers unfamiliar with it) and
shows how it can account for the puzzling statistics presented in the opening
chapter of his book. Yet it remains unclear how anybody would come up
with this way of accounting for these puzzling statistics in the first place.
Bub’s Bananaworld, especially the notion of correlation arrays, allows us to
do better. The correlation arrays for the puzzling statistics we start from can be
parametrized by the sines and cosines of certain angles. In quantum mechanics
such sines and cosines naturally emerge as components of vectors in various
bases in what is called a Hilbert space. In Section 2.6, we introduce just enough
formalism to get this basic idea across to non-specialists. More rigorous and
more general versions of the arguments in Chapter 2 will be given in Chapter
4, which the reader can skip or skim (along with Chapter 5) without losing the
thread of the overall argument (but we hope the reader will at least take a look
at the pictures of correlation polyhedra in Figures 4.11, 4.13 and 4.17). The
connection between quantum mechanics and general statistics and probability
theory will be explored further in Chapter 3, also accessible to non-specialists
with the exception of the later parts of Section 3.4. The upshot of Chapters
2–5 is summarized at the beginning of Chapter 6, making that chapter largely
self-contained and thus suitable, all by itself, for courses on the foundations of
quantum mechanics.
Polytopes, philosophy and pedagogy are the main interests of Janas, Cuf-
faro and Janssen, respectively. Accordingly, even though all three of us made
substantial contributions to all seven chapters, Janssen had final responsibil-
ity for Chapters 1–2, Janas for Chapters 3–5 and Cuffaro for Chapters 6–7.
The three of us came to this project from different directions. Janssen, a his-
torian of science, is a recovering Everettian who has been defending Bub’s
xviii Preface
us to an important gap in one of our key results, which we have since managed
to close (see Chapter 3, notes 10 and 11). In June 2019 the three of us met
again in Minneapolis. Over the ensuing months we finalized (or so we thought)
our manuscript and in October we posted it on the arXiv and on the PhilSci
Archive preprint servers. By that time Janas had filled several whiteboards
in Tate Hall, housing part of the School of Physics and Astronomy of the
University of Minnesota, many times over to go over (preliminary versions
of) the results presented in Chapters 2–5 with Janssen and, when in town,
Cuffaro. Janas also did the computer programming needed for Section 4.2 and
for Figures 2.8 and 2.16. Janssen is responsible for most other figures. Cuffaro
handled whatever LATEX issues we ran into.
Janssen gave two talks on parts of our preprint at the Second Chilean Con-
ference on the Philosophy of Physics organized by Pablo Acuña in Santiago in
December 2019, where he had the opportunity to discuss the material in person
with Jeff Bub. A slightly revised version of our preprint was then pre-circulated
among participants in a symposium on the foundations of quantum mechanics
organized by Janssen, Jürgen Jost and Jürgen Renn at the Max-Planck-Institut
für Wissenschaftsgeschichte in Berlin in January 2020. In this symposium,
Cuffaro and Janssen presented parts of what was starting to get referred to as
the “Three Mikes Manifesto,” a play on the famous Dreimännerarbeit (Three
men paper) with which Max Born, Werner Heisenberg and Pascual Jordan
(1926) consolidated matrix mechanics. Based on feedback from the partici-
pants in this symposium (especially Guido Bacciagaluppi, Jürgen Jost, Jürgen
Renn and Matthias Schemmel) and from others who had read our preprint,
we added further material to Chapter 5 and substantially rewrote Chapters 1
and 6 (especially Section 6.5 on measurement). We also changed the title. The
title of our preprint, “Putting probabilities first: How Hilbert space generates
and constrains them,” would have been fine for a journal article in a special
issue devoted to Bananaworld. It would have been obvious, for instance, in
that context that our topic is quantum mechanics even though the title does
not explicitly mention this. Given the use of Hilbert space methods in general
probability theory and statistics, however, this would not have been clear for
a monograph with that same title. We settled on the new title Understanding
Quantum Raffles. Raffles of various designs are ubiquitous in this volume.
And while we are hardly the first to argue that the basic formalism of quan-
tum mechanics is essentially a new framework for handling probabilities (cf.
Chapter 1, notes 16 and 29), we are the first to do so on the basis of a sustained
comparison between raffles serving as toy models of local hidden-variable the-
ories and the statistical ensembles characterized by density operators in terms
xx Preface
of which John von Neumann (inspired by Richard von Mises) first formulated
quantum mechanics (Von Neumann, 1927b). The “quantum raffles” in the title
of our book refer to these statistical ensembles introduced by von Neumann.
In the Fall of 2020, after trying out some of the material in Chapter 2
in classes at the University of Minnesota and Washburn High School in Min-
neapolis, Janssen, assisted by Janas, taught a seminar in the Honors Program of
the University of Minnesota under the title of Gilder’s (2008) The Age of Entan-
glement, covering—in addition to Gilder’s book and the graphic novel Totally
Random by Tanya and Jeff Bub (2018)—Chapters 1–3 of the manuscript of Un-
derstanding Quantum Raffles. In response to student feedback, we reorganized
some of the material in Chapters 2 and 3.
We are grateful for the questions from the audiences at the various work-
shops and talks mentioned above as well as for the feedback from students at
the University of Minnesota and Washburn High School. In addition, we want
to single out a number of individuals not explicitly mentioned so far and thank
them for helpful comments and discussion: Jossi Berkovitz, Victor Boantza,
Harvey Brown, Časlav Brukner, Adán Cabello, Joe Cain, Cindy Cattell, Radin
Dardashti, Michael Dascal, Robert DiSalle, Tony Duncan, Lucas Dunlap,
Laura Felline, Sam Fletcher, Mathias Frisch, Chris Fuchs, Louisa Gilder, Sona
Ghosh, Peter Gilbertson, Peter Grul, Bill Harper, Stephan Hartmann, Geof-
frey Hellman, Leah Henderson, Federico Holik, Luc Janssen, Christian Joas,
Molly Kao, David Kaiser, Jim Kakalios, Alex Kamenev, Jed Kaniewski, Mar-
ius Krumm, Femke Kuiling, Samo Kutoš, Christoph Lehner, Charles Marcus,
Tushar Menon, Eran Moore Rea, Markus Müller, Max Niedermaier, Sergio Per-
nice, Vincent Pikavet, Serge Rudaz, David Russell, Rob “Ryno” Rynasiewicz,
Juha Saatsi, Ryan Samaroo, Chris Smeenk, Rob Spekkens, Jos Uffink, David
Wallace and Brian Woodcock. We thank Lindy Divarci, Jürgen Renn and
Matteo Valleriani of the Max-Planck-Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte for
their help in turning our manuscript into a book. We thank an anonymous
referee who reviewed our book for Springer both for the enthusiastic endorse-
ment and for helpful comments. We thank Lucy Fleet, Prasad Gurunadham
and Svetlana Kleiner at Springer for shepherding our manuscript through the
production process.
We saved our most important intellectual debts for last. A heartfelt thanks
to Jeff Bub for his enthusiastic support of our efforts and for his patience in
explaining and discussing his views on the foundations of quantum mechanics
with us, both in person and in email exchanges dating back to 2007. We are also
grateful for all we learned from Itamar Pitowsky (1950–2010) and William
Preface xxi
1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1
xxiii
xxiv Contents
7 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 227
Chapter 1
Introduction
This volume is a brief for a specific take on the general framework of quantum
mechanics. In terms of the usual partisan labels, it is an informational interpre-
tation in which the status of the state vector is epistemic rather than ontic. On
the ontic view, state vectors represent what is ultimately real in the quantum
world; on the epistemic view, they are auxiliary quantities for assigning prob-
abilities to values of observables in a world in which it is impossible to do so
simultaneously for all observables. Such labels, however, are of limited use for
a classification of interpretations of quantum mechanics. A more promising
approach might be to construct a genealogy.1 As this is not a historical work,
a rough characterization of the relevant phylogenetic tree must suffice for our
purposes.2
1 The contemporary literature on quantum foundations has muddied the waters in regards to
the classification of interpretations of quantum mechanics, and it is partly for this reason that
we prefer to give a taxonomy in terms of a genealogy. Ours is not an epistemic interpretation
of quantum mechanics in the sense compatible with the ontological models framework of
Harrigan & Spekkens (2010). In particular it is not among our assumptions that a quantum
system has, at any time, a well-defined ontic state. Actually we take one of the lessons of
quantum mechanics to be that this view is untenable (see Section 6.3 below). For more on the
differences between a view such as ours and the kind of epistemic interpretation explicated
in Harrigan & Spekkens (2010), and for more on why the no-go theorem proved by Pusey,
Barrett, & Rudolph (2012) places restrictions on the latter kind of epistemic interpretation
but is at most only indirectly relevant to ours, see Ben-Menahem (2017).
2 One of us is working on a two-volume book on the genesis of quantum mechanics. The
first volume has already been published (Duncan & Janssen, 2019).
The main thing to note then is that the mathematical equivalence of wave and
matrix mechanics papers over a key difference in what its originators thought
their big discoveries were.3 These big discoveries are certainly compatible with
one another but there is at least a striking difference in emphasis. For Erwin
Schrödinger the big discovery was that a wave phenomenon underlies the parti-
cle behavior of matter, just as physicists in the 19th century had discovered that
a wave phenomenon underlies geometrical optics (Joas & Lehner, 2009). For
Werner Heisenberg it was that the problems facing atomic physics in the 1920s
call for a new framework to represent physical quantities just as electrodynam-
ics had called for a new framework to represent their spatio-temporal relations
two decades earlier (Duncan & Janssen, 2007, Janssen, 2019, pp. 134–142).4
What are now labeled ontic interpretations—e.g., Everett’s many-worlds inter-
pretation, De Broglie-Bohm pilot-wave theory and the spontaneous-collapse
theory of Ghirardi, Rimini and Weber (GRW)—can be seen as descendants
of wave mechanics; what are now labeled epistemic interpretations—e.g.,
the much maligned Copenhagen interpretation5 and Quantum Bayesianism or
QBism—as descendants of matrix mechanics.6
3 As Bacciagaluppi & Valentini (2009, pp. xv–xvi) explicitly acknowledge in the preface of
their carefully annotated edition of the proceedings of the 1927 Solvay conference, their main
objective was to show how the current debates over the foundations of quantum theory could
benefit from being traced back to the discussions between the founding fathers attending
this conference shortly after the theory in its various guises had first been formulated.
4 In Bananaworld, Bub makes a similar point. Heisenberg’s first paper on what would
become matrix mechanics, he writes, “contained the germ of a radically new way of thinking
about physical systems . . . while Schrödinger’s wave mechanics evoked a very different
structural picture that has turned out to be misleading in many ways” (Bub, 2016, p. 4). The
development of quantum mechanics—as Olivier Darrigol (2014, p. 237) puts it about as
concisely as one can imagine—was driven by two analogies, “the analogy between classical
and quantum theory [and] the analogy between matter and light. These analogies led to
two different versions of the new mechanics: the Heisenberg-Born-Jordan matrix mechanics
and the De Broglie-Schrödinger wave mechanics, which occurred in two different contexts:
atomic constitution and the statistical properties of matter and light.”
5 In the preface of his book on quantum computing, Mermin (2007, p. xii) notes that his
presentation “is suffused with a perspective on the quantum theory that is very close to the
venerable but recently much reviled Copenhagen interpretation,” so much so, in fact, that he
considered calling his book Copenhagen Computation.
6 David Wallace (2019) provides an example from the quantum foundations literature that
shows that the “big discoveries” of matrix and wave mechanics are not mutually exclusive.
He argues that the Everett interpretation should be seen as a general new framework for
physics while endorsing the view that vectors in Hilbert space represent what is real in the
quantum world. Wallace and other Oxford Everettians derive the Born rule for probabilities
in quantum mechanics from decision-theoretic considerations instead of taking it to be given
1 Introduction 3
The interpretation for which we will advocate in this volume can, more
specifically, be traced to the (statistical) transformation theory of Pascual Jor-
dan (1927a,b) and Paul Dirac (1927, amplified in his famous book, Dirac,
1930) and to the “probability-theoretic construction” (Wahrscheinlichkeitsthe-
oretischer Aufbau) of quantum mechanics in the second installment of the
trilogy of papers by John Von Neumann (1927a,b,c) that would form the back-
bone of his famous book (Von Neumann, 1932). While incorporating the wave
functions of wave mechanics, both Jordan’s and Dirac’s version of transforma-
tion theory grew out of matrix mechanics. More strongly than Dirac, Jordan
emphasized the statistical aspect. The “new foundation” (Neue Begründung)
of quantum mechanics announced in the titles of Jordan’s 1927 papers con-
sisted of a number of postulates about the probability of finding a value for
one quantum variable given the value of another. Von Neumann belongs to
that same lineage. Although he proved the mathematical equivalence of wave
and matrix mechanics in the process (by showing that they correspond to two
different instantiations of Hilbert space), he wrote his 1927 trilogy in direct
response to Jordan’s version of transformation theory. His Wahrscheinlichkeits-
theoretischer Aufbau grew out of his dissatisfaction with Jordan’s treatment
of probabilities. Drawing on work in probability theory by Richard von Mises
(soon to be published in book form; Von Mises, 1928), he introduced the now
familiar density operators characterizing uniform (pure state) and non-uniform
(mixed state) ensembles of quantum systems.7 He showed that what came to be
known as the Born rule for probabilities in quantum mechanics can be derived
from the Hilbert space formalism and some seemingly innocuous assump-
tions about properties of the function that gives expectation values (Duncan
& Janssen, 2013, sec. 6, pp. 246–251). This derivation was later re-purposed
for the infamous von Neumann no-hidden variables proof, in which case the
assumptions, entirely appropriate in the context of the Hilbert space formal-
by the Hilbert space formalism the way von Neumann showed one could (see below). For
other Everettians, such as Christoph Lehner, state vectors are both ontic and epistemic. They
help themselves to the Born rule à la von Neumann but also use state vectors to represent
physical reality. One way to argue for such a position (suggested by a talk by Lehner
during the workshop in Berlin in January 2020 mentioned in the preface) is to insist on a
Lewisian modal realist interpretation of probabilities. One could then agree with members
of the “epistemic camp” that quantum mechanics provides a new framework for handling
probabilities but at the same time hold on to the notion of a multiverse.
7 For historical analysis of these developments, focusing on Jordan and von Neumann, see
Duncan & Janssen (2013) and, for a summary aimed at a broader audience, Janssen (2019,
pp. 142–161).
4 1 Introduction
8 The video of their talk could, at the time we wrote this, still be watched at <users.ox.ac.
uk/~everett/videobub.htm>. See Bub & Demopoulos (2010) for a moving obituary of
Pitowsky.
9 See, e.g., the review in Physics World by Minnesota physicist Jim Kakalios (2018), well-
known for his use of comic books to explain physics (Kakalios, 2009), the review in Physics
Today by philosopher of quantum mechanics Richard Healey (2019), and the essay review
co-authored by one of us (Cuffaro & Doyle, 2021).
10 In an essay review of Ball (2018), Becker (2018) and Freire (2015), Bub (2019a) gives a
concise characterization of his views and places them in the lineage of Heisenberg sketched
above (cf. note 4). In Chapter 6, we will quote various passages from Bohr (1928, 1935,
1937, 1948, 1958) that help convey the way that Bohr fits into this lineage (see Section
6.5, notes 23, 45, 47 and 49). For more on our lineage’s connection with Bohr’s views, see
the preprint Bub (2017, the sections on Bohr were dropped in the published version of the
paper), Bub (2019a, pp. 235–236) and an unpublished monograph by Demopoulos (2018,
see below).
1 Introduction 5
11 Bub (2016, 2nd ed., p. 232, note 29) acknowledges the importance of discussions with
Demopoulos for his thinking about quantum mechanics and cites Demopoulos (2010, 2012).
12 We consider the views of Bub, Demopoulos and Pitowsky to be our neighbors on the
phylogenetic tree of interpretations of quantum mechanics. Although we would not call
QBism a neighboring view, we take it to be closer to us than many others. The same, we
think, can also be said about the views of, among others, Scott Aaronson (2013), Časlav
Brukner (2017), Lucien Hardy (2001), Richard Healey (2017) and Carlo Rovelli (1996).
13 We adopted the convention of using “Chapter” and “Section” when referring to other
parts of this volume and “Ch.” and “sec.” when referring to chapters and sections in other
sources we cite or quote. Equations are numbered by section (e.g., Eq. 2.3.1 refers to the
first equation in Chapter 2, Section 2.3). Figures and tables are numbered by chapter (e.g.,
Figure 2.1 refers to the first figure in Chapter 2). Notes are also numbered by chapter. Unless
a chapter number is specified, a reference to a note is to the note of that number in the same
chapter.
14 See Section 6.5 (especially note 41 and Figure 6.1) for a description of such experiments,
first performed by Walther Gerlach and Otto Stern (1922).
6 1 Introduction
15 This departure from Bub is not as big as it sounds. As Bub (2016, p. 6) makes clear
in Bananaworld, “[i]n modern formulations, information theory is about random variables
. . . and correlations between random variables. As such, information theory is a branch of
the mathematical theory of probability.” We chose to call our interpretation “informational”
(in part) to emphasize our proximity to Bub’s view, but unlike Bub we chose not to call our
interpretation “information-theoretic.” The latter term would suggest an explicit connection
to results from information theory in the Shannon or Schumacher senses, but in our case we
are using information only in the general sense just described.
16 Others who have endorsed this view include Hardy (2001, p. 1), who has called quantum
theory “simply a new type of probability theory” (quoted by Darrigol, 2014, p. 318), and
Aaronson, who in the preface of Quantum Computing since Democritus relates the amusing
story of how an Australian TV commercial made him realize that a passage from his
book used in that commercial nicely captures the book’s central thesis: quantum mechanics
is “about information, probabilities, and observables, and how they relate to each other”
(Aaronson, 2013, p. xii–xiv, p. 110). See also note 29.
1 Introduction 7
only have to specify its velocity with respect to the inertial frame of interest, not
what it is made of. Special relativity imposes certain kinematical constraints
on any physical system allowed by the theory. Those constraints are codified in
the geometry of Minkowski space-time. There is no need to reify Minkowski
space-time, no need for “fetishism of mathematics” as John Stachel (1994,
p. 149) would put it. We can think of space-time in relational rather than
substantival terms (Janssen, 2009, p. 28).
The slogan “Quantum mechanics is all about information/probability” can
be unpacked in a similar way. Quantum mechanics imposes kinematical con-
straints on allowed values and combinations of values of observables. Which
observables? Any observable that can be represented by a Hermitian operator
on Hilbert space. The constraints quantum mechanics imposes on the values
of such observables are codified in the geometry of Hilbert space. And as in
the case of Minkowski space-time, there is no need to reify Hilbert space. So,
yes, quantum mechanics is obviously about more than just information, just as
special relativity is obviously about more than just space-time. Yet the slogans
that special relativity is all about space-time and that quantum mechanics is
all about information (or probability) do capture—the way slogans do—what
is distinctive about these theories and what sets them apart from the theories
they superseded.
In Chapter 6, we will further explore this parallel between quantum me-
chanics and special relativity.17 We should warn the reader upfront though that
the kinematical take on special relativity underlying this comparison, while
in line with the majority view among physicists, is not without its detractors.
In fact, the defense of a kinematical interpretation of special relativity by one
of us (Janssen, 2009) was mounted in response to an alternative dynamical
interpretation of special relativity articulated and defended most forcefully by
Harvey Brown (2005).18 Both Bub (2016, p. 228) in Bananaworld and Bub
& Pitowsky (2010, p. 439) in “Two dogmas . . . ” have invoked analogies with
special relativity to defend their information-theoretic interpretation of quan-
tum mechanics. Brown & Timpson (2006) have disputed the cogency of these
analogies (see also Timpson, 2010, 2013, sec. 8.3.3).19
Our second response to the parochialism charge is that the quantum for-
malism for dealing with intrinsic angular momentum, i.e., spin, laid out in
Section 4.1 and used throughout in our quantum-mechanical analysis of an ex-
perimental setup to test the Bell inequalities, is key to spectroscopy and other
areas of physics as well, such as, e.g., the theory of the electric susceptibility of
diatomic gases. These two responses are not unrelated. In Section 6.4, drawing
on papers on the history of quantum physics co-authored by one of us,20 we
will give a few examples of puzzles for the old quantum theory that physicists
resolved not by altering the dynamical equations but by using key features of
the kinematical core of the new quantum mechanics.
What about the other charge against informational interpretations of quan-
tum mechanics, instrumentalism or anti-realism? What invites complaints on
this score in the case of Bub and Pitowsky is their rejection of the second
of the “two dogmas” they identified: “the quantum state is a representation
of physical reality” (Bub & Pitowsky, 2010, p. 433).21 This statement of the
purported dogma is offered as shorthand for a more elaborate one: “[T]he
quantum state has an ontological significance analogous to the significance of
the classical state as the ‘truthmaker’ for propositions about the occurrence
or non-occurrence of events” (ibid.). Of course, denying that state vectors in
Hilbert space represent physical reality in and of itself does not make one an
anti-realist. We can still be realists as long as we can point to other elements
of the theory’s formalism that represent physical reality. The sentence we just
quoted from “Two dogmas . . . ” suggests that for Bub and Pitowsky “events” fit
that bill. However, as John Earman (1989, p. 186) has argued regarding taking
point coincidences to exhaust what is real in general relativity, such an event
ontology smacks of “a crude verificationism and an impoverished conception
of physical reality.” In Section 6.5 we argue that one can do considerably better
without reinstating the dogma that Bub and Pitowsky want to reject.
19 What complicates matters here is that the distinction between kinematics and dynam-
ics tends to get conflated with the distinction between constructive and principle theories
(Janssen, 2009, p. 38; see Section 6.1 below for further discussion).
20 Duncan & Janssen (2008, 2014, 2015) and Midwinter & Janssen (2013).
21 In what he identifies as “orthodox quantum mechanics,” Wallace (2016, p. 4) detects
“an inchoate attitude to the quantum state . . . where it is interpreted either as physically
representational or as probabilistic, according to context.” This representational/probabilistic
distinction is cited by Bub (2016, 2nd ed., p. 231, note 21). In Section 6.5, we will return to
this point and characterize the “inchoate attitude” Wallace draws attention to more carefully.
1 Introduction 9
22 For reflections by one of us on how new theories get introduced, see Janssen (2002, 2019).
10 1 Introduction
Pitowsky, however, it does not follow that classical and quantum states have
a different “ontological significance.” Neither vectors in Hilbert space nor
points in phase space represent our physical world.23 Both are mathematical
auxiliaries for assigning values (albeit in radically different ways) to quantities
that do.24
What about the first dogma Bub & Pitowsky (2010, p. 433) want to reject:
Measurement outcomes should be fully explained in terms of the dynamical
interaction between the system being measured and a measuring device? Strik-
ing this dogma from the quantum catechism trivially solves the measurement
problem in its traditional form of having two different dynamics side-by-side,
unitary Schrödinger evolution as long as we do not make a measurement, state
vector collapse as soon as we do. If we reject the demand for a dynamical
account of how a measurement results in a particular definite outcome, this
problem obviously evaporates. As we will show in Section 6.5, renouncing
this dogma does not amount to black-boxing measurements.25 On Bub and
Pitowsky’s view, any measurement can be analyzed in as much detail as one
can ask for. It does mean, however, that one accepts that there comes a point
where no meaningful further analysis can be given of why a measurement
gives one particular outcome rather than another. Instead it becomes a matter
of irreducible randomness—the ultimate crapshoot.26
Bub & Pitowsky (2010, p. 438) distinguish between what they, with thick
irony, call a “big” and a “small” measurement problem. This distinction maps
nicely onto the two ways distinguished above in which the quantum state
vector fails to be a “truthmaker”. Those two ways correspond to two questions:
(I) How does one set of observables rather than another get selected to be
assigned definite values? (II) Why does an observable, once selected, take on
one value rather than another? These two questions can be seen as statements
of the “small” and the “big” measurement problem, respectively.27 Rejection
of what Bub and Pitowsky identify as the first dogma of quantum mechanics
then amounts to dismissing the “big” measurement problem as a pseudo-
problem. They urge us to resist the call for a general dynamical account of how
measurements result in definite outcomes and endorse their “totally random”
response to question (II) instead. Though arguments from authority will not
carry much weight in these matters, we note that a prominent member of
the Copenhagen camp did endorse this very answer. In an essay originally
published in 1954, Wolfgang Pauli wrote: “Like an ultimate fact without
any cause, the individual outcome of a measurement is . . . in general not
comprehended by laws” (Pauli, 1994, p. 32, quoted by Gilder, 2008, p. 169).
Bub and Pitowsky thus do not see the “big” measurement problem as a problem
but as a lesson quantum mechanics has taught us about how the world behaves.
It is not a puzzle to be solved but a feature to be embraced.
The same is true for the “small” measurement problem. As we will explain
in more detail in Chapter 6, our response to the question of which observables
get assigned definite values is that this is decided by the experimenter. The
experimenter chooses which question to put to nature. It is, we submit, not a
task for physics to account for such decisions. It certainly never was for classical
mechanics. One might object that this is only because, in classical mechanics,
such decisions are irrelevant to the way in which observables acquire definite
values. In classical mechanics, the decision to perform this rather than that
measurement amounts to no more than choosing to ascertain the value of this
rather than that observable, where all these values are taken to be pre-given.
In quantum mechanics, by contrast, a decision to perform a measurement to
obtain a value for one observable will typically preclude the assignment of a
definite value to another observable that could have been measured instead.
Such decisions thus select the catalog of values of observable quantities used
in the construction of our conception of reality.
Yet the difference between classical and quantum mechanics on this score
is not as big as it seems. Even though according to classical mechanics de-
cisions about which measurement to perform do not influence the possible
outcomes of that measurement (or any other measurement that could have
been performed instead), these decisions clearly do affect the actual catalog
of values of observables obtained and hence the reality constructed with the
help of them. What door a contestant picks on Monty Hall’s “Let’s make a
deal” does not affect what is behind that door but it obviously does make a
difference whether that door has a check for a thousand dollars or a goat behind
it (cf., e.g., Janssen & Pernice, 2020). As this simple example illustrates, the
difference between quantum mechanics and classical mechanics is not whether
decisions about what to measure affect what is real or what happens. What
is different is that in quantum mechanics such decisions affect what is real
or what happens at a deeper level than in classical mechanics, namely at the
level of possibilities. Rather than insisting that quantum mechanics provide an
account of the kind of decisions we did not expect classical physics to account
for, however, we can take the fact that it does not as another lesson quantum
mechanics taught us about the world—just as it taught us that, at rock bottom,
the world is irreducibly stochastic.
The “small” measurement problem, we will argue in Section 6.5, is only a
problem if we insist that we, as observers, can be completely written out of
our description of the physical world. This was certainly the goal of classical
physics. But quantum mechanics tells us that we and our measuring devices are
entangled with the rest of the world, that the probabilities quantum mechanics
gives us are ultimately all marginal probabilities obtained once we trace out the
degrees of freedom of us and our measuring devices. To use another slogan
we will unpack in Section 6.5, quantum mechanics is hard to square with
the classical ideal of the “view from nowhere.” To bolster our case, we will
briefly discuss the analysis of two historians of early-modern science of how
this classical ideal took shape in the 17th century through developments in
optics from Kepler to Descartes (Gal & Chen-Morris, 2013, Ch. 1, “Science’s
disappearing observer”). Their analysis suggests that while this classical ideal
proved to be extremely useful for the development of optics and physics more
generally from the 17th through the 19th century, it was never inevitable.
Whether or not we are able to convince the reader that either the “big” or
the “small” or both measurement problems are pseudo-problems—not bugs
but features—we hope to convince the reader of the more general thesis that
quantum mechanics, at its core, is a new framework for handling probabilities
(cf. notes 6, 16 and 29). Our main argument for this thesis will come from
our analysis—in terms of Bub’s correlation arrays and Pitowsky’s correlation
polytopes—of correlations found in measurements on systems in a special but
informative quantum state in a simple experimental setup due to David Mermin
(1981, 1988) to test a Bell inequality (see Figure 2.6 for the correlation array
for Mermin’s example of correlations violating this particular inequality).
1 Introduction 13
within this elliptope (see Figures 2.15 and 2.16). This provides a concrete
example of the way in which Pitowsky and others (see, e.g., Goh, Kaniewski,
Wolfe, Vértesi, Wu, Cai, Liang, & Scarani, 2018) have used nested polytopes28
to represent the convex sets formed by these classes and subclasses of corre-
lations (compare the cross-section of the non-signaling cube, the tetrahedron
and the elliptope in Figure 2.8 to the familiar Vitruvian-man-like cartoon in
Figure 2.5). Such polytopes completely characterize these classes of correla-
tions whereas the familiar Bell inequalities (in the case of local hidden-variable
theories) or Tsirelson bounds (in the case of quantum mechanics) only provide
partial characterizations.
As Pitowsky pointed out in the preface of Quantum Probability—Quantum
Logic:
The possible range of values of classical correlations is constrained by linear in-
equalities which can be represented as facets of polytopes, which I call “classical
correlation polytopes.” These constraints have been the subject of investigation by
probability theorists and statisticians at least since the 1930s, though the context of
investigation was far removed from physics (Pitowsky, 1989a, p. IV).
28 The term was coined by Alicia Boole Stott, George Boole’s mathematician daughter,
who was introduced to the mathematics of higher dimensions by her brother-in-law, Charles
Howard Hinton, also a mathematician (who was at the University of Minnesota in the late
1890s) and a notorious polygamist. We are grateful to Louisa Gilder for alerting us to the
relevant Wikipedia entries.
29 As the authors of a book on quantum information intended for a broad audience write:
“the mathematical formalisms [sic] underlying quantum theory can be precisely and usefully
viewed as an extension of probability theory” (Rieffel & Polak, 2011, p. 331, cf. note 16
above). The story of Pearson, Yule, Fisher and De Finetti in Chapter 3 illustrates their lament
1 Introduction 15
In Section 2.6 we show that it follows directly from the geometry of Hilbert
space that the correlations found in our simple quantum system are constrained
by the elliptope inequality and do not saturate the non-signaling cube. This
derivation of the elliptope inequality is thus a derivation from within quantum
mechanics.
Popescu & Rohrlich (1994) and others have asked why quantum mechanics
does not allow all non-signaling correlations. They introduced an imaginary
device, now called a PR box, that exhibits non-signaling correlations stronger
than those allowed by quantum mechanics.30 Several authors have looked
for information-theoretic principles that would reduce the class of all non-
signaling correlations to those allowed by quantum mechanics and rule out
devices such as PR boxes (Clifton, Bub, & Halvorson, 2003; Bub, 2016, Ch.
9; Cuffaro, 2020). Such principles would allow us to derive the elliptope
inequality from without.31
What the result of Yule and others shows is that the elliptope inequality
expresses a general constraint on the possible correlations between three arbi-
trary random variables. It has nothing to do with quantum mechanics per se.
As such it provides an instructive example of a kinematical constraint encoded
in the geometrical structure of Hilbert space, just as time dilation and length
contraction provide instructive examples of kinematical constraints encoded
in the geometrical structure of Minkowski space-time.
After summarizing the results presented in Chs. 2–5 in Section 6.1, we
return to this and other analogies between quantum mechanics and special
relativity in the remainder of Chapter 6. In Section 6.2, we take a closer look at
the interplay between from within and from without approaches to understand-
ing fundamental features of quantum mechanics. In Section 6.3 we present our
take on the new kinematics of quantum mechanics. In Section 6.4, as men-
tioned above, we give some examples of puzzles of the old quantum theory
solved with the help of the new kinematics of the new quantum mechanics. In
Section 6.5, we address the thorny issue of measurement, arguing in support
of Bub and Pitowsky’s claim that what they identified as the “big” and “small”
that “the close relationship between the formal structures underlying quantum mechanics
and probability theory is surprisingly neglected” (ibid.).
30 See Figure 2.3 for the correlation array for a PR box. Figures 2.9 and 2.10 show that it is
impossible to design tickets for a raffle that could simulate the correlations generated by a
PR box.
31 We took the within/without terminology from the chorus of Bob Dylan’s song “The Mighty
Quinn”: “Come all without, come all within. You’ll not see nothing like the mighty Quinn.”
Could “Mighty Quinn” be an oblique but prescient reference to a quantum computer?
16 1 Introduction
32 For the views of one of us on the basic framework of Bohr’s interpretation of quantum
mechanics, see Cuffaro (2010).
Chapter 2
Representing distant correlations by
correlation arrays and polytopes
Peeling and tasting quantum bananas in the Mermin-style setup • Trying to simulate the
quantum correlations with classical raffles • Nested classes of correlations: non-signaling
cube, quantum elliptope, classical tetrahedron.
In the preface and in Chapter 1, we promised that this chapter would be acces-
sible to readers without any background in physics and would not presuppose
any mathematics beyond basic high-school algebra and geometry (and would
involve absolutely no calculus!). We intend to make good on that promise.
But before we start, in Section 2.2, with our elementary introduction to some
of the most puzzling facts about the physical world that quantum mechanics
confronts us with, we need to say a few words about how our approach fits
with earlier attempts to explain these matters to a broader audience.1
In addition to Bananaworld (Bub, 2016), our approach owes much to the
work of David Mermin (especially 1981, 1988). Like Mermin and Bub (and
many other popularizers), we will focus on so-called Bell inequalities, named
after John S. Bell (1964), who was the first to formulate one in the context of
quantum mechanics. As we will explain in detail in the course of this chapter,
quantum mechanics predicts that such inequalities will be violated by the
results of certain measurements on various quantum systems. These violations
have consistently been found in an ongoing series of remarkable experiments
stretching back to the early 1970s. An excellent account of these developments,
written for a general audience and based on interviews both with those who
formulated the inequalities and those who did the experiments showing that
they are violated can be found in The Age of Entanglement by Louisa Gilder
(2008, Chs. 29–31, pp. 250–289), a book we highly recommend.2
1 See also our comments in the preface, especially about the relation between our approach
and the approach taken in Albert (1992).
2 The term entanglement (Verschränkung in the original German) was introduced by
Schrödinger (1935). In quantum mechanics, the state of a composite system A + B can
in general not be decomposed into separate states for the two subsystems, A and B. Instead,
The specific Bell inequality tested in most of these experiments was for-
mulated by John Clauser, Michael Horne, Abner Shimony and Richard Holt
(1969). Like the inequality originally proposed by Bell, the CHSH inequality—
to use the acronym by which it has come to be known—is a bound on the
strength of distant correlations allowed by so-called local hidden-variable the-
ories.3 The reason these inequalities are violated in quantum mechanics is
that the distant correlations found in measurements on pairs of systems in
entangled quantum states (see note 2) are stronger than the bounds set by these
inequalities. In Section 2.5, we will introduce special raffles that can serve as
toy models of local hidden-variable theories. For now, it suffices to say that, in
a local hidden-variable theory, outcomes of measurements are always prede-
termined by variables that (a) are not included in the quantum description of a
system (hence: hidden) and (b) cannot be affected by superluminal signals (i.e.,
signals traveling faster than light; this is what “local” means in this context).
The setup used to test the CHSH inequality involves two parties (affection-
ately known as Alice and Bob in much of the literature on quantum foundations,
quantum information and quantum computing), two settings per party of some
measuring device,4 and two outcomes per setting (labeled ‘0’ and ‘1’, ‘+’ and
‘−’, or ‘up’ and ‘down’). Bell (1964, pp. 18–19) originally considered three
rather than four settings, which we can label {â, b̂, ĉ}. In Bell’s setup, one party
performs measurements using the pair {â, b̂} while the other uses {b̂, ĉ}. In
the CHSH setup the two parties use two pairs that have no setting in common,
{â, b̂} and {â0 , b̂0 } in our notation. Mermin (1981, 1988) kept Bell’s three
settings but in his setup both parties use all three settings rather than just two
the states of the components A and B are inextricably intertwined or “entangled” in the state
of the compound system A + B. This linkage persists no matter how far the two subsystems
are separated, famously leading Einstein to refer to the phenomenon as “spooky action at
a distance” (spukhafte Fernwirkung; letter to Max Born of March 3, 1947; Born, 1971, p.
158). In an oft-quoted passage, Schrödinger (1935, p. 555) wrote that he “would not call
[entanglement] one but the characteristic trait of quantum mechanics” (quoted, e.g., in Bub
& Bub, 2018, p. 9). We will focus on a particular entangled state of two identical particles
characterized by their intrinsic angular momentum or spin. Eq. (2.6.38) gives this state for
the case of spin- 12 particles. This is the only quantum state we need for our purposes in this
chapter.
3 The Pearson correlation coefficient, which we will introduce in Chapter 3 (see Eq. (3.1.9)),
provides a measure of the strength of a correlation.
4 E.g., a polarizer to measure the polarization of photons or a Du Bois magnet to measure
the component of the spin of a particle in certain direction, as used in variations on the
Stern-Gerlach experiment (cf. Section 6.5, especially note 41 and Figure 6.1).
2.1 Taking Mermin to Bananaworld 19
of them. He derived a Bell inequality for this setup, so simple that even those
without Mermin’s pedagogical skills can explain it to a general audience.5
We use a Mermin-style setup to illustrate the power of some of the tools
in Bananaworld. We represent the correlations Mermin considered by corre-
lation arrays, the workhorse of Bananaworld, and parametrize these arrays in
such a way that they and the correlations they encode can, in turn, be repre-
sented as points in convex sets in so-called non-signaling cubes (a geometrical
representation of all correlations one can imagine for a given setup that can-
not be exploited to send superluminal signals). This approach was pioneered
by Itamar Pitowsky (1989b) in Quantum Probability—Quantum Logic and is
promoted in Bananaworld.6
The representation of classes of correlations in terms of (the geometry of)
convex sets is well-established in the quantum foundations literature (see, e.g.,
Goh et al., 2018). Our efforts can be seen as another attempt to bring this
approach to a broader audience by applying it to Mermin’s particularly simple
and instructive example. Here is what makes it so. Since the CHSH setup uses
four different settings, its non-signaling cube is a hypercube in four dimensions,
which is hard if not impossible to visualize. The Mermin-style setup only uses
three different settings and its non-signaling cube is an ordinary cube in three
dimensions, which is easy to visualize. The convex set representing the non-
signaling correlations allowed classically in this case is a tetrahedron spanned
by four of the eight vertices of the three-dimensional non-signaling cube (see
Figure 2.15); the convex set representing those allowed quantum-mechanically
is an elliptope enclosing this tetrahedron (see Figure 2.16).
In Bananaworld, settings become peelings, outcomes become tastes, and
parties become characters from Alice in Wonderland (Alice stars as Alice, the
White Rabbit as Bob). Fictitious quantum bananas can be peeled “from the
stem end (S)” or “from the top end (T )” and can only taste “ordinary (“o” or
0)” or “intense, incredible, indescribably delicious (“i” or 1)” (Bub, 2016, pp.
8–9, see also p. viii).7
5 For an excellent textbook treatment of the Bell inequality for this setup and the quantum-
mechanical results maximally violating it, see McIntyre (2012, sec. 4.1, pp. 97–102).
6 In addition to Quantum Probability—Quantum Logic, Bub (2016, p. 120) cites Pitowsky
(2006), his contribution to a Festschrift for Bub, as well as Pitowsky (1986, 1989a, 1991,
2008).
7 Betraying his information-theoretic leanings, Bub (2016) occasionally refers to inputs and
outputs (both taking on the values 0 and 1) rather than peelings and tastes (see, e.g., p. 51,
Figure 3.1).
20 2 Representing distant correlations by correlation arrays and polytopes
8 Bub’s illustrator, his daughter Tanya, has the Cheshire Cat (starring as Clio) peel the third
GHZ banana (Bub, 2016, pp. 122–123, Clio and Charlie are introduced on p. 8).
9 This figure closely matches Figure 4.2 in the treatment of the Mermin-style setup in the
quantum-mechanics textbook by McIntyre (2012, p. 99, cf. note 5 and note 28).
2.2 Correlations found when peeling and tasting pairs of quantum bananas 21
Fig. 2.1 Mermin-style setup in Bananaworld (I). Two parties: the chimps Alice and Bob.
Three settings per party: three peelings, (â, b̂, ĉ), given by three unit vectors (ea , eb , ec ), in
the corresponding peeling directions (i.e., the direction of the line going from the top to the
stem of the banana while it is being peeled). In Mermin’s specific example, the angles ϕab
between ea and eb , ϕac between ea and ec , and ϕbc between eb and ec are all equal to 120°
but we will also consider other values for these angles. Drawing: Laurent Taudin with a nod
to Andy Warhol.
Fig. 2.2 Mermin-style setup in Bananaworld (II). Two outcomes per setting: the tastes
“yummy” (+) or “nasty” (−) for different peeling directions. The peeling and tasting is done
by the chimps Alice and Bob. Drawing: Laurent Taudin.
When all bananas are peeled and tasted, Alice and Bob are allowed to
compare notes. Just looking at their own records, they see nothing out of
the ordinary—just a sequence of pluses and minuses as random as if they
had faked their results by tossing a fair coin for every run. Comparing their
records, however, they note that, every time they happened to choose the same
peeling (in roughly 33% of the total number of runs), their results are perfectly
anti-correlated. Whenever one banana tasted yummy, its twin tasted nasty. In
and of itself, this is not particularly puzzling. Maybe our bananas always grow
in pairs in which one tastes yummy and the other tastes nasty and it is random
which one goes to which chimp. This simple explanation, however, is ruled out
by another striking correlation Alice and Bob discover while poring over their
data. When they happened to peel differently (in roughly 66% of the runs),
their results were positively correlated, albeit imperfectly. In 75% of the runs
in which they used different peelings, their bananas tasted the same (Mermin,
1981, p. 86).10 The tastes of two bananas coming from one pair thus depend
on the angle between the peeling directions used. This is certainly odd but one
could still imagine that our bananas are somehow pre-programmed to respond
differently to different peelings and that the set of pre-programmed responses
is different for the two bananas in one pair. What Mermin’s Bell inequality
For some days I saw but little of Frank. Ponty took him into her tender
keeping and set about nursing him back to health, only allowing him to
come downstairs and lie on the Chesterfield couch by the hall fire for a few
hours every day. It was astonishing to me to find Ponty so good to Frank.
She had always resented his presence at Restham even before he had
worked any mischief there: yet now she took him into her charge, and
nursed him as devotedly as if she had been his mother.
I remarked upon this change of front one day. "I am surprised you are so
kind to Mr. Wildacre, Ponty, considering how angry you were when first I
asked him to come and live at the Manor. I was afraid you wouldn't like his
coming back in this way."
"Well, you see, Master Reggie, when I was that set against his coming to
the Manor, he was strong and well, and so could stand up to me, as you
might say: but now he is too weak and ill to hurt a fly. There's lots of folks
as you can't stand at any price when they are able to stick up for themselves:
but when they are knocked down you'd do anything you could to help them
to get up again."
"I remember there was a girl at Poppenhall who'd had a fine upstanding
young man after her for years and years, and she couldn't so much as look
at him, though all the other girls envied her for having such a handsome
beau: but he lost an arm and got his face scarred in an accident down a coal-
pit, and then she married him at once, and spent the rest of her life in
looking after him and trying to take the place of his lost arm."
"And all the same, Master Reggie, I'm not such a woman as you seem to
think—though I dare say I'm as weak as most of them if I'm taken the right
way: but it was one thing to have Mr. Wildacre here when I felt it in my
bones that he'd come between you and her dear young ladyship, and quite
another to have him here when there is nobody to come between. It wasn't
that I objected to Mr. Wildacre himself—far from it—any more than I
objected to Miss Annabel, whom I'd had from a month old: but what I did
say—and always shall say—is that it's best for married people to fight
things out for themselves, without having any relations on either side to
back them up. And I shall stick to this till my dying day, even if I was to
hang for it!"
I had no intention of hanging my old nurse when she talked in this strain,
but I had every objection to listening to her. So I closed the conversation by
going out of the nursery.
Annabel came over to see Frank a few days after his arrival at Restham:
but Ponty, who was paramount in the sick room, forbade her entrance. I had
already perceived that my sister's despotic sway at the Manor was gradually
being undermined, in secret and insidious ways, by the redoubtable Ponty,
whenever a suitable opportunity presented itself.
"I'm not going to let Miss Annabel see Mr. Wildacre till he is stronger,"
my old nurse said: "she's no good in a sick room isn't Miss Annabel, being
far too managing and interfering for invalids. And after all that poor young
gentleman has gone through, it would be heathen cruelty to upset him still
worse. Miss Annabel on the top of the Germans would be too much for
anybody!"
"But Miss Annabel, as you call her, used to be so fond of Mr. Wildacre,"
I pleaded.
"Not after he crossed her will and ran off with her ladyship. You could
put on the top of a threepenny-bit all Miss Annabel's love for them as don't
do exactly as she tells them, and have room to spare. If she is as fond of Mr.
Wildacre as she used to be, she can go on with it as soon as he is strong
again, and able to stand her domineering ways; though there won't be much
fondness to go on with, if I know Miss Annabel. But as long as he's ill, and
in my charge, I can't have him bothered with nobody—not even with Deans
and Chapters and all other dignities of the Church, including Miss Annabel.
And so I tell you straight, Master Reggie."
And Ponty had her way, having found a secret supporter in my humble
self.
As Frank under Ponty's care grew stronger, I saw more of him, and we
gradually got into the way of talking naturally about my lost darling. He
could not bear even yet to say much about his awful experiences during that
terrible time at Louvain; but he repeated the story of how Fay had given her
life to save another's after risking it for some time in order to tend the sick
and wounded. And that made me love her all the more dearly, and mourn
her all the more deeply.
"I don't want to bother you, Reggie," he said one day, when relations had
grown less strained between us; "but I just want you to know how
dreadfully sorry I am that I behaved as I did. Lady Chayford told me that
you couldn't forgive me, and I feel I haven't the right to ask you to forgive
me. But I just want to tell you that I am sorry, and that I would give my life
to undo what I did."
He was lying in his usual place on the couch, and I was sitting in an
easy-chair on the other side of the great fire-place. For a few seconds I
smoked in silence: then I said: "I hope you understand it isn't that I won't
forgive you, Frank, but that I can't. I've tried, and I find it impossible."
Frank nodded his head in the way that reminded me so keenly of Fay. "I
know: Lady Chayford told me. And she also told me how not forgiving me
had made you lose your wonderful gift of healing. It is dreadful to think that
I had power to spoil your life as much as that!"
I smiled sadly at the childishness which made the loss of my healing
powers seem greater than the loss of Fay. And then my smile faded as I
realised that it is only when we speak as little children that we speak truth;
for the loss of my healing powers stood sacramentally for more than even
the loss of my wife. It was the outward and visible sign of my separation
from God.
"I know it's no good saying I'm sorry now, but I must say it," Frank
continued; "and I shall go on feeling it as long as I live. I don't really see
how you could forgive me: I know I couldn't if I were in your place. In fact,
I shouldn't even want to."
"But although I own I did my best towards the end to induce Fay to
come away with me," continued Frank, in that throaty and rather husky
voice which was so like Fay's that sometimes it thrilled my heart-strings to
breaking-point, "I can't help saying that she oughtn't to have listened to me.
After all, she was bound to you by vows, and I wasn't."
"You are very loyal to her," he replied, after a short pause, in which I did
him the justice to believe that he felt ashamed of himself.
"I loved her," I said. Then I corrected myself: "I mean I love her."
But it was not easy to suppress a Wildacre even when he did feel
ashamed of himself. "Then you have forgiven her," said Frank: "Lady
Chayford told me you hadn't."
There was a few minutes' silence whilst I tried to be honest with Frank
and with myself. Then I said slowly: "I don't believe I really did forgive her
altogether till I heard of her death, though I loved her all the time more than
I loved life itself. But after she died I gradually realised that there was
nothing to forgive. I had been weighed in her balance, and had been found
wanting, and she had no further use for me: therefore she threw me on one
side as worthless. I was hers to do what she liked with, and she had a
perfect right to retain or to reject me as she thought fit. But, mind you, I
didn't see this at first. I am no better than my neighbours, and for a long
time I was as harsh and bitter and vindictive as any poor beggar of the so-
called 'criminal classes' could have been in the circumstances. It is only
since Fay's death that I have realised that she was justified in the course she
took."
"No, no! Say what you like about yourself, my boy, but not a word
against Fay. And don't think that because I completely exonerate her I also
exonerate you. For I don't. Whatever lay between her and me, was sacred to
her and me, and no one had any right to intermeddle in it. Neither had you
nor anybody else a right to try to put asunder those whom God had joined
together: and that—unless I do you a grave injustice—is what you did."
Frank pondered on my words for a short time and then he said: "To a
certain extent, perhaps, I did come between you and Fay, and, as I have told
you, I repent of what I did in dust and ashes. But I never meant to come
between you. On that score my conscience is clear. What I did do was to
persuade her to come away with me: but I never did that until something or
somebody had already come between you and her, and I saw she was
fretting her life out because of it."
He did his best to make matters clearer. No Wildacre was ever at a loss
for words. "You see, it was in this way: Fay absolutely adored you—simply
worshipped the ground you walked on. I'm not justifying her for feeling like
this," he added, with the first touch of his old whimsicalness that he had
shown since his return; "I don't deny that it was very foolish of her to set up
any man as a god and worship him like that: but that is what she did; and it
is right for you to know it, before you judge her for what she did besides."
"Well, then, before you understand what she did, if you prefer the word.
It really was Fay's absorbing and unreasoning adoration of you that upset
the apple-cart and did all the mischief. If she'd been more sensible and
discriminating, all this trouble would never have happened: but she was
young and foolish, and madly in love at that. And she was so wild with
jealousy, because she thought you loved your sister more than you loved
her, that she hardly knew what she was doing."
"I thought she found me old and dull and tiresome," I murmured.
"I know you did, and that really was too idiotic for anything! Why, she
was simply crazy for love of you from the first time she saw you till the day
she ran away; but you footled the whole thing! I'm sorry to say it, Reggie,
but you really did."
Nothing loth, he continued: "Well, if you want the truth, you shall have
it. And of course you must bear in mind that, if Fay hadn't been so
ridiculously in love, silly little things wouldn't have hurt her as they did,
and she wouldn't have gone off her head with jealousy of Miss Kingsnorth.
I know men like to feel that their wives are very much in love with them:
but the wives who aren't so much in love are really the best for everyday
wear. They are more tolerant and much less exacting."
Frank was a wiser man than he had been when he left Restham. I noted
that. And for the first time a tiny doubt crept into my mind as to whether
even then he had been the most unwise man there.
"In the first place," he went on, "Fay was most frightfully upset at your
asking Miss Kingsnorth to stay on living with you after you were married.
That started the feeling."
"I thought that as Fay was still such a child it would be a comfort to her
to have a kind and loving woman to turn to and lean upon," I explained.
"But that only made the matter worse. Fay didn't want me any more than
she wanted Miss Kingsnorth to come poking my nose in between you and
her. She wanted you to herself."
"I'm afraid that she and Annabel did not get on together as well as I had
hoped," I said.
Frank shrugged his thin shoulders. "They'd have got on all right together
in their proper places. Fay was quite fond of Miss Kingsnorth as a sister-in-
law: but when she found Miss Kingsnorth put in place of her husband, why
of course she kicked. Anybody would."
"Yes, she was; and of course the thing didn't work. You seemed to have
an idea that Fay's love was transferable, like a ticket for a concert, and that
if you didn't use it your sister could. But it's no good trying to transfer other
people's affections any more than it's any use trying to change other
people's religions. You can take the old one away, but you can't give them a
new one in its place."
But Frank was firm. "Yes, you did. Or, at any rate, Fay thought you did,
which comes to the same thing as far as she was concerned, and that was
what made her so mad. For instance, when she particularly asked you to
give her a Prayer Book with her name written in it by you, so that religion
and you might all get mixed up together in her mind, and you be part of
religion and religion part of you, what did you do? You got Miss Kingsnorth
to give her the Prayer Book, so that Miss Kingsnorth should become part of
her religion instead of you! Now it really was absurd to expect Miss
Kingsnorth—I beg her pardon, I mean Mrs. Blathwayte—to become part of
anybody's religion, except of old Blathwayte's—I mean the Dean's. I
suppose she's part of his religion now, right enough. But she wasn't the kind
of person to be ever part of Fay's religion, and I should have thought you
could have seen that for yourself."
"Did Fay tell you that about the Prayer Book?" I asked, with a stab of
anguish. It was incomprehensible to me how my darling could have
discussed, even with her brother, things which lay entirely between her and
me. I could never have talked to Annabel about matters which concerned
Fay and myself alone! I should have regarded them as too sacred. But that
is where men and women are so different from each other, and where
women are so much less reserved than men. I believe that good wives tell
more about their husbands than bad husbands ever tell about their wives.
But good Heavens, how it hurt!
"Then another time," Frank went on, the Wildacres never having been
denied freedom of utterance, "she was almost mad with joy because you
came all the way from Restham to Liverpool Street to meet her on her way
home from Bythesea. It looked as if you really were as much in love with
her as she was with you. And then you went and spoilt it all by saying that
you had come to please your sister. Now, I ask you, what wife could stand
that? I'm sure you wouldn't have liked to feel that Fay married you in order
to please me: and in the same way she didn't like to feel that you had
married her to please Mrs. Blathwayte."
"But it was absurd of her to feel like that! She must have known that I
worshipped the very ground she walked on, and that the only fly in my
ointment was that I felt I was too old and dull to make her happy."
Frank still had me on the hip. "Then that was equally absurd of you! Fay
wasn't the only absurd one apparently. You see all the time that you were
inventing trouble by thinking that you were too old and dull for her, she was
inventing trouble by thinking that she was too young and silly for you, and
that you were comparing her with your sister, and finding her inferior. And
you know how mad a woman gets when she thinks her husband likes
anybody else more than he likes her. There's nothing she wouldn't do to
punish him and hurt herself at the same time! And that is how Fay got. She
was so wild at finding you thought more of Miss Kingsnorth than you did
of her, that she didn't care what happened. She thought you despised her,
and that simply finished her off altogether. And when she was unhappy she
tried to drown her unhappiness in theatricals and fallals of that kind, which
didn't really do her the slightest good: but when husbands fail, women set
up all sorts of ridiculous scarecrows in their place. It's the way they're
made, I suppose. And when the theatricals turned out to be no good in
helping her to forget, she took to travelling, and that was how we came to
be in Belgium when the war broke out. But travelling didn't really help her
either, though she had an idea that the old cities of Flanders might be rather
soothing. But as things panned out they were quite the reverse, and we'd far
better have remained in Australia!"
But Frank had no mercy. "The long and the short of it is you were so
busy worrying yourself about the relations between Fay and your sister, that
you let the relations between Fay and yourself slide. And that was really the
only thing that mattered. Then Fay got it into her head that you regretted
having married her when you compared her with Miss Kingsnorth and saw
how young and silly she was in comparison: and so she decided to leave
you and your sister once more alone together, as she believed that that was
what really could make you happy. And even now I can't help admitting that
Miss Kingsnorth is far more your sort than Fay was."
I was silent for a time. The solid earth seemed slipping away beneath my
feet. Then I said: "Do you mean to tell me, on your word of honour, that to
the best of your belief neither you nor Annabel tried to come between my
wife and me?"
"But you did. And it is for what we do that we are punished—not for
what we meant to do. It is a way of yours to mix up essentials with non-
essentials, and I expect always will be: I suppose you are made like that,
and can't help it. But if you'd only realised that the important thing was not
how Fay and Miss Kingsnorth got on together, but how Fay and you got on
together, all this misery would never have happened."
I felt I could bear no more: so I went out alone into the autumn dusk to
commune with my own soul on the revelations which Frank had vouchsafed
to me. And when we met again, we did not refer to it, but talked only on
indifferent things. For the boy not only knew when to speak: with a wisdom
beyond his years he knew also when to be silent.
And then wherever I went I heard nothing but one awful message: the
dying leaves whispered it, the dropping rain repeated it, and the autumn
winds thundered it in my ears: the message which long ago struck terror and
remorse to the heart of a great King struck terror and remorse also to mine.
Wherever I went and whatever I did I kept hearing the appalling word of
condemnation: "Thou art the man."
CHAPTER XXIII
Or, rather, I had come to the knowledge that there was nothing to
forgive: that the man whose insensate folly had spoilt my life and Fay's was
not Frank at all, but myself.
But the result was the same. After nearly three years of the outer
darkness I had come once more into the light: I was at peace with Man and
therefore with God: and that seemed to be all that signified.
With a joy beyond all earthly joy I rose and dressed and went out into the
hazy autumn morning. It was Sunday: and as I stood in the grey mist which
still lay over everything and which shrouded the garden and the fields from
my view, I heard the church-bell ringing for the eight o'clock Celebration.
And for the first time for more than two years that bell called to me, and
bade me come and take my place at the Eucharistic Feast: for at last I was
in love and charity with all men, and intended to lead a new life.
I answered the Call and entered the Church which was hallowed by the
worship of centuries: and there I made my confession to Almighty God,
meekly kneeling upon my knees, as the pilgrims had knelt there ages and
ages before me. And as in lowly adoration I partook of the Blessed Food
Which Christ Himself had ordained, I thereby received Him into my heart
by faith: and the peace of God, which passeth all understanding, once more
filled my heart and mind with the knowledge and love of God and of His
Son, Jesus Christ.
I did not see Frank when I came home after the Service was over, as he
never came down to breakfast: but as I sat at my solitary meal I knew no
loneliness: the glory of the Great Reconciliation was about me still.
"I am sorry to trouble you, Sir Reginald," he began, "and I told Maggie
Pearson so, but she wouldn't take no, and begged me to come and give you
her message."
Jeavons still appeared confused. "I really did my best, Sir Reginald, to
make her understand that you'd given up all that sort of thing and never
went in for it now, finding it more or less uncertain, as you might say, and
out of the usual course of events, and so not altogether to be depended
upon; and that she'd much better stick to the doctor and not trouble you, Mr.
Wildacre being laid up in the house, and you with enough on your hands as
it is. But she went on crying, and said her mother'd never forgive her if she
didn't give you the message."
"Well, what was the message?" I repeated, with (I cannot help thinking)
commendable patience.
"Well, Sir Reginald, begging your pardon, the fact is that Mrs. Pearson's
baby is dying of brownchitis or pewmonia or some other disease connected
with its teething, and nothing will satisfy her but that you should come and
lay your hands on it, like as was your custom at one time, having outgrown
it since. I told Maggie as how you had given up the habit long ago, which
she said her mother knew: but all the same, Mrs. Pearson still persisted that
she was sure you could cure the baby if you tried, which was just like her
obstinacy, and to my thinking a great impertinence."
"Yes, Sir Reginald, and he can't do nothing more than what he has done,
he says, and he is afraid the child will die. Though what they wants with
that extra child at all, beats me, having six besides, and none too much food
for them all, with the dreadful war sending up the prices of everything."
For two years now I had refused all the villagers' requests that I would
exercise my gift of healing upon them, as I knew, alas! that the gift was no
longer mine: and they had gradually ceased to proffer these requests.
Therefore it struck me as noteworthy that on the very day when, as the old
theologists put it, I had "found peace," I should be asked to exercise this lost
power once more. It seemed to be one of those wonderful instances of
direct Interposition which we of this faithless and perverse generation
disguise under the pseudonym of "remarkable coincidences."
How joyfully those who had laughed Him to scorn when He contradicted
their conventional assumption that death was the final ending—laughed,
doubtless with the uncomfortable, mocking laughter of all materially
minded people when confronted with things undreamed of in their smug
philosophy—must have hurried to lay the table and prepare the meal, and
perform all the trivial little duties which form the essence of the normal and
the commonplace. How relieved they must have felt to find themselves
once more in the ordinary routine of everyday existence!
And I like to think that it was then His turn to smile—He Who knew
them so well, and remembered that they were but dust; yet the dust wherein
He had clothed Himself in order to identify Himself with them. But I am
sure that in His smile there was no scorn. He knew what they needed, and
He supplied all their need.
Obedient to the Call which had come to me, I went through the village,
hardly conscious of any volition on my own part. I had merged my will in
another's, and had no longer any desire to act on my own initiative. It is a
strange feeling, this absolute surrender of self, and brings with it that peace
which the world can never give nor take away.
Still as in a dream I entered the cottage at the far end of the village, and
found Mrs. Pearson rocking in her arms her dying child; the other children
hanging round, all more or less in a state of tears.
"I will do what I can," I said, "but it is years now since I have had the
power to heal anybody. I lost it when her ladyship went away."
"So I've heard, Sir Reginald. But I minded that story of the woman who
wouldn't take 'No' even from the Blessed Lord Himself, but begged for just
the crumbs under the table: and her child was healed in consequence."
I knelt down beside the rocking-chair, and laid my hands upon the little
form lying on the mother's lap, at the same time lifting up my whole soul in
prayer. And straightway the answer came—as in my heart of hearts I had
known it would come. Like a mighty electrical force the healing power
rushed through me to the child. I could feel it in every vein and every fibre
of my body. And at the same time my consciousness of the Presence of
Christ was so acute that it was almost as if I actually saw and heard and felt
Him close beside me.
Whilst I prayed the moaning of the child ceased, and its laboured
breathing grew gradually soft and easy: and when I rose from my knees and
looked at it, I knew that it would live.
The poor mother clung to my hand, and wept tears of gratitude. But I
told her—as I always made a point of telling those whom I was permitted to
help—that her thanksgivings were not due to me, but to Another Whose
messenger for the time I was allowed to be: and then I hurried back through
the village to the Church, there to render thanks, with the rest of the
congregation at the office of Matins, for the blessings that had (in my case
so wonderfully) been vouchsafed to me.
When I returned home after the morning service, I found Frank dressed
and downstairs: but it was not until lunch was over and we had settled down
in our usual places—he on the Chesterfield on one side of the hall fire, and
I in my easy-chair on the other—that I found an opportunity of telling him,
without fear of interruption, of the marvellous thing that had happened to
me.
"Frank, my boy, I have something to say to you," I began.
"Fire away," said Frank encouragingly. "I shall catch on right enough,
never fear."
"Well, first and foremost, I want you to know that I have forgiven you
completely for any share that you may have had in helping Fay to leave
me."
Frank gave a little cry of joy. "Oh, Reggie, how splendid of you!" he
began.
But I lifted up my hand to stop him. "Wait a bit, my boy. Please hear all I
have got to say before you cut in. I was going to tell you that I forgave you
freely because I had found that there was nothing to forgive. It sounds
rather Irish, I know: but I think you will understand that we are obliged to
forgive people when we think they have injured us, even when we find they
haven't really injured us at all. I mean we are bound to get back into love
and charity with them, whether the lapse from love and charity was their
fault or ours."
Frank nodded his head in the way that reminded me so of Fay. "I know
exactly what you are driving at. When we quarrel with anybody we've got
to bury the hatchet before we can be happy or good again: and the original
ownership of the hatchet has no effect whatever upon the importance of the
funeral."
"Precisely so. I'd got to forgive you whether you'd done anything
needing forgiveness or not: because I believed you had, and acted according
to that belief. Therefore it was imperative upon me to root the bitterness
towards you out of my heart: the fact that the bitterness to a great extent
was undeserved, did not altogether rob it of its flavour. Well, then, that is
the first thing: I want you to know that at last I am at peace with you after
nearly three years of hot anger against you: whether you in any way
deserved that anger, is your affair not mine."
Here Frank's enforced silence broke down. "I didn't deserve it as much
as you thought, but I did deserve it a bit. I never tried to set Fay against you:
but when I saw she was set against you, I induced her to cut and run,
instead of using my influence to make her see things in a different light, and
to bring you and her together again. After all is said and done, you were her
husband: and when I saw the bond between you was loosening I ought to
have helped to tie it tight again instead of undoing it altogether. Let's try to
be just all round!"
"No, I wasn't. Neither was Fay, when you come to that, though I know
you won't let me say so."
"Certainly I won't: so don't try it on. Let us pass on to the next thing.
And that is that as I have forgiven you, so God has forgiven me, and has
restored to me my power of healing."
"Oh, Reggie, is that really true? I minded that more than anything!"
Frank's voice was hoarse with emotion and his language was confused: but
I understood him right enough.
Frank was trying so hard to choke back his sob that he could not speak.
He was still very weak after his awful experiences in Belgium. So I went
on, order to give him time to recover himself.
I turned my head in surprise, and for the first time since Frank's return to
Restham, I saw his face within close range of my short-sighted eyes. For a
moment I was literally paralysed with amazement, and my heart and pulses
seemed to stand still and then to rush on in a very delirium of unheard-of
joy. For the face into which I looked at such close quarters—the face
quivering with emotion and disfigured with tears, and yet to me the dearest
and most beautiful face in the whole world—was not Frank's at all—but
Fay's!
CHAPTER XXIV
CONCLUSION
This then is the story of the drama of my life; the story of how in my
case the greatest miracle of all was accomplished, and the shadow on the
dial was brought ten degrees backward. She who had been dead was alive
again, she who had been lost was found. The past was given back to me to
be lived over again, with its misdeeds expiated and its mistakes retrieved.
I learnt from my darling that the greater part of what she had told me
was absolutely true; only that it was Frank who gave his life to save the
child that was playing in the sun when the shells began to fall in that
doomed street of Louvain—not Fay.
So Frank Wildacre died the death of a hero: for there is no more glorious
death for any man than to give his life for another's. Again it struck me
afresh, as it had often struck me before, how since the beginning of the
Great War the prophecy had been literally fulfilled that the last should be
first, and the first last. Frank, who had been thoughtless and irresponsible
and frivolous, had been called to lay down his life for one of those little
ones whose angels do always behold the Face of the Father: whilst I, who
had taken the world so seriously, and had ever longed to do great deeds and
think high thoughts, was left amongst the useless ones at home. Yet we
were all part of the great army of the living God, and it was not for us to
pick and choose who should go forth with the hosts and who should stay at
home by the stuff. That was all left in the Hands of "Our Captain, Christ,
under Whose colours we had fought so long."
Frank only lived for about an hour after he was hit. They managed to
carry him into a house, but there was no hope from the first. He was
conscious almost to the end; and he devoted those last moments to careful
thought for his sister. He told her to cut off her long hair and dress herself
up in his clothes, and try to get away to England as soon as she could, as it
was not safe for her to remain in Belgium now that he was no longer there
to take care of her: and as terrible and ghastly rumours were already current
as to the unspeakable way in which the ruthless invaders were treating such
women as were hapless enough to fall into their hands, he thought Fay
would be safer if her sex were not known. And so he fell on sleep.
As soon as Frank had passed to his well-earned reward, Fay followed out
all his instructions to the letter, and succeeded, after many vicissitudes, in
escaping to England with a crowd of Belgian refugees. No one penetrated
her disguise—not even Isabel Chayford, who put down Fay's extraordinary
likeness to her own self to the fact that she and Frank were twins, and so
were expected to resemble one another. And Fay kept to her own room most
of the time that she was at the Chayfords', for fear Isabel should discover
her identity. Ponty found her out at once: there was never any deceiving
Ponty! But Fay could always twist my old nurse round her little finger, and
therefore Ponty kept her secret for her.
To this hour I cannot conceive how I could have been such a fool as not
to know my darling the moment I set eyes on her. But the grim fact remains
that I am by nature a fool, and this was one of the occasions of my
displaying my folly. My one excuse—and a feeble one it is!—is my
extreme short-sightedness: the first moment that Fay's dear face was close
to my own I recognised her like a shot: but lying in the Chesterfield on the
other side of the fire-place, with her short curly hair and elfin face, she
looked so like Frank that I took it for granted she was Frank; and she was so
much aged and changed, alas! by all she had suffered, that she had lost
much of her likeness to the Fay of the past. As to her voice, Frank's was so
high for a man's and hers was so deep for a woman's that I frequently had
mistaken the one for the other in the old days: so no wonder I did so now,
when I was convinced in my own mind that Fay was dead, and that Frank
was talking to me from the other side of the great fire-place.
I gathered that Fay's original idea was to find out whether or not I had
forgiven her. If I had, she meant to reveal herself to me and to ask me to
take her back as my wife: but if I had not forgiven her, she intended to
return to Australia, leaving me with the idea that she was dead and I was
free. A wild, childish scheme, just like my impracticable darling!
But when Isabel told her how deeply my anger against Frank had eaten
into my very soul, destroying my gift of healing and coming between me
and my God, Fay realised that there was far more at stake than just the
relations between herself and me. The salvation of my soul was hanging in
the balance, and it was for her dear hands to adjust the scales. With an
insight beyond her years, she understood that before I could find peace I
must forgive Frank, believing him to be alive: the easy forgiveness which
we accord to the dead, who can no longer hurt or be hurt by us, was not the
thing that was demanded of me. I was called upon to forgive Frank fully
and freely, even although I believed that it was through him that my darling
had gone to her death, and that therefore there was no possibility of her ever
coming back to me, or of the wrong which he had done me ever being
rectified.
And now we are once more all in all to each other; and the love that is
stronger than death can lighten even the long shadows cast by the Great
War.
I do not think there is any more to add to my story, save the interesting
fact that we have christened our first-born son Francis.
I think that some day "Sir Francis Kingsnorth" will be quite an effective
name and sound very well indeed. But I shall not be there to hear it.
THE END
*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK TEN DEGREES
BACKWARD ***
Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will
be renamed.
1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the
United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the
terms of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying,
performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this
work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes
no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country other than the United States.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or
expense to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or
a means of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original
“Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must
include the full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in
paragraph 1.E.1.
• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive
from the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”
• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.
1.F.
1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
Welcome to our website – the ideal destination for book lovers and
knowledge seekers. With a mission to inspire endlessly, we offer a
vast collection of books, ranging from classic literary works to
specialized publications, self-development books, and children's
literature. Each book is a new journey of discovery, expanding
knowledge and enriching the soul of the reade
Our website is not just a platform for buying books, but a bridge
connecting readers to the timeless values of culture and wisdom. With
an elegant, user-friendly interface and an intelligent search system,
we are committed to providing a quick and convenient shopping
experience. Additionally, our special promotions and home delivery
services ensure that you save time and fully enjoy the joy of reading.
ebooknice.com