The Gentle Civilizer of Nations The Rise and Fall of International Law 1870 1960 Hersch Lauterpacht Memorial Lectures 1st Edition Martti Koskenniemi
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations The Rise and Fall of International Law 1870 1960 Hersch Lauterpacht Memorial Lectures 1st Edition Martti Koskenniemi
com
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-gentle-civilizer-of-
nations-the-rise-and-fall-of-international-
law-1870-1960-hersch-lauterpacht-memorial-lectures-1st-
edition-martti-koskenniemi/
OR CLICK BUTTON
DOWLOAD EBOOK
https://ebookgate.com/product/faxed-the-rise-and-fall-of-the-fax-
machine-jonathan-coopersmith/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-oskar-klein-memorial-lectures-
volume-3-1st-edition-gosta-ekspong/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/fall-of-capitalism-and-rise-of-islam-
mohammad-malkawi/
ebookgate.com
The rise and fall of ergativity in Aramaic Cycles of
alignment change 1st Edition Coghill
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-rise-and-fall-of-ergativity-in-
aramaic-cycles-of-alignment-change-1st-edition-coghill/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/colossus-the-rise-and-fall-of-the-
american-empire-1-xerox-edition-niall-ferguson/
ebookgate.com
The Last Gasp The Rise and Fall of the American Gas
Chamber 1st Edition Scott Christianson
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-last-gasp-the-rise-and-fall-of-the-
american-gas-chamber-1st-edition-scott-christianson/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-software-paradox-the-rise-and-fall-
of-the-commercial-software-market-1st-edition-stephen-ogrady/
ebookgate.com
https://ebookgate.com/product/egypt-on-the-brink-from-the-rise-of-
nasser-to-the-fall-of-mubarak-osman/
ebookgate.com
This page intentionally left blank
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
The Rise and Fall of International
Law 1870–1960
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
The Rise and Fall of International Law 1870–1960
0 521 62311 1
Self-Determination of Peoples
A Legal Appraisal
0 521 63752 X
International Law and the Antarctic Treaty System
0 521 46311 4
The International Law Commission
0 521 46320 3
-
Corporations in and under International Law
0 521 46324 6
The Gentle Civilizer
of Nations:
The Rise and Fall of International
Law 1870–1960
http://www.cambridge.org
Preface page xi
List of abbreviations xiv
Introduction 1
vii
Contents
viii
Contents
Epilogue 510
Bibliography 518
Index 558
ix
Preface
The essays in this book are inspired by many sources and reflect various
conversations I have had with international lawyers in the course of the
past four years or so. The initiator of the idea of the book was Professor
Sir Elihu Lauterpacht, who kindly invited me to give the Sir Hersch
Lauterpacht Memorial Lectures at the University of Cambridge in
1998, and in that connection pointed out that this privilege also involved
a commitment to prepare the lectures for publication. Eli’s hospitality in
Cambridge in 1997 and the discussions I had with him also underlie my
interpretation of his father’s work in chapter 5. As always, I am indebted
to Professor David Kennedy from the Harvard Law School for innu-
merable conversations and collaborative projects, Dighton weeks and
weekends, shorter and longer periods together and in wider company in
the Boston area, Helsinki and other places, at various stages of writing
of these essays. But the only person to have read the whole of this work,
and whose comments and criticisms are reflected on every page, as in
everything about its author, is Tiina Astola. This book would not exist
without them.
Many other friends and colleagues have been involved. The com-
ments and work of Dr. Outi Korhonen are reflected in the description
of the culture of late nineteenth-century internationalists. The account
of international lawyers and imperialism (chapter 2) draws on the
important work of Professors Antony Anghie and Nathaniel Berman,
and from discussions I have had with them over the years. That section
owes much to the invitation I received from Dr. Surya Subedi to give the
Josephine Onoh Memorial Lecture at the University of Hull in February
1999. I also want to thank the participants in the international legal
history project under Professor Michael Stolleis at the Max Planck
xi
Preface
Institute for Legal History in Frankfurt for the debate on persons and
problems relating to my German story (chapter 3), among them partic-
ularly Dr. Betsy Roeben, whose work on Bluntschli I have plundered in
chapter 1 and Dr. Ingo Hueck whose writings on the institutional aspects
of the German inter-war scene underlies sections of chapter 3. I am
grateful for a number of French friends and colleagues, too, among them
in particular Professors Pierre Michel Eisemann and Charles Leben,
who directed me to primary and secondary materials without which I
could not have made sense of the French story in chapter 4. I also thank
Doyen Vedel for correspondence on Louis Le Fur, Dr. Oliver
Diggelmann for a discussion and a copy of his unpublished dissertation
on Max Huber and Georges Scelle as well as Professor Geneviève
Burdeau and Mr. Pierre Bodeau for providing relevant materials or ref-
erences. Chapter 6 on Carl Schmitt and Hans Morgenthau and the
“fall” of international law collects several strands of conversation over
the years. Some of it draws on papers and discussions at a conference
organized by Dr. Michael Byers in Oxford in 1998, and a continuous
debate I have had with Professor Anne-Marie Slaughter about the
meaning and direction of her “dual agenda.” David Kennedy’s work
underlies much of the description of the American scene. People with
whom I have discussed various aspects of the following essays but whose
influence cannot be clearly allocated to particular sections include Philip
Allott, David Bederman, Thomas M. Franck, Gunther Frankenberg,
Benedict Kingsbury, Karen Knop, Jan Klabbers, Mattias Kumm, Susan
Marks, Reut Paz, Jarna Petman, and Joseph Weiler. The librarians at the
Library of Parliament (Helsinki) were again as helpful as ever.
Colleagues at the Erik Castrén Institute of International Law and
Human Rights (Helsinki) bore without complaint the additional burden
of my absent-mindedness about current matters that needed attention.
At home, Aino and Lauri took their father’s excessive book-wormishness
with a fine sense of irony. So did my mother, Anna-Maija Koskenniemi.
I thank them all.
I could not have written this book without one year’s leave of absence
from the University of Helsinki, made possible by a grant received from
the Finnish Academy (Suomen Akatemia).
Parts of this book draw on materials that I have published earlier.
Chapter 5 on Lauterpacht is essentially the same essay that was pub-
lished in (1997) 8 European Journal of International Law (pp. 215–263).
Chapter 2 contains passages included in ‘International Lawyers and
Imperialism’ in Josephine Onoh Memorial Lecture 1999 (University of Hull,
xii
Preface
Martti Koskenniemi,
Helsinki, January 17, 2001
xiii
Abbreviations
xiv
Introduction
I
This book grew out of the Sir Hersch Lauterpacht Memorial Lectures
that I gave at the University of Cambridge in the fall of 1998. It is,
admittedly, quite a bit longer than those original lectures were, but it is
still informed by the same interest. This was to expand upon an article
I had written a year earlier on Hersch Lauterpacht himself for the
European Journal of International Law and in which I had attempted to cover
the same ground I had done in a book ten years earlier, but from an
altogether different perspective. In that book I had described inter-
national law as a structure of argumentative moves and positions,
seeking to provide a complete – even “totalising” – explanation for
how international law in its various practical and theoretical modes
could simultaneously possess a high degree of formal coherence as well
as be substantively indeterminate.1 The result was a formal–structural
analysis of the “conditions of possibility” of international law as an
argumentative practice – of the transformational rules that underlay
international law as a discourse – that relied much on binary oppositions
between arguments and positions and relationships between them. But
as perceptive critics pointed out, whatever merits that analysis had, its
image of the law remained rather static. Even if it laid the groundwork
for describing the production of arguments in a professionally compe-
tent international law practice, it fell short of explaining why individual
lawyers had come to endorse particular positions or arguments in dis-
tinct periods or places. Even if it claimed that all legal practice was a
1
Martti Koskenniemi, From Apology to Utopia: The Structure of International Legal Argument
(Helsinki, Lakimiesliiton kustannus, 1989).
1
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
2
Introduction
created it, modern international law was defeated as much by its spec-
tacular successes as its equally striking failures. Many of the political
objectives of the first modern international lawyers – the men who set
up the Institut de droit international in 1873 – were sooner or later realized
in their domestic societies: general suffrage, social welfare legislation,
rule of law. Support for international institutions and advancing the
international rule of law became defining attributes to a new multilat-
eral diplomacy, however much “idealist” and “realist” accounts might
have disagreed about their centrality to the conduct of foreign policy.
But many large objectives proved to be unrealizable – global federalism,
peace, universal human rights – while some turned out to have conse-
quences that were the exact opposite of the lawyers’ expectations: the
projection of Western sovereignty in the colonies is the most conspicu-
ous example. What was distinctive about the internationalist sensibility
was not only its reformist political bent but its conviction that interna-
tional reform could be derived from deep insights about society, history,
human nature or developmental laws of an international and institu-
tional modernity. While the first generation of internationalists ima-
gined that those insights were embedded in their shared Victorian
conscience, later generations sometimes departed from this assumption in
one or another direction, only to return to it in a secondary, or default
mode some time in the immediate post-war era. The attempt to imagine
international law either as a philosophy or a science of the development of soci-
eties that was pursued with energy in Germany and France during the
first half of the twentieth century failed to produce or even support
viable policies and collapsed with the inter-war world in 1939. The pro-
fession never really recovered from the war. It was, instead, both depol-
iticized and marginalized, as graphically illustrated by its absence from
the arenas of today’s globalization struggles, or turned into a technical
instrument for the advancement of the agendas of powerful interests or
actors in the world scene. As a sensibility, it was compelled to fight nos-
talgia, or cynicism, or both.
II
This book is informed by two intuitions I have had about the history of
international law in the period from 1870 to 1960. One was the sense
that earlier accounts of the profession’s pedigree failed to give an ade-
quate sense of the radical character of the break that took place in the
field between the first half of the nineteenth century and the emergence
3
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
4
Introduction
The most important exception to this was their support of official impe-
rialism, as discussed in chapter 2 below. Until 1914, they did advocate
the extension of Western sovereignty beyond Europe as the only orga-
nized way to bring civilization to their “Orient.” After the First World
War, however, they started increasingly looking for internationalized
solutions to colonial problems.
Finally, the recounting of the story about the “rise” and “fall” of inter-
national law seemed to me necessary not only because of what it might
tell us of the profession as it was then but what it could say of it as it is
now. I hope that these essays provide a historical contrast to the state of
the discipline today by highlighting the ways in which international
lawyers in the past forty years have failed to use the imaginative oppor-
tunities that were available to them, and open horizons beyond aca-
demic and political instrumentalization, in favor of worn-out
internationalist causes that form the mainstay of today’s commitment to
international law.2 This is not to say that I should like to propose a return
to the themes of academic or political controversy in which the protag-
onists of this book were once engaged. Return to “gentle civilizing” as a
professional self-definition is certainly no longer plausible. But this is not
to say that international lawyers could not learn from their fathers and
grandfathers in the profession. Understanding the way they argued in
particular situations, often in great crises and sometimes heavily involved
as participants or even victims, provides a sense of the possibilities that
could exist today. The limits of our imagination are a product of a
history that might have gone another way. There is nothing permanently
fixed in those limits. They are produced by a particular configuration of
commitments and projects by individual, well-situated lawyers.
So although this book covers quite a bit of the same ground as the one
I published ten years ago, the move from structure to history makes this
a completely different work. Or almost does. For the play of apology and
utopia is of course effective in the writings of the lawyers I discuss below
and continues to account for the fact that they became highly regarded
representatives of the profession. But I have consciously tried to down-
play that aspect of their work, and to focus instead on the political and
in some cases biographical context in which they worked and on the pro-
fessional and political projects that they tried to advance through their
2
Cf. also Martti Koskenniemi, “Between Commitment and Cynicism; Outline of a
Theory of International Law as Practice,” in Collection of Essays by Legal Advisors of States,
Legal Advisors of International Organizations and Practitioners in the Field of International Law
(New York, United Nations, 1999), pp. 495–523.
5
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
practice, on the struggles for power and position in which they were
engaged, and on their defeats and victories.
III
The move from structure to history in the analysis of international law
is thus the first ambition of this book. But to refer to “history” probably
begs more questions than it answers. Lawyers – especially those with an
interdisciplinary interest – should bear in mind that the grass is not nec-
essarily any greener in the adjoining fields. Historiography, like sociol-
ogy or philosophy, is at least as much riddled with methodological
controversy, and uncertainty about premises, as law is. What kind of
history, then, do the following chapters offer to the reader? Two alterna-
tives had to be discounted at the outset. One was the grand history that
would paint a canvas of “epochs” following each other under some
metahistorical law about the workings of “culture” or “power” on the
destinies of peoples or civilizations, patterns of creation, flourishing, and
decline. There already were such histories and little could be added to
them that would be new or interesting.3 Perhaps more importantly, they
implied philosophical, methodological, and political assumptions that
seemed hard to sustain. Already the identification of the relevant
“epochs,” not to say anything about the ways in which they reduced a
complex world into hierarchical blocs, following each other in a more or
less monotonous parade headed by laws of interdependence, Great
Power policies, or perhaps “progress,” seemed burdened with contest-
able assumptions about what was central and what peripheral, what val-
uable and what harmful in the past, and failed to address the question
3
The standard English-language introduction remains Arthur Nussbaum, A Concise
History of the Law of Nations (Revised edn., New York, Macmillan, 1954). Like that work,
most of the writing in the field has been undertaken by Germans. See particularly
Wilhelm Grewe, Epochen des Völkerrechtsgeschichte (Baden-Baden, Nomos, 1984) recently
published as The Epochs of International Law (trans. and rev. by Michael Byers, Berlin
and New York, de Gruyter, 2000). Ernst Reibstein, Völkerrecht. Eine Geschichte seiner Ideen
in Lehre und Praxis (2 vols., Freiburg and Munich, Alber, 1958 and 1963), is a collection
of citations, chronologically arranged to support the author’s sometimes idiosyncratic
theses. Shorter recent introductory overviews are Karl-Heinz Ziegler, Völkerrechts-
geschichte. Ein Studienbuch (Munich, Beck, 1994) and Antonio Truyol y Serra, Histoire du
droit international public (Paris, Economica, 1995). Still impressive is Robert Redslob,
Histoire des grands principes du droit des gens depuis l’antiquité jusqu’à la veille de la grande guerre
(Paris, Rousseau, 1923). An extensive (though not exhaustive) bibliography is Peter
Macalister-Smith and Joachim Schwietzke, “Literature and Documentary Sources
relating to the History of Public International Law: An Annotated Bibliographical
Survey” (1999), 1 Journal of the History of International Law, pp. 136–212.
6
Introduction
7
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
4
Cf. Albert Geouffre de Lapradelle, Maîtres et doctrines du droit des gens (2nd edn., Paris,
Editions internationales, 1950); Les fondateurs du droit international (Intr. Antoine Pillet,
Paris, Giard, 1904). Truyol y Serra, Histoire, also belongs largely to this group.
5
Cf. the Symposia in the European Journal of International Law on Georges Scelle (1990),
1 European Journal of International Law (EJIL), pp. 193–249; Dionisio Anzilotti (1992), 3
EJIL, pp. 92–169; Alfred Verdross (1995), 6 EJIL, pp. 32–115; Hersch Lauterpacht
(1997), 8 EJIL, pp. 215–320; Hans Kelsen (1998), 9 EJIL, pp. 287–400.
8
Introduction
6
Here I think especially of the new work by Antony Anghie, David Bederman,
Nathaniel Berman, Anthony Carty, David Kennedy, Karen Knop, Outi Korhonen,
Carl Landauer, and Annelise Riles.
9
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
which the constraints of any rigorous “method” have been set aside in
an effort to create intuitively plausible and politically engaged narratives
about the emergence and gradual transformation of a profession that
plays with the reader’s empathy. The essays do not seek a neutral
description of the past “as it actually was” – that sort of knowledge is
not open to us – but a description that hopes to make our present situa-
tion clearer to us and to sharpen our own ability to act in the professional
contexts that are open to us as we engage in our practices and projects.
In this sense, it is also a political act. I hope that it does not treat its pro-
tagonists unjustly. But if it seems that it does, then I have Goethe’s ironic
response to fall back on, namely, that it is the one who acts that is always
unjust, and the one that merely observes, that is just.
10
1
11
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
War – and a positive obstacle to the spread of liberal ideas.1 Men who
extolled the spirit of liberalism in the mid-Victorian age were compelled
to conclude that the prevailing economic and political conditions by no
means guaranteed further progress and were positively responsible for
the presence of that other redoubtable nemesis, revolution.
A manifesto
Under such conditions, many felt that action needed to be taken in order
to ensure the spread of liberal ideas. This was one of the purposes of the
Association internationale pour le progrès des sciences sociales that was set up in
Brussels in September 1862 following the example of a British associa-
tion that had been established five years earlier with the same name.2
Among the participants to the Brussels Conference were three young
lawyers, Gustave Rolin-Jaequemyns (1835–1902), an avocat from Ghent,
Tobias Asser (1838–1913), 24-year-old lawyer from Amsterdam who
had just been appointed Professor of Contemporary Law at what today
is the University of Amsterdam, as well as John Westlake (1828–1913),
barrister of Lincoln’s Inn, author of a well-received 1858 treatise on
private international law and Secretary to the British association.3 The
three men met at and outside the formal sessions of the conference and
became friends. The following year Rolin invited Asser and Westlake to
stay with him in Ghent during the Association’s second conference, of
which he was the principal organizer.
The Association internationale advocated liberal ideas, religious toler-
ance, freedom of opinion and free trade, as well as the development of
contacts between peoples.4 It sought to provide a secular and scientific
1
Cf. e.g. Charles Vergé, “Le droit des gens avant et depuis 1789,” in G. F. de Martens,
Précis de droit des gens moderne de l’Europe, précedé d’une Introduction et complété par l’exposition
des doctrines des publicistes contemporains et suivi d’une Bibliographie raisonnée du droit des gens par
M. Ch. Vergé (2 vols., 2nd French edn., Paris, Guillaumin, 1864), pp. xlv–xlvi.
2
The National Association for the Promotion of Social Science (NAPSS) had been set
up in Britain in 1857 to deal with social reform and improvement of legislation. It was
divided into five “departments” (legal reform, penal policy, education, public health,
and social economy), functioning as a kind of unofficial Parliament that was regularly
addressed by leading liberal politicians and intellectuals such as Gladstone or John
Stuart Mill. Stefan Collini, Public Moralists. Political Thought and Intellectual Life in Britain
1850–1930 (Oxford, Clarendon, 1991), pp. 210–211.
3
A Treatise on Private International Law, or the Conflict of Laws, with Principal Reference to its Practice
in the English and Other Cognate Systems of Jurisprudence (London, Maxwell, 1858). Another
participant at the meeting was Rolin’s friend the Swiss Alphonse Rivier, later Professor
at the University of Brussels and Secretary-General to the Institut de droit international.
4
Cf. Ernest Nys, “Notice sur Rolin-Jaequemyns” (1910), Annuaire de l’Académie royale
des sciences, des lettres et des beaux-arts de Belgique, pp. 57–58; T. M. C. Asser, “Le droit
12
“The legal conscience of the civilized world”
13
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
Legislators and jurists needed to learn about the laws and legislative pro-
jects of different countries so as to better appreciate the effects of pro-
posed domestic reforms and to reduce conflicts that might be caused by
differing laws. Today, the prospectus declared, nobody who wanted to
ameliorate social conditions could afford to neglect the study of compar-
ative law.8
Westlake agreed to the scope and spirit of the prospectus although he
wondered whether the national spirit always worked in the direction of
peace and objected to the appeal to vague notions such as the “con-
science of the age.” The text was therefore amended so as to replace the
esprit d’internationalité by a less controversial reference to how nations (“ces
grandes individualités collectives”) had recently ceased regarding each
other as enemies and started to co-operate for the furtherance of
common aims.9 Rolin and Asser then communicated the prospectus to
Pasquale Mancini (1817–1888) of Turin, Professor of Public, Foreign,
and International Law10 and member of Sardinia’s Parliament from the
constituency of the Democratic Left, already a famous advocate of the
nationalities principle, whose prestige and experience they wished to
enlist. Mancini gave enthusiastic support to the project, proposing that
the journal should also treat questions of international law proper.11 The
text was revised accordingly and the first issue of the Revue de droit inter-
national et de législation comparée – the first international law journal – was
published at the end of 1868.
In the manifesto that headed the first issue, Rolin inaugurated the
Revue as a professional forum for liberal legislative reform in Europe.
Comparative study of legislation was instrumental in this, he noted, with
specific reference to Bentham and Montesquieu, and then listed his
agenda:
In the matter of personal status, the abolition not only of slavery but of servitude;
in civil matters the freedom of establishment; in penal matters, the creation of a
more just relationship between the crime and the punishment and the applica-
tion of the punishment in the interests of the criminal as well as that of society;
the suppression of the criminalisation of usury, and of privileged corporations,
the liberation of the value of gold and silver, and the freedom of association.12
18 9
Roeben, “Bluntschli,” pp. 117–118. Asser, “Fondation de la revue,” p. 112.
10
A Chair instituted for him in 1850. Cf. Rodolfo di Nova, “Pasquale Stanislao
Mancini,” in Institut de droit international, Livre de centenaire: évolution et perspectives du droit
11
international (Basle, Karger, 1973), p. 5. Asser, “Fondation de la revue,” p. 113.
12
Gustave Rolin-Jaequemyns, “De l’étude de la législation comparée et de droit inter-
national” (1869), I RDI, p. 11.
14
“The legal conscience of the civilized world”
13
Rolin-Jaequemyns, “De l’étude de la législation comparée et de droit international,”
p. 235.
14
Rolin-Jaequemyns, “De l’étude de la législation comparée et de droit international,”
p. 256.
15
Rolin-Jaequemyns, “De l’étude de la législation comparée et de droit international,”
pp. 225–226.
15
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
16
“The legal conscience of the civilized world”
theory. In his prolific writings in the Revue he often reported on the activ-
ities of professional organizations and inaugurated a new genre of legal
writing – the chronique de droit international – that allowed him to review and
comment upon the international events of the day. This created a prac-
tical means for him to apply the view of the jurist as the organ of liberal
public opinion that often felt strongly about international matters such
as the Balkan War of 1887–1888, the Russian advances in the Caucasus,
or the Turkish treatment of Christians, on which he focused his detailed
commentary.
In fact, none of the men behind the Revue came from the tradition of
Grotius, or the school of “European Public Law” that had dominated
international legal writing from Vattel well into the mid-nineteenth
century. None was a lawyer–philosopher in the vein of Suarez or a dip-
lomat like Wheaton. Like Rolin, Asser was and continued as a practic-
ing lawyer in addition to holding a university chair. In later years, he was
instrumental in setting up the Hague Conference on Private
International Law and undertook a number of activities in the field of
unification of private law. He failed to get elected to the Dutch
Parliament but did secure the Nobel Peace Prize in 1911. Westlake had
practiced as a barrister since 1854 and, aside from being a “thoroughly
trained and competent equity lawyer”20 was also a “convinced and
unflinching liberal.”21 After a brief period in the House of Commons he
was elected Whewell Professor of International Law in Cambridge in
1887 but continued taking part in various foreign policy activities includ-
ing the British Government’s Balkan Committee and the manifesto in
favor of Finland.
Establishing professional journals was one means whereby the mid-
Victorian generation institutionalized the various scientific disciplines –
including economics and social sciences.22 Rolin’s objective, too, was to
organize reformist lawyers interested in contacts with other countries
and in international affairs around a tangible focal point that his journal
was to provide. Up until then, international law had been an affair of
professors and philosophers, diplomats with an inclination to reflect on
the history and procedure of their craft. Now it was to be discussed in
the pages of the Revue like any legal problem from the status of women
20
A. V. Dicey, “His Book and His Character,” in Memories of Westlake, p. 24.
21
Lord Courtney of Penwith, “Public Affairs,” in Memories of Westlake, p. 61.
22
Cf. Peter Gay, The Cultivation of Hatred. The Bourgeois Experience: From Victoria to Freud (5
vols., New York, Norton, 1993–2000), III, pp. 484–485; Collini, Public Moralists, p.
213.
17
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
23
Aside from Rolin’s programmatic articles on private and public international law, and
the first of his series of chroniques, the first issue contained an article on the abolition
of corporal punishment in France in 1867 together with a comparative review of cor-
poral punishment in various European States. Franz von Holtzendorff (1829–1889)
from Berlin reviewed recent publications on the prison system, arguing against
absurdly long sentences and in favor of prison leave. Pradier-Fodéré (1827–1904),
consultant to South American governments, criticized the Western misuse of capitu-
lations in Turkey and argued in favor of their abolition. The French essayist, poet,
and historian Edouard Laboulaye (1811–1883), Professor of Comparative Legislation
at the Collège de France and later a member of the French National Assembly, wrote
a short piece on the lack of historical perspective in Montesquieu’s Esprit des lois while
the Argentinian lawyer–diplomat Carlos Calvo (1824–1906), reiterated the Calvo
doctrine – that governments should not be held responsible for damage caused by acts
24
of domestic insurgents. Gay, The Cultivation of Hatred, p. 526.
18
“The legal conscience of the civilized world”
An old-fashioned tradition
In his manifesto, Rolin made no reference to earlier continental writing
on international law – although he did dwell briefly on humanitarian
ideas and federalist proposals by Rousseau, Kant, and others. He com-
pletely passed over the treatises that had come out earlier in the century,
particularly in Germany, written by experts in public law, with an inter-
est in international affairs often triggered by consultant work to a sove-
reign. The founders of the Revue sought a complete break from that
tradition: its focus had been too narrow, its ambition too limited. Indeed,
it must have seemed more part of the problem than an instrument for
its resolution.
Perhaps the most famous representative of that tradition had been
Georg Friedrich von Martens (1756–1822), Professor at the University
of Göttingen until 1808 and counsellor to the Courts of Westphalia and
Hanover.25 A close observer of diplomatic events and publisher, since
1790, of the extensive Recueil de traités, von Martens had prepared in
1821 a completely revised third edition (in French) of his 1796 introduc-
tion to European international law.26 The concept of law employed in
that book had been that of the fully rational social compact.27 Like indi-
viduals in the natural state, European States had contracted positive
rules so as to complement and mitigate natural law and to guarantee its
realization – to determine uncertain points, to modify its rigors, some-
times to set aside the reciprocity of rights that it initially provided.28 But
25
For biographical detail, cf. Arthur Nussbaum, A Concise History of International Law (2nd
rev. edn., New York, Macmillan, 1954), pp. 179–185.
26
I have here used the 1864 edn. prepared by Vergé of the Précis du droit des gens moderne
27
de l’Europe. Martens, Précis, I, pp. 37 § 2, 40–41 § 4.
28
Martens, Précis, I, p. 46 § 6.
19
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
29 30
Martens, Précis, I, p. 56 § 8. Martens, Précis, I, pp. 91–117 § 18–29.
31
Cf. e.g. Martens, Précis, II, pp. 201–273 § 263–289.
32
Cf. e.g the analogy between possession of territory and ownership, in Martens, Précis,
33
I, p. 151 § 44. Martens, Précis, I, pp. 322–336 § 120–124.
34
Martens, Précis, I, p. 60 § 10, p. 83–88 § 17.
20
“The legal conscience of the civilized world”
35
Johann Ludwig Klüber, Europäisches Völkerrecht (2nd edn., by Carl Morstadt,
Schotthausen, Hurter, 1851). The text essentially follows the 1st edn. For biography
and comment, cf. A. de La Pradelle, Maîtres et doctrines du droit des gens (2nd edn., Paris,
Editions internationales, 1950), pp. 183–193.
36
Leonard Krieger, The German Idea of Freedom. History of a Political Tradition (Boston,
Beacon, 1957), p. 156.
37
In a period of reaction and secrecy, this was understood as part of liberal resistance.
Michael Stolleis, Geschichte des öffentlichen Recht in Deutschland (3 vols., Munich, Beck,
1992–1998), 2: 1800–1914, pp. 71–72, 83–85.
38
Cf. also Klüber, Europäisches Völkerrecht, pp. 10–11 § 9.
39
Klüber, Europäisches Völkerrecht, pp. 23 § 21, 54 § 45.
40
The three absolute rights are quite analogous to the rights of citizens under the
American Declaration of Independence, namely the rights of life, liberty and the
pursuit of happiness.
21
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
22
“The legal conscience of the civilized world”
dynasties and wars and their politics the conservative principle of the
balance of power. They provided no foothold for activism outside
governmental diplomacy, indeed any activism seemed a priori suspect
inasmuch as it tended to disturb the balance of power that both asso-
ciated (sometimes seemed to think identical) with the maintenance of
the States.48
But the two books also seemed untenable from a scientific perspective.
As an explanation of society, rationalism was on the way out. In
Germany, Fichte and Hegel had focused on society in terms of the spirit
that occupied it, in the case of the latter, a spirit that was, though uni-
versally inclined, embedded in the nation’s specific history and culture.
Savigny’s historical school of law made much the same argument –
coming to the paradoxical conclusion that identified the German legal
Bewusstsein with the maxims of Roman law. In France, Comte had taught
that in a study of society rationalist imagination should be replaced by
observation. Society, like nature, was not only to be examined by expert
savants but also developed in accordance with the causal–instrumental
insights they had produced. In Britain, Benthamite abstractions were
being overridden by the writings of John Stuart Mill – whose On Liberty
was published in 1859 – that were not only compatible with but drew
express inspiration from Comtean sociology. However rationalistic a
basis utilitarianism had as theory, its practice encouraged legislators to
fieldwork rather than armchair imagination. As James Reddie
(1773–1852) observed in 1842, through a tortuous prose perhaps inevi-
table in a transitional work, it was time:
[t]o give up the idea of transferring the rules applicable to men viewed
abstractly, apart from any condition, in which they have ever been found to
exist, to nations or communities, formed by union of men in civil society; and
to investigate the principles of the human constitution, as ascertained by obser-
vation, experience, and the records of history.49
By the 1860s, the international law taught by von Martens and Klüber
had become old-fashioned. It had compressed European reality into an
a priori system of political ideas with little attention to the special nature
and history of the relations between European sovereigns and even less
to the political consciousness of European societies. It possessed no
48
Martens, Précis, I, pp. 323–336 § 121–124. Klüber did not think the balance a legal
principle. Disturbing it was not a legal ground for war – although it was, he said, self-
evident that all States were entitled to oppose any illegitimate attempt at supremacy,
Klüber, Europäisches Völkerrecht, pp. 50–52 § 42.
49
James Reddie, Inquiries in International Law (Edinburgh, Blackwood, 1842), p. 114.
23
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
Many of such criticisms had been voiced by Carl Baron Kaltenborn von
Stachau (1817–1866), Privatdozent from Halle and later Professor of
German Public Law in Königsberg and member of the Kur-Hessian
Foreign Ministry in Kassel.50 In his Kritik des Völkerrechts of 1847,
Kaltenborn had noted the Grabesstille in the field between 1820 and 1840
and had aimed to introduce a scientific study of international law that
would collect the facts of international life into a system of principles
(“ein organisches System von Grundsätzen”).51 He wanted to connect
the reality of the Vienna settlement – in particular the central role of
sovereignty – with a standpoint outside sovereignty by the systematic
ordering of the law’s leading principles.
Kaltenborn’s scientific ambition expressed itself in his stress on inter-
national law as a historical subject (as well as a distinctly Protestant disci-
pline).52 He attacked the abstract rationalism of earlier writers as well as
their frequent failure to discern any principle beyond the positive facts
of diplomacy.53 He shared the mid-century view that science was con-
stituted of “the rational organisation of ideas”54 and the peculiarly
German understanding that this meant that legal science was to group
its facts into a system of concepts.55 Previous scholarship had worked
with arbitrarily chosen concepts, confusing Roman law and natural law
with international law, positive law with philosophical law.56 By abstract-
ing principles from the normative relationships between individuals von
50
Stolleis regards him a “conservative” – assessed by reference to his Einleitung in das con-
stitutionelle Verfassungsrecht (1863) that sided with Bismarck. His critique, and especially
the objective/subjective distinction at the heart of it, came from the legal philosophy
of the monarchist–conservative professor Friedrich Julius Stahl. Cf. Erich Kaufmann,
Das Wesen des Völkerrechts und die Clausula rebus sic stantibus (Tübingen, Mohr, 1911), pp.
185–186.
51
Carl Kaltenborn von Stachau, Kritik des Völkerrechts (Leipzig, Mayer, 1847), pp. 92, 111.
52
Kaltenborn, Kritik, pp. 24–25. Only Protestantism could make room for freedom, and
for a modern concept of sovereignty as representative of such freedom.
53
Natural law theory being an arbitrary product of the author’s mind, Kaltenborn,
Kritik, pp. 28, 52.
54
Roger Cotterell, The Politics of Jurisprudence: A Critical Introduction to Legal Philosophy
55
(London, Butterworth, 1989), p. 47. Cf. Kaltenborn, Kritik, pp. 243–246.
56
Cf. especially Kaltenborn, Kritik, pp. 103–127.
24
“The legal conscience of the civilized world”
25
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
65
“Zur Revision der Lehre von internationalen Rechtsmitteln,” (1861), 17 Zeitschrift für
66
Staatswissenschaft, pp. 69–124. Kaltenborn, “Zur Revision,” pp. 89–94.
67
Kaltenborn, “Zur Revision,” pp. 122–123.
68
“Davor möge uns freilich Gott noch recht lange bewahren!,” Kaltenborn, Kritik, p.
69
13. Kaltenborn, Kritik, pp. 13–14.
26
“The legal conscience of the civilized world”
70
This applies also to the systematization a decade later by Professor August
Bulmerincq, who sought an even fuller purification of positive law from “extraneous”
philosophical or political elements. Cf his Die Systematik des Völkerrechts von Hugo Grotius
bis auf die Gegenwart (Dorpat, Karow, 1858).
71
Vergé, “Le droit des gens avant et depuis 1789,” pp. i–lv.
72
Vergé, “Le droit des gens avant et depuis 1789,” p. xxxi.
73
This was in line with the Victorian anxiety to overcome selfishness and egoism – seen
as primitive desires – and to develop a more sophisticated altruistic outlook on society.
Cf. Collini, Public Moralists, pp. 60–90.
74
Vergé, “Le droit des gens avant et depuis 1789,” p. xxxvii.
75
Vergé, “Le droit des gens avant et depuis 1789,” pp. xxii–xxiii.
27
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
An amateur science
At the time when Vergé wrote his introduction to von Martens’ old trea-
tise, and Rolin began his Revue, there was very little consciousness of
international law as a discipline of its own, separate from philosophy,
diplomacy, or public and civil law.79 In France, the writings of the phil-
osophes continued to dominate the way in which the subject was con-
ceived well into and beyond the Napoleonic era.80 Works such as that
by Gérard de Rayneval (1736–1812) on Institutions du droit de la nature et
des gens (1803) derived international law from a discussion of the origin
of human society in the natural state and restated the principles of
76
Vergé, “Le droit des gens avant et depuis 1789,” p. xlvi.
77
Vergé, “Le droit des gens avant et depuis 1789,” p. lii.
78
Vergé, “Le droit des gens avant et depuis 1789,” p. liv.
79
For reviews of the study of international law teaching in Europe in the 1870s, cf.
(1878), 2 Annuaire de l’Institut de droit international (Annuaire IDI ), p. 344; (1879–1880), 3–4
Annuaire IDI, pp. 324–347.
80
Cf. e.g. Paul Challine, Le droit international public dans la jurisprudence française de 1789 à
1848 (Paris, Loviton, 1934), pp. 10–14.
28
“The legal conscience of the civilized world”
29
Another Random Document on
Scribd Without Any Related Topics
with active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or
expense to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or
a means of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original
“Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must
include the full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in
paragraph 1.E.1.
• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive
from the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”
• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.
1.F.
1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.
Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.
ebookgate.com