relativism
relativism
Objective Facts: True independent of what anyone believes, thinks, feels, etc.
Subjective Facts: Their truth depends on (at least one person’s) beliefs, thoughts,
feelings, etc.
1. Ethical Relativism: Did you think (6) belongs to the ‘subjective’ category? If so, you
may find the following moral theory plausible:
Ethical Relativism: An action is morally wrong (or right) for someone if and only
if that person’s culture believes it is wrong (or right).
According to the ethical relativist (sometimes called the ‘cultural relativist’), we just
DECIDE, as a society, which actions are morally wrong (and which are not). And once we
do, then those actions ARE morally wrong for everyone in that society. So, morality is a
subjective matter on this view, since moral truths depends upon what people THINK
about morality. On this view, morality is basically a matter of personal taste (or societal
taste, etc.).
Some disagree, arguing that moral truths are objective; i.e., morality does NOT depend
upon what people think. Morality is NOT a matter of taste. Rather, there are some things
that are just plain wrong (or right) REGARDLESS OF WHAT ANYONE THINKS.
[Note: There is a third view; Namely, that there is no such thing as morality at all! This
view is called ‘ethical nihilism’. I will say more about this below.]
1
For example, “Ice cream is good” is clearly a subjective truth, since it is only true FOR
ME because I THINK it is true. “The Earth orbits the Sun” on the other hand is an
objective truth, because it would be true REGARDLESS OF WHAT ANYONE THINKS.
If I say that “Ice cream is good” and you say that “Ice cream is bad”, we can both be
right. But, if I say that “The Earth is round” and you say that “The Earth is flat”, we cannot
both be right. One of us MUST be mistaken (and, in this example, you are mistaken).
Relativity: Morality is also relative on this view. For instance, if one society says
cannibalism is morally wrong, while another says it is morally permissible, then the fact
of whether or not cannibalism is morally wrong for some person will be a relative one—
namely, the answer will depend upon which society that person is a member of.
We will now ask the question: Does some action become right or wrong just because
one’s society SAYS it is right or wrong? Or rather, is it the case that there are some
moral standards that apply to ALL people in ALL societies, regardless of whether or not
those societies believe in those standards? i.e., are there any OBJECTIVE moral truths?
2. The Argument From Disagreement: Why believe that morality is relative? Relativists
often say that widespread moral disagreement supports this conclusion. They say:
Lots of people disagree about moral issues. There are heated debates and bitter
arguments between people, and wars between civilizations, over what the morally right
and wrong actions are. The relativist’s claim is that this disagreement is an indication
that there simply ARE NO OBJECTIVE FACTS OF THE MATTER about morality.
Now, the argument above is not valid. There is a missing premise. What premise might
we supply in order to make it valid? Answer: Something like this:
Objection: But, this argument is obviously unsound, since premise 2 is clearly false. To
illustrate, consider the following argument, which is clearly flawed:
2
1. Different people have different beliefs about the shape of the Earth (some think it
is spherical, while others believe it to be flat).
2. Whenever people disagree about something, there is no objective fact about the
matter.
3. Therefore, there is no objective fact about the shape of the Earth.
The mere fact that there is disagreement about certain moral issues does not prove that
there is no objective FACT of the matter, or that EVERYONE is right.
How much disagreement is there? So, premise 2 is false. But, premise 1 might be false as
well! At the very least, there may not be as much moral disagreement in the world as the
relativist claims. The relativist will often point to actions that other cultures practice
without hesitation or guilt, which seem horribly immoral to us, as proof of the claim that
there is clearly disagreement about the principles of morality. But, this is not so obvious.
For instance, consider one popular example that the relativist uses to prove their case:
Clearly, in our culture, we believe that infanticide is a moral atrocity. So, at first, there
seems to be a HUGE disagreement between us and the Eskimos regarding infanticide.
But, consider the predicament under which the Eskimos did this. If they did NOT do it,
their whole society would have died off. They did not kill infants FOR NO REASON.
Rather, they only did so when the survival of the whole population depended on it.
Thus, it seems that they were really operating under some moral principle such as, “It is
permissible to kill if doing so is required in order to save many lives.” But, does this
principle seem obviously false to you? Most of us would probably ACCEPT this claim. So,
perhaps there is not really moral disagreement after all. There are just different
CIRCUMSTANCES.
3. Four Undesirable Implications of Ethical Relativism: We have already seen that the
primary argument for relativism is flawed. Also, there may not be as much moral
disagreement as the relativist claims. In this section we will see that, even if ethical
relativism IS correct, then a number of incredibly undesirable outcomes follow:
3
(1) No condemning of other cultures: If morality were relative to one’s culture,
there would be no basis for claiming that the practice of any other culture is
morally wrong, no matter how atrocious their deeds seemed to us. For
instance, if there were a society that practiced cannibalism, there would be no
basis for us to condemn their actions. Of course, since OUR society believes
cannibalism is morally wrong, it IS morally wrong for us (according to
relativism). But, so long as the other society APPROVED of cannibalism, it
would NOT be morally wrong for THEM to kill and eat people. But, this
verdict seems mistaken. Shouldn’t we rather say that the people of that other
culture are MISTAKEN about morality, and that they are doing something
morally abhorrent which they MISTAKENLY believe to be morally acceptable?
(Or consider other practices like female genital mutiliation—i.e., what Rachels
called “excision”—and bride-burning and gendercide.1 Are we really prepared
to say, “While those things are wrong HERE in the U.S. because we disapprove
of them, there is nothing morally objectionable about them over THERE
because the people in those societies approve of such things”? Or, rather,
doesn’t it seem like such practices would be morally wrong for ANYONE to
engage in, and that those who approve of them are simply MISTAKEN?)
(2) No condemning of one’s own culture: If ethical relativism were true, one could
never criticize their OWN culture’s standards. Under relativism, it is impossible for
any society to be mistaken about the moral status of any action. Under relativism,
we decide morality by majority vote; we simply poll our citizens, and whatever the
majority says is permissible IS permissible. Whatever they say is wrong IS
wrong—for EVERYONE within that society. So, if the majority of our society says
abortion is permissible, then all of those individuals who think that it is morally
wrong are simply mistaken. In short, if relativism is true, there is no justification
for moral disagreement. But this seems false. Morality should not be decided by
majority vote. Furthermore, it seems like it IS possible for one’s own society to
have reached the wrong conclusion about some moral issue.
1
As of 2019, there are over 200 million women and girls in the world who have been subject to excision. (source)
To put that number in perspective, there are only about 168 million women/girls in the entire United States.
4
But, on relativism, there is no such standard; no fixed moral yardstick against
which to measure our changing moral beliefs. So, though our moral views DO
change over time, they never get BETTER on relativism. They only get DIFFERENT.
In 1800, the majority of our society APPROVED of slavery. So, according to
relativism, slavery was PERMISSIBLE in 1800. That is, slave-owners were NOT
DOING ANYTHING MORALLY WRONG by owning other human beings as
property. That fact alone is already repugnant. But now consider: Today, the
majority of our society does NOT approve of slavery. According to relativism,
then, slavery is MORALLY WRONG in the present day. Most people would like
to say that our moral views today regarding slavery are BETTER now than they
were 200 years ago. But, if relativism is true, we cannot make this claim. On
relativism, neither the present view nor the 1800 view regarding slavery is
morally better than the other. Since, on relativism, a culture is NEVER mistaken
about morality, we simply went from one correct belief about slavery in 1800
to a different, but also equally correct view about it today. Our current view is
not “better”—it is just different.
But that seems false. It seems to most of us that a society’s moral beliefs CAN
get better or worse over time—i.e., they can get closer or further from the real
truth of the matter about what is right and what is wrong.
(4) Absurd scenarios: If ethical relativism is true, then we can think of absurd
scenarios involving cultures where, if some members of that culture were to
perform a wrong action enough times, it would become a right action. For
instance: Consider a culture where 60% of the people think cannibalism is wrong,
while 40% of the people think it is NOT wrong. In that culture, cannibalism is
morally wrong, since (on the whole) the majority of the culture does not approve
of it. However, now imagine that the pro-cannibalization citizens come up with a
plan to change the moral status of cannibalism: They make plans to kill and eat
half of the anti-cannibal citizens so that, once enough of the anti-cannibalists are
gone, the citizens in favor of cannibalism would then be in the majority. In this
way, cannibalism would go from being morally WRONG to morally PERMISSIBLE,
since then (on the whole) the majority of that culture would now approve of it.
5
4. Conclusion: It appears that ethical relativism must be false. Morality is not subjective.
The moral status of actions like rape or murder are not merely a matter of taste. It is
simply not true that things are wrong ONLY because most of us presently disapprove of
them, or that they would BECOME permissible if our society suddenly started finding
these actions to be acceptable. No, it seems obvious that actions like rape or murder are
wrong not just because most of us find them distasteful—but rather because there is
some OBJECTIVE moral truth of the matter about the moral status of such actions.
In short, some things are just plain wrong, regardless of what anyone thinks.
So, for the rest of this class, we will be explorers. We are on a quest for the objectively
correct answers to a number of ethical questions. We will not decide any issue by
majority vote. Rather, we will attempt to decide issues by appealing to plausible
fundamental objective moral principles. For instance, here’s a plausible candidate:
It is morally wrong to cause great harm to another individual for little or no benefit.
It is plausible to think that the following moral truth would be true EVEN IF EVERYONE
ON EARTH THOUGHT IT WAS FALSE:
An action is morally acceptable if, on the whole, it benefits all those affected by it.
And, likewise, an action is morally unacceptable if, on the whole, it harms all those
affected by it.
Isn’t it plausible to think that this principle is one that applies to ALL people of ALL
cultures of ALL times, and is independent of what people think, believe, desire, etc.? This
seems universally and objectively true, regardless of what anyone thinks. If there has
ever been an individual, or a society, who thought that it was NOT wrong to cause great
harm for little benefit (for example, blowing up an entire city full of people to make
room for a new highway), they were simply mistaken.
But, this is something that the relativist must reject (for, if ENOUGH people in our
culture thought that this principle was false, it WOULD be!).
6
Ethical Nihilism
Ethical Nihilism: There is no such thing as morality; i.e., there is no right and
wrong, or good and bad.
This view is sometimes called “error theory.” By this, it is meant that, whenever we make
statements like, “He is a bad person,” “She did the right thing,” or “Stabbing babies for
fun is wrong,” we are simply mistaken. These claims are all false. There simply are no
such things as right, wrong, good, or bad. (Note that the argument from disagreement
is also used by nihilists, but to reach an even stronger conclusion.)
Against Nihilism: Note that the ethical nihilist must accept some conclusions that many
of us feel very strongly are not true. Things like:
But, think about this for a second. Is it really the case that there is nothing wrong with,
say, sawing a little kid in half? The fact that the child will experience intense pain and
suffering, or that you are taking away everything good that this child has—on nihilism
these do not count as reasons to NOT saw her in half. For there ARE no such things as
moral reasons against any action. According to nihilism, you are merely separating some
atoms from some other atoms, and this has no moral significance.
…Is this a bullet that any human being with any empathy at all could bite?
But, Don’t We Just THINK, e.g., Infanticide is Wrong Because of Evolution?: Perhaps our
strong intuitions about “morals” are merely a byproduct of biological evolution; e.g., the
belief that murder is wrong is merely a sentiment which has been biologically selected
for not because it is a perception of some “real, moral truth”, but because it is
advantageous for survival. For, any species that didn’t oppose murder would likely die
out quickly. (Another good example is the moral taboo of incest.)
Reply: First, many of our moral beliefs seem to go AGAINST survival of the fittest (e.g.,
rape is wrong, as is killing the genetically diseased or disabled). Second, objective moral
facts seem to be the best explanation for converging global moral consensus (see here).