Van Niekerk 1998 A Common Law For Southern Africa Roman Law or Indigenous African Law
Van Niekerk 1998 A Common Law For Southern Africa Roman Law or Indigenous African Law
GJ van Niekerk**
Associate Professor: Department ofJurisprudence
University of South Africa
INTRODUCTION
When one considers whether Roman law should be regarded as a source of
a southern African ius gentium or ius commune, the first important point to
be established, is what exactly is meant by 'Roman law'. At most universities,
so far, the emphasis has been on the substantive rules of Roman law, many of
which have no application in southern African today. This attitude to the
teaching of Roman law has placed it in the same dilemma in which indigenous
African law found itself for many years. 1 Today Roman law is under threat of
being relegated to the periphery of legal education. At some South African
universities, notably the University of South Africa, the introduction ofafour-
Reproduced by Sabinet Gateway under licence granted by the Publisher (dated 2009).
year LLB has only enhanced this possibility. Is it possible and, importantly, is
it desirable to save Roman law from this threat?
Domanske is of the opinion that it is important to retain Roman law in legal
education, not only because it underlies much of our private law; or because
it enables students to obtain an overview of the entire system of private law;
or because we have much to learn from the Romans' inherently pragmatic,
community-based approach to law; or because, from a lego-technical point of
view, it focuses on the skills oflega! analysis, legal distinction, legal definition
and legal dialectic3 and thus trains the legal mind; but primarily he thinks that
Roman law should be retained because it displays universal qualities which
make it useful to any sotiety at any time. Indeed, Domanski shows that it is
possible to shift the emphasis in Roman law teaching away from its substantive
itself able to deal with advancement and modernisation, and has shown its
ability to form the scientific framework within which non-spedalised legal
systems (the Germanic customary laws~ in Europe) could adapt. In other
words, it seems quite simple that Roman law should ideally be seen as, or be
promoted to, that very common law we are looking for in Southern Africa.
But, if this is so, the emphasis must indeed be shifted away from substantive
Roman law. History teaches that it is not the rules, but the underlying
principles, the scientific framework and the methodology of Roman law which
proved decisive in its subsequent reception. This reception occurred not only
in Western Europe, but also in Eastern European countries where a scientific
reception took place even though the rules of Roman law themselves were
never received. It is this framework and methodology and the underlying
principles of Roman law which form the core of the South African common
law. In fact, many of the principles or jural postulates of Roman law are
entrenched in the South African Constitution. They are the principles of
natural law, justice and equity.
These aspects of Roman law also form the substratum of the common law of
other Southern African countries. Mr Justice Schreiner once referred to South
Africa (and Namibia), Zimbabwe and the former High COmmission Territories
ubuntu. One may accept that the basic prindples or jural postulates of
western law and those of indigenous law are not the same, but are they also
necessarily incompatible? Is it possible to regard both Roman law and
indigenous law as sources of a common law for Southern Africa?
It should first be established what is meant by these so-called 'basic prindples'
or 'jural postulates'. One may start by saying that these prindples embrace the
fundamental purposes of law and constitute starting points for legal reason-
ing. 7 Jural postulates are the basic axioms which underlie law and are based
on societal values of what is desirable and what not. 8 They fonn an integral
part of the structure oflaw and a conflict between such underlying prindples
is often reflected in a political struggle, 9 as has been amply proved in
Southern Africa.
lOOU Plessis Die juridiese relevansie van cbristelike geregngbeid (1978) unpublished
un thesis University of Potchefstroom at 797 and 821-822.
I1In the spirit of western chauvinism, western jurisprudential ideas and modes of
thought are often regarded as universally applicable and unchanging. Scant
attention is usually paid to the principles underlying other systems of law and non-
western jurisprudential ideas are mostly relegated to the fields of sociology or
anthropology.
12Pound n 7 above at 112-113, 11&-118, and 133-134; see also Freeman n 7 above
at 528-531.
BOne should bear in mind that whilst Pound is of the opinion that law embodies the
consciousness of a community as a whole, he also views society as a homogeneous,
static and cohesive entity with 'shared values and traditions and a common
cognition of reality'.
I'Hoebe1 n 8 above at 13-17; Pound n 7 above at 133-134; see also Freeman n 7
above at 529Jf, Ogwurike The concept of law in English speaking Africa (1979) at
134. It is here that Pound's view of the function of law as the halancing of
conflicting and competing interests in a community is best illustrated. The
importance of public policy in internal conflict management in South Africa also
illustrates the role of jural postulates in the halancing of different interests.
15Seidman The jural postulates ofAfrican law (1970) at 16.
16Domanski n 4 ahove at 49.
17These jural postulates are all supported by the principles of justice embodied in the
concept of individual freedom and for this reason they are also referred to as
postulates of justice.
162 XXXI elLSA 1998
cannot prevail over the truth. The jural postulates which will now be
discussed are but illustrations of the differences between the values which
underlie western and indigenous law. This may assist one to detennine
whether Roman law could in fact serve as the exclusive source of a Southern
African common law.
Although order and justice do not always coincide and although a proper
balance between them should be maintained, they may, for purposes of a
comparison between western and indigenous jural postulates, be regarded as
an integrated whole. Likewise, fairness, reasonableness, generality, equality
and certainty may be regarded either as separate specific postulates,19 or as
postulates of justice and as part of this integrated system of values which forms
the starting point for legal reasoning in western law. Wille20 adds to these
postulates of justice that law should be in accordance with public opinion, a
postulate which emphasises the important role of public policy in legal
development and reform.
Over the years various theories of the concept of justice have been developed.
Reproduced by Sabinet Gateway under licence granted by the Publisher (dated 2009).
The primacy of the individual and the concept of equality have played an
increasingly important role in most of these theories and it is in this sense that
the dichotomy between western and indigenous jural postulates reveals itself
most clearly. 21
Aristotle's concept of justice is often used as a framework for examining
different conceptions of justice. 22 He emphasised the connection between
justice and equality and distinguished between distributive and corrective
18Hahlo & Kahn The South African legal system and its background (1973) 25 26; see
also Van der Westhuizen 'Opmerkings in verband met regsnonne, legitimiteit en
samelewing' (unpublished paper read at a ColloqUium Iuridicum on 'Regsfilosofie
en Samelewing' held at the University of the Orange Free State September (1987»
at 5 on the close relatiOnship between justice and the maintenance of order and
stability. It seems that Du Plessis n 10 above also regards justice as an important
diffuse postulate. He makes the following statement (at 827): 'Hierdie geregtigheids-
vanne is tewens Die grondnorme an sich nie, maar leidingsfunksies (of rigtende
prinsipes) vir die handelinge van staatsowerheid en -burgers in hulle konkrete doen
van geregtigheid (wedersyds teenoor mekaar) langs die weg van die instellings
(waaronder inter alia grondnorme).'
19Or, according to Hahlo & Kahn n 18 above at 31-35, as criteria with which law
must comply in order to be just; see also Hutchinson et al n 9 above at 13-16.
~utchinson et al n 9 above at 15-16.
211t should be borne in mind that although the primacy of the individual and
absolute individual freedom dominate modem liberal jurispnldence, nea-Marxist
and critical-Iegal-studies theorists have criticised the mainstream liberal theories: see
Freeman n 7 above at 857-861 and 935-941.
22Freeman n 7 above at 456-357.
A common law for Southern Africa 163
ous jural postulates, the theory of justice of the modem western liberal
philosopher, John Rawls, may serve as an example.
In his assessment of the role of justice in a sodety, Rawls27 draws a distinc-
tion between the concept of justice and conceptions of justice. The concept
of justice is seen as an objective phenomenon which entails the maintenance
of a balance between competing claims. This concept encompasses a set of
2lVan der Westhuizen n 18 above at 5; Van der Vyver 'Reg(ter) en geregtigheid' 1975
DejuTe at 8-22 and 8-11.
24See Gennjurisprudence and legal theory textbook (1991) at 194-195, Clark The
entetprise of law (1987) at 61-64.
25See Freeman n 7 above at 379-381.
lDyet, it should be remembered that equality and liberty are both separately
entrenched in the constitution and that this may lead to practical tension and
conflict between the two concepts. liberal equality entails the dominance of
freedom, whilst socialist eqUality allows for fewer limitations of equality by
individual freedom. This tension comes to the fore especially in the law of contract.
It is solved by either limiting individual freedom in the interest of material equality
(thus obtaining socialist equality), or by limiting material eqUality for the sake of
liberty (thus obtaining liberal equality). See generally the discussion by Hawthorne
'The principle of equality in the law of contract' 1995 THRHR 157-176 on the
tension between equality and freedom of contract.
27See generally Rawls A theory ofjustice (1992) at 3-22.
164 XXXJ CILSA 1998
prindples 28 which assign rights and duties and which define the appropriate
division of sodal advantages and distribution of burdens necessary for sodal
cooperation. By contrast, conceptions of justice are subjective interpretations
of the role of the prindples of justice in a particular situation.
Rawls points out that for a theory of justice to be useful, it must be general,
universally applicable, publicly known, able to impose an ordering on
competing claims, and must have finality.29 Proceeding from the premise that
his is a universally applicable theory, indigenous laws would have to be
assessed within the framework of justice as an objective set of prindples
which govern the asSignment of rights and duties and regulate the distribution
of sodal and economic disadvantages. It may indeed even appear that the
ideals of justice as we understand them in a western sense, are to an extent
realised in indigenous law. But in Rawls's theory, the individual is, in typically
western liberal fashion, awarded a central role and individual freedom takes
priority over the greater good shared by the community. 30
Rawls 31 makes provision for the possibility that individuals in the same
community may have different conceptions of justice: they may have different
views on the content of the prindples which should govern their assodation
with each other. Yet, he is of the opinion that individuals or groups of
individuals who have different conceptions of justice, should still agree on the
basic need for a set ofprindples to assign basic rights and duties and should
agree that 'institutions are just when no arbitrary distinctions are made
between persons in the assigning of basic rights and duties and when the rules
Reproduced by Sabinet Gateway under licence granted by the Publisher (dated 2009).
28According to Rawls the principles of justice are derived from a hypothetical ideal
original position of equality in which free and rational people agree on the
principles which should organise society. It is their reason which induces
individualistic, egocentric individuals to realise the necessity of social control to
restrain excessive greed and maintain order in a society. Agreement is the rational
way to establish such social control. The principles are: First, each person is to have
an equal right to the most extensive basic liberty compatible with a similar liberty
of others. Second, social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they
are both (a) reasonably expected to be to evetyane's advantage, and (b) attached to
positiOns and offices open to all. The basic liberties of the first prinCiple are
political liberty (to vote and to be eligible for public office), freedom of speech and
assembly, liberty of conscience and thought, freedom of the person and the right
to personal property and freedom from arbitrary arrest in accordance with the rule
of law. These liberties are fundamental rights which all people have. Once equal
liberty is attained, equal opportunities must be given to persons of similar skills,
ability and motivation. Also contained in the second principle of justice is the
difference principle which requires that inequalities must be arranged to the
greatest benefit of the least advantaged. See generally Rawls n 27 above at 60-67,
HeynsA critical study ofthe difference principle inJobn Rawls's ~ theory ofjustice ,
unpublished MA dissertation, University of Pretoria (1985) at 29-34, Freeman n 7
above at 356-367.
~wls n 27 above at 130-136; Genn n 24 above at 202.
30Uberal justice asserts the primacy of the individual and his inalienable human rights
and stresses mechanisms to check and balance state rule.
llRawls n 27 above at 5-6.
l2Rawls n 27 above at 5.
A common law for Southern Africa 165
individuals may differ on the basic concept of justice only to the extent to
which their notions of 'arbitrary distinctions and proper balance' may differ.
Indigenous laws are underscored by wholly different jural postulates. Starting
points for indigenous legal reasoning are different and this makes the
conceptions oflaw and justice in an indigenous context very different from the
western conceptions. The individual takes primacy over the common good
and equality is assigned a central role, not only in the general conceptions of
justice put forward by Rawls, but also in the concept of justice. 33 TIlls is not
consonant with the most important diffuse postulate of indigenous law,
namely harmony of the collectivity in which the collective good takes primacy
over individual claims.34 Judged then by western standards of justice, many
indigenous laws will be found to be unjust and should consequently be
reformed or abolished. By the same token, if judged within the framework of
indigenous jural postulates, western law may be regarded as falling short of
the standards of justice of indigenous jurisprudence.
Thus, in a society where there is legal pluralism it is in the practical administra-
tion of justice that the conflict between western and indigenous value systems,
and accordingly between jural postulates, is most apparent. 35 Aguda36
makes the following remark in an assessment of the judidary in a developing
country:
Here the judiciary has a task, and a very difficult one, of re-thinking and adapting
the concept of justice and fair hearing to which they have become accustomed
during their learning under the common law so that the concept will be
acceptable to the generality of the people they are called upon to serve.
Reproduced by Sabinet Gateway under licence granted by the Publisher (dated 2009).
33Rawls n 27 above at 504-512; see also Van der Westhuizen n 23 above at 5, Van der
Vyver n 23 above at 8-12, Du Plessis n 10 above at 820ff.
l4But the collectivity cannot be seen as an entity separate from its component
members. Therefore, it is also not quite correct to speak of the absolute primacy of
the collectivity over the individual good. Indeed, indigenous law has other
mechanisms to protect the dignity of the individual.
3s-rbe existence of unofficial legal institutions provides a fine example of the
dichotomy that prevails in the western and indigenous values regarding procedural
justice. The functioning of these institutions should not merely be ascribed to
political differences and the prevalence of unjust and racial legislation, but also to
the different perceptions of the concept of justice. In contrast, the application of
unofficial indigenous law by the official chiefs courts may serve as an illustration
of the difference in perceptions of substantive justice prevailing in actual legal
norms. Marriage, and other family relations, the law relating to land and criminal
law are but a few examples of where this conflict of value systems comes to the fore.
36Aguda 'The judiciary in a developing country' in Marasinghe & Conklin (eds) Third
world perspectives in jurisprudence (1984) at 162.
166 XXXI CILSA 1998
African countries today,37 it still forms part of the legislation of South Africa
and of other countries belonging to the South African Law Assodation. In fact,
the repugnancy clause has been entrenched in the South African Constitution.
What are the most important prindples which direct legal reasoning in
indigenous law? Although many of the rules of the traditional indigenous
African law have changed, or no longer exist, there are basic prindples which
still constitute the fundamental axioms of indigenous law. Although there are
also specific postulates which underlie specific indigenous legal rules, I will
briefly explain the most important general postulates, namely the harmony of
the collectivity; the prindple that superhuman38 forces are superior to man;
and the identity postulate. 39
The first postulate, namely the harmony of the collectivity, is evidenced in the
fact that the indigenous African approach to law is permeated by the idea that
the equilibrium in the community should be maintained.
The second postulate explains the pre-eminence of religion and ritual in
African law and culture. Law is aimed at the harmonious co-existence with the
superhuman and the visible world is interpreted in terms of superhuman
forces. The perception of a higher law which originates in the superhuman
and to which all laws must conform, puts the role of the superhuman in
indigenous legal orders into perspective and attributes to Africa a natural law-
like philosophy. Ayittey40 writes:
Endowed with lethal powers, all the supernatural and cosmic forces exhibit
Reproduced by Sabinet Gateway under licence granted by the Publisher (dated 2009).
The third postulate, the identity postulate, explains the fact that indigenous
law is able to accommodate change whilst retaining its fundamental premise,
37See Bennett A sourcebook ojAfrican customary law Jor Southern Africa (1991) at
130-13l.
38Ancestra1 spirits, witches, nature spirits, the supreme being, and the like all form
part of the cosmology of indigenous people. But these beings are regarded as part
of their natural world and it is therefore incorrect to refer to them as supernatural.
There is a direct and close link between these beings and living humans, usually
through the ancestors. Mbiti African religiOns and philosophy (1975) at 83 points
out that the ancestors still speak the language of the living with whom they have
been recently (up to five generations of deceased ancestors according to Mbiti).
However, they are bilingual and also speak the language of the superhuman. These
forces are thus interpreted in human terms and called superhuman rather than
supernatural. This is also in line with the primacy of human beings in indigenous
culture and the solidarity of living beings and the superhuman. And it is in contrast
to the sharp distinction between the natural and the supernatural in western
thinking. In western thought the supernatural is mostly relegated to the realm of
superstition: see Kaunda A humanist in Africa (1966) at 29.
39For a detailed discussion, see Van Niekerk The interaction oj indigenous law and
western law in South Africa: a historical and comparative perspective unpublished
doctoral thesis, University of South Africa (1995) at 194ff
40Ayittey Indigenous African institutions (1991) at 11.
A common law for Southern Africa 167
Ubuntu
Is it at all possible for Roman law to override ubuntu? The jural postulates
which underlie indigenous African law are founded in the African tradition.
This tradition transcends extra-African influences and encapsulates the African
spirit of ubuntu. It is this ethos of ubuntu which gives indigenous law a
different dimension and which distinguishes it from mere primitive law, from
mere religiOUS law or mere customary law or from African law in its present-
day meaning. Ubuntu is a fundamental value; an inherent belief system which
underscores indigenous cultures and indigenous legal orders in Africa. The
concept of ubuntu has been subject to many interpretations by different
people at different times. This Nguni word~ may be translated as 'humane-
ness' or the 'link that binds men together'. It emphasises the connection
between the individual and the community.43 The term has also been
described as 'the art of being a human being', a description which focuses on
tolerance, compassion and forgiveness in relation to other human beings. 44
Reproduced by Sabinet Gateway under licence granted by the Publisher (dated 2009).
It has been likened to the English 'person-hood', an abstract term which aims
at community building and which manifests itself through concrete acts in
different situations. 45
Ubuntu has often been presented as African humanism46 and it is perhaps
41Kaunda n 38 above at 29-30; see also Fabian 'Religion and change' in Paden & Soja
(eels) The African experience Vol I (1970) at 384 on the accommodating nature of
indigenous culture as illustrated in its ready acceptance of christianity whilst
retaining traditional beliefs.
421n Sotho languages the tenn is botho.
43See also Mbigi & Maree Ubuntu. The spirit ofAfrican transformation management
(1995) at 109jJ.
44Dhlomo 'Strategic advantages that can be derived from ubuntu' in Secretariat of the
EconomiC Community of Southern Africa Incorporation of ubuntu into a uniquely
Soutb African approacb to management (one-<i2Y seminar held in Midrand 30
October 1991 (hereafter 'Ubuntu in management'). He refers to ubuntu (for which
all indigenous African languages have a tenn) as a purely African philosophy of life.
See also Mbigi & Maree n 43 above at 12.
4SJ'rinco & Valente 'Ubuntu at work situated in an international environment' in
'Ubuntu in management' n 44 above at 44-47; Mbigi 'A new dimension for business'
1995 Enterprise 57.
460mi & Anyanwu African philosophy. An introduction to the main philosophical
trends in contemporary Africa (1981) at 139 describe African humanism as 'virtues
of the heart'. These virtues are self-control and humility; faithfulness and friendship;
and goodness and kindness. These virtues are aimed at maintaining the equilibrium
in the group. Both horizontal social solidarity (between the living. and between the
168 XXXI eILSA 1998
easier to explain the concept with reference to that familiar western concept.
Humanism puts the human being at the centre of all things. It is a belief in the
centrality, the sacredness, the primacy of human beings in all spheres of life.
It emphasises the values of human dignity, safety, welfare, health, development
and that these should take priority over economic, financial and political
considerations. 47
But ubuntu can be understood only within the context of the world view of
indigenous people. 48 They regard the world as an integrated whole of nature,
life on earth and the after-life. People on earth should live in harmony with
each other, with nature, and with the gods and the ancestors. 49 To maintain
this harmonious state of affairs, the interests of the individual, as a component
of the collectivity, should be looked after. The individual's dignity, health and
sodal welfare should be protected. But her welfare is only one side of the
coin, the other side being the welfare of the community. 50 And in that lies the
essence of ubuntu: the welfare of the individual is inextricably linked to the
welfare of the collectivity and that, in turn, is inextricably linked to an
harmonious relationship with the ancestors and with nature. Although man is
at the centre of things, man can be defined only in relation to other men. And
the community can likewise be defined only with reference to its individual
members:
The relationship between "man" and "society" was never thought of in
hierarchal terms. Uubuntuism teaches that "I am because they are; and they
are because I am". The "community" is the "I" writ large - and the "I" is the
community individualised. And ... this tie-up between the "I" and the
Reproduced by Sabinet Gateway under licence granted by the Publisher (dated 2009).
Kaunda and others52 trace the historical roots of the concept of ubuntu back
to small-scale societies in Africa.
living, the deceased ancestors and those not yet born) and vertical solidarity
(between the living and the creator god) must be maintained.
'Vllakui 'The roots of ubuntu' in 'Ubuntu in management' n 44 above at 7.
48Hammond-Tooke Rituals and medicines. Indigenous healing in South Africa (1989)
at 33 explains that world view 'is essentially a (cognitive) attempt to make sense of
the world, and impose meaning on it'. Besides intellectual statements to explain the
world and life, world view comprises concepts and beliefs, with a strong emotional
content, about the sense of being and as such it comprises subjective value systems.
See also Ntshangase Ubuntu-botho, education, nationalism and democracy,
unpublished M Phil thesis, University of the Western Cape (1994) 24-32.
4This is comparable to the Buddhist tradition which has a profound influence on the
Japanese world view. It recognises 'the temporal, passing, impermanent and
changing nature of the ego, and by so doing finds the true self through identifica-
tion with universal oneness': see Smith 'Ajase and Oedipus: ideas of the self in
Japanese and western legal consciousness' 1986 University ofBritish Columbia Law
Review 341-377 at 355.
solt seems that English 'Ubuntu. The quest for an indigenous jurisprudence' in 1996
South African Journal on Human Rights 645 does not fully grasp the essence of
ubuntu when she writes: 'To make any sense of the idea, you have to pick and
choose between conflicting interpretations. Either it means individual human
dignity. Or it means conformity to basic norms and collective responsibility.'
51Trinco & Valente n 45 above at 45.
52Kaunda n 38 above at 22-28; Vllakui n 47 above at 9, DhIomo 'Strategic advantages
that can be derived from ubuntu' in 'Ubuntu in management' n 44 above at 51.
A common law for Southern Africa 169
57This is sometimes described as the bias for morals and emotions in indigenous
decision making. In practice it is, eg, illustrated by the reintegration of criminals
into the community and by the reconciliation of the parties to a dispute.
SBsmith n 49 above at 346.
5~rinco & Valente n 45 above at 45.
SJsmith n 49 above at 346 347; Yasaki 'Issues in African socialism' in Otite (ed)
Themes in African social and political thought (1978) at 185.
61Smith n 49 above at 347.
&smith n 49 above at 347, and see generally at 347-352.
A common law for Southern Africa 171
treason. 63
Because of the weak position of 'we', as opposed to the strong position of T
in western cultures. western legal orders are characterised by analysis.
discrimination, differentiation, individualism, intellectualism, objeCtivism,
indUCtive reasoning, sdentific thought, generalisation, conceptualism,
legalism, organisation, self-assertion, and impersonality. By contrast,
indigenous Japanese and indigenous African legal orders, because of a well
developed we-consdousness, are characterised as synthetic, totalising,
integrative,non-discriminative,non-systematic, dogmatic, intuitive, non-discur-
sive, subjeCtive, communalistic and spiritually individualistic. 64
The difference between ubuntu and amae seems to be that the I-conscious-
ness in Japanese law is weak and the we-consdousness is strong, whilst
ubuntu is founded upon a strong we-consdousness as developed through a
strong I-consciousness. Ubuntu is more in line with the ideal position in
which the I-consdousness and we-consdousness develop in hannony. 'I' and
'we' are not regarded as conflicting opposites between which a balance
should be maintained. 'There can be no 'I' without a 'we', nor conversely, a
'we' without a set of Ts'. 6,
Conclusion
In mainstream liberal jurisprudence, the proteCtion of the individual has
become a reasoned process which is sadly devoid of human feeling, emotion
and compassion. Because individual rights are so rigidly conceptualised, the
Reproduced by Sabinet Gateway under licence granted by the Publisher (dated 2009).
~ee MacIntyre 'Individual and social morality in Japan and the United States: rival
conceptions of the self 1990 Philosophy East and West 489-497 at 495.
69Smith. n 49 above at 352, and see also at 356-365.
A common law for Southern Africa 173
Southern African countries revolve. These values and the African values
founded in the spirit of ubuntu, are in many respects different, but they are
not irreconcilable. The fact that there are differences in these systems oflaw
does not mean that Roman law should be the exclusive source of the Southern
African ius commune or that ubuntu should be denied for the sake of Roman
law. Western jurisprudence may have a lot to learn from African thought. Both
Roman law and indigenous African law have much to contribute to a common
law for Southern Africa. Just as the European ius commune drew on Roman
law, canon law and the customary Germanic laws of the time, so should our
African ius commune be based on both Roman law and African law. All that
remains is to find open minds to accommodate the ideals of ubuntu in the
same way in which the postulates of justice are accommodated and thus to
create a just and acceptable legal order that suits the unique needs of this part
of Africa.
Reproduced by Sabinet Gateway under licence granted by the Publisher (dated 2009).