Mental Representations a Dual Coding Approach(Paivio, 1990)
Mental Representations a Dual Coding Approach(Paivio, 1990)
ALLAN PAIVIO
Professor of Psychology
University of Western Ontario
10987654321
Printed in the United States of America
To Kathleen
This page intentionally left blank
Preface
erences and the index. Elizabeth Henderson was responsible for typing the
entire text using a computerized system that made revisions and publication
easier than would otherwise have been the case. The copy editing was done
skillfully by Marie Milton and Joan Bossert of Oxford University Press. To
all, my warmest thanks.
This book would not have been possible without the years of research
support that I have received from the Natural Sciences and Engineering
Research Council of Canada (grant A0087). The final stages of my work on
the book were also aided by a Research Professorship and an accompanying
research stipend awarded to me by the Social Science Faculty of the Uni-
versity of Western Ontario.
References 277
Author Index 307
Subject Index 315
This page intentionally left blank
Mental Representations
This page intentionally left blank
1
Meta-theoretical Issues
and Perspectives
This book is about the form and functions of individual knowledge. How
do we represent information mentally and how do we use that information
to interact with the world in adaptive ways? The problem is old and persis-
tent. Our distant ancestors must have wondered about it long before they
knew how to represent information on the walls of caves or on wax tablets;
and we still wonder, though we know how to represent information in com-
puters and use it with lightning speed.
The problem persists because it is extraordinarily difficult, perhaps the
most difficult one in all of science. It is essentially the question of the nature
of knowledge and of thought, and all that these imply in terms of observable
behavior, brain activity, developmental origins, environmental effects, and
so on. Because it is so complex, we lack agreement on how to approach the
problem theoretically, and even empirically. Of course, controversy is a nor-
mal part of science, so it is not surprising that it accompanies the study of
mental representations. What is unusual is its current intensity and the fact
that it is polarized around an old philosophical issue that seemed to have
been largely resolved in the history of science, namely, empiricism versus
rationalism as ways of arriving at a scientific understanding of natural phe-
nomena. The revival has been sparked especially by a resurgence of logical
rationalism, which warrants more than a footnote here because it is closely
tied to a new discipline, called cognitive science, which takes the problem
of mental representations as its main domain. But empiricists are also con-
cerned with internal representations as natural phenomena, so we have a
meta-scientific dilemma that needs to be resolved even as we try to under-
stand the phenomena themselves.
I address those general issues here from the perspective of an empiricist
philosophy of science, that is, an empiricist approach to theories and theory
construction. The stand is reflected in an empiricist approach to the study
of mental representations. Or, more correctly stated, the general philosoph-
ical stance is itself a consequence of the empirical approach to mental phe-
nomena, including philosophical beliefs. The approach is empirical in the
sense that inferences about mental processes are based on observable behav-
ior. It is appropriate, therefore, to refer to it as objective mentalism or behav-
ioral mentalism (Paivio, 1975c). The mentalistic or cognitive emphasis dis-
3
4 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
initions and "sticking close to the experimental data." The choice was moti-
vated by a general "wait and see strategy" according to which one
"postpones certain crucial commitments (such as entailed by operational
definitions) with the intention of avoiding the most costly potential dead
ends" (p. 429).
The strategy described by Pylyshyn is reasonable up to a point and all
theorists follow it in that they suspend definitive judgments about the cor-
rectness (predictive value, etc.) of a theory until sufficient data have been
accumulated, or they will wait and see before rejecting a theory on the basis
of isolated facts that appear to be inconsistent with the theory. A full-blown,
top-down, wait-and-see strategy is risky, however, for it could lead to the
most costly dead end of all, where the whole structure built from the top
down eventually collapses for want of empirical support.
The rationalist approach has been justified in other ways in contemporary
cognitive science, and subsequent chapters will touch on those aspects that
are relevant to specific empirical and theoretical questions. The main point
to be noted here is that the other arguments are all secondary to and moti-
vated by the commitment to a computational approach to psychological
issues, which entails a formal rationalistic attitude because the computer
can only operate according to formal rules. We turn now to the implications
of that point.
One way to bypass the difficulties associated with the distinction was to
avoid the use of nonobservable theoretical concepts altogether, as the radi-
cal behaviorists have tried to do—rather unsuccessfully, as we shall see
later. The other way is to accept the conceptual-equivalence position, as
some cognitive scientists are beginning to do.
My perspective on the issue is pragmatic and psychological. The basic
assumption is that the observational-theoretical distinction becomes psy-
chologically real when interpreted in terms of the correlated difference
between concrete and abstract terms (Clark & Paivio, 1989). The for-
mer are terms like horse and wagon, with direct, observable referents
whereas the latter are terms like truth and beauty that have no direct refer-
ents although they can be illustrated by pointing to examples. The relevant
point is that concrete and abstract terms differ psychologically in terms of
such criteria as memorability, image arousal, and ease of communication.
Thus, at some point in theory construction, we cannot be indifferent to the
distinction between concrete observational terms and abstract theoretical
ones because they entail behavioral differences relevant to the practitioner
of science. Of course, observational and theoretical terms cannot always be
distinguished because theories can include the former, but it is important to
recognize when they can and should be distinguished because it will help us
avoid the pitfalls of reification that have plagued mentalistic psychology
throughout its history. Chapter 3 elaborates on this point with respect to
some recent approaches to the study of cognitive representations.
tion, perhaps by virtue of its association with the generic term dog and con-
textual conditions that make that association salient (likely to be activated).
Under other conditions, a dog image may "stand for" a particular dog. The
image in either case can be said to be "interpreted" (cf. Pylyshyn, 1973) by
virtue of the particular verbal associations that it evokes in particular cir-
cumstances, or by the verbal and other contextual cues that generate the
imagery in the first place. I return to such possibilities in more detail in
chapter 4, where I show how dual coding theory copes with issues associated
with the terminal meta-postulate.
This chapter and the next review the concept of representation from a psy-
chological perspective. We begin here with a discussion of defining charac-
teristics and controversial issues associated with the concept, followed by a
summary of the various forms that it has taken in the history of psychology.
This conceptual analysis provides the background for an evaluation in the
next chapter of three general attitudes and approaches to cognitive repre-
sentations among contemporary researchers. We shall see that the meta-the-
oretical issues discussed in chapter 1 also become relevant to the analysis.
16
The Concept of Representation 17
The distinctions have been the subject of much discussion and disagree-
ment (e.g., Palmer, 1978; Shepard, 1978; Sloman, 1971) although a consen-
sus seems to be developing around the idea that the fundamental distin-
guishing dimension is the degree of arbitrariness of the mapping relation
between the form of the representation and the form of the represented
world. Thus, the terms picture-like, analogue, iconic, and isomorphic all
imply that such representations map onto represented objects or events in
a nonarbitrary way. In the case of language-like representations, on the other
hand, the relation is completely arbitrary. This arbitrariness is so funda-
mental that it was explicitly recognized by Hockett (1963) as one of the
design features of human languages. At a more general level, Palmer (1978)
expressed the distinction as a contrast between intrinsic and extrinsic rep-
resentations. The representing relation in the former has the same "inherent
constraints" as the relation that it represents (e.g., differences in object
height might be represented by differences in size). The structure of a rep-
resentational relation in the extrinsic case, however, is totally arbitrary
whereas that of its represented relation is not. Referring specifically to cog-
nitive representations, Palmer suggested that the analogue-propositional
distinction makes sense if it is interpreted in terms of the intrinsic-extrinsic
(nonarbitrary-arbitrary) representational contrast. Johnson-Laird (1983, p.
156) relies similarly on degree of representational arbitrariness to distin-
guish between mental (analogue) models and propositional representations.
Representations can also be described as varying in concreteness-abstract-
ness, a dimension that correlates with the distinction between picture-like
and language-like symbols. Thus, at one extreme we have highly concrete,
iconic, modality-specific representations of objects and events. A three-
dimensional colored motion picture with a sound track could be indistin-
guishable perceptually from real world events. At the other extreme we have
completely abstract, amodal (or at least not modality-dependent) represen-
tations that are only arbitrarily related to real world objects and events.
Human language is a clear case, but artificial languages such as those used
by computers are, if anything, even more abstract.
The correlation is imperfect, however, because picture-like and language-
like representations can both vary in abstractness in a structural or func-
tional sense. For example, drawings of objects are structurally more abstract
than photographs because they have fewer details. Caricatures are even
more abstract and their symbolic function can be highly arbitrary and gov-
erned by convention. For example, structurally abstract silhouettes of a man
or woman serve to indicate toilets, curves on road signs represent curves on
a road, and so on, but they could be used equally well to represent any num-
ber of other situations. Such symbols have some degree of structural icon-
icity but they are functionally abstract and rather arbitrary in their relation
to the represented world. Language-like representations also vary in their
referential abstractness from concrete nouns at one extreme to abstract
terms that lack specific objective correlates at the other.
18 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
memory and other tasks. It has been shown, for example, that imaging the
referents of a pair of concrete nouns in some kind of interactive relation
facilitates associative memory for the pair. Through such findings, we have
come to know something about the functional properties of imagery. Struc-
ture is also implied by the idea that an interactive relation between the imag-
ined element is important to recall, but we only know it through the
observed functional relations. The structure of imagery has not been directly
revealed by such research nor has it led to a theory of such structure.
In contrast, others have explicitly set out to study the structure of mental
images using different procedures. Shepard and his colleagues (e.g., Shepard,
1978) have done the most elegant research on the problem using mental
rotation and other tasks. The rationale is that such tasks permit one to infer
that mental images share a high degree of isomorphism with perceptual
structures—for example, that an imaged letter R looks like the perceived
letter, and that it can be rotated mentally as a holistic entity. It can be
argued, even in this case, however, that all we have gained is functional
knowledge. That is, we know that experimental procedures designed to
arouse imagery permit one to answer the questions in the mental rotation
task (e.g., to say whether a rotated letter R is correctly oriented or a mirror-
image reversal) with a speed that is systematically related to the degree of
rotation. The structural inference is no more direct or compelling than it is
in the case of superior associative learning when subjects are asked to con-
struct interactive as compared to structurally separate images to word pairs.
From the entire set of operational procedures and resulting behaviors, we
can make inferences either about function or structure, or both, depending
on the precise manipulations involved and on our theoretical goal.
The pragmatic position to be taken here is that it is theoretically useful to
distinguish between structure and function (or representation and process)
to the extent that it helps explain facts associated with such phenomena as
imagery and generates new research that might add to the understanding. In
brief, the theoretical constructs are useful fictions. The specific consequences
of that belief are spelled out in subsequent chapters, but a concrete example
will provide a hint of the direction to be followed.
Consider once again the task of counting the corners of an imaged letter
E. The instruction to image the letter can be followed by any number of
further instructions and questions: Rotate the letter mentally, reverse it to
its mirror-image position, count the corners in any of these representations
clockwise or counterclockwise or in a random order, and so on. It is useful
and parsimonious to assume that we have one structural representation
over which we can operate in many different ways. At the same time, we
must be willing to entertain the procedural counterargument that the differ-
ent instructions simply activate different processes or procedures, provided
that the two interpretations can be empirically distinguished so that we may
determine which one accounts for the broader range of relevant data.
22 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
REPRESENTATIONAL CONCEPTS
(e.g., memory trace, features, prototype, schema, and logogen). In any case,
the most relevant attributes and their implications will be identified.
Mental image
Imagery may be the oldest and is certainly the most persistent of all specific
representational concepts. It has been the subject of discussion and study by
philosophers and psychologists in Western culture from the time of Plato
and Aristotle to the present. Its history has been marked by repeated con-
troversy, first during the Protestant Reformation (see Paivio, 1971, chap. 5;
Yates, 1966), then the behaviorist period in America, and, as already noted
in chapter 1, contemporary cognitive psychology. Too compelling experi-
entially to be denied or ignored, it has ranged in its explanatory status from
that of a representational medium attributed with magical powers in mem-
ory and thought, to an epiphenomenon without functional significance. The
swings occurred during each of the controversies, during which an imagery
period was followed by a theoretical reaction associated with the rise of
another representational concept, usually language-like in its form (inner
speech, verbal mediator, proposition).
Why this conceptual persistence coupled with controversy? The simple
answer to the first part is that imagery refers to an important psychological
phenomenon of universal scope. Phenomenologically, it is experienced by
people in all cultures in dreams as well as waking imagery. Its linkage with
memory, thought, and language is compelling because people often image
during those activities. It is natural, therefore, that early philosophers and
psychologists would assign a causal role to imagery. However, such a view
could not escape criticism because experienced images seem too specific in
form to "stand for" abstract ideas and, as the Wiirzburg imageless-thought
experiments demonstrated, they do not always accompany thinking. These
and other objections were countered in various ways accompanied by the
general conceptual stretching we have already noted. The major shift was
from the original picture metaphor to a more psychological metaphor in
which imagery was viewed as essentially equivalent to or at least similar to
perceptual activity. Processing assumptions are necessary in both interpre-
tations. Thus, the classical picture metaphor was accompanied by another
metaphor, the Shakespearean mind's eye, so that we have the familiar idea
of mental pictures that can be viewed by an inner eye in the same way as
real pictures or scenes are viewed by the real eye. The subsequent perceptual
metaphor was more of a processing interpretation in that imagery was
equated with the conditioned activity of sensory and perceptual response
systems rather than with mental pictures. Curiously, the swing of the con-
ceptual pendulum has gone back to the picture-plus-inner eye metaphor,
especially in the case of Kosslyn's (1980) theory, where it appears in the
guise of a television set that permits an image to be generated on a screen
and processed further by scanning, zooming, rotating, and other mecha-
24 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
nisms, all under the control of a computer program. This sophisticated con-
temporary metaphor was itself a reaction to criticisms by other theorists
who sought to replace the picture metaphor entirely by a propositional-com-
putational metaphor. Kosslyn's solution essentially was to mix metaphors.
I return to a further discussion of the implications of that approach in a later
section, and a psychological alternative will be spelled out in the next
chapter.
Memory trace
The mental image overlaps historically with the concept of the memory
trace. In fact, the two concepts were once treated essentially as synonyms in
the context of the metaphorical view that memories are images and images
are like the impressions left by a signet ring on a wax tablet. The term mem-
ory trace is now used in a general theoretical sense to refer to any kind of
psychological record or representation of past episodic experience. More-
over, the concept has undergone considerable stretching in that the trace is
commonly viewed as having various components or attributes that corre-
spond to spatial, temporal, associative, and other properties of the remem-
bered event (e.g., Bower, 1967; Eich, 1982; Murdock, 1982; Underwood,
1969; Wickens, 1970). Finally, the hope persists that one day it might
become an observational term identified with particular brain processes. If
that happens, the concept will have shifted its metaphorical status com-
pletely from recording artifacts (wax tablets, etc.) to a physiological base.
What will persist, however, is its fundamental status as a psychological rep-
resentational concept to be defined and studied by behavioral procedure, as
exemplified here in chapter 8.
Nonverbal mediators
The nonverbal mediator is a neobehavioristic concept that refers to pro-
cesses that intervene between observable stimulus and response, and was
introduced to account for S-R relations that seemed inexplicable in direct
S-R terms alone. Behaviorists have generally described this mediating pro-
cess in terms of covert stimulus-response chains that have exactly the same
functional properties as overt S-R sequences. Osgood (1953) proposed a
more complex theoretical construct with representational as well as media-
tional functions. This representational mediation process presumably con-
sists of fractional response components that have been "detached" from
overt responses and retain stimulus properties. Bundles of such fractional
rm-sm components become conditioned to words or other stimuli and con-
stitute their meaning. Analytically, therefore, Osgood's representational
concept refers to processes that are psychologically real, highly abstract
(detached from overt responses), and componential or atomic (rather than
holistic) in nature.
The Concept of Representation 25
Cell assembly
Various neuropsychological representational concepts have been proposed
in the history of psychology and physiology. Hebb's (1949) cell-assembly
construct is the best known and the most completely defined of those in
terms of its hypothetical neurophysiological structure as well as its psycho-
logical (behavioral) origins and functions. Hebb has always insisted that the
cell assembly is a hypothetical construct (see Hebb, 1980), but it nonetheless
had a plausible observational base in the closed neuronal loops discovered
by Lorente de No. Cell-assembly systems presumably arise from perceptual-
motor experience and constitute the neuronal basis of thought and orga-
nized behavior. These systems are assumed to be hierarchically organized,
with lower order assemblies corresponding to simple percepts, images, and
so on, and higher order assemblies corresponding to more abstract ideas.
26 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
Template
The concept of template was first applied to the analysis of pattern recog-
nition (see Neisser, 1967, for a review), the idea being that recognition
occurs when a perceptual pattern can be matched with a corresponding rep-
resentation of such a pattern in long-term memory. Initially, the concept
had connotations of high concreteness, specificity, and rigidity, much like
the wax tablet model of the mental image. This version fell into disfavor
because it could not account for findings that seemed to show that recogni-
tion accuracy was relatively unaffected by the orientation and retinal locus
of the perceptual pattern. More recent studies suggest that the negative con-
clusion needs to be qualified. For example, Jolicoeur and Landau (1984)
reported that they found strong and systematic effects of orientation on the
identification of alphabetic characters. Such findings justify a reevaluation
of the template concept, but in the meantime it has been largely replaced by
the following "stretched" versions that are structurally and functionally
more abstract than the earlier ones.
Prototype
The concept of prototype refers to representations of conceptual categories
that correspond to such general terms as bird, animal, and furniture. One
classical general interpretation was that the prototypical representation is
some kind of composite of specific instances. A modern version of this idea
is that the prototype is a statistical averaging of some kind, as in Posner and
Keele's (1968) research on the generation of a prototype from exposure to
specific instances of dot patterns. Another interpretation was that it is the
specific instances themselves that stand for the category. The best known
The Concept of Representation 27
Schema
The term schema came into modern psychology through the writings of
Head (1920), Piaget (1926), and Bartlett (1932). Schemata refer to mental
structures that represent our general knowledge of objects, situations, and
events. Current variants of the concept include frames (Minsky, 1975),
scripts (Schank & Abelson, 1977), and ideals (Bregman, 1977). These con-
cepts refer to perceptual knowledge as well as schematic descriptions, much
like a verbal summary of the theme and main points of a scene. Models
based on the script concept in particular have been applied to the analysis
of reactions to passages that describe typical behavioral situations, such as
dining in a restaurant or visits to doctors or dentists. The assumption is that
a script includes general perceptual knowledge of the objects and events in
such settings, as well as knowledge of how one typically behaves in relation
to them. Such knowledge structures are usually assumed to be hierarchically
organized, so that the restaurant script, for example, might include general
knowledge pertaining to ordering and eating a meal, and more specific,
lower-level verbal and behavioral components such as asking for the wine
menu and using a fork. Alternatively, scripts could be viewed simply as
sequentially organized event structures without any assumption of levels of
generality, although this is not the usual interpretation.
Variants of the schema concept have been used in the analysis of percep-
tual recognition, memory, motor skills, and understanding of discourse. In
the case of perception, a specific stimulus pattern is compared with a sche-
matic representation, much as in template matching. Recognition is
achieved if the stimulus represents a possible "instantiation" of the sche-
matic pattern. Similar processes are assumed to occur in memory and com-
28 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
Features
We have already seen that feature representations were first used systemat-
ically in the analysis of speech sounds (Jakobson, Fant, & Halle, 1951). Pho-
nemes are described in terms of articulatory features (e.g., consonantal,
labial) or acoustic features (e.g., resonant, spirant), which are usually treated
as binary dimensions. A given phoneme is viewed as a pattern of such fea-
tures, so that b, for example, is + consonantal, +stop, + labial, and + voice.
This approach allows for descriptive parsimony in that a relatively small set
of features can be used to classify all of the phonemes of a language, and it
reveals the systematic relations between different sounds in terms of the
number and kind of distinctive features in their descriptions.
Phonemic features have empirical correlates in that articulatory and
acoustic patterns can be directly observed. The observational status of the
features concept is less clear when it is extended to other phenomena. In
the case of visual pattern perception, the discovery of feature detectors in
the visual cortex of the cat (Hubel & Wiesel, 1962) provided a possible neu-
rophysiological base for visual features. However, the original concept has
The Concept of Representation 29
Proposition
We turn, finally, to the proposition, which is the most abstract and theoret-
ical (least observational) representational concept of all. It is also the most
widely used one in computational models of cognition. At one level, it
serves as a kind of lingua franca that can be used to characterize psycholog-
ical phenomena or redefine other theoretical constructs. For example, it is
popular today to describe mental images and to recast feature representa-
tions, structural descriptions, and schema in propositional terms. At
another level, it is treated as a "real" mental representational unit that
serves as the basic building block of general knowledge structures. In view
of its popularity, generality, and flexibility, this representational concept
deserves careful examination.
Recall from the last chapter that a proposition, is basically a truth state-
ment. It was given that meaning in the context of symbolic logic, where
truth refers to the internal consistency of a statement within the set of state-
ments that constitute a logical system. Accordingly, the truth value of a
proposition is evaluated in terms of its logical consistency: It is true if it
follows logically from other statements, otherwise it is false. This definition
applies as well to the concept as used in formal scientific models. It follows
that such a "definition of a proposition of a scientific model rules out of
consideration all truth statements having to do with the correspondence
between the predictions of the model and the empirical domain it purports
to represent" (Dubin, 1969, p. 166).
The Concept of Representation 31
REPRESENTATIONAL SCEPTICS
33
34 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
REPRESENTATIONAL EMPIRICISTS
Representational empiricism characterizes those approaches that Skinner
described (and rejected) as "the mind that is constructed from observations
of the behavior of others," or what I referred to as objective or behavioral
mentalism (Paivio, 1975c). It stems from British empiricism and the theory
that knowledge derives from experience and is based on associations
between ideas. American structuralism and functionalism were part of the
historical chain because images and other forms of mental representation
constituted their subject matter, but their reliance on subjective (introspec-
tive) methods removes them somewhat from my definition. Specific ante-
Attitudes and Approaches to Representation 37
cedents that do fit the definition include Galton's (1883) studies of mental
imagery and mental words, and the objective studies of memory by Binet
(1894) and Ebbinghaus (1885/1964) and Hunter's (1913) delayed-reaction
experiments, in which an animal's choice behavior seemed explainable only
in terms of some kind of cognitive representation of the situation. Leeper
(1951) provided a useful review of such behavioral evidence for cognitive
processes in both animals and humans.
Hebb's (1949) neuropsychological theory is another landmark in behav-
ioral mentalism. According to Hebb, the behavioral evidence for attention
and mental set demanded a mechanism for maintaining activity in the brain
between stimulus input and response output. The closed neural circuits of
cell-assembly theory provided that mechanism. Assumed to result from per-
ceptual exploration of objects, cell assemblies and their activity constitute
the neural basis of perception, imagery, abstract ideas, and whatever else is
involved in thinking. The theory served to integrate seemingly contradic-
tory facts about perception and learning, provide a physiological basis for
the distinction between short-term and long-term memory, and so on. It
also generated some unusual predictions and experiments on the effects of
early experience on perceptual development, and on the nature of percep-
tual fluctuation when the retinal image is stablized.
The experimental results supported aspects of the theory and refuted oth-
ers. Such findings together with new neurophysiological discoveries moti-
vated changes in the model (see Hebb, 1980) that were intended to account
for the discrepancies and for other recent observations. The details are not
necessary for present purposes. The general point is that this was the first
comprehensive theory of the representational units and structures that are
the hypothetical basis of conceptual activity at different levels of abstract-
ness. The approach is empiricist because the theoretical concepts were based
on inferences from the facts of behavior and neurophysiology. Moreover,
the empiricism is constructive in that Hebb views his model as a working
hypothesis that is to be believed only to the extent that it is empirically
adequate.
Behaviorism also branched out into a variety of empirically based repre-
sentational approaches. Osgood's (1953) mediational theory is a clear exam-
ple because its rm-sm units are assumed to be derived, via conditioning, from
behaviors to things and to retain some of the functional properties of those
behaviors. Other cognitive behaviorists have relied similarly on such expe-
rientially based representational-mediational constructs as cognitive maps
(Tolman, 1948), and images viewed as conditioned sensory responses
(Mowrer, 1960; Sheffield, 1961; Staats, 1968). These are all examples of
behavioral mentalism by my definition, with behavioristic concepts replac-
ing mentalistic ones.
Two other empirical-theoretical streams have had a major influence on
the development of this neomentalism. One is the rote-memory tradition
that began with Ebbinghaus (1885/1964) and the other is the information-
38 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
that Kosslyn has also tried to capture the best of both the empiricist and
rationalist approaches by expressing his theory in computational terms.
A specific feature of the empiricist approaches deserves special emphasis
because it contrasts sharply with its parallel in current rationalist theories.
This feature is the assumption that mental representations are ultimately
modality specific in character. Thus, verbal mediational theorists assumed
that the effective mediators are implicit verbal responses. Empiricist
approaches to imagery assume that images are analogue representations in
the sense that the represented information is modality specific (e.g., visual)
and isomorphic with perceptual information in a strong sense. The attribute
approaches to memory imply that representations are multimodal. We
might note, too, that Kolers (1978), though critical of current structural
approaches to the representation of knowledge, nonetheless assumes in his
procedural approach that representations are means dependent rather than
totally abstract.
The stage models of memory also included modality-specific representa-
tional assumptions. Thus, the sensory store was assumed to store informa-
tion about the input modality of items for a brief period and the short-term
store was generally assumed to be auditory-motor-linguistic in character.
However, the theorists were vague with respect to long-term memory rep-
resentation and simply assumed on empirical grounds that the stored infor-
mation was semantic. This assumption raised the question of what "seman-
tic" means, and opened the way for the development of semantic-memory
models that incorporated computational-rationalistic assumptions, includ-
ing the view that semantic representations are amodal.
An evaluation of the empiricist approaches will lead us appropriately into
rationalistic views. As already mentioned, the main evaluative criterion was
predictive and explanatory success, and many of the empirically derived
representational constructs proved to be inadequate on those grounds. For
example, verbal mediational approaches to memory had difficulty with
organizational phenomena and simply failed to account for the mnemonic
effects of imagery variables. A logical criterion was added to the picture from
the rationalist side. It began with Chomsky's view that stimulus-response
theories of language are essentially finite-state models, and that such models
cannot account for syntactic creativity. Fodor (1965) argued similarly that
meaning cannot be explained by covert responses (rm's) because they have
the same properties as the overt responses from which they are derived, and
so they also suffer from the inadequacies of nonmediational S-R theories.
This line of reasoning was generalized and formalized as the so-called
terminal-meta-postulate (see chap. 1), which was asserted to be the downfall
of any theory that describes mediational or representational processes in the
same language that is used to describe overt behavior. I leave further dis-
cussion of that issue to chapter 4, where I hope to show that, whatever the
general merits of the critique, it does not apply to certain classes of empiri-
Attitudes and Approaches to Representation 41
cist theories, and in particular the dual coding theory described in that
chapter.
RATIONALISTIC APPROACHES
derived through intuition and not through sense data, and (d) that such
ideas, not being empirically derived, must therefore be innate.
These assumptions show up in the following ways in contemporary
rationalistic approaches to the study of mental representations. First, the
emphasis on logical reasoning is essential if the computer is to be used as a
model of mind. It follows that a computational mind must use descriptive
units and elementary statements (propositions) to build logically organized
knowledge structures. These features are the basis of computational models
of language and semantic memory. The classical reliance on intuition and
rejection of empiricism reemerges today as a relative emphasis on intuitive
and speculative approaches coupled with a relative neglect of experimental
and other observational procedures and data. Finally, the doctrine of innate
ideas reemerges essentially in its pristine form but with its implications
more fully developed: The basis of knowledge is found in innate mental
structures, which function as filters for sense data and determine their man-
ifest form in observable language or other behavior.
Plato and Descartes used geometric knowledge to illustrate their argu-
ments concerning innate ideas. Since we never experience perfect circles or
triangles but nonetheless have the idea of such perfect forms or ideals, the
ideal must be innately given. The modern concepts of prototype, schema,
deep structure, and the like, are all related to this idea. Bregrnan (1977) even
adopted the term "ideal" and related it approvingly to the Platonic original.
Of course, a nativist view is not logically necessary for the acceptance of the
idea of schema, and Piaget (e.g., 1980) and others have explicitly adopted a
constructivist approach according to which schemata are cognitively con-
structed on the basis of sense data.
Representational theorists vary in the degree to which they adopt the clas-
sical rationalist assumptions. Chomsky is clearly at the upper extreme
because he argues strongly for the doctrine of innate mental structures,
shows a relatively strong preference for intuitive or speculative methods,
rejects empiricist philosophy, and deemphasizes empiricist methodology.
For example, following an approving discussion of Descartes's views con-
cerning innate ideas, Chomsky outlined its implications for a universal gen-
erative grammar and then concluded as follows: "I believe that these pro-
posals can be properly regarded as a further development of classical
rationalist doctrine, as an elaboration of some of its main ideas regarding
language and mind. Of course, such a theory will be repugnant to one who
accepts empiricist doctrine and regards it as immune to question or chal-
lenge" (1968, p. 73). Chomsky thereby affirmed both his rationalist
approach and its contrast with empiricism. His nativistic theory of language
acquisition, the so-called language-acquisition device, or LAD (Chomsky,
1965) explicitly reflected that philosophy. The rationalism extends to meth-
odology in that Chomsky has argued that the essential facts about language
are available to everyone and, therefore, it suffices for theorists to draw on
their linguistic intuitions as the data base for analysis of language. Subse-
Attitudes and Approaches to Representation 43
quent writings (e.g., Caplan & Chomsky, 1982) indicate that these views
remain essentially unchanged.
Fodor's (1975) views are in some respects even more extremely rational-
istic. First, he asserts that "The only psychological models of cognitive pro-
cesses that seem even remotely plausible represent such processes as com-
putational" (1975, p. 27). Second, he reasoned that one can learn a natural
language only if one already knows a language rich enough to express what
can be expressed in the natural language. Thus, the original (internal) lan-
guage or, more generally, the first conceptual system must be innately deter-
mined (pp. 79-97). However, Fodor is more empirical than Chomsky in
that he relies relatively more on objective data to support his "speculative
psychology."
The extreme forms of nativistic rationalism are stultifying in regard to the
growth of empirical and theoretical understanding of the wide variety of
cognitive and behavioral phenomena that must be learned in some way. For
example, the great variety of surface forms of human language cannot be
explained by any explicit nativistic hypothesis such as Chomsky's LAD. The
crucial and complex question of how the various linguistic performance
skills are acquired is relegated to a secondary and relatively minor position
in the Chomskyan program. Its reliance on formal constraints to define the
possible linguistic structures that can be learned by a child leaves it open to
charges of circularity and other limitations of formal rationalism described
below. These charges apply as well to recent developmental elaborations of
Chomsky's ideas by others (see chap. 5).
Weaker forms of rationalism appear in other contemporary approaches to
mental representation. For example, J. Anderson and Bower (1973) suggest
that their theory of human associative memory is partly rationalistic (nativ-
istic) and partly empiricistic. The rationalistic components of their model
are the perceptual and linguistic parsers that encode sensory information so
that it can be used by the long-term (associative) memory system. The latter
is the empirical component that stores the experientially determined infor-
mation in the form of prepositional networks. Anderson's and Bower's
rationalism is quite weak because they have not attempted to specify the
nature of the innate structural properties of the parsers in HAM and no pre-
dictive consequences arise from them. Only the empirically acquired prop-
erties of the long-term memory component are spelled out in the detail nec-
essary to use it as an explanatory and predictive model.
The Anderson and Bower position is essentially like that of all psycholo-
gists concerned with learning and memory. All accept the idea that organ-
isms come to a learning situation with biologically determined capacities
that limit what can be learned, but their strategy is to focus on learning
because such complex skills as speaking and tying shoe laces are obviously
a product of experience.
Other computational theorists are committed to the rationalistic assump-
tion that the mind is a logical device that operates according to formal rules.
44 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
concerning the behavior of systems under certain descriptions" (p. 26). Rep-
resentation appears to be intended here as a descriptive convenience. Else-
where, however, cognitive representations become reified as "concrete enti-
ties" (p. 193), now described variously as "sentence analogues," "mentalese
sentences," or "discrete sentencelike symbolic expressions" (pp. 194-196)—
conceptual equivalents of propositions but viewed as less abstract. The
interpretive ambiguity is there, but I don't wish to belabor the point because
Pylyshyn clearly intends to equate sentence-like representations with "real"
psychological processes as part of his commitment to a literal or "strong
equivalence" (as opposed to a metaphorical) view of the mind as a com-
putational device (Pylyshyn, 1984).
The statements of other key figures in the debate have also been ambig-
uous. In the quotation cited earlier, Kieras first refers to all knowledge being
expressed in propositional terms and then goes on to say that there is no
fundamental difference in how perceptually based and verbally based infor-
mation is represented in memory. These are quite different assertions. The
first implies that all information can be described in propositional terms;
the second characterizes memory as being amodal. J. Anderson (1978) at
times discusses the proposition as a theoretical construct whose function it
is to represent "information in an image or in a sentence or information
from any other source" (p. 257). At other times, he gives the concept psy-
chological and even physiological status, as when he concludes that "studies
on hemispheric specialization provide very little evidence on the form of
information representation. One could propose that all information has a
propositional form, but that propositions encoding visual information are
stored in the right hemisphere and propositions encoding verbal in the left
(p. 271)."
As a final example, Olson and Bialystok (1983) launched their inquiry
into spatial cognition with the stated intention of using a propositional "rep-
resentational format" as a way of describing the structure of mental repre-
sentations involved in spatial cognitive tasks (see their Preface). This "prop-
ositional way of talking and thinking" (p. ix) changed quickly into a reified
view of a structural description as "a propositional representation of the
properties or features and their relations constructed by the mind which per-
mits the recognition of and assignment of meaning to objects" (p. 8). The
theory developed on that basis is explicitly "intended as a contribution to a
computational theory of mind" according to which propositional structural
descriptions "are the internal structures used to model reality" (pp. 258-
259). The treatise is a contribution but it also leaves us wondering whether
the reification of computational terminology is really intended.
The conceptual ambiguity just described seems to be quite unlike that in
other sciences. For example, physicists are guided by a theory that describes
the behavior of atoms and subatomic particles in abstract, mathematical
terms. They do not equate the description with the entities nor with their
behavior. They postulate entities whose behaviors involve regularities that
Attitudes and Approaches to Representation 47
can be described as laws, and they aim to account for those laws in terms of
a mathematical theory. Thus, "a physical theory ... is a system of mathe-
matical propositions, deduced from a small number of principles, which
aim to represent as simply, as completely, and as exactly as possible a set of
experimental laws" (Duhem, 1974 translation). Such a theory represents
simple properties with mathematical symbols, numbers, and magnitudes.
These symbols have no intrinsic connection with the properties they rep-
resent; they bear to those properties only the relation of sign to things sig-
nified. The physical theorist does not assert that the descriptive elements
(i.e., the mathematical symbols) are the underlying entities, as propositional
theorists have tended to do with their descriptive units (for a general dis-
cussion of reification in cognitive science, see R. Hoffman & Nead, 1983).
very least provide for considerable uncertainty rather than relying on invar-
iant concepts and rules. Without such provisions, propositional descriptions
are bound to be inadequate as explanatory constructs.
Circularity of descriptive systems
No representational theory can provide a satisfactory explanation of psy-
chological phenomena if the basic descriptive units of the theory are defined
entirely in a circular fashion. The circularity problem has plagued proposi-
tionally based theories in which the conceptual units are characterized as
labelled nodes that represent objects and their properties as well as relations
among the objects and properties. Thus, a labelled entity such as bird is
defined in terms of labelled properties such as has wings, has feathers, can
fly. These properties are in turn defined by reference to their labelled prop-
erties, and so on, ad infinitum. Such a description provides an illusory
explanation because we know the meanings of the descriptive labels, just as
we can discover the meaning of a word in a dictionary provided that the
defining terms are already familiar. The illusion is shattered, however, if we
try the reductio ad absurdum of labelling the nodes and relations in a foreign
language, which is essentially equivalent to looking up the meanings of for-
eign words in a dictionary in that language. Ultimately, the elemental units
must be meaningful in some more direct psychological sense, and we must
have a language-independent (and computer-independent) way of identify-
ing them; otherwise, we are simply caught in an infinite descriptive regress.
Some theorists (e.g., J. Anderson & Bower, 1973; Pylyshyn, 1973) sought
to escape the circularity, at least in principle, by suggesting that the ultimate
defining units are perceptual features, but they proposed no independent
means for identifying such features. Pylyshyn (1984) recognizes the circu-
larity inherent in describing mental activity in terms of semantically inter-
preted representations alone, and he gets out of it by postulating a psycho-
logical or cognitive transducer whose purpose is to "map physical events
into cognitive, or computational events" (p. 178)—essentially the functional
equivalent of sense organs and effector systems. He proposed a series of cri-
teria or design specifications for these cognitive transducers, but how they
are discovered remains mysterious since Pylyshyn explicitly argued that
they cannot be identified by neurophysiological methods, psychophysical
methods, or functional analysis. In any case, the circularity problem cannot
be solved by transducers that only provide an interface between physical
events and cognitive events if the latter are characterized only as "discrete
sentencelike symbolic expressions." We can think about the environment
even when we are not overtly interacting with it, so the cognitive system
itself must represent the environment and our ways of interacting with it in
some form that is different from and independent of the sentence-like rep-
resentational system and its discrete atomic symbols. If not, we are back in
the descriptive cognitive circle in which the only referents for meaningless
descriptions are other descriptions.
Attitudes and Approaches to Representation 49
The circularity problem does not exist in dual coding theory or other
approaches in which perceptual and behavioral knowledge of the world is
represented in a nondescriptive, analogue fashion. Computational theorists
have also begun to recognize the need for analogue representations. For
example, J. Anderson (1983) incorporated nonpropositional cognitive units
(phrases and spatial images) into the latest version of his general theory,
although most of his analyses still rely on propositional representations.
Johnson-Laird's (1983) theory includes mental models (structural analogues
of the world) and mental images along with propositional symbol strings
that correspond to natural language. The analogue or image systems of such
theories provide the essential cognitive-referential interface between the
physical world and a descriptive-symbol system.
The above is not a denial of the reality of compositional skills that are
used in the construction or generation of novel linguistic strings, images,
and behavior patterns. Constructive skills are ubiquitous and they are
explicitly revealed in such tasks as anagrams and jigsaw puzzles, in which a
meaningful complex pattern is generated from smaller components, and in
simple multiplication, in which a small set of rote habits (including recur-
sive acts) are used to generate a novel sequence of symbols. Such skills
require explanation, but they need not themselves form the metaphorical
basis of a more atomic compositional approach to the understanding of per-
ception, language, and even imagery.
Despite the logical problems that have been raised here in regard to propo-
sitional approaches, they are currently the major alternative to empiricist
52 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
53
54 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
cessing functions that are served by the symbolic systems. Also listed are the
empirical or operational procedures that make it possible to evaluate the
theory, and the classes of psychological phenomena to which it is particu-
larly relevant. The following sections expand on the outline.
Dual coding theory is basically about the nature of symbolic systems. The
interpretation of the term system is complicated by the empiricist assump-
tion that the symbolic representations retain the properties of different sen-
sory and response modalities. The conceptual difficulty is resolved by
assuming that the verbal-nonverbal symbolic distinction is orthogonal to
the sensorimotor modalities in the manner illustrated by the examples
shown in Table 4-2. This analysis was originally proposed specifically to
accommodate episodic memory phenomena (Paivio, 1972) but it is applic-
able to cognition in general. It represents a kind of modularity position with-
out the exclusive nativism associated with recent computational views on
the modularity of mind (Fodor, 1983). It is more closely related to empiri-
cally based approaches that emphasize a high degree of functional specificity
between and within sensory subsystems. For example, rather than being
viewed as a single system for producing an integrated representation of the
external world, the visual system appears to consist of a network of inde-
pendent sensorimotor channels (Goodale, 1983). The present position
Dual Coding Theory 57
Table 4-2. Orthogonal conceptual relation between symbolic
systems and sensorimotor systems with examples of types of
modality-specific information represented in each subsystem
Symbolic Systems
Sensorimotor Verbal Nonverbal
Visual Visual words Visual objects
Auditory Auditory words Environmental sounds
Haptic Writing patterns "Feel" of objects
Taste Taste memories
Smell — Olfactory memories
UNIT-LEVEL ASSUMPTIONS
This section deals with three interrelated assumptions: (a) the representa-
tional units in each system are modality-specific perceptual-motor ana-
logues, (b) units are hierarchically organized structures, and (c) intraunit
functional structure differs so that component information in higher-order
nonverbal units is synchronously organized (permitting parallel processing
up to some informational limit), whereas verbal components are sequen-
tially organized (implying sequential constraints on intraunit processing).
The modality-specific analogue assumption follows from the general empi-
ricist postulate, and the two organizational assumptions are corollaries of
the analogue assumption. The three assumptions are necessarily intertwined
in the following discussion.
I have previously referred to the hypothetical nonverbal and verbal rep-
resentational units as imagens and logogens (Paivio, 1978f). The logogen
concept is borrowed from John Morton (1969) who introduced it to account
for perceptual word-recognition results. The present usage is more general
in that it does not imply acceptance of all of the features of Morton's logogen
model, but the functional properties are essentially parallel. Morton's (1979)
revision of the model is particularly pertinent because empirical evidence
compelled him to postulate modality-specific (e.g., auditory and visual)
logogens, as well as separate input and output logogens. The concept of ima-
gen refers similarly to representations from which mental images are gen-
erated under appropriate conditions (cf. "iconogen"; Attneave, 1974). The
detailed analysis of representational units given below implies that the ima-
gen, too, must be viewed as a multimodal concept.
The two terms are problematic because they imply fixed entities corre-
sponding to static objects and words. While those are appropriate referent
classes, the present usage is intended to be broader and more flexible. The
terms serve mainly to distinguish the underlying (hypothetical) cognitive
representations from their expressions as consciously experienced images
and inner speech, or overt behaviors such as drawing and speech. The term
unit can also be misleading because it falsely implies a discrete entity of
some fixed size and character. Nonetheless, it can be interpreted in a way
that is consistent with such psychological units as the chunk (G. Miller,
1956), integral stimulus (Garner, 1974), or "blob" (Lockhead, 1972). Thus,
imagens and logogens are assumed to vary in size but they are nonetheless
unitary in the sense that they can function as integrated informational struc-
tures or response generators for some purposes. This is a kind of compo-
nential approach in which the components are concrete, modality-specific
entities that can also combine to form more complex entities.
The two classes of units differ in the nature of their internal structure in
a way that reflects their perceptual-motor origins. Thus, imagens correspond
to natural objects, holistic parts of objects, and natural groupings of objects.
The represented information includes not only static appearance but
60 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
because the perceptual experiences on which they are based are sometimes
conjoint and sometimes separate.
Logogens, too, are assumed to vary in size, but they differ from imagens
in internal structure so that smaller units are organized into larger units in
a sequential or successive fashion. This structure is most apparent in the
case of auditory-motor representations corresponding to heard or spoken
language, where phonemic units are organized in syllables, syllables into
words, and so on, up to sequential structures as extensive as poems or entire
plays. Similarly, writing is a sequential motor activity that must have its
own sequentially organized representational base. The visual logogens that
correspond to print differ in that, up to some limit, they are functionally
equivalent to linear spatial structures than can be processed as visual units.
Thus, we can image letters and short words, perhaps up to a limit of three
or four letters in length (Weber & Harnish, 1974). Such visual word repre-
sentations presumably do not differ from those that correspond to the rep-
resentations of nonverbal objects except in the linear arrangement of smaller
units into larger ones, which is itself dictated by the fact that written lan-
guage maps onto the sequential structure of speech and, hence, is subject to
the same sequential processing constraints.
The synchronous-sequential structural contrast was originally made by
the British empiricists, Berkeley and James Mill, who distinguished between
simultaneous and successive order in the association of ideas. Simultaneity
implied simultaneous availability and freedom from sequential constraints,
but was more specifically defined by the property of redintegration whereby
the occurrence of an idea is simultaneously accompanied by other ideas that
derive from perceptual experiences in which the component elements
occurred together. Although not described in those terms, the synchronous-
sequential contrast reemerged during the behavioristic era in the form of a
controversy concerning the nature of maze learning, with Hull arguing that
the animal learns response sequences and Tolman arguing that the animal
learns spatial structures or "cognitive maps" that permit it to take a short
cut to a goal in a spatial maze (see Tolman, 1948). Thus, Hull's theory
implied sequential representational structures and Tolman's theory explic-
itly relied on synchronous representations in which component information
is simultaneously available. In retrospect, the present analysis is a synthesis
and extension of these antecedents as applied specifically to the structural
properties of verbal and nonverbal representations, as defined functionally
by different indices of sequential constraints and simultaneous availability.
SYSTEM-LEVEL ASSUMPTIONS
The discussion now turns to the structural and functional properties of the
symbolic systems as a whole, involving relations among representational
units within and between verbal and nonverbal systems. The principal
62 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
Between-system relations
The nonverbal and verbal symbolic systems are assumed to be functionally
independent in the sense that one system can be active without the other,
or both can be active in parallel. They are also independent in the infor-
mation processing sense of independent stages, although the preferred met-
aphor in dual coding is that one system triggers activity in the other, rather
than the idea that information flows from one to the other. The activation
of one system by the other implies that representations in the two systems
must be interconnected. The interconnections are incomplete or partial in
the sense that "access routes" are only available between certain represen-
tations in each system. Thus, a structural connection exists between those
representations, but interunit processing is nonetheless optional in the met-
aphorical sense that the pathways are only "used" or activated under certain
conditions but not others. This means, for example, that picture naming is
not automatic although it is highly likely to occur under some circum-
stances. Similarly, one can but need not image to concrete nouns or descrip-
tions. This conceptualization of the structural-functional relation between
systems is important theoretically because it provides for the possibility of
flexible yet organized processing activity of the symbolic systems, so that
they can function independently and additively for some purposes and coor-
dinate their activities for others.
The points of functional contact between systems are between imagens
and logogens—usually auditory-motor logogens, although direct connec-
tions to other modalities of verbal representations are not ruled out. The
simple case is the relation between the representations corresponding to an
object and its name. The most direct evidence of such interconnections are
acts of reference—for example, naming objects and pointing to named
objects. Clear evidence is also found at the internal level in the occurrence
of images to names and names to images. Thus, if I am asked to describe
my dining room table, 1 first experience an image of that table, which I can
then describe by naming its components and adjectival attributes. Note that
the referent object in this case is a particular table and the name that evokes
the corresponding image is the compound expression, my dining room
table. The latter is not necessarily represented cognitively as a wcll-inte-
Dual Coding Theory 63
grated logogen unit in the way that compound words (e.g., armchair) pre-
sumably are, but it nonetheless evokes a unitary representation of a partic-
ular object. Such functional semantic units can be freely created in speech,
just as they can in imagery, which is a problem for a later section. The
important point here is that the relations between images and descriptions,
however complex these may be, depend on functional connections between
some elements in the verbal system and the image-generating system.
It should be emphasized, too, that the interconnections are not assumed
to be one-to-one but, rather, one-to-many, in both directions. The assump-
tion parallels the familiar fact that a thing can be called by many names and
a name has many specific referents. This translates into the dual coding
assumption that a given word can evoke any of a number of images, corre-
sponding to different exemplars of a referent class (e.g., different tables) or
different versions of a particular class member (e.g., my dining room table
imaged from different perspectives). Conversely, a given object (or imaged
object) can evoke different descriptions.
Precisely which images or descriptions will be activated at any moment
depends on the stimulus context interacting with the relative functional
strength of the different referential interconnections. Functional strength is
determined by prior objective experiences with referent class members and
verbal descriptions associated with them, and strength translates operation-
ally into the probability distribution of overt referential responses. This
analysis obviously has its roots in the analysis of associative probabilities in
word-association data (e.g., Deese, 1962; Kiss, 1975). The present concep-
tion generalizes the analysis to the relations between objects and their verbal
descriptions or, theoretically, imagens and logogens. Labeling data show
that pictures of common objects elicit a range of names that vary in their
probability. Similar data have been obtained for labeling of environmental
sounds. The reverse relation, imaging to words, has not been studied as sys-
tematically but exploratory experiments have shown that names elicit
drawn images that vary in type and orientation in a probabilistic way. For
example, just as shirt is a highly probable (and prototypical) associate to the
stimulus word clothing, subjects are likely to draw a shirt when given cloth-
ing as a stimulus word. Moreover, they are most likely to draw it in a par-
ticular orientation, as though viewed from the front with the arms out to
the sides. Ratings have also been used to measure variability in the type and
number of different images elicited by words (Snodgrass & Vanderwart,
1980). Various procedures of this kind need to be used to obtain systematic
empirical data on the precise nature of the distribution of different images
to words and vice versa.
Note that the assumptions are similar to those associated with semantic
memory models (e.g., Collins & Loftus, 1975) that distinguish between con-
ceptual representations and lexical representations. However, such models
assume that the conceptual representations are abstract and descriptive
(propositional) in nature and (in the interests of cognitive economy) that the
64 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
relations are between type nodes rather than between specific instances, or
tokens. Neither assumption is necessary in the present approach, as I will
indicate more fully later on.
This analysis of between-system relations emphasizes internal represen-
tations for discrete objects and their names. The analysis is more complex
in the case of the relations between attributes of objects and motor activities
on the one hand, and their adjectival and verbal descriptions on the other.
The relations appear to be relatively direct between focal colors and their
names in that such colors can be named quickly and reliably and the names
are rated high in imagery value. This observation suggests some kind of dis-
crete representational base for colors (color imagens?) despite their percep-
tually continuous character, and indeed some color-processing data are con-
sistent with such a view (Kolers & von Griinau, 1976; Paivio & te Linde,
1980). On the other hand, it is not clear that the referential relations are
symmetrical: Individuals can name focal colors as quickly as familiar
objects, but can they image as quickly to color names as to object names?
And when they image colors, do they image colors alone or concrete objects
for which the named color is a typical attribute?
Some motor reactions can be similarly interpreted. For example, verbal
commands to walk, run, or jump can elicit corresponding activities quite
promptly, as though referential interconnections exist between verb logo-
gens and well-integrated motor schemata. However, imaging to such verbs
may require concretization of the referent (e.g., "run" imaged as a boy run-
ning). Other classes of properties and activities are even less independent of
concrete objects and the property-name relations may be relatively indirect,
implicating within-system associative connections (discussed below) as well
as between-system referential connections. Such complications come up
again in specific empirical contexts (e.g., chap. 7) and a more detailed the-
oretical analysis will depend on new data.
Within-system relations
We turn next to the relations between units within each of the two symbolic
systems. The verbal system is assumed to be structured in an associative
fashion that can be inferred from word-association data and other proce-
dures. A probabilistic network of relations describes the overall structure,
so that auditory-motor logogens are linked to each other in a many-to-many
fashion as determined by associative experience. The terms link and asso-
ciation again refer to functionally defined relations, that is, the probability
that logogens will activate each other given initial activation by a specific
target word and its accompanying context. The elements of the system are
assumed to correspond to words or unitized word groups as discussed ear-
lier in connection with the logogen concept. Thus, no abstract entities are
postulated, although words themselves vary in denotative abstractness and
generality. It is possible, accordingly, to describe aspects of the structure as
Dual Coding Theory 65
Moreover, the imagery can expand and shift continuously to portions of the
broader setting.
The continuity is not unbroken, however, for my perspective can shift
suddenly to my home, my work setting, or to another country. Moreover,
some of my knowledge of the world is inherently discrete, derived from pho-
tographs of objects or settings that I have never visited nor even seen from
the perspective of a motion picture camera. My static imagery of such infor-
mation reflects that discreteness. How are these discrete aspects of one's
world knowledge organized? Any answer would be pure speculation because
the problem has not been studied empirically, but we can be more confident
about the conditions that determine the activation of the discrete chunks.
One determinant is the verbal system and its interconnections with the
imagery system: Questions about my cottage, my house, or the Leaning
Tower of Pisa evoke images of those objects and their immediate settings in
the probabilistic fashion already discussed in the context of the imagen con-
cept. Such activation is presumably governed by processing mechanisms to
be considered in the next section, following a summary of the structural
assumptions.
The structural assumptions of dual coding are summarized in Figure 4-
1, which illustrates the idea of separate but interconnected systems, repre-
sentational units within systems, and the organization structure of the rep-
resented information. The interconnections are between referentially con-
crete representations, with abstract logogens and "unnamed imagens"
represented within their respective systems but not directly interconnected.
The figure also symbolizes the associative and logically hierarchical nature
of the assumed organizational structure of the verbal system, and the
nested-set character of the organization of nonverbal information. Finally,
the figure indicates that the symbolic systems are connected to sensory input
and response output systems, whose characteristics will be discussed only to
the extent necessary to explicate the behavioral functions of the symbolic
systems.
Processing operations
This section deals with the basic functional properties of the representa-
tional systems that make it possible for representational information to be
used in cognitive tasks and the guidance of behavior generally. These prop-
erties consist of cognitive processing mechanisms for accessing and activat-
ing mental representations directly or indirectly (implicating different levels
of processing), and for manipulating them in various ways at a conscious
and unconscious level. These hypothetical processes implicate all of the
operational indicators and procedures that have been used traditionally to
define symbolic processes. These are conceptually related on the one hand
to the behavioristic concept of controlling variables and on the other to the
cognitive psychological concept of control processes. The former translates
Dual Coding Theory 67
figure 4-1. Schematic depiction of the structure of verbal and nonverbal symbolic
systems, showing the representational units and their referential (between system)
and associative (within system) interconnections as well as connections to input and
output systems. The referentially unconnected units correspond to abstract-word
logogens and "nameless" imagens, respectively.
tual stimuli in a given task. The target stimuli are those that are presented
for processing, such as items to be remembered, compared, comprehended,
or mentally manipulated in some way. Examples of contextual stimuli are
experimental instructions that arouse a task set (the Aufgabe and Einstel-
lung of the Wiirzburg school) and the general context in which the experi-
mental task is presented.
More specifically, empirical observations have supported the assumption
that the activation of nonverbal representations as manifested in imagery
processing is a function of the (independently determined) concreteness or
image-arousing value of stimuli. Thus, imagery is more likely to be evoked
and used with objects or pictures as stimuli than with words as stimuli, and
with concrete than with abstract words, even in the absence of specific
instructional sets. Image arousal and processing is also increased by instruc-
tions to image to target stimuli or to use imagery in the task. Conversely,
verbal representational activation and processing (implying continuous rep-
resentational activity) are maximized when (a) words serve as stimuli, espe-
cially ones that are high in their acquired capacity to arouse verbal associ-
ations, (b) the task demands verbal processing, and (c) instructions are given
to carry out a task verbally.
Note that stimulus attributes and instructional sets are both aspects of the
stimulus situation. The effects of these variables can be summarized by say-
ing that they simply modify the probability with which verbal and nonver-
bal representations are activated in a given situation. The empiricist basis
of the theoretical statements is apparent from the fact that the hypothetical
mental processes are inferred directly from relevant variables—imagery
from the imagery-value of stimuli and instructions, and verbal processing
from the verbal emphasis in either class of input. We shall see later that this
approach has interesting and strong empirical implications, especially when
combined with other experimental task variables—implications that are not
suggested by any approach (such as radical behaviorism) that assumes that
the inferred processes are redundant, nor by cognitive theories that assume
a single, amodal (propositional) representational base.
Individual differences, which presumably reflect innate factors and the
experiential history of the individual, are specified operationally by perfor-
mance on tests of symbolic habits and abilities. The former include mea-
sures of cognitive style, preferences for thinking verbally or imaginally, and
so on. The latter include tests of spatial, figural, or imagery abilities on the
one hand and a variety of verbal abilities on the other. The functional role
of individual difference variables, like those of stimulus and contextual vari-
ables, can be expressed in probabilistic terms: They influence the probability
with which verbal and nonverbal representations will be aroused (and used
successfully) in a given task.
To summarize, the overall probability of the activation and use of verbal
and nonverbal representations is a function of the combined effect of stim-
Dual Coding Theory 69
ulus attributes, instructions and other contextual stimuli, and individual dif-
ferences. The precise nature of the combination (whether additive or inter-
active, for example) is an empirical question. The activation resulting from
the specified factors could involve one or both symbolic systems. For exam-
ple, the arousal of images by high imagery words implies a "crossover" from
verbal to imaginal system. This implication is made explicit in the following
processing assumptions, which are essentially a specific conceptualization
of the activation processes just discussed in operational terms.
Levels of processing
The present treatment is modified from one that I introduced earlier (Pai-
vio, 1971, pp. 52-59) in the context of the analysis of meaning. Three dif-
ferent kinds of processing can be identified, namely, representational, refer-
ential, and associative. Representational processing refers to the relatively
direct activation of verbal representations by linguistic stimuli and of non-
verbal representations by nonlinguistic stimuli. The activation is only rela-
tively direct because of the complications associated with perceptual analy-
sis of linguistic stimuli of different modalities, which implicate
representations corresponding to those modalities. Thus, naming (reading)
printed words takes longer than naming (repeating) spoken words, suggest-
ing that the former uses a "longer" route. Nonetheless, the representational
processing of visual words takes less time and is presumably more direct
than either referential or associative processing.
Referential processing refers to the activation of the nonverbal system by
verbal stimuli or the verbal system by nonverbal stimuli. Imaging to words
and naming objects are paradigmatic examples of tasks that require refer-
ential processing. Theoretically, these are indirect because they require a
crossover of activity from one symbolic system to the other, so that objects
must first activate imagens before logogens are activated and naming can
occur, and words initiate activity in logogens before imagens can be acti-
vated and experienced as images. Note, too, that image generation and
object-naming tasks often implicate other processes as well. For example, as
discussed below, the generation of complex, novel images to verbal cues
requires organizational processing of referentially activated image compo-
nents to produce an integrated image. Such constructive processes are given
special emphasis in Kosslyn's (1980) model of image generation.
Associative processing refers to the activation of representations within
either system by other representations within the same system. This kind of
processing corresponds to what is ordinarily assumed to occur during word
associations and when nonverbal situations trigger nonverbal memories
(images) of related situations. Associative processing and referential pro-
cessing need not differ in any quantitative sense (e.g., reaction time for refer-
ential and associative responding) but they do differ theoretically in type.
A given task may require any or all of the three kinds of processing. Sim-
ple perceptual recognition or judgments of the familiarity of stimuli requires
70 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
verbal processes in that regard. The present analysis is based on the modi-
fied hypothesis that both systems are capable of transforming symbolic rep-
resentations, but they do so in different ways, following the constraints
imposed by the organizational structure of verbal and nonverbal informa-
tion and the processes that operate on them.
Verbal transformations presumably operate on a sequential frame, impos-
ing changes in temporal order or substitution of new elements for ones that
occupy a particular temporal slot. These sequential changes could entail
simple reordering of a randomly ordered list of words, or syntactic transfor-
mations analogous to those described by Chomsky (1957). The concept of
transformational rules is equivalent, therefore, to one kind of verbal trans-
formational process. This characterization implies that such processes can
operate at a rather abstract level, since syntactic transformations apply to
word classes. The present interpretation is that they operate at different lev-
els—a specific level based on experiences with verbal units in many different
contexts, and a more abstract level generally described as internalized gram-
matical rules but viewed here as being essentially equivalent to verbal state-
ments concerning permissible combinations of verbal units (a special case
of the reflexivity of language). We shall see later that linguistic transforma-
tions are also influenced by nonlinguistic (nonsequential) information, but
the effects of the latter are nonetheless constrained by sequential verbal
processes.
Nonverbal transformations, on the other hand, are governed by the struc-
tural and processing constraints associated with nonverbal representations.
Thus, they can include spatial transformations and changes in the sensory
properties of representational content. For example, spatial transformations
as manifested in imagery include mental rotations on any plane, changes in
imaged size, distortions of shape, and changes in the relative position of two
or more objects. All of these are dynamic changes, so they could be regarded
as imagined movements of different kinds. However, they also imply covert
manipulation by the person doing the imaging, which may differ from the
processing required for imagining an object moving on its own. In any case,
the present hypothesis is that all mental transformations engage motor pro-
cesses that derive originally from active manipulation of the referent objects
and observations of perceptual changes in objects as they move or are
manipulated by others.
This theoretical analysis of transformational processes has a number of
historical precedents. The most obvious is the motor theory of thought. The
present view differs from the peripheralist version of motor theory in that
the processes need not be reflected in detectable overt motor activity. More
importantly, I assume that the covert motor processes operate on mental
representations with synchronously organized sensory properties. It is more
difficult to distinguish the theoretical assumptions from Osgood's theory of
representational mediation processes, although important differences in
detail will be addressed later. Other precedents include behavioral views
Dual Coding Theory 73
The following three sections deal with the mediating functions of cognitive
processes, that is, the adaptive uses of mental representations and processes
in the performance of specific cognitive tasks and generally in the guidance
of behavior. The functions implicate the structural properties and process-
ing operations already discussed, with the addition of some task-specific
hypotheses concerning the relative degree of involvement and effectiveness
of one or the other of the representational systems. The topic is covered
under the general headings of evaluative, mnemonic, and motivational-
emotional functions. These are assumed to be basic functional categories,
all of which are implicated to some degree in complex tasks, such as prob-
lem solving (see chap. 9).
Evaluative functions
The term evaluation refers literally to the determination of quantitative val-
ues of objects and events. Thus, it implicates whatever processes arc used
in the analysis and computation of absolute or relative values, with refer-
ence here to the information contained in mental representations. Some
Dual Coding Theory 75
examples from the research literature are: (a) scanning mental images to
determine the relative distances between locations on imaged maps, (b)
counting the corners of an imagined block letter, (c) "reading out" the infor-
mation in an imagined matrix, and (d) symbolic comparisons of objects on
any perceptual dimension (size, color, weight, and so on). In the case of ver-
bal representations, we have such tasks as mental arithmetic, analysis of the
structure of a mental word (e.g., the number of syllables, number of vowels
and consonants, etc.) or sentences (e.g., classifying the words sequentially
into nouns or non-nouns).
Most of these tasks implicate both symbolic systems. For example, count-
ing the windows in one's home requires verbally cued generation of visual
images of the house as viewed from different perspectives, entailing verbal
representational and verbal-to-imaginal referential processing. Counting the
windows is a verbal process operating over the encoded nonverbal represen-
tations. Moreover, some evaluative activities depend on transformational
processes. For example, the cube visualization task may include imagining
the cube being cut into smaller cubes, separating them, then determining the
number of colored faces on each small cube.
These examples suggest that the functional processes are largely under
conscious control of verbal mechanisms. Thus, verbal instructions initiate
image generation, scanning, counting, comparison, etc., and these mental
activities are kept "on track" at least partly by the subject's own covert ver-
balization during the task. This suggestion does not imply that all such pro-
cesses must operate at the conscious level. We might carry out mental scan-
ning or comparison in the service of everyday problems without being aware
of what we are doing and without verbal directives of any kind, but we lack
evidence on the issue and need not pursue it here. We know at least that
verbal cues can initiate and guide evaluative processing. It seems likely,
therefore, that this control originates in similar overt processing of percep-
tual information as a response to verbal instructions, paralleling what is
assumed to occur in the case of mental transformations.
Mnemonic functions
The relations between imaginal and verbal processes and memory are
among the most intensively investigated problems in psychology. Imagery
was the key element in the ancient mnemonic technique called the method
of loci, and it has been a focus of research attention in the modern era since
the early 1960s. The role of verbal mediation processes in verbal memory
attracted similar research attention for a number of decades. The implica-
tion has always been that imaginal and verbal systems have important func-
tions in the encoding, storage, and retrieval of episodic information.
The present analysis is based on the theoretical assumption that the mem-
ory trace is a modality-specific encoded representation of verbal or nonver-
bal input information. Words activate logogens, objects or their pictures
76 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
ings about memory. Still, in keeping with the constructive empirical nature
of the present theoretical enterprise, all of the theoretical assumptions that
I have presented are tentative and subject to modifications if the weight of
empirical evidence presses for change. The assumptions are retained as long
as they "save the phenomena."
The more specific reason for rejecting the rationalist critique is that some
postulates of dual coding theory directly violate the connectionist and
mechanistic statements of the terminal meta-postulate. First, the connec-
tionist statement is violated by the assumption that the imagery system can
construct novel representations that do not correspond directly to contigu-
ities of experience. For example, I can imagine an elephant riding on top of
an ambulance (an interactive image) although I have never actually seen
such an event. These novel constructions are reflected in such behavioral
consequences as the striking superiority of verbal-associative recall follow-
ing interactive as compared to separate imagery instructions. A similar anal-
ysis can be applied to the constructive nature of verbal processes. A second
violation of the connectionist statement is the assumption that similarity
can play a role in associative behavior independent of experiential conti-
guity. For example, a perceptual stimulus can evoke a memory image of a
previous experience that somehow resembles the current situation. These
and other experimental examples of the role of similarity in associative reac-
tions will be considered in the chapters to follow.
In summary, the so-called terminal meta-postulate does not pose a prob-
lem for dual coding theory for general as well as specific reasons. The general
reasons relate to the failure of critics of traditional empiricist-associative
approaches to consider the role of all relevant associative variables and sit-
uational contexts in the explanation of particular behaviors—factors that
are taken into account in dual coding theory. The specific reasons are that a
number of the assumptions of the theory violate aspects of the terminal
meta-postulate.
84
Development of Representational Systems 85
Brainerd, 1983; Case, 1978; Chi, 1976), which are genetically constrained
although learning plays a role in the rate of reaching the genetic limit.
Infants might also begin life with some built in perceptual "preferences"
(e.g., Field, 1982) and genetic factors presumably contribute to more com-
plex nonverbal skills, such as spatial ability (McGee, 1982). We know, too,
that language is a species-specific skill, although we remain uncertain about
what aspects of it are genetically determined. The genetic determinants have
been viewed traditionally as biological constraints on what can be learned.
Chomsky (1965) conceptualized these limitations as formal constraints on
language acquisition, and the implications of this view have been explored
in detail recently in the context of cognitive development generally (e.g.,
Keil, 1981) and language acquisition in particular (e.g., Pinker, 1984; Wexler
&Culicover, 1980).
The eventual contribution of the formal constraints approach to the sci-
entific understanding of cognitive development remains to be seen, but at
the moment it runs into all of the problems associated with formal com-
putational approaches that we reviewed in chapter 3. For example, the
learnability theory proposed by Wexler and Culicover (1980) consists of a
language-learning mechanism that uses a trial and error process to test
hypotheses about possible formal grammars, rather than observable prop-
erties of natural languages. The child obviously receives speech but the
datum received by Wexler's and Culicover's learning device is a formal
description consisting of a deep structure phrase marker and a surface string
derived by a transformational component applied to the former. They could
have developed the theory using some other formal grammar, but this
would not change the argument. The problem is that formal grammars are
not natural languages, they are theories that attempt to characterize natural
languages. The step from natural language to the formal description is not
bridged by formal learnability theory, it is simply assumed. The theory
might show how a computer could be programmed to choose among alter-
native formal grammars but as an explanation it appears to be circular and
irrelevant to the question of how a child learns a vocabulary and how it uses
it for communicative purposes in particular situations. Wexler and Culi-
cover (1980, p. 493) recognize that language learnability theory is not a the-
ory of language development in children, but they do suggest that the con-
straints that operate in linguistic theory also operate in the grammars of
children. There is no evidence to justify such an assumption and there
seems to be no way to test it because formal constraints apply only within
a formal system. The formal constraints approach to other areas of cognitive
development is similarly circular and limited as an explanatory theory to
the extent that it remains wedded to formal criteria.
The approach taken here is guided by the general empiricist assumption
that the specific things that individuals know and can do with that knowl-
edge (the content and functional properties of internal representations) must
86 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
Learning mechanisms
The development of mental representations that correspond to environ-
mental objects and events and linguistic patterns obviously requires expo-
sure to such stimuli, but the precise nature of the effective experience is less
clear. The candidates are classical and operant conditioning, which depend
on reinforcement, and sensory conditioning and perceptual learning, which
do not. In fact, sensory conditioning and perceptual (or observational)
learning can be considered as variants of simple experiential contiguity,
with the addition that perceptual learning implies an active observer (Ban-
dura, 1977; I. Brown, 1979). What relevant evidence do we have?
Beritoff (1965) emphasized the role of sensory and classical conditioning
in the development of imaginal representations ("psychoneural com-
plexes"), supported by evidence from animal studies. More recent studies
of animal behavior provide strong evidence for conditioned representations
that are image-like in the sense that they can be aroused by their associates
and function as the original stimuli in a variety of situations (e.g., see Hol-
land, 1983; Rescorla, Grau, & Durlach, 1985). Some human studies also
suggest that imagery can be classically conditioned to nonverbal and verbal
stimuli (e.g., Ellson, 1941; Leuba, 1940; Lohr, 1976). Sensory conditioning
(object-word pairing) may also be sufficient (Begg, 1976), although it has
been surprisingly difficult to demonstrate such effects experimentally (Phi-
lipchalk, 1971). The proponents of the classical conditioning approach refer
to images as conditioned sensations or perceptions (e.g., King, 1973;
Mowrer, 1960; Sheffield, 1961; Staats, 1961). Skinner (1953, 1957), on the
other hand, emphasized the response characteristics of perception itself and
accordingly interpreted visual imagery in terms of operant conditioning,
referring to it as operant seeing.
Bugelski (1982) presented a thoughtful review of the relation between
learning and imagery in which he highlights the continued importance of
understanding learning mechanisms if we are to understand imagery, and
vice versa. He views images as associations formed between neural events
as a result of co-occurrence over a sufficient time period. Thus, images are
conditioned, sensory neural activities that normally occur on the occasion
of some conditioned stimulus. Moreover, the relation between imagery and
conditioning is reciprocal, so that all imagery is said to be conditioning and
all conditioning is the formation of images with or without accompanying
subjective experience. An interesting feature, based on proposals by Mowrer
(1960) on the function of proprioceptive stimuli and Greenwald (1970) on
ideomotor action, is the suggestion that proprioception, or kinesthetic
neural activity, is qualitatively the same as imagery and that such activity
can move forward in time to serve as a conditioned stimulus to initiate
Development of Representational Systems 87
DEVELOPMENTAL SEQUENCE
processes that are brought into play when the child's language skills extend
beyond the one-word stage.
be confident about the causal factors (for a relevant review, see Terrace,
1985). The general problem comes up again later in connection with the role
of nonverbal experience in the development of grammatical skills.
related to the grammars in various ways. The most relevant of these was a
syntax-correlated condition, in which the syntactic constraints of the lan-
guage were also mirrored in the logical constraints of the pictures. For exam-
ple, the "words" in the 1973 experiment were grouped into classes so that
some words referred to rectangles of different colors, others to various non-
rectangular forms, others to changes in orientation or shape of the rectangle,
and still others to variations in the borders of the shapes.
The results showed that learning was generally best under the syntax-cor-
related conditions. The effect was particularly striking in the 1973 study,
where subjects in a words-only condition were unable to learn a complex
grammar even when they had seen a total of 3,200 instances of correct sen-
tences. In contrast, subjects in the syntax-correlated condition did very well.
The experiment showed in addition that, once the syntax had been learned
in the context of pictures, the syntactic class membership of new words
could be learned in a purely verbal context. The dependence of initial syn-
tactic learning on correlated referents and the freedom of later learning from
such dependence are both consistent with the dual coding hypothesis. It is
relevant, too, that a later study (Mori & Moeser, 1983) showed that subjects
learning an artificial language ignored syntactic markers when the language
was learned in the context of semantic referents, as in the earlier studies, but
subjects were able to use the syntactic markers effectively when referents
were not used during learning.
This completes our survey of developmental issues and evidence from the
dual coding perspective. Further relevant evidence will be mentioned in the
context of the following chapter, which deals with individual differences in
representational skills.
6
Individual Differences
96
Individual Differences 97
associated with the definition of similarity, and other issues that need not
detain us here. As evidence for the theory, Ferguson (1956, pp. 127-129)
cited experiments showing substantial and systematic changes in the factor
structure of a learning task with continued practice, so that abilities
involved at one stage differ from those involved at another stage. Other
studies showed markedly different ability patterns for children reared in
relatively isolated regions as compared to urban communities.
The emphasis on experiential factors in Ferguson's theory is especially
compatible with the present approach, and transfer as interpreted by him
provides a possible mechanism whereby experience has its differential
cumulative effects. However, the specific theoretical approach to which we
now turn does not depend on the validity of Ferguson's general theory. It
simply provides an acceptable point of departure.
sley, & Klare, 1978). Guilford (1974) has defended his general approach, and
he is increasingly sensitive to the need for a combination of multivariate
experimental and factor-analytic research in order to better identify infor-
mation-processing functions (Guilford, 1982). In any case, the important
point for our purposes is that the SI model is the most general of existing
approaches to the study of individual differences and the richest source of
data for evaluating dual coding theory. A conceptual comparison of the two
approaches is accordingly warranted without getting into the methodologi-
cal issues that others have addressed.
First of all, there is no one-to-one correspondence in the conceptual cat-
egories used in the two theories. Instead, dual coding categories generally
map onto two or more SI categories, and vice versa. The following are some
of the salient differences. First, unlike dual coding, the SI model does not
draw a major distinction between verbal and nonverbal content categories
or processes. It turns out, however, that most of the SI tests that use verbal
materials and processing define factors that fall under symbolic and seman-
tic content categories, whereas most of the nonverbal tests fall into the fig-
ural categories. Some of Guilford's tests are also mixtures in that the mate-
rial may be nonverbal but the task requires verbal processing or vice versa.
In the dual coding framework, such tasks initially depend on referential pro-
cessing, followed perhaps by additional cognitive processing by one repre-
sentational system or the other.
The two approaches also differ in the way they define the terms symbolic
and semantic. Guilford (1967) defines symbolic information as being "in the
form of signs, materials, the elements having no significance in and of them-
selves, such as letters, numbers, musical notations, and other 'code' ele-
ments" (p. 227). In dual coding theory, however, symbols do have signifi-
cance in that they correspond to cognitive representations and they "stand
for" something else in the sense that they can activate other representations.
Moreover, pictures and images are viewed as having a symbolic function
along with the more verbal symbolic elements listed by Guilford. Guilford's
treatment of semantic information is appropriately complex (1967, pp. 227-
236) and generally similar to the present approach, including recognition of
the possibility that semantic information can be nonverbal or figural. None-
theless, there is much less emphasis in his approach on the nonverbal than
on the verbal side, and the SI semantic information tests are generally verbal
in content and processing requirements. This verbal emphasis is unlike the
emphasis on verbal-nonverbal referential relations and imaginal processing
in the dual coding approach to semantics.
The product and operation categories of SI generally have comparable
conceptual distinctions in dual coding theory, but here, too, there are differ-
ences that appear to stem from a relatively greater emphasis on processing
in the present approach. The emphasis shows up specifically in the distinc-
tion between representational, referential, and associative levels of process-
ing, which has no direct counterpart in the SI model. The latter includes
Individual Differences 99
only a partial parallel in that the convergent and divergent production cat-
egories correspond primarily to the associative level in dual coding. The dif-
ferential emphasis also appears in the product categories, which are essen-
tially structural concepts in SI (e.g., relations and transformations viewed as
the end product of operations) whereas dual coding explicitly accommo-
dates both the structural and processing aspects of such concepts (e.g., trans-
formations are dynamic processes, which generate a transformed represen-
tation). Nevertheless, the difference is mainly one of conceptual emphasis,
as will be seen from the fact that many of the SI factor-defining tests provide
evidence for dual coding processing distinctions.
Other correlational and factor-analytic approaches are generally more
restricted in scope than Guilford's, but they are equally relevant to aspects
of the dual coding approach. The more prominent ones include Carroll's
(e.g., 1976) analysis of cognitive dimensions, the work of E. B. Hunt and his
collaborators (e.g., Hunt, Frost, & Lunneborg, 1973) on memory and lan-
guage processes, and the work of Das, Kirby, and Jarman (1975) on simul-
taneous and successive modes of processing. Some of these and other spe-
cific contributions will be reviewed in appropriate contexts in the following
sections.
be inferred from ability tests that require the subject to access representa-
tional information in different ways, so processes and structures generally
will not be distinguished. Again, we must rely on scattered findings because
we lack systematic evidence from comparisons of the three levels using
comparable types of tests.
Representational processing
Representational processing can be measured by tests that tap the individ-
ual's ability to recognize objects and words varying in familiarity. Thresh-
olds and reaction times for perceptual recognition are appropriate candi-
dates. Production measures such as reading latency would do only as
approximations because they involve a modality crossover from visual rep-
resentations to speech production systems for words, rather than simple
access of representations that correspond to the stimulus itself. In brief, even
at this level we run into all of the complications that motivated Morton
(1979) to elaborate his logogen model so as to include visual and auditory
input logogens as well as output logogens common to each. Reading mea-
sures also raise the further problem of finding a comparable measure on the
nonverbal side. Picture naming will not do because it clearly shifts to the
referential coding level as specified by the theory. Thus, we are left ideally
with measures that require only identification of a stimulus by recognition
or matching tests of some kind. That idealization, however, will have to be
relaxed in the present review.
The relevant factors in Guilford's model fall under cognition of figural
and symbolic units. We have already considered tests that require recogni-
tion of words under impoverished conditions (e.g., Mutilated Words). All
have the problem that they require a spoken or written naming response to
stimuli. This problem is especially serious in the case of figure completion
or closure tests that require verbal identification of mutilated pictures of
objects because this confounds representational and referential encoding.
The fact that the nonverbal completion tests load significantly (though mod-
estly) on the same factor (cognition of figural units) as comparable tests
involving words (Guilford & Hoepfner, 1971, p. 74) could mean that the
different tests are tapping a general ability to deal with representational units
on which referential ability is dependent. Be that as it may, the general fac-
tor-analytic studies have not included a sufficient number of appropriate
tests to permit "pure" verbal and nonverbal representational abilities to
emerge as factors even if such a distinction exists.
Ernest (1980) obtained results consistent with the view that Mutilated
Words and Closure Speed (with nonverbal stimuli) both implicate nonver-
bal processing related to the imagery system: Scores on both tests correlated
significantly with imagery ability as measured by spatial manipulation tests.
Mutilated Words also correlated slightly (r = .20) with a measure of verbal-
associative fluency and the verbal scale of the IDQ in one of two studies.
104 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
Associative processing
At the associative level, we again find more relevant evidence on the verbal
side than on the nonverbal side. Verbal-associative ability has been mea-
sured most often by production tasks which, in Guilford's framework, are
divided into divergent and convergent production. An example of the for-
mer is associative fluency, in which the subject is required to write as many
word associates as possible in a given time to some stimulus such as a first
letter or a word. Convergent production tasks require a unique response to
a simple or compound stimulus. An operationally clear example would be
giving a common associate to two or more stimulus words, although Guil-
ford reports that such tests divide their variance into divergent and conver-
gent production. As mentioned earlier, another problem is that some of
Guilford's tests implicate a mixture of referential and associative process-
ing, so we need to be selective in the examples we draw from his research.
The SI tests that are most relevant to verbal-associative processing ability
fall under factors involving symbolic and semantic content. Tests of sym-
bolic and semantic divergent production abilities that seem to be highly ver-
bal are Word Fluency (writing words containing a specified letter), Associ-
ational Fluency (writing synonyms to word stimuli), and Expressional
Fluency (writing different four-word sentences given a set of initial letters
for each word). Examples of convergent production ability tests that appear
to be highly verbal are: Word Group-Naming (described earlier), Associa-
tion III (writing a word similar in meaning to two given words), and Missing
Links (producing three words to complete a chain of associations between
two words).
The mixed verbal-nonverbal character of some of Guilford's factors was
illustrated earlier by the Picture-Group Naming test, which loads on a sym-
bolic convergent production factor along with verbal association and verbal
relation tests. Another less obvious example is Object Naming, in which the
stimuli are general class labels, such as minerals. Here, the associations may
be mediated by imagery, as indicated by our own factor-analytic finding
(Paivio, 1971, p. 496) that Object Naming loaded on an imagery factor
rather than one of several verbal factors. The latter were defined by more
"purely" verbal tests, including verbal fluency as measured by the number
of associations to four concrete and four abstract words. In Guilford's
research, too, symbolic and semantic factors have their strongest loadings
on verbal tests. These observations suggest that a common set of verbal-
associative abilities can be isolated, though nonverbal factors sometimes
contribute to the verbal-associative responding through referential
interconnections.
We turn now to the even more difficult problem of identifying individual
differences in nonverbal-associative processing. One of the guiding assump-
tions is that nonverbal visual information is organized synchronously (in
parallel) into higher-order structures, and that processing is governed by
108 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
Evaluative abilities could be tested by any task that requires the individ-
ual to make judgments about nonverbal or verbal information stored in
semantic or episodic memory. A clear example of the former is the symbolic
comparison task that requires one to decide which of two symbolically pre-
sented items has more or less of some property, such as size (which is larger,
a lamp or a zebral), weight (which is heavier, an apple or a baseball ?), value
(which costs more, a shirt or a toaster ?), and so on. Reaction time experi-
ments of this kind are discussed in chapter 9. Individual differences were
studied in many of these experiments, and one correlational study has been
reported (Paivio, 1980, pp. 142-152). The latter used paper-and-pencil tests
of symbolic comparisons of size and shape (angularity roundness) of pairs
of named objects, and comparisons of the angular separation of pairs of
clock times (in which of the following times are the minute hand and hour
hand farther apart, 9:20 or 7:50?). Performance as measured by the number
of items correctly answered in a fixed time period was correlated with a vari-
ety of other cognitive tests. A multiple regression analysis showed that Space
Relations and a verbal Inference test were significant predictors of size and
clock comparisons, with Inference being best in the case of size and Space
Relations in the case of clock comparisons. These results are relevant here
because they show clearly that verbal and spatial abilities are components
of the reflexive evaluative activity involved in symbolic comparisons, and
that the contributions of each class of ability differs, depending on the exact
nature of the information that is being analyzed and compared. A further
general point of interest is that the correlations between comparison task
performance and the other cognitive tests, though sometimes significant,
were modest (range .01 to .43) indicating that the comparison tasks require
processing abilities that are partly independent of those used in the other
tasks.
The above tasks presumably require evaluative processing of nonverbal
representational information generated to verbal cues. A simple example of
a comparable verbal evaluative task is comparisons of the relative pro-
nounceability of pairs of printed words or the names of items presented as
pictures. The task has been investigated experimentally (see chap. 9) but not
systematically from the perspective of individual differences.
Evaluative abilities are also tapped by tests that require one to "compute
over" mental representations, that is, to determine the quantitative value of
some structural aspect of representational information. Counting the win-
dows of one's house from memory is a commonsense example. A compa-
rable task in which the structural information would be the same for differ-
ent respondents is counting the corners of an imagined block letter. The
latter task has been studied experimentally (see chap. 9) and it could be used
to study individual differences, although this has not been done. Note that
the quantitative target information in such tasks presumably is not directly
represented in long-term memory, although the structural information from
which it can be computed is directly available. The tasks are complex in that
114 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
they entail mental scanning or other kinds of internal processing of the rep-
resentational information, thereby implicating component skills on which
individuals could differ.
The above examples illustrate the kinds of tasks that could be used to
measure evaluative abilities that depend on representational information.
We now turn to relevant factors and tests from Guilford's research. These
fall primarily under the evaluation category of operations, which is defined
as "Comparison of items of information in terms of variables and making
judgments concerning criterion satisfaction (correctness, identity, consis-
tency, etc.)" (Guilford & Hoepfner, 1971, p. 20). The nonverbal tests in this
category are grouped under the figural evaluation factors, and most consist
of items that require perceptual judgments rather than ones based on figural
information in long-term memory. For example, the test with the highest
factor loading on evaluation of figural units is Perceptual Speed, which
requires the respondent to find, from a set of alternatives, a pictured object
that is identical to a given one. From the present perspective, such tests
clearly implicate nonverbal and verbal evaluative processing, but the pro-
cesses generally do not operate on internal representations. The defining
tests for evaluation of figural transformations are exceptions in that they
implicate mental rotation or rearrangement of given figures, suggesting that
the figures must first be imaged.
The verbal evaluation tests generally fall under the symbolic and semantic
content cagetories. For example, evaluation of symbolic classes has been
defined most consistently by Sound Grouping, which requires one to find a
word that does not belong to a set of printed words because it sounds dif-
ferent. The judgment must be based on an analysis of the acoustic structure
of words, perhaps requiring covert pronunciation. Other potentially rele-
vant tests can be found under evaluation of symbolic relations, systems,
transformations, and implications. The interesting point in the present con-
text is that virtually all of the symbolic evaluation tests are verbal in content
and in the analytic processing they demand.
The tests for evaluation of different kinds of semantic content (units,
classes, etc.) also consist of verbal items, but many require mental compar-
isons that could be based on either verbal or nonverbal knowledge. For
example, Word Checking requires the respondent to choose one of four
words that fits a specified criterion, such as that a named object must be
manmade. The test called Best Word Class similarly requires selection of
one of four classes to which a given object best belongs (e.g., palm best
belongs to the class tree), which could be based on associations in either the
nonverbal or the verbal system. Other tests implicate interactive processing
based on both verbal and nonverbal information. For example, Verbal
Analogies III consist of such items as Traffic is to Signal as River is to (bank,
dam, canal, sandbags). The correct choice presumably depends on images
of situations that include the relevant objects and on verbal evaluation of a
functional relation between them (e.g., that signals and dams both stop
Individual Differences 115
Mnemonic abilities
The emphasis here is on abilities related to performance in episodic memory
tasks, particularly with reference to meaningful stimulus items that are pro-
cessed in some way by verbal or imaginal systems during encoding. The
mnemonic functional category is directly related to Guilford's operational
category of memory abilities, which he defines as "Fixation of newly gained
information in storage" (Guilford & Hoepmer, 1971, p. 20). Memory abil-
ities should be further divided into encoding, storage, and retrieval com-
ponents, but this breakdown does not appear in Guilford's research nor in
the ability literature in general, and so we are restricted in what can be said
about such refinements.
Let us first consider the SI memory factors and then the gaps they leave
according to the present perspective. The verbal-nonverbal distinction is
especially clear in this case in that the vast majority of tests with significant
loadings in the figural memory category use nonverbal forms or pictures of
objects as target items, whereas those in the symbolic and semantic content
categories use words or numbers (Guilford & Hoepfner, 1971, pp. 238-241).
The exceptions are generally ambiguous in that their variance is shared
between different factors and some clearly require dual (referential) process-
ing during encoding or retrieval. Thus, Books and Authors and Number-
Letter Association are designated as figural implications memory tests, but
they turn out to have even higher loadings on the corresponding semantic
and symbolic (verbal) memory factors. Conversely, two tests consisting of
nonverbal items load primarily on the symbolic or semantic content cate-
gories, but they also load on corresponding figural factors. Two others with
nonverbal items load significantly only on the semantic units and semantic
classes factors, but both implicate verbal processes: Picture Memory
requires the respondent to recall the names of studied pictures, and Picture
Class Memory is a recognition memory test in which the items to be studied
and the correct test pictures are different objects from the same object class,
so that mediation by a class label is likely to be the most efficient strategy.
It can be concluded, accordingly, that all of Guilford's most relevant mem-
ory tests and factors can be consistently classified in dual coding terms as
implicating either verbal or nonverbal processing or a referential crossover
between systems.
Other relevant points for our purposes are that memory for items (units)
is relatively distinct factorially from associative memory (implications), and
each of these from order memory tests (generally grouped under memory
116 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
Imagery-vividness
I have left imagery-vividness to the last because it does not fit neatly into
the dual coding framework despite its historical prominence and general
conceptual relevance to the theory.
The study of individual differences in the functional attributes of imagery
began with vividness. This debut is understandable in light of the emphasis
on consciousness in early structuralist and functionalist schools of psychol-
ogy: Images are conscious experiences that can vary in their vividness or
clarity, and performance on any task that depends on such images should
be predictable from individual differences in vividness. Gallon (1883) ini-
tiated the study of this attribute using a questionnaire that asked respon-
dents to think of some definite objects, such as their breakfast table, and
then answer questions concerning the brightness, definition, coloring, and
so on, of the image. Betts (1909) developed a quantifiable expansion of the
questionnaire in which subjects rated their images of various objects and
experiences on a 7-point scale ranging from "Perfectly clear and as vivid as
the actual experience" to "No image present at all, you only knowing that
you are thinking of the object." The items referred to different sensory
modalities of imagery and, as we noted earlier, Betts found a positive cor-
relation between the reported vividness for the different modalities, without
any evidence of different imagery types as defined by modality. This obser-
vation was confirmed in a later factor-analytic study by Sheehan (1967)
using a shortened version of the Betts questionnaire. Other modifications of
Galton's method have also been developed (e.g., Marks, 1972).
We have also seen that self-report measures of imagery tend to be uncor-
related with objective performance tests, and this generalization holds par-
ticularly for the vividness questionnaires (see Ernest, 1977, p. 184). The viv-
idness measures do show moderate correlations with other self-report
measures, including the imagery scale of the IDQ, but the correlation coef-
ficients are variable and often nonsignificant. Such results are disappointing
from the classical viewpoint that the functional usefulness of imagery is
linked to consciousness and, accordingly, to vividness as a prominent
dimension of conscious experience. The early research using the Gallon and
Betts questionnaires failed to show the expected relations with performance
on objective performance tests in which vividness should have been impor-
tant (e.g., Fernald, 1912). Similar failures have been common in more recent
118 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
studies as well, indicating that the effective use of imagery does not always
depend on its reported vividness or clarity.
A specific problem is that imagery-vividness is inherently a subjective
experience that cannot be directly linked to an objective correlate in the
same way as reported perceptual experiences can be matched against per-
ceptual objects. Comparisons of vividness ratings accordingly depend
entirely on the assumption that raters are using the same criteria when they
respond to the scale. In fact, vividness scales are known to be subject to
response bias, particularly among males (Ernest, 1977, p. 185). Such
research has been sparse, however, and it deserves to be pursued more
extensively using a variety of techniques. For example, measures of other
subjective attributes should be included so that any general response set
could be partialled out to yield purer measures of vividness.
Despite the empirical and logical problems associated with the vividness
tests, there is some encouraging recent evidence that the test scores some-
times can successfully predict memory performance (i.e., Marks, 1973; see
Ernest, 1977, for a review) as well as performance on other tasks presumed
to require the use of imagery (e.g., Finke, 1980; Finke & Shepard, in press;
Wallace, 1984). Further confirmation of such observations using improved
tests would buttress the case for the classical idea that imagery-vividness has
real functional significance.
Eidetic imagery is relevant in the present context because it refers to a
particularly vivid form of visual imagery in which the image seems to be
projected onto a surface, rather like a perceptual afterimage. The phenom-
enon received considerable research attention in the early decades of this
century, and again more recently when interest in it was revived by Haber
and Haber (1964). They introduced a measurement procedure that was sub-
sequently adopted by others. Their subjects were shown a standard set of
picture slides one at a time for a fixed period. After each slide, the subject
continued to look at the screen where the picture had been exposed and
answered a series of questions designed to reveal the presence of eidetic
imagery. The suggested criteria for such imagery included the experience of
an image "out there," which endured at least 40 seconds, and which the
subject described in the present tense. Accuracy of memory had previously
been considered a key criterion, but the evidence that the Habers obtained
in different studies turned out to be inconsistent on that point (see Paivio,
1971, chap. 14).
Cohen and I (Paivio & Cohen, 1979) investigated eidetic imagery as a
psychometric problem by assigning scores to each of the component tests
and then correlating and factor analyzing these along with scores from a
battery of other cognitive tests. We confirmed the presence of an eidetic fac-
tor as defined by the items that refer to the subjective experience of an exter-
nalized image. However, we found no evidence of a bimodal distribution
but obtained instead a continuous distribution of scores. Other observations
were that the memory performance items defined a factor that was relatively
Individual Differences 119
independent of the subjective eidetic factor, and that spatial abilities and
imagery-vividness tests loaded on different factors, which also were separate
from eidetic imagery. These results confirm various distinctions already dis-
cussed in earlier sections. The relevant point here is that they also raise
doubts concerning the phenomenon of eidetic imagery as traditionally inter-
preted. While a subjective eidetic factor can be identified, it seems to be
unrelated to a variety of other cognitive abilities, and only slightly and
inconsistently related to memory performance. Haber (1979), too, has
recently taken a skeptical position in regard to this over dramatized but
seductive phenomenon.
We have now concluded the analysis of individual differences in mental
representations and processes. The empirical findings show a reasonable
consistency with the general framework provided by dual coding theory,
although the gaps in relevant information are striking in all of the areas cov-
ered. I have entirely omitted any discussion of individual differences in
motivational and affective characteristics from the dual coding viewpoint
because direct evidence is lacking. An interpretive analysis would be quite
straightforward because such traits are often measured symbolically by
questionnaires, rating scales, and other verbal response techniques that
sometimes implicate imagery as well. The subjects' responses reflect the
strength of their verbal-associative and referential habits in the content
areas defined by the test items—for example questionnaire or projective
tests of needs, motives, emotions, and so on. I have used a variety of such
techniques in my research on individual differences in emotional reactions
to audiences (summarized in Paivio, 1965b) and the implications of dual
coding theory could be explored in such problem areas. In the meantime,
the cognitive aspects of individual differences will be considered again in
the subsequent chapters in the context of research evidence on the various
functional implications of dual coding and other representational theories.
7
Meaning and Semantic Memory
The aim of this chapter is to apply dual coding theory to problems of mean-
ing and semantic memory. The application is quite direct because the theory
is largely about the structure and functions of semantic memory represen-
tations. It will be useful to begin by rephrasing the theoretical assumptions
in order to appreciate their implications for the empirical studies of mean-
ing and semantic memory that follow.
MEANING
The dual coding approach to meaning adheres to the general empiricist per-
spective on which the theory is based. The psychological meaning of a stim-
ulus pattern is defined by the total set of reactions typically evoked by it.
The reactions may be verbal or nonverbal, so that the potential meaning
reactions to a word would include word associations, referent images, non-
verbal motor reactions, and affective reactions. Nonverbal objects are sim-
ilarly meaningful by virtue of the referent (descriptive) labels, motor and
emotional reactions, and associated images that they can arouse. The reac-
tion potential is, of course, a characteristic of the responding individual and
not of the stimulus, and the precise nature of that potential depends on the
experiential history of the person. Common experiences account for shared
meanings within a community. That is what is meant by the above reference
to typicality of reactions as a defining characteristic of meaning.
The actual pattern of reactions that is aroused by a stimulus in a particular
situation depends on contextual factors as well as the person's particular
semantic response repertoire. Thus, activated meaning is probabilistic and
variable over situations and people. Of course, some reactions are highly
probable within individuals and groups, which accounts for the relative sta-
bility of the meanings of such conventional stimuli as words.
The theory shares general and specific features with a variety of other
empirically based theories of meaning, but it is distinguished from any given
one by the total set of assumptions and the special emphasis placed on some
of those assumptions. The recognition that meaning is variable and contex-
tually determined is shared with contextual theories at least as old as Titch-
ener's (see Allport, 1955) and as recent as Olson's (1970). The identification
of meaning with reaction patterns is in agreement with associative and
120
Meaning and Semantic Memory 121
SEMANTIC MEMORY
First, the availability of verbal and imaginal representations is itself an
essential part of semantic memory, and the activation of such representa-
122 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
tions constitutes the first level of effective meaning. It suffices as a basis for
stimulus recognition and for judgments of familiarity or frequency. Second,
the referential interconnections correspond to traditional views of meaning
as reference, with the addition that the relationship is assumed to be bidi-
rectional (though not necessarily symmetrical). Moreover, the connections
in each direction are one-to-many and their activation is probabilistic and
dependent on the experiential history of the individual with such relations.
Finally, associative interconnections between verbal representations corre-
sponds to classical word-association approaches to meaning, with the differ-
ence that it is explicitly stated that the associations are between cognitive
representations of words (cf. Hayes-Roth & Hayes-Roth, 1977; Kiss, 1973).
The verbal-associative component of dual coding theory also corresponds
in principle to network models of the organization of the subjective lexicon.
However, the associative structure of the nonverbal system has no direct
parallel in current network approaches to semantic memory. The closest
parallel is with the idea of concept nodes, which are distinguished from lex-
ical representations in theories such as that of Collins and Loftus (1975).
The sharp difference is that such theories assume that the conceptual entities
are discrete and amodal at all levels of a conceptual hierarchy, whereas dual
coding theory assumes that they are modality specific and holistic. This
point was explicated in chapter 4 in the discussion of the analogue nature
of imagens, which correspond to entities of different sizes—parts of objects,
whole objects, objects as part of larger ensembles (scenes) and events, which
are based on prior perceptual experiences and imagery reactions. Units are
hierarchical in the sense of perceptual nested sets, and what portion of a
hierarchy is activated to generate imagery or to affect task performance
depends on contextual cues and target stimuli.
The model nonetheless accommodates the problems to which traditional
and contemporary semantic memory concepts are addressed. Associative
meaning has already been mentioned. The differences between specific and
general terms is conceptualized in terms of the organizational structure of
both systems. Within the verbal system, a given general term must share
associations with a range of specific members of the general class, and the
associations vary in probability or strength. These can be viewed as ver-
tical associations within a hierarchy. In addition, there are direct (horizon-
tal) associations among specific members of the class. These associative rela-
tions can be inferred partly from category-instance norms (Battig &
Montague, 1969) and from free-association norms (e.g., Palermo & Jenkins,
1964)—partly, because the data may also reflect the influence of nonverbal
representations activated through referential interconnections. For example,
table as a verbal response to furniture may be mediated by an image of a
table for some subjects some of the time, but not necessarily for all subjects
nor under all circumstances. The determining factors would be individual
difference variables and contextual cues. The same reasoning applies to hor-
izontal associations.
Meaning and Semantic Memory 123
Processing assumptions
Semantic memory models include special assumptions concerning pro-
cesses that operate over representational structures to permit semantic deci-
sions to be made about relations between concepts at different levels of gen-
erality. The most widely adopted assumption is that of spreading activation
over the pathways of the network (e.g., J. R. Anderson, 1983; Collins & Lof-
tus, 1975). An alternative view is that concepts are related to each other in
terms of shared features, and that semantic decisions are based on feature
matching, that is, computation of feature overlap (e.g, Smith, Shoben, &
Rips, 1974). It has been shown that the two approaches are structurally iso-
morphic (Collins & Loftus, 1975; Hollan, 1975), but they assume different
processing mechanisms, with network models emphasizing retrieval of
pathways between concepts, and feature models emphasizing comparison of
semantic elements (Smith et al., 1974). Ratcliff and McKoon (1981) failed
to confirm predictions from spreading activation models using a priming
task involving episodic memory for paragraphs. However, their data may
not be relevant to semantic memory tasks and in any case evidence from
other recent studies (e.g., de Groot, 1983; Seidenberg, Waters, Sanders, &
Langer, 1984) suggests that activation spreads automatically to close
associates.
The present theory incorporates variants of both classes of processing
assumptions. Functionally, spreading activation is assumed with respect to
referential and associative processing, where one representation activates
another via connecting pathways. A matching process is assumed in the case
of perceptual recognition, where a perceptual pattern activates and is some-
how compared with memory representations. Verbally evoked images can
also be compared with perceptual stimuli or with each other in tasks requir-
ing similarity judgments. However, the comparison process in dual coding
theory is not based on totally abstract, amodal semantic features. It is
assumed instead that a comparison can be based either on the global shape
of perceptual or semantic memory representations, or on particular percep-
tual components or dimensions of those patterns, depending on task
demands or contextual cues.Thus, judgments of the similarity of the shape
of American states (Shepard & Chipman, 1970) and of colors (Fillenbaum
& Rapoport, 1971) given only their names as cues may be achieved by a
global comparison, whereas symbolic comparisons of objects on such attri-
butes as size (e.g., Moyer, 1973; Paivio, 1975d) are based on a single dimen-
sion. The conceptualization is essentially the same as Garner's (1974) dis-
tinction between integral and dimensional processing. It may be, too, that
126 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
This section reviews illustrative studies that bear directly on dual coding
predictions concerning meaning and semantic memory processes and struc-
tures. Additional relevant studies are considered in other contexts in sub-
sequent chapters. The review emphasizes the distinction between represen-
tational, referential, and associative levels of meaning as well as
implications of the overall structural-processing model involving all three
processing levels.
Perceptual recognition
Paivio and O'Neill (1970) reasoned that perceptual identification should
depend primarily on the availability of representations corresponding to the
target stimuli rather than on further processes or associated representations
evoked by them. The problem is related to phenomena associated with the
concepts of perceptual sensitization, perceptual defence, and subception,
which imply that affective and other semantic properties of stimuli can
affect stimulus recognition, or that the properties can be identified at thresh-
olds below the recognition thresholds for the stimuli. The issues are con-
troversial and different analyses have been proposed (e.g., Erdelyi, 1974;
Zajonc, 1980). A full discussion is unnecessary here and it suffices to say
that O'Neill and I assumed that cognitive representations that are associa-
tively related to a stimulus cannot be evoked unless the stimulus is first
identified, so they cannot affect the identification process.
We accordingly predicted that word attributes related to representational
availability will affect perception, whereas referential and associative mean-
ing attributes will not. Word frequency and familiarity presumably reflect
representational availability, so they should correlate positively with ease of
identification. Word-imagery value is a measure of the availability of refer-
ent images, and verbal-associative meaningfulness (m) is a measure of the
availability of verbal associates. Neither should affect word identification.
These predictions were generally confirmed in a tachistoscopic recognition
experiment: Word frequency showed its usual positive relation to ease of
identification, word-imagery had no effect when familiarity and m were con-
trolled, and m showed a small but significant relation so that high m words
were identified somewhat more easily than low m words. These findings
were replicated in binaural and dichotic auditory recognition experiments
(O'Neill, 1971), with the difference that the effect of m was further reduced
when words were controlled on both frequency and rated familiarity. Thus,
Meaning and Semantic Memory 127
except for a small residual effect of m, the results were consistent with pre-
dictions from dual coding theory.
The absence of any effect of imagery value on perceptual recognition is
particularly noteworthy because it contrasts so sharply with the strong pos-
itive effect of the variable in a variety of episodic memory tasks. Those
effects will be reviewed in the next chapter. Here, it is relevant to mention
that the contrasting effects were obtained within a single experiment by
Winnick and Kressel (1965). They found no difference in visual duration
thresholds for concrete and abstract words but a subsequent free recall test
for the same words, administered without any further exposure to them,
showed better recall for the concrete (high imagery) words.
The above findings for imagery value appear to be contradicted by some
studies in which high imagery concrete words were reported to be identified
more easily than abstract words when presented to the left visual hemifield
(presumably implicating the right hemisphere) though not when presented
to the right field (left hemisphere). However, such an interaction can be
interpreted without reference to imaginal representations or processes sim-
ply by assuming that concrete words are represented in the right hemisphere
as well as the left, whereas abstract words are more likely to be represented
predominantly in the left hemisphere. The empirical justification and the-
oretical rationale for that suggestion are considered in chapter 12. Let it be
noted, however, that the findings from different studies are inconsistent and
that one of the most extensive studies (Boles, 1983) found no interaction
between concreteness and visual field. At the same time, Boles strongly con-
firmed the Paivio and O'Neill findings with respect to representational and
referential processing in that word familiarity was significantly related to
overall recognition whereas imagery and concreteness values were not (see
also Gernsbacher, 1984).
high frequency member of the pair 80% more often than the high frequency
synonym elicited its low frequency partner. Moreover, the asymmetry
occurred with both concrete and abstract pairs, indicating that the frequency
effect is independent of referential meaning. Name frequency also has a
powerful effect on the time it takes to name a picture (e.g., Oldfield, 1966),
and frequency effects appear in picture- and word-priming studies (e.g., Hut-
tenlocher & Kubicek, 1983; Kroll & Potter, 1984) independent of other vari-
ables to be discussed in a later section.
The above examples serve to illustrate frequency and familiarity effects
that are pervasive in semantic memory tasks requiring associative process-
ing of one kind or another. We turn now to such associative tasks without
further discussion of the contributions of representational processing as
reflected in frequency effects, except to note that the effects of the variables
to be considered are independent of frequency.
In contrast with the negative results for representational processing, the
imagery-concreteness level of words is a potent variable in semantic mem-
ory tasks. Moreover, it interacts in theoretically relevant ways with other
variables. One kind of interaction reflects the distinction between referential
and verbal-associative processing. For example, Paivio (1966) showed that
reaction time for image arousal is faster for concrete than abstract nouns, as
expected from the idea that the former have more direct functional connec-
tions with the image system than do abstract nouns. However, reaction time
to generate a verbal associate differed much less for concrete and abstract
words, suggesting that verbal-associative interconnections are more com-
parable for the two word types than are referential interactions. Janssen
(1976) demonstrated the differential effect on imagery and verbal reaction
time with rated imagery-value varied over a 7-point scale. Yuille and Paivio
(1969) extended the task to pairs of nouns differing in imagery-concreteness
level. Participants were asked to generate an image or a verbal mediator to
connect the members of each pair. Again, imagery latency varied with word-
imagery level but verbal-mediational latency did not. Completely consistent
with dual coding theory, these simple interactions are not readily explaina-
ble in terms of common coding theories without post hoc assumptions.
J. Clark (1978; 1983) tested predictions from dual coding theory in an
associative task using concrete and abstract words, and explicitly contrasted
those predictions with ones suggested by verbal-associative and conceptual-
representational (e.g., propositional) models. The task required participants
to generate discrete free associations to synonyms distributed with various
interword lags in a list. The crucial variable was the concreteness level of
the synonyms, so that half were concrete and high in imagery (e.g., revolver-
pistol) whereas others were abstract (e.g., liberty-freedom). The predictions
were based on the three models as shown in Figure 7-1.
Note that the verbal model shows that synonymous words are represented
separately in semantic memory and that they are related only through their
associations with each other and the associations they share with other word
Meaning and Semantic Memory 129
Figure 7-1. The structure of semantic similarity for three models of semantic mem-
ory according to J. Clark (1978).
The results were most consistent with the dual coding model in that asso-
ciative overlap scores were significantly higher for concrete than abstract
synonyms. The proportion of related associative responses were .35 for con-
crete synonyms and .23 for abstract synonyms, when different subjects asso-
ciated to each member of a synonym pair, and .45 and .32, respectively,
when the same subjects associated to both members of a synonym pair at
different times. Other interpretations are always possible but for our pur-
poses the study serves to illustrate the kinds of predictions that dual coding
theory suggests in regard to a semantic memory task—predictions that differ
from and were better supported empirically than predictions arising from
two other general classes of models.
It is relevant also to consider effects attributable to properties of the image
system and of individual imaginal representations on performance in refer-
ential processing tasks. One implication of dual coding theory is that the
speed with which images can be evoked by words should depend partly on
the probability distribution (uncertainty) of referent imagens. We tested this
prediction in the referential processing study by Paivio, Clark, and Digdon
(unpublished), which was described in chapter 6 from the individual differ-
ence perspective. Our measure of image uncertainty was the number of dif-
ferent objects that subjects drew to illustrate their mental images after they
had pressed the reaction-time key. These uncertainty scores correlated sig-
nificantly (r = .29) with mean image latency scores for a set of 255 items,
confirming the prediction and paralleling the effects of response uncertainty
in naming and verbal associative tasks (see further below).
Such characteristics as size and complexity of the imaged objects could
also affect reaction times, depending on task demands. The synchronous-
organization hypothesis of dual coding theory (see chap. 4) implies that ima-
gens corresponding to integrated objects are available as holistic entities.
Thus, referential access time to such imagens should not vary with com-
plexity or size, although any post-access processing of component informa-
tion could take additional time that would be affected by these attributes.
The variable results that have been obtained in different studies are gen-
erally consistent with the above analysis. Hoffmann et al. (1983) found no
correlation between image latency to words and complexity of the imaged
concepts as measured by estimates of the number of figurative features for
the concepts. In the unpublished study described above, we found no cor-
relation between image latency and rated size of the imaged objects but we
did find a low but significant correlation of .23 between latency and rated
complexity of the imaged objects. A possible interpretation is that some sub-
jects delayed pressing the reaction-time key until they were sure that they
could draw a reasonable facsimile of the image, which would result in longer
delays for more complex images. Such post-access influences presumably
were absent in the Hoffmann et al. (1983) study. Kosslyn (1980) and his
colleagues (e.g., Farah & Kosslyn, 1981) have usually found that image gen-
eration time increased with the complexity of the imaged objects and the
Meaning and Semantic Memory 131
size of the generated image. Kosslyn predicted such effects from his com-
putational model, but they could be alternatively interpreted in terms of the
kinds of post-access processes discussed here. For example, Kosslyn's imag-
ery instructions typically emphasize the importance of forming "clear and
accurate" images, which could reinforce attention to details. The use of epi-
sodic memory tasks (e.g., Farah & Kosslyn, 1981), in which subjects study
displayed objects until they think they can form accurate images of them,
could also affect response time because episodic retrieval becomes more dif-
ficult as amount of detail increases, or because subjects spend more time
deciding about the "accuracy" of their generated images as complexity
increases. These and other possibilities require further study before different
models can be appropriately evaluated.
However, the inference is not necessarily correct for all tasks. General terms
such as furniture and insect are rated high on concreteness and imagery
value (Paivio, Yuille, & Madigan, 1968). Moreover, there are at least two
ways in which general information could be represented in images. One is
by a grouping of category instances so that, for example, a general category
such as fruit might be imaged as a basket containing different kinds of fruit
(cf. Paivio, 1971, chap. 3). The other is a representation of general infor-
mation by imaged exemplars (cf. Anderson & McGaw, 1973), which serve
as category prototypes in Rosch's (1975b) sense.
Dual coding theory actually suggests that decisions about general infor-
mation might be made on the basis of either general terms or concrete (ima-
ginal or perceptual) representations, depending on task demands. If verbal
processing is emphasized by contextual cues or instructions, participants
may rely primarily on associative relations within the verbal system, such
as the association between sparrow and bird. If perceptual characteristics
and imagery are made salient, performance might be based on imaginal
structures and associations, or on referential relations between representa-
tions in the two systems. The following studies illustrate some of the
possibilities.
Friedman and Bourne (1976) presented subjects with pictures or verbal
labels of object pairs that were either the same or different in their category
memberships (e.g., both animals or not) or in physical size (e.g., both either
large or small, as compared to one large and one small). They found that
both category and size judgments were faster with pictures than words. They
interpreted this finding to be inconsistent with dual coding theory because
they assumed that the theory predicts that category judgments should be
faster with words than pictures. They accordingly attributed the picture-
word difference to a picture advantage in perceptual discrimination. Pelle-
grino, Rosinski, Chiesi, and Siegal (1977) obtained a similar result with a
task requiring size or category judgments of single stimuli in relation to a
predefined reference point. They suggested that the picture superiority is due
simply to the extra acoustic-phonemic decoding step that is required before
words can be processed at the semantic level. The semantic decisions them-
selves are mediated by a memory system common to both pictures and
words.
The above results are also quite consistent with dual coding theory, for
reasons presented earlier. Indeed, the Pellegrino et al. (1977) hypothesis is
formally equivalent to a dual coding interpretation of performance in tasks
that depend on nonverbal information for their execution. Like Friedman
and Bourne, however, Pellegrino et al. (1977) assumed that the common
semantic memory representations are conceptual and abstract, rather than
being imaginal and modality specific. Their studies did not permit one to
distinguish between the alternative interpretations.
Te Linde (1982) attempted to tease the alternatives apart using the Fried-
man and Bourne (1976) procedure, and asking participants to make judg-
Meaning and Semantic Memory 133
names in a lexical decision task. In one experiment, the primes were con-
ceptually identical, associatively related, or unrelated to the target words. In
another, the target words were related to the primes in different ways: cate-
gory labels (e.g., bear-animal as the prime-target pair), verbs (e.g., broom-
sweep), adjective (needle-sharp), members of a compound (e.g., telephone-
call), or a general term (e.g., dress-fashion, clock-time). The critical result
was that, in all of these conditions, related pictures (as compared to unre-
lated ones) primed the word targets at least as effectively as word primes.
Vanderwart's interpretation was that the results are consistent with a single
system of semantic representation rather than form-specific systems.
It is particularly important to evaluate carefully the basis for the negative
conclusion regarding form-specific systems because it was directed explicitly
at dual coding theory and serves as a paradigm case for such criticisms.
Thus, Vanderwart stated that the picture-priming results "are clearly not
consistent with Paivio's (1971) dual-coding theory which maintained that
time-consuming intersystem translation would cause cross-form priming to
be less than within-form priming, particularly for abstract targets" (1984, p.
79). She then added (p. 80, footnote 3) that her data refuted even the more
recent formulation of the theory according to which abstract attributes that
pertain to qualities of objects can be processed by the image system. If this
were true, she argued, then an interaction effect should have occurred in
which targets that more directly represent dimensions of objects (e.g., adjec-
tives) show more evidence of image processing (i.e., a relative picture-prim-
ing advantage) than other dimensions. That interaction was absent.
Vanderwart's conclusion is not an inappropriate inference from the ear-
lier versions of dual coding theory. I had suggested (1971, chap. 3) that
imaging to abstract nouns, adjectives, prepositions, etc., requires concreti-
zation which might usually occur via verbal-associative processing. For
example, one images to "religion" by first thinking of the verbal associate
"church." If we assume that this interpretation applies to picture-word rela-
tions, Vanderwart's conclusion is correct. However, the 1971 analysis also
allowed for the development of more direct associations between images
and abstract terms that are frequently used in association with concrete
referents, e.g., "liberty" and the Statue of Liberty for Americans. Though
not explicitly stated at that time, the analysis was obviously intended to
encompass any word class. Still, my guess at that time was that such direct
activation of images by abstract terms is less likely than mediated activation
by more concrete associates, which could turn out to be wrong.
It was also recognized explicitly in the 1971 formulation that objects have
different referential labels varying in strength or probability of occurrence
in a manner similar to verbal-associative hierarchies. The precise nature
and range of such referential hierarchies was left for future research to deter-
mine, although picture-naming studies already provided considerable infor-
mation. What is especially lacking is information on contextual modifica-
tion of the probabilities with which different referential reactions occur, as
138 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
The empirical ambiguities in the above studies (as well as the bilingual
processing studies reviewed in chap. 11) were noted by several commenta-
tors in the same journal issue (Glucksberg, 1984; Kolers & Brison, 1984;
Snodgrass, 1984). Among these, Snodgrass proposed a resolution in terms
of a three-level model in which the first two levels correspond essentially to
the general features of dual coding theory and the third is an abstract, amo-
dal representational system that can be accessed from either of the two
modality-specific systems. The general processing assumption is that sub-
jects are flexible in their processing strategies, so that they can use the second
or third level according to task demands. Thus, results such as those of Kroll
and Potter (1984) would be explained in terms of level-two processing and
one's like Vanderwart's (1984) in terms of level-three processing. The main
problem with this approach is that it presently lacks independent means for
specifying when the different processing levels will be used. Without such
specification, the theory has unlimited power and is essentially untestable
because any outcome can be accommodated post hoc by resorting to one or
the other level of processing. Dual coding theory also is flexible but it is
based on principled assumptions and operational processes that permit it to
be tested, not always with positive outcomes, as we shall see later.
This completes the review of dual coding theory as an approach to prob-
lems of meaning and semantic memory. It differs from other contemporary
approaches primarily in its emphasis on modality-specific, symbolic infor-
mation about objects, events, and reactions to them as the psychological
basis of meaning and semantic decisions. The theory accounts for general
and abstract meanings in such terms without resorting to such amodal con-
ceptual entities as abstract semantic features and more complex proposi-
tional representations. This is not to deny the usefulness of features, prop-
ositions, and the like as concepts that describe the information that is
assumed to be psychologically coded as perceptual, motor, affective, and
verbal memories. Such abstract entities simply play no explanatory role in
the theory. The issues will be considered further along with more evidence
in subsequent chapters, including the following one, which focuses on epi-
sodic memory.
8
Episodic Memory
140
Episodic Memory 141
Dual coding also differs from schema theories, which assume that the
memory trace is amodal, propositional, or script-like. Nonetheless, the pres-
ent approach incorporates the idea that the trace is schematic, in the sense
that it is both incomplete and systematically altered; incomplete, because of
inherent structural limitations on how much information can be encoded
and stored, and because encoding processes are necessarily selective; altered,
because representational information generated from long-term memory is
added to the composite trace. The changes are systematic in ways that are
yet to be fully understood.
The present theory also includes specific assumptions concerning the
organization of nonverbal and verbal information in episodic storage. These
assumptions derive directly from the general assumption that the nonverbal
(image) system is specialized for processing spatial and synchronous infor-
mation whereas the verbal system is specialized for sequential processing.
With respect to the episodic trace, the nonverbal, visual trace information
about a unitary object or an organized scene, whether derived from external
objects or imagery-encoding activity, is characterized by its spatial organi-
zation and synchronous (simultaneous) availability. The corollary is that
order information about a series of objects or pictures should be poorly
retained unless encoding activity adds information from which the sequen-
tial order can be reconstructed. Verbal labeling of the objects is one way of
achieving this, but other possibilities are discussed below as well.
In contrast, the information in a verbal trace is assumed to be organized
sequentially, so that the presented order of a list of words is relatively well-
retained. The sequential organization is attributable to the auditory-motor
(phonemic) nature of verbal memory representations and the processes that
operate on them, which implies that printed words must be phonemically
coded if list order is to be well-retained. A general implication is that
sequential memory effects should be dependent on how directly the pho-
nemic code can be accessed from the stimuli.
Other storage issues concern the mnemonic efficiency and durability of
the memory trace. A strong implication of the independence hypothesis of
imaginal and verbal codes is that dually-coded items will be remembered
better than unitarily coded items. This implication is a simple quantitative
consequence of additivity of independent components of a memory trace.
We shall also see that the nonverbal trace component, at least if it is visual,
leads to better memory performance than the verbal component, both indi-
vidually and in their additive combination when items are encoded dually.
However, dual coding theory contains no primitive assumptions that would
suggest that imaginal and verbal episodic traces differ in rate of forgetting,
and no simple empirical generalization is possible because relevant studies
have produced different patterns of results (e.g., Begg & Robertson, 1973;
Deffenbacher, Carr, & Leu, 1981; Hasher, Ricbman, & Wren, 1976; M. J.
Peterson, 1975; Postman & Burns, 1973, 1974).
Episodic Memory 143
ENCODING ASSUMPTIONS
All memory theories assume that the memory trace is a product of encoding
activity. In dual coding theory, the encoding possibilities follow the struc-
tural and processing assumptions of the general model. Thus, a target item
can be encoded to representational, referential, or associative levels. Rep-
resentational encoding implies that a given item generates a perceptual
memory trace that preserves the structural attributes of the input item. For
example, printed words and pictures set up visual traces, and auditory
words and environmental sounds set up auditory traces. The encoding can
be quite elaborate even at this stage because the presented item generates a
specific new trace and also activates a "similar" mental representation from
semantic memory. The "new" trace corresponds to what is traditionally
meant by iconic or sensory memory as well as short-term memory because
it is assumed that the trace retains sensory information for a longer period
than is usually attributed to iconic memory (cf. Paivio & Bleasdale, 1974).
If the input item is completely novel, as in early learning by the infant or as
approximated if adults are presented unfamiliar stimulus patterns, the trace
is correspondingly new and relatively unelaborated. Its effective duration is
also relatively brief, although aspects of the trace may persist for some time
to constitute the beginning of a stable mental representation. The issue here
parallels Hebb's distinction between a short-term activity trace and a long-
term structural trace, a distinction that he later questioned (Hebb, 1961)
because of his own evidence that novel sequential patterns set up a memory
trace that is not disrupted by subsequent items to the degree that he
expected if the trace consisted only of temporary (reverberatory) activity.
We need not take a strong stand on the issue here, although it remains
important for memory theories in general.
A further complication is that printed words are ordinarily coded
promptly into an auditory-motor (phonemic) form in a manner analogous
to imaginal-verbal referential encoding. Whether such recoding is automatic
or not is an open question in reading research, but in any event it is clear
that reading is commonly associated with articulatory and auditory activity.
The occurrence of such activity is generally important theoretically because
it points to the sensory modality-specific nature of the mental representa-
tions that result from the recoding activity. The evidence is somewhat prob-
lematic for amodal representational (e.g., propositional) theories, but it is
not decisive with respect to the contrast between processing theories and
dual coding because both predict that phonemic verbal coding of printed
words is less effective than "deeper" semantic coding, at least in some tasks.
The preceding analysis also applies in principle to the relation between
different nonverbal sensory modalities. For example, familiar environmen-
tal sounds presumably activate nonverbal auditory representations rela-
tively directly and might also activate visual images of the corresponding
objects: The ring of a telephone and the sound of laughter are recognized
144 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
and are memorable to some degree as distinctive sounds, but they also tend
to evoke visual images of a telephone and a laughing person. It may be more
appropriate theoretically to view such sensory elaboration within symbolic
modalities as a special type of associative processing rather than represen-
tational processing, but the conceptual distinction is unimportant as long as
it is recognized that such processing activity is relevant to episodic memory
performance in some tasks.
Referential encoding
Referential encoding activity produces referentially related verbal and non-
verbal memory trace components. Such a dual trace can arise, for example,
if an object or picture is presented together with its name, or if the subject
names a presented picture or generates a referential image to a word. The
subject-generated memory representations are assumed to be functionally
equivalent to representations that are directly elicited by presented items in
the sense that an image of an object generated to its name has the same
mnemonic properties as the image evoked by the object itself, and likewise
for generated and presented verbal labels. The parallel refers to the nature
of the information that can be retrieved from verbal and nonverbal traces
(see further below) and the relative mnemonic value of the two types of
codes. For example, visual images that are elicited by pictures (representa-
tional coding) or generated to their names (referential encoding), are percep-
tual memory representations that contain information about the spatial
properties and appearance of the remembered objects, whereas a verbal epi-
sodic memory trace, however generated, does not contain such information
directly.
Associative encoding
Associative encoding entails elaborative processing within either symbolic
modality, so that the resulting memory trace includes information about
more than one verbal or nonverbal item. Associative encoding occurs to
some extent in all list-learning tasks, but paired-associate learning is the par-
adigm case and serves as the principal example in the present discussion.
Organizational effects, elaborative encoding at the word or sentence level,
schemas, and so on, are also accounted for at the associative level of
encoding.
Like referential encoding, associative encoding can be based directly on
representations corresponding to the input items, or a combination of these
together with representations generated from semantic memory. Thus,
direct (new) associations begin to develop between verbal traces evoked by
a pair of contiguously presented words, or between nonverbal traces evoked
by pictured objects, even if the pair members are not associated through
prior experience. If they are associated, the contiguous presentation alone
Episodic Memory 145
RETRIEVAL PROCESSES
& Bleasdale, 1974). Thus, recognition accuracy remains high over a longer
test interval if the distractors are dissimilar to the target than if they are
similar. Confusion errors are a function of both physical similarity and func-
tional or conceptual similarity (e.g., Anisfeld & Knapp, 1968; Frost, 1972;
Nelson, 1981; Underwood, 1965). In terms of the present analysis, the con-
ceptual similarity effects are based on verbal or nonverbal encoding reac-
tions that are stored as part of the trace.
Finally, retrieval effects are assumed to be an interactive function of the
structure of the stored trace and the demands of the retrieval task. For exam-
ple, the degree of trace integration is crucial to redintegration of the entire
compound trace by a retrieval cue, as indicated by the positive effect of
interactive pictures or interactive imagery instructions on cued recall. The
degree of integration is relatively ineffective in noncued item recall or rec-
ognition tasks, and integration may even hinder performance in tasks
requiring discrimination between different items (Begg, 1982). This analysis
is particularly relevant to dual coding theory because its organizational
assumptions suggest differences in the nature and degree of integration that
is possible within verbal and nonverbal memory structures, differences that
lead to predictions of interactive effects of theoretically relevant empirical
variables and task demands.
Let us summarize the principal theoretical assumptions before turning to
the empirical evidence. According to dual coding theory, the episodic mem-
ory trace is a conglomerate of modality-specific information (rather than
amodal or propositional information) based on internal and external
sources. The trace is generated through some combination of representa-
tional, referential, and associative process activity. Retrieval of target infor-
mation is influenced by the similarity relation between the trace compo-
nents evoked by the retrieval cue and the encoding pattern resulting from
all factors operating during the original episodic experience, as well as by
associative factors. A number of more specific assumptions are related to
the special status attributed to the distinction between verbal and nonverbal
events and the memory systems that are specialized for dealing with the two
kinds of information, along with the sensory distinction. These include: (a)
distinctiveness (modality specificity) of verbal and nonverbal memory
codes, (b) independence and additivity of their joint effects in some tasks,
(c) differences in the way that complex verbal and nonverbal information is
organized in storage, and (d) retrieval differences associated with the orga-
nizational distinctions and task demands.
EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE
Predictions and interpretations based on the above assumptions will now
be evaluated using the operational procedures associated with the dual cod-
ing approach, with emphasis on the effects of relevant stimulus attributes
Episodic Memory 149
tion (see also Dosher & Russo, 1976). However, the reverse effect has also
been observed. Data from dual coding research incidentally revealed that
verbal recall was higher for pictures or words (picture labels) that had been
explicitly repeated (picture-picture, picture-word, word-word) than for once-
presented pictures or words that subjects repeated by generating imaginal or
verbal codes to them, even when the images and verbal codes were exter-
nalized as drawings and written words (e.g., Paivio, 1975a, Fig. 1, p. 191).
Thus, an additional experimenter-provided item contributed more to recall
than did equivalent subject-generated (internal source) information. A
related observation comes from unpublished studies done in collaboration
with Wallace Lambert and James Clark. Subjects in these studies were
required to generate translation equivalents (French or English) or syn-
onyms to stimulus words and then recall either the elaborated-on stimulus
or the generated response. Recall in all cases was at least as high and usually
higher for the stimulus than the response. The reasons for the different pat-
terns of effects are not yet clear, but for present purposes they illustrate that
external and internal sources of information can contribute differentially to
recall.
The above experiments indicate that subjects are able somehow to distin-
guish between external and internal sources of information. How this is
done has been the focus of research by Marcia Johnson and her colleagues
(e.g., Johnson, 1983; Johnson, Kahan, &Raye, 1984; Johnson &Raye, 1981;
see also R. E. Anderson, 1984) on what they call "reality monitoring," which
refers to processes that people use to decide whether remembered informa-
tion had an external or internal source. Some of the differences that play a
role in the decisions are that external memories include more contextual,
sensory, and semantic details, whereas internal memories include more
information about cognitive operations. Such differences can lead to mem-
ory traces that preserve source information very well, but confusion is
increased by semantic and sensory similarity between memories from the
two sources. This kind of confusion is particularly relevant here because it
suggests that the two sources of trace information are functionally equiva-
lent, that is, they can contain similar (confusible) information, including
modality-specific sensory information. A related phenomenon, modality-
specific interference, will be discussed in more detail shortly.
In addition to the above effects, the two sources of information may com-
bine in ways that suggest some kind effusion or modification of source com-
ponents in the memory trace. Tulving (1983) presents a systematic analysis
of this idea in terms of the process of ecphory, which he defines as a con-
structive activity that combines the episodic information from the engram
(memory trace) and the semantic memory information from the retrieval
cue. In Tulving's theory, ecphory plays a central role in retrieval along with
the process by which the ecphoric information is converted into a recollec-
tive experience or overt memory performance. He describes similar ideas
by others and cites indirect or suggestive evidence for ecphory, such as
152 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
changes in memory for a perceptual episode after subjects have been pre-
sented misleading verbal information relevant to some aspect of the episode
(Loftus & Loftus, 1980).
In a later section, I present more direct evidence for the present version
of the dual-source hypothesis, showing that internal and external source
information can be functionally equivalent and that they can combine in
their effect on performance.
learning. The effect occurred even when the stimuli were highly meaningful
words that were conceptually distinct, suggesting that the physical similarity
effect was largely automatic. It is as though the subjects could not turn off a
physical analogue (shape) processor operating at the verbal stimulus and
representational level, despite the distinctiveness of the items in terms of
referential and associative meaning.
The following studies are especially relevant to dual coding theory
because they demonstrated positive or negative similarity effects that were
presumably based on imagery and verbal encodings. Groninger and Gron-
inger (1982) required their subjects to encode a series of concrete and
abstract nouns by spelling, defining, or generating images (which they then
described). Three weeks later, the subjects tried to recognize the words using
encoding sets that were either congruent or incongruent with those used dur-
ing initial encoding. The results showed significant (facilitative) congruence
effects for imagery encodings with concrete words and for definitional
encoding with abstract words. Moreover, in the case of imagery, recognition
was improved more for words having the same specific image during both
encoding and retrieval than for ones having different image representations.
Groninger and Groninger interpreted the results in terms of a combination
of dual coding and the Lockhart et al. (1976) view of encoding-retrieval sim-
ilarity matching in recognition memory tests. Moreover, a subsequent rep-
lication and extension enabled Groninger and Groninger (1984) to conclude
that it is the congruent content (e.g., images) rather than congruent process-
ing operations (e.g., Kolers, 1973) or similarity of gist that best accounts for
the facilitating effect of congruent encoding sets.
Conceptually similar results were obtained by Slack (1983) using sen-
tences. Subjects heard sentences in the context of either a comprehension
task or an image-generation task, and then tried to recognize the sentences
in a forced-choice recognition test in which the distractors were similar to
the targets in different ways. Image-generation instructions enhanced later
recognition, but only for semantically similar test items and only for high
imagery sentences containing concrete noun concepts. Slack argued that the
effect could not be accounted for by an alternative (semantic) model of test-
item recognition and interpreted the results to mean that subjects discrim-
inated the semantically similar items by elaborating the sentence encodings
through image processing. He did not directly test for imagery during the
recognition test, but the implication is that rather precisely encoded imagery
was reinstated as part of the retrieval context for target sentences, permitting
them to be discriminated from the semantically similar distractors.
The following experiments revealed contrasting positive and negative
effects of common imaginal encoding to different words. Recall from the
previous chapter that concrete synonyms presumably can be represented by
common referential images whereas abstract synonyms generally lack such
common representations. From this assumption, J. Clark (1984) predicted
and confirmed that repetitions of synonyms in a list would produce a greater
154 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
increment in the recall of concrete than abstract words because the concrete
synonyms would benefit from the repeated arousal of a common image. On
the other hand, despite higher overall accuracy of recall for concrete mate-
rials, more synonym confusions would be expected in memory tasks involv-
ing concrete than abstract synonyms, and this, too, has been confirmed in a
number of experiments (Anderson & Hidde, 1971; Begg & Paivio, 1969;
Kuiper & Paivio, 1977; but see also Brewer, 1975).
The above findings indicate that sensory similarity (spatial orientation),
representational-structural similarity (rhyming or visual shape), and simi-
larity of imaginal or verbal referential encodings can affect episodic memory
retrieval of either verbal or nonverbal items. The effects can be either posi-
tive or negative, depending on the nature of the memory task. It is unlikely
that all of these effects can be attributed to a correlation between sensory
similarity and associative contiguity in past experience, and, to the extent
that they cannot, the similarity effects violate the terminal meta-postulate
as discussed in chapter 3.
We turn now to evidence relevant to the more specific assumptions of
dual coding theory. First we deal with various implications of the assump-
tion that verbal and nonverbal memory systems are structurally distinct and
functionally independent, and second, with the implications of the organi-
zational assumptions of the theory.
to use particular associative strategies (Paivio & Yuille, 1969): Those ques-
tioned after one learning trial generally reported following a given strategy,
whereas those who were questioned after the second or third trial shifted
progressively away from apparently inappropriate or inefficient instruc-
tional strategies (e.g., imagery with abstract pairs, verbal mediators with
concrete pairs) and toward the pattern predicted from dual coding theory.
Second, the frequency of reported use of imagery correlates highly with
recall scores for concrete pairs but not abstract pairs. Third, reports indicat-
ing correct recall of a mediating image are associated with correct response
recall under imagery instructions (Yuille, 1973), and verbally reported recall
of the image can precede recall of the target response (May & Clayton,
1973).
Subjective reports are open to the criticism that they may not accurately
reflect the cognitive processes actually used in task performance. They may
instead be epiphenomenal correlates without any causal role, or they may
simply reflect the subjects' conformity with what they believe to be the
expected responses. Such arguments are familiar from other areas of psy-
chology (e.g., Nisbett & Wilson, 1977), and they have reappeared in the con-
text of other imagery tasks (to be considered in the next chapter) in the guise
of the use of tacit knowledge to simulate operations on images (Pylyshyn,
1981). Similar interpretations of this kind had already been considered and
rejected in regard to subjective reports of mediation strategies (Paivio,
1971). For example, if subjects used knowledge about their memory perfor-
mance as a basis for their reported strategies, performance and reports
would be expected to correlate. However, this account would not explain
why the frequency of reported use of imagery correlated with learning per-
formance, whereas verbal mediation reports did not, nor why the imagery-
performance correlation only occurred with concrete, high imagery noun
pairs (see also J. Richardson, 1978). A strong case could thus be made that
subjects' reports actually tell us something about representational processes
that play a causal role in episodic memory. A weaker conclusion is that sub-
jective reports are not decisive in themselves but, when considered together
with the experimental data, they provide compelling evidence for dual cod-
ing effects in episodic memory. Of course, the verbal reports themselves
require explanation in terms of the experiential history of the individual and
the current task, as well as analysis in terms of the cognitive mechanisms
employed (cf. Ericsson & Simon, 1984). The dual coding analysis would
emphasize verbal-referential and associative responding to the episodic
memories themselves and to the contextual cues in the postexperimental
questionnaire.
Modality-specific interference
When a perceptual task selectively disrupts performance on a concurrent
mental task (involving episodic or semantic memory processes) or vice
versa, it is generally assumed that common processing systems are invoked.
156 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
Figure 8-1. Correct recall proportions for pictures (P) and words (W) encoded
by drawing (Dr) or writing (Wr), and repeated and once-presented words encoded
imaginally (I) or verbally (V) on each presentation. Adapted from Paivio (1975a,
Figure 1).
using a subset of the studied patterns along with new distractors. Recogni-
tion performance was significantly better for the high imagery than for the
low imagery patterns. A subsequent experiment (Hall & Buckolz, 1983)
showed similarly that reproductive free-recall performance varied directly
with the imagery value of a pattern. Moreover, the effect was the same
whether or not subjects had been instructed to image the patterns. The
majority of subjects in each condition in fact reported both imaging and
verbally labelling the patterns. The dual coding interpretation of these
results is that visual imagery facilitated memory for movement patterns by
adding to a kinesthetic memory baseline. Verbal coding could have contrib-
uted as well, either by facilitating image coding or by directly mediating
retrieval of the movement pattern.
The additive effect of imaginal and verbal coding was more directly sup-
ported in an experiment by Chevalier-Girard and Wilberg (1980). Their sub-
jects were presented geometric movement patterns under a no-strategy con-
trol condition, visual imagery instructions, and imagery-plus-labelling
instructions. Free recall of the movement patterns increased dramatically
with number of codes for both immediate and delayed tests. For example,
the immediate recall probabilities (estimated from Fig. 2, p. 113 of the
article) were .48, .68, and .83 for the control, imagery, and imagery-plus-
labelling conditions, respectively. The authors suggested that the coding
Episodic Memory 163
recognition. The authors suggested that "a concrete phrase makes a good
conceptual peg because it is likely to be given a specific, stable coding and
because it tends to redintegrate the whole sentence" (1977, p. 142). Picture-
word studies have similarly demonstrated quite consistently that pictures
are superior to their concrete-noun labels as stimulus terms, although not
necessarily as response terms in paired-associate learning (Dilley & Paivio,
1968; Paivio & Yarmey, 1966; Yarmey, 1974). The conceptual-peg interpre-
tation was strongly supported recently by a stages-of-learning analysis of the
associative effects (Brainerd, Desrochers, & Howe, 1981), which located the
picture-superiority effect at the retrieval stage.
Considered together, the effects of integration variables and stimulus
imagery are clearly consistent with the hypothesis that the imagery system
is specialized for synchronous organization of separate meaningful units in
episodic memory. The interpretation was strengthened and its implications
systematically extended in a series of experiments by Ian Begg. These capi-
talized on comparisons of performance in cued and noncued memory tasks.
Begg (1972) compared free and cued recall of individual words from con-
crete phrases, such as white horse, and abstract phrases, such as basic truth.
He found that cuing by one member of the pair incremented recall relative
to the free-recall condition for the concrete phrases but not for abstract
phrases. Following a line of reasoning previously proposed by Horowitz and
Prytulak (1969), Begg concluded that the differential cuing effects can be
interpreted in terms of integrated imaginal memory traces that are redinte-
grated by high imagery words. Subsequently, Begg (1973) found that a recall
increment from free to cued recall for concrete noun pairs was greater under
integrated than separate imagery instructions. Thus, interactions of task
with item-imagery value and with integrative-imagery instructions con-
verged on the organization-redintegration hypothesis.
Begg (1982) further extended the theoretical reasoning to include cases in
which integrative imagery might actually have a negative effect. This effect
would be expected in item recognition and verbal discrimination learning,
which require discrimination in memory between a correct target item and
one or more incorrect alternatives. Embedding the target item and the incor-
rect alternatives into integrated traces should make it more difficult to
achieve such discrimination. Begg (1982) obtained the predicted negative
effects in a number of experiments.
In summary, a wide variety of findings are consistent with the hypothesis
that the imagery system is specialized for synchronous organization of mul-
tiple units of information in memory. The relevant classes of observations
are that: (a) paired-associate learning is easier if the pair members are shown
or are encoded imaginally in an interactive relation as compared to a con-
junctive (separated) relation; (b) learning is positively related to the con-
creteness or image-arousing value of the items, particularly the items that
serve as retrieval cues for their associates, and this differential effect has
been identified as a redintegration effect; (c) a recall increment from free to
Episodic Memory 169
cued recall is greater with concrete, high imagery words than with abstract
ones, and under interactive imagery than under separated imagery instruc-
tions, supporting the integrative and redintegrative capacity of imagery; (d)
these effects have been obtained with different types of materials (noun
pairs, adjective-noun pairs, pictures and picture-word pairs, sentences),
indicating that synchronous organization is a very general capacity of the
nonverbal imagery system.
Empirical and theoretical challenges to imagery organization
Some important qualifications must also be recognized. Most of the research
to date has used pairs of items and we need more information on how many
and what kinds of units can be effectively integrated in episodic memory.
Howe's (1985) test of a mathematical model of associative memory sug-
gested that three concrete words could be effectively integrated, and Baker
and Santa (1977) found that instructions to form interactive images to
groups of four successively presented words in a list of 24 concrete words
substantially increased recall relative to a standard control condition. A
number of other studies have similarly used sets of three or more items (e.g.,
Begg, 1978; Begg & Sikich, 1984; Morris & Stevens, 1974). The problem
needs to be more systematically explored in such extensions. A second qual-
ification is that the theoretical conclusions are essentially restricted to visual
imagery. That is, we know little about synchronous organization in other
modalities or across sensory modalities. One exception, suggested particu-
larly by the ability of blind subjects to profit from spatially integrative imag-
ery instructions (Jonides, Kahn, & Rozin, 1975; Kerr, 1983) is that nonvi-
sual (e.g., motor or haptic) information apparently can be integrated in the
memory trace. Finally, we have assumed that the integration-redintegration
effects in episodic memory are not attributable to verbal traces. This
assumption was justified by absence of evidence for integrative memory
with abstract verbal material. There are, however, some discordant findings
that warrant close attention.
Day and Bellezza (1983) questioned the integrated visual imagery inter-
pretation of the effects of concreteness in associative learning. Their critique
was based on experiments in which subjects were asked to form composite
images to pairs of concrete or abstract nouns, rate the clarity and vividness
of each image, and then recall the second member of each pair given the
first one as a cue. In addition, the pair members were either highly related
or unrelated according to ratings by independent judges. The critical results
were that the subjects in the recall experiment rated their composite images
to related abstract pairs (e.g., democracy-liberty) as being more vivid than
their images to unrelated concrete pairs (e.g., cheese-fur), but they nonethe-
less recalled more concrete than abstract response words. Day and Bellezza
took this as evidence against dual coding theory and the visual imagery
hypothesis, and proposed instead that the results are best explained by a
concreteness hypothesis according to which learning "is based on general
170 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
naming reactions. The crucial findings for present purposes were that, at the
fast rate, pictures were inferior to words in the sequential memory tasks
(memory span and serial learning) but not in item-memory tasks (free recall
and recognition); at the slow rate, conversely, pictures were not significantly
inferior to words in the sequential tasks and they were superior to words in
the item-memory tasks. The inferiority of pictures in fast-rate sequential
tasks is attributable to the inaccessibility of the verbal code, and their supe-
riority in slow-rate item-memory tasks is consistent with the additivity
hypothesis of dual coding theory, as discussed earlier.
We confirmed the sequential memory results using discrimination of
recency and serial reconstruction tasks, which do not require verbal
responding (Paivio, 1971, p. 237). The results have also been extended to
auditory verbal and nonverbal stimuli (Paivio, Philipchalk, & Rowe, 1975;
Philipchalk & Rowe, 1971; Rowe & Cake, 1977). Specifically, we found that
environmental sounds (of a telephone, train, clock, etc.) were inferior to
words in serial recall but not in free recall tasks. Confirmatory results were
also obtained by del Castillo and Gumenik (1972) using forms that varied
in familiarity and nameability.
A number of studies have also provided evidence relevant to both the
synchronous and sequential organizational hypotheses of dual coding the-
ory. Smythe (1970; summarized in Paivio, 1971, p. 284) followed unidirec-
tional paired-associate learning of pairs of pictures, concrete nouns, or abs-
tact nouns with both forward and backward cued-recall tests. Reaction
times for correct recall showed associative symmetry for pictures and con-
crete words, but faster forward than backward recall for abstract pairs. Thus,
recall was free from sequential constraints (e.g., synchronous) when the
image code was available but not when only the verbal code was readily
available.
Snodgrass, Burns, and Pirone (1978) referred to the differential organiza-
tion hypothesis of dual coding theory as the interaction hypothesis which
"states that pictorial memory codes are specialized for spatial structures and
verbal memory codes are specialized for temporal structures" (p. 206). They
tested the hypothesis using a pair-order recognition paradigm in which sub-
jects were shown picture pairs and word pairs in a spatial (side by side) order
or a temporal (successive) order, and were then required to recognize
whether test pairs were in the same or reverse order. In addition, pairs were
studied under either imagery or verbal coding instructions. Snodgrass et al.
(1978) developed several versions of a mathematical model that permitted
them to evaluate both item and order recognition independently. The
results of several experiments were consistent with the interaction hypoth-
esis. Moreover, the data were predicted better by two versions of the dual
coding model (deterministic and probabilistic dual coding) than by a single-
code (levels of processing) model.
Santa (1977) used a reaction-time procedure to investigate the contrasting
organizational properties of imaginal and verbal representations in short-
Episodic Memory 173
changing into the other. In the case of color, however, the change is discrete
and sudden rather than gradual. The two types of change could be induced
at the same time, so that perceived motion of a red square and a blue tri-
angle is accompanied by a gradual change in shape and a sudden change in
color, with the color always appearing to fill the contours of the changing
shape. Since the physical change in shape was also sudden, the perceived
continuous change in form must reflect a transformational capacity of the
visual system that is absent in the case of color processing. The implications
of the functional contrast remain to be directly investigated in memory
tasks.
Certain findings from auditory perceptual research are relevant to the
visual problem just discussed as well as the specific functional properties
that underlie the sequential processing capacities of the verbal system. War-
ren, Obusek, Farmer, and Warren (1969) found that subjects were unable to
report the order of four nonverbal sounds (hiss, buzz, high tone, low tone)
presented rapidly in a repetitive cycle, although they had no difficulty rec-
ognizing the individual sounds. Conversely, they were able to judge the
order of similarly presented spoken digits. These findings are obviously con-
sistent with the dual coding hypothesis concerning sequential memory. Sub-
sequently, Bregman and Campbell (1971) showed that subjects could judge
the order of tones if they were perceived as a unitary stream. Such apparent
streaming was determined by tonal similarity (membership in a common
high or low frequency range). It was also affected by the nature of the tran-
sition, so that tonal sequences were more likely to be perceived as unitary
when the frequency transitions from tone to tone, though fast, were gradual
rather than sudden. Rhythm has also been found to contribute, along with
similarity, to stream organization and sequence identification.
Bregman and Campbell (1971, pp. 248-249) also suggested that temporal
judgments are relatively easy with speech units because vocal sounds form
similarity groupings and because transitions in speech are not instanta-
neous. Accordingly, a sequence of speech sounds constitutes a unitary
stream for the speech system. To this we can add the earlier suggestion that
the sequential processing capacity of the verbal system is related to its artic-
ulatory motor properties. The specific hypothesis, then, is that the verbal
system is specialized for sequential (including sequential memory) process-
ing because of its simultaneous capacity for dealing with rapid articulatory
transformations and acoustic (tonal and rhythmic) transitions. If nonverbal
auditory sequences (e.g., music) contain similar transitions or can be simi-
larly processed (e.g., by humming), they can be effectively remembered as
well. The same generalization may be applicable to visual sequences.
SUMMARY
The evidence considered in this chapter provides a systematic, comprehen-
sive, and coherent case for the dual coding approach as well as for the con-
176 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
177
178 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
and the uses to which that information can be put. Some procedures
demand reactions to single stimuli under perceptual and imagery condi-
tions, and others, comparisons of pairs of perceived or imagined objects. A
selective and brief summary follows because the evidence has been compre-
hensively reviewed and interpreted by others (e.g., Finke, 1980, 1985; Finke
& Shepard, in press).
One approach capitalizes on the fact that perceptual responses can be
primed. For example, prior exposure to particular printed words will selec-
tively reduce tachistoscopic thresholds for the same words. The relevant
studies in the present context are ones that have used imagery to prime per-
ception. Leeper (1935) and Steinfeld (1967) showed that relevant verbal
information (e.g., a story about the sinking of a liner, which presumably
evoked imagery) facilitated recognition of fragmented objects (e.g., a frag-
mented figure of a ship). More recently, Shepard and his colleagues (e.g.,
Shepard & Metzler, 1971; Cooper, 1975) have used a similar paradigm in
which they measured the reaction time to a test stimulus when the subject
has or has not formed a preparatory visual image of the stimulus. The typ-
ical result is that the discriminative response (for example, indicating
whether a numeral is correctly oriented or a mirror image) is fast and accu-
rate when the preparatory image is appropriate, but considerably slower
when no image or an inappropriate image has been formed. Such results are
generally accepted as evidence that the mental representation aroused by the
priming condition is structurally similar to the analogous perceptual
representation.
Podgorny and Shepard (1978) provided more direct evidence for the com-
parability of imagery and perception using spatially localized probes. A sub-
ject is shown a grid with a figure, such as a block letter F, or simply imagines
such a figure on a blank grid. One or more small colored dots are presented
and the subject indicates whether or not at least one dot falls on the portion
of the grid defined as figure. The following were some of the crucial results.
Reaction time was only slightly slower (50 msec on the average) under the
imagery than the perceptual condition; error rates in both conditions were
low; reaction times showed no consistent dependence on the position of the
probe within the grid; and off-figure responses in both cases decreased in
reaction time with the distance of the probed square from the figural portion
of the grid. These and other findings (e.g., Attneave & Pierce, 1978; Farah,
1985; M. J. Peterson & Graham, 1974) are all consistent with the idea that
common representational structures underlie imagery and perception.
Psychophysical studies by Kerst and Howard (1978) and Moyer, Bradley,
Sorensen, Whiting, and Mansfield (1978) also provided information on the
quantitative similarity of perceptual and memory (presumably imaginal)
representations. Their participants were required to estimate the sizes or
lengths of stimulus objects or patterns that were presented perceptually or
only named. The functions observed under the two conditions were similar,
except that the exponent of the power function was smaller for remembered
Manipulation and Use of Representational Information 179
than perceived size. The interpretation favored by the investigators was that
memory judgments involve "re-perception" of the stimuli. Results obtained
more recently by Algom, Wolf, and Bergman (in press) using a variety of
procedures also are generally consistent with the re-perception hypothesis.
An alternative interpretation, suggested by a study of individual differences
in size estimates (McKennell, 1960), is that perceptual-size judgments of
familiar objects are themselves determined primarily by remembered size.
The relevant point for present purposes, however, is the general similarity
in the quantitative information that is available from imaginal representa-
tions and perceptual ones.
Perceptual-imaginal similarities have also been revealed by studies that
require comparisons of perceived or imaginal stimuli. Shepard (1978) used
the concept of second-order isomorphism to describe the similarity
observed in the functional relations among objects when they are perceived
as compared to when they are imagined in response to names. The conclu-
sions were based on analyses of similarity-rating data for pairs of stimuli.
The general finding was that the similarity data were statistically indistin-
guishable between the perceptual and imagery conditions for such objects
as two-dimensional shapes (e.g., of the states of the United States), spectral
colors, familiar faces, and musical sounds. Multidimensional analyses indi-
cated further that, in both conditions, subjects based their judgments on
physical properties of the objects—irregularity and other dimensions for
shape, hue for colors, and so on.
Kosslyn and his collaborators (e.g., see Kosslyn, 1981; Kosslyn, Pinker,
Smith, & Schwartz, 1979) have also provided evidence for perceptual-like
functional properties of visual imagery. The following observations illus-
trate different functions: (a) more time is required to "see" properties of
smaller than of larger images; (b) image-scanning time varies directly with
the distance between points in a spatial image; (c) larger objects "overflow"
sooner than smaller ones when the subject is asked to imagine the object
approaching the viewer; and (d) the acuity of visual imagery decreases
toward the periphery of the visual field, much as in visual perception. Also
relevant in this context is a study by Lockhead and Evans (1979), which
showed that the apparent size of a mentally imaged object decreased mon-
otonically with increases in the distance of a blank screen that was provided
as a viewing surface.
Finke's (1980) general review included evidence from his own research
showing that the functional similarity between perception and imagery in
the kinds of tasks we have been considering is clearer for vivid imagers than
for nonvivid imagers as defined by a vividness questionnaire. Recently,
Wallace (1984) reported particularly striking vividness effects on the ability
to use visual imagery to produce visual illusions. Subjects in the imagery
conditions were asked to imagine lines that were missing from illusion-
inducing figures. The results of three experiments showed that vivid imagers
consistently reported image-produced illusions, which were equal in mag-
180 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
SYMBOLIC COMPARISONS
Figure 9-1. Mean reaction time for pronounceability comparisons for (the names
of) pictures and concrete and abstract words as a function of the difference in rated
pronounceability.
ceptual and symbolic information in different ways. Both times can be pre-
sented digitally, or both as drawings of analogue clocks, or one digitally and
the other analogue. A simple prediction from dual coding theory is that
comparison times should be faster for the mixed condition than for the dig-
ital-digital condition because only the one digital time need be converted
into an imagined analogue clock in the former case. The prediction is not
trivial because precisely the reverse prediction can be derived from propo-
sitional-type theories, namely, that the digital-digital condition should be
faster than the mixed condition. Banks (1977) in fact made a conceptually
equivalent prediction in connection with size comparisons of perceptual
forms that varied in size and nonsense names that had been repeatedly asso-
ciated with the forms. The results of the Paivio (1978a) experiment con-
firmed the dual coding prediction in that comparison times were faster for
the mixed digital-analogue than for the digital-digital condition. Of course,
the comparisons were fastest for the perceptual (analogue-analogue)
condition.
The generality of the additivity of perceptual and symbolic information
was confirmed in another study (summarized in Paivio, 1980) using angu-
larity-roundness comparisons of objects presented as pictures, words, or pic-
ture-word pairs. Subjects saw pairs of items (e.g., tomato-goblet, penny-news-
paper) that differed in roundness according to normative ratings, and they
were asked to indicate which member of each pair was the rounder or more
angular. The results were that the comparison times were reliably slowest
for word-word pairs, intermediate for the mixed word-picture pairs, and
fastest for picture-picture pairs, again as expected from dual coding theory.
The theory also suggests that the difference between purely symbolic and
mixed conditions should reverse if subjects could be induced to do the com-
parison task verbally or computationally. This can be achieved in the case
of clock comparisons in which subjects are required to compare the angular
separation of the hands on two clocks. A computational algorithm can be
used to arrive at the correct answer because minutes are related to hours by
multiples of 5, and this ratio is faithfully reflected in the relative positions
of the two hands of a clock. If such a strategy were used, the comparisons
should be faster for a digital-digital than for a digital-analogue condition.
The problem was investigated in an unpublished experiment in which
subjects were instructed on the computational procedure and then were
required to apply it to comparisons of digital-digital or digital-analogue
clock times. Other subjects were asked to use imagery in the same task. Fig-
ure 9-3 shows an interaction that strongly confirmed the crucial prediction
in that comparisons were much faster for the pure digital than for the mixed
condition under computational instructions but the difference was in the
opposite direction under imagery instructions. The latter aspect differs from
the Paivio (1978a) experiment in that the mean reaction time for digital-
analogue comparisons was considerably slower under imagery instructions
than without such instructions. This could be because subjects who were
Manipulation and Use of Representational Information 185
instructed to use images thought about them as well as using them (cf. Hol-
yoak, 1977, p. 48), whereas the uninstructed subjects in the earlier experi-
ment simply used them. The results in any case demonstrate sharply con-
trasting effects when subjects do the same task using a computational
(verbal) procedure as compared to imagery.
Conceptually similar contrast effects were reported by W. J. Friedman
(1983) using comparison tasks and other procedures that required reasoning
about the months of the year. For example, two experiments required sub-
jects to decide which of two months would come next going either forward
or backward from a reference month. Friedman reasoned that this task
would most likely involve image processing. The contrasting (verbal) tasks
required subjects to recite month names covertly in order to determine a
particular temporal distance. The results showed relatively faster responses
on the former task and greater effects of temporal distance and direction on
the latter task, which Friedman interpreted as supporting the distinction
between image and verbal-list processing. Other results in the study were
also consistent with that interpretation.
concluded that kinesthetic ability was the best predictor of symbolic weight-
comparisons in our experiments.
The results are consistent with the view that the representations used in
symbolic comparisons include a modality-specific component that is shared
with or similar to the perceptual processes involved in discriminating
objects on various sensory dimensions. Thus, the individual-difference data
converge on the perceptual interpretation of processing in experimental
studies of imagery reviewed earlier. The conclusion from the present data
remain tentative, however, in view of the fact that we failed to confirm it in
a subsequent experiment. A clear implication of the modality-specific
hypothesis is that we should be able to demonstrate modality-specific cor-
relations between perceptual and symbolic comparison tasks whatever the
modality involved. For example, reaction time for perceptual-size compar-
isons should be the best predictor of symbolic-size comparisons, just as
weight comparisons were the best predictor of symbolic weight-comparison
time. We tested this in a factorial experiment using both size and weight
dimensions. The results were entirely negative in that none of the critical
correlations was significant, including those involving weight comparisons.
The failure to replicate the pattern obtained in the three previous experi-
ments on weight comparisons is particularly puzzling. It may reflect subtle
procedural changes but, if so, the modality-specific correlations are less
robust than the initial positive results led us to believe. The inconsistency
can only be resolved by further experiments. In the meantime, the positive
results remain encouraging, but tentative, in regard to the strong modality-
specific hypothesis.
include: the symbolic distance effect, faster comparison times with pictures
than words on attributes of concrete objects and the reverse on attributes of
linguistic representations, correlations between relevant individual-differ-
ence variables and symbolic comparisons, and positive effects of associa-
tive-(experiential) relatedness between pair members or between the search
cues (e.g., the comparative term) and the representations to be compared. A
modified set of conclusions will be presented following a consideration of
criticisms, additional puzzling findings, and alternative interpretations of
the various symbolic comparison phenomena.
original one. Foltz and his collaborators recognized this anomaly and pro-
posed what seems to me to be a modified dual coding interpretation based
on differences in speed of accessing different kinds of information: "In the
word condition, responses would be made more quickly by retrieving pre-
vious responses, whereas in the picture condition, responses would be made
more quickly by comparing the size of the objects on each trial. Thus, a size-
congruity effect would be observed for pictures but not words" (p. 244).
Third, my 1975 prediction was that the congruity (conflict) effect should be
absent or reduced in the case of words, that is, at least smaller than the effect
for pictures. Foltz et al. (1984) counter this by pointing out that the congru-
ity effect (incongruent RT minus congruent RT) in their infinite-set design
using words (115 ms) was larger than the effect in my picture condition (89
ms). However, these differences are based on very different mean RTs in the
two experiments—more than twice as long in the Foltz et al. (1984) exper-
iment than in mine. The proportionate (to baseline) difference was actually
greater in my experiment than in theirs, e.g., the incongruent/congruent
ratio was 1.15 for my pictures and 1.08 for their words. Fourth, in compar-
ison with same-size pairs, Foltz et al. (1984) observed only a congruity effect
and not an incongruity effect, for object names, whereas I obtained both in
the case of pictures, with the effect in each case being approximately the
same magnitude as the Foltz et al. (1984) congruity effect. This difference,
too, is left unexplained. Finally, they do not comment on my finding, crucial
to dual coding theory, that my size-congruity effect with pictures was
reversed when subjects were asked to judge the relative apparent distance
of the two pictured objects.
The above analysis shows that the dual coding interpretation of picture-
word differences in the size-congruity effect remains plausible. However, the
Foltz et al. (1984) study also revealed a general effect of perceptual-size dif-
ferences that modified symbolic comparisons regardless of the content of the
physical stimuli. I would not have predicted that general effect from dual
coding theory and some theoretical modification may be required to accom-
modate the effect after we know more about its limiting conditions through
further research.
A second general finding that seems problematic for dual coding theory is
that the symbolic distance effect occurs even when the comparisons are
made on such abstract dimensions as pleasantness and monetary value of
objects (Paivio, 1978d), intelligence and ferocity of animals (Banks & Flora,
1977; Kerst & Howard, 1977), and the goodness or pleasantness values of
abstract words (A. Friedman, 1978; Paivio, 1978d). Since imagery and ana-
logue theories assume that the distance effect is mediated by representations
that somehow represent values on continuous dimensions, the question
arises as to the nature of such analogues when the information is abstract
rather than perceptually concrete. The problem appears to be compounded
for dual coding theory by the further observation that comparison times on
pleasantness and value of objects in the Paivio (1978d) studies were faster
with pictures than words.
Manipulation and Use of Representational Information 193
The converse of the above problem occurred in the case of symbolic com-
parisons based on memory for color information. Paivio and te Linde
(1980) found that the reaction time to compare objects mentally on either
brightness or hue did not differ for pictures (uncolored line drawings) and
words. This finding was unexpected from a dual coding perspective because
color, being a perceptual attribute of things, should be more closely associ-
ated with imaginal than verbal representations. This apparent anomaly was
reinforced by the finding that imagery-ability scores did not correlate with
the comparison times. We were able to rationalize the findings because other
behavioral and neuropsychological data have independently shown that
color is a puzzling attribute. For example, De Renzie and Spinnler (1967)
found that aphasics with normal color perception showed disturbances in
their memory for object color even when the color-memory task did not
require color naming. This observation, along with others reviewed by Pai-
vio and te Linde (1980), implicates verbal mechanisms in the processing of
long-term memory information about object color more closely than in the
processing of other dimensions. The precise nature of the verbal contribu-
tion and other possible sources of the anomaly remain to be determined.
Pending such clarification, we conclude from the observations that color
information is associated as closely with verbal representations as with
object representations in long-term memory.
At first sight the color-comparison results seem consistent with abstract
representational theories, the argument being that knowledge about object
color is amodal and conceptual in nature, and equally accessible from either
pictures or words. Such an explanation would conflict with other post-hoc
propositional interpretations regarding picture superiority effects in com-
parison tasks and other semantic memory tasks. The typical claims from
the propositional perspective are that semantic memory representations are
more quickly accessed from pictures than words, or that pictures have some
perceptual-processing advantage over words. Such an account offers no
principled solution to the variable results. We have seen that dual coding
theory runs into the same problem, but it fares better than the abstract con-
ceptual approaches in that it predicts picture-word reversals on tasks that
involve verbal as compared to nonverbal attributes. The color-comparison
data are anomalous and challenging for any current theory of mental rep-
resentations. As such, they are clear evidence that dual coding predictions
can be disconfirmed, and that modifications or additions are required.
Another troublesome observation concerns the effect of transferring from
pictures to words or vice versa in comparison tasks. Paivio and Marschark
(1980) obtained asymmetrical transfer effects with animal intelligence and
object pleasantness comparisons when subjects first completed a block of
trials with one kind of material and then switched to comparisons of the
same concept pairs with the other type of material. Switching from pictures
to words appeared to have a negative effect, whereas switching from words
to pictures appeared to have a positive effect. We proposed a tentative inter-
Manipulation and Use of Representational Information 195
pretation that would be consistent with the general assumptions of dual cod-
ing theory, but our attempt turned out to be inadequate to account for
results that we obtained in subsequent experiments. Marschark, te Linde,
and I explored the generality of the apparent transfer effect using the attri-
butes of size and brightness. These attributes are interesting because both
are concrete and yet they differ in terms of the initial picture-word difference
in comparison time. That is, symbolic-size comparisons are faster with pic-
tures, whereas brightness-comparison times do not differ for pictures and
words. To our surprise, we found essentially no concept-specific transfer
with either attribute. When materials were switched but concepts remained
the same, it was as though the subjects were starting the task from scratch.
Their reaction time pattern was indistinguishable from that of subjects who
were given new concept pairs along with the switch in materials.
These results seem puzzling from the viewpoint of dual coding as well as
conceptual coding models because both suggest that some positive transfer
should occur when materials are switched because subjects would continue
to use the same imaginal or propositional representations for the compara-
tive judgments. The repeated activation of those representations would be
expected to facilitate comparisons even if new encoding processes are
required by the switch in materials.
We explored the problem further by repeating the study with the more
abstract dimension of intelligence and pleasantness. As in the original exper-
iments by Paivio and Marschark (1980), we found some evidence of con-
cept-specific transfer, revealed in this case by faster reaction times for con-
ditions in which only materials were switched than for conditions in which
both concepts and materials were switched. Moreover, the differential effect
was clearest when switching from words to pictures, at least in the case of
intelligence. Assuming that the encoding problems after the switch are
equivalent for experimental and control groups, it appears that the transfer
effect is attributable to comparison processes.
The two results to be explained are the absence of transfer effects in the
case of concrete attributes, and evidence of some asymmetrical transfer in
the case of abstract attributes. The absence of transfer can be readily explain-
able by a joint consideration of episodic and semantic memory processes.
First, repeated comparison trials with the same concept pairs and materials
results in progressively faster reaction times. This obviously is a learning
effect, which is dependent on episodic memory. That is, reaction times
decrease to the extent that subjects remember that particular word or picture
pairs had occurred before and they had made a particular response to them
(cf. the earlier discussion of the effects of repeated-pair designs in the context
of the Stroop-like size-congruity effect). Semantic memory processes are also
activated repeatedly, but their activation is not thereby facilitated to any
marked extent because they are a product of long-term learning experience
and reaction times based on them are relatively asymptotic.
196 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
MENTAL ROTATIONS
Mental rotation studies have been cited most often as support for analogue
models of mental representations. However, J. R. Anderson (1978) and oth-
ers (e.g., Yuille, 1983) have argued that propositional-computational models
could also account for the findings. That argument is plausible in the case
of mental rotation of perceptual stimuli, such as the block diagrams origi-
nally used by Shepard and Metzler (1971). A propositional account is more
dubious in the case of the rotation function obtained when subjects compare
an imaged and a perceptual stimulus, as in one experiment by Cooper and
Shepard (1973). They asked subjects to image a letter or number and then
rotate the image through a series of 45-degree angles to the verbal cues "up,"
"tip," "down," and so on, prior to the presentation of a variably oriented
perceptual-test stimulus that was to be identified as a normal or backward
version of the target character. The major result was that the reaction time
Manipulation and Use of Representational Information 197
the experimenter as well as the subject. The control is most obvious in the
Cooper and Shepard task described above, in which subjects were asked to
image an alphanumeric character and then rotate the image to verbal cues.
Thus, the task promotes referential coding and the activation of transfor-
mational processes that operate on the generated representation. The rep-
resentations and processes alike are modality-specific derivations of percep-
tual-motor experiences with the same types of objects.
Figure 9-4, Processing time for counting the corners of block letters clockwise or
counterclockwise and spelling words left-to-righl and right-to-left under perceptual
and imagery conditions.
200 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
dence tells us something about the nature of different kinds of structures and
the functions that they serve.
logical potential implies, too, that verbal processes may predominate in the
later stages of the task sequences, e.g., the so-called verification stage of dis-
covery, whereas imagery may predominate at earlier stages, at least in some
tasks.
Kaufmann (1980) presented a theory of problem solving that has much
in common with the present approach, particularly in that he emphasizes
similar functional distinctions between imagery and linguistic representa-
tions, although he also disagrees with some specific points in dual coding
theory. The agreements are that the imagery system brings together previ-
ously unrelated pieces of information that can be examined together in a
unified image (p. 124) and subjected to transformational activity (p. 155),
whereas linguistic representations are more precise, superior in sequential
organization (p. 125), and subject to processing constraints (pp. 138-139).
Kaufmann also agrees that visual imagery is crucial during the discovery
phase of problem-solving, which he deduces from his general theory in
which the functional usefulness of the two systems is related to the novelty
of the task. Thus, he views linguistic representations as more appropriate
when the task is familiar, whereas imagery becomes increasingly appropriate
and adaptive as the novelty of the task increases (p. 167).
The disagreements may be more apparent than real, resulting from differ-
ences in interpretation and emphasis. For example, Kaufmann argues (pp.
44-45) that, in contrast to my view (Paivio, 1971; p. 388), it is language
rather than imagery that lends speed to thinking. This particular claim is
difficult to evaluate because Kaufmann provides little direct evidence on
processing speed, but I can comment on the general problem. My statement
in 1971 referred essentially to transformational thinking, and I still maintain
theoretically that transformations of spatial and visual information cannot
be done rapidly by means of language alone, although some transforma-
tional problems can be solved indirectly and slowly using verbal or com-
putational reasoning if one knows the algorithm. I would now add the qual-
ification that the verbal system would be superior in problems requiring
transformations of sequential information and that the imagery system
could only mimic such transformations by encoding sequentially organized
information into a linear-spatial analogue and then reorganizing the spatial
order of elements. Finally, any theoretical perspective needs to accommo-
date different components and stages of complex tasks, some of which may
be handled more quickly and efficiently by the verbal system and others by
imagery. For example, Kaufmann and I would agree that imagery is likely
to be more efficient ("swifter") than language in encoding multiple bits of
concrete information into an integrated whole, whereas the reverse would
be expected when abstract information must be encoded and organized into
logical or grammatical sequences. These comments are also relevant to
other objections raised by Kaufmann—for example, that I have "pressed
the case for imagery too hard at the expense of language" (p. 45)—but I will
forgo a detailed examination of the contentious points and turn instead to
Manipulation and Use of Representational Information 203
some illustrative research findings. Interested readers will find a more com-
prehensive review of relevant studies in Kaufmann (1980).
of visual images (which subjects reported using) because the spatial incon-
sistency may result from retrieval or inference processes operating on spa-
tially consistent representations, or from the use of separate visual images,
each of which may individually contain spatially consistent properties.
The results of a series of experiments by Hintzman, O'Dell, and Arndt
(1981) are more difficult to reconcile with any simple analogue interpreta-
tion of cognitive maps. Hintzman et al. (1981) required their subjects to
indicate surrounding environmental target locations while imagining them-
selves in a particular spot facing in various directions. Interest centered on
the possible use of mental rotation to achieve the orientation shifts and on
the relative accessibility of locations in the cognitive map. Reaction time
and error data suggested that mental rotations were used when the spatial
information was visually presented but not when subjects relied on a mem-
orized cognitive map. In regard to the accessibility question, the response
data showed a striking M-shaped pattern, so that targets were located most
quickly when they were adjacent to or directly opposite the imagined ori-
entation, and slowest when they were in intermediate positions. Hintzman
et al. (1981) interpreted this pattern to mean that the locations were not
equally accessible, as a parallel access hypothesis would predict. These and
other results, such as practice effects for particular orientation-target pairs,
led Hintzman et al. (1981) to suggest generally that "cognitive maps are not
strictly holistic, but consist of orientation-specific representations, and—at
least in part—of relational propositions specific to object pairs" (p. 149).
The authors also cite other studies in which the investigators favored a prop-
ositional-representation hypothesis because it accounts for biases in spatial
judgments that are difficult to explain in terms of analogue maps.
Let us examine the cognitive-mapping problem from a dual coding per-
spective. The most general point to emphasize at the outset is that dual cod-
ing does not imply that synchronous cognitive maps are completely veridi-
cal (Euclidian) analogue representations of a spatial environment, nor that
performance on cognitive-mapping problems depends solely on nonverbal
representations, whatever their form. Distortions and inconsistencies occur
even in perception as a function of contextual factors, as evidenced most
clearly by visual illusions, so there is no reason to expect that cognitive
maps would be any more Euclidian in their functional properties. Verbal
processes would also be expected to play a role in cognitive-mapping
because we learn to express spatial locations, distances, and relations in lin-
guistic terms. Some of these become strong habits that serve as cardinal ref-
erence points (e.g., right, left, front, back; north, south, east, west) that guide
and sometimes bias our spatial responding, as do other heuristic devices (cf.
Lederman, Klatzky, & Barber, 1985; B. Tversky, 1981). The linguistic and
behavioral spatial habits can be described in propositional terms, but such
rephrasing adds nothing to the explanation.
As in the case of other tasks, the relative contributions of nonverbal and
verbal processes to performance in cognitive-mapping tasks would depend
Manipulation and Use of Representational Information 205
Cube visualization
The cube visualization task described in chapter 6 is another classical exam-
ple of a problem that apparently requires use of the imagery system. Per-
formers who are asked how they solved the problem invariably report using
visual imagery and it is difficult to see how it could be done otherwise,
except by laborious verbal computations. Nonetheless, the task as a whole
also requires use of the verbal system in that the performer must respond
appropriately to the verbal instructions to think of a cube of a particular
color, to slice it in certain ways, and to count the number of cubes with the
properties indicated by the question. Thus, the task demands elaborate
referential, transformational, and evaluative processing involving both sys-
tems in specifiable ways.
Syllogistic reasoning
Three-term series problems also reveal the contributions of both symbolic
systems. Subjects are given a problem such as Tom is taller than Sam. John
is shorter than Sam. Who is tallest! This task was the focus of a debate in
which some theorists (e.g.. DeSoto, London, & Handel, 1965; Huttenlocher,
1968) proposed an image-based explanation even in the case of abstract
206 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
problems, whereas others (e.g., Carpenter & Just, 1975; H. Clark, 1969) have
favored a more abstract, linguistic analysis. The upshot of the debate seems
to be that both positions are partly correct. Johnson-Laird (1972) suggested
the subject may change strategies with increasing experience with the task.
The individual may first use an image-based procedure, supplemented per-
haps by some principle of "natural order," and later switch to a procedure
more consistent with a linguistic model. Such a change would be consistent
with Kaufmann's novelty hypothesis concerning the usefulness of imagery
and linguistic representations. The effective use of different strategies can
also be modified by experimental manipulations. For example, Shaver, Pier-
son, and Lang (1974) showed that performance on three-term series prob-
lems improved when subjects were instructed to use imagery. Finally, as we
have already seen (chap. 6), individuals differ in their preferred strategies
and abilities, so that some individuals may rely on spatial imagery to solve
such problems, whereas others use a linguistic strategy (e.g., MacLeod,
Hunt, & Mathews, 1978; Sternberg, 1980; Steinberg & Weil, 1980). Such
observations are completely consistent with dual coding theory.
ginal acuity and map scanning, and identification of rotated hands after per-
ceptual or imaginal priming. In each case, perceptual-imaginal reaction time
differences varied with the experimenters' beliefs. Analysis of taped tran-
scriptions of instructions given by experimenters showed that those who
expected imagery to yield faster reactions than perceptual conditions took
more time to read the imaginal-prime portion than the perceptual-prime
portion in the hand-rotation task; and conversely for the experimenters who
expected imagery to be slower than perception.
Intons-Peterson (1983) was careful to point out that her results did not
suggest that imagery was not used in such tasks nor that previous imagery
research should be dismissed as biased. In fact, her own experiments yielded
distance functions in imaginal as well as perceptual map-scanning, and men-
tal rotation effects in the hand-rotation task, both of which are consistent
with imagery interpretations. She emphasized instead that her results argue
for the inclusion of safeguards against experimenter expectancy and demand
effects, especially in the more ambiguous and vulnerable paradigms that are
used to study imagery. Finally, she recommended that imagery researchers
use tasks that typically require mental manipulations that are difficult to
achieve without using imagery, such as comparisons of imagined figures.
Other recent studies have shown directly that the tacit knowledge hypoth-
esis is plausible in the case of imagery effects but not others. Denis and Car-
fantan (1985) gave adult subjects a questionnaire in which they were asked
to predict the typical outcomes of various imagery experiments that were
described. The subjects generally predicted correctly that imagery would
have positive effects in verbal memory, spatial reasoning, and deductive
reasoning. However, they were generally unable to predict the typical out-
comes of experiments on mental rotation, mental scanning, verification
times for properties of objects in small versus large images, and the effects
of imagery rehearsal on motor performance. Reed, Hock, and Lockhead
(1983) had people estimate lengths and mentally scan diagonal lines, spirals,
and mazes. They obtained large differences in the rate of scanning the three
configurations, regardless of whether people scanned percepts or images.
These differences could not be accounted for by differences in length esti-
mates or by the subjects' tacit knowledge of their scanning rates. The
authors concluded that their results are most consistent with the hypothesis
that people actually scan in the mental scanning task.
The above studies demonstrate that the tacit knowledge hypothesis can
be tested empirically and that the kinds of tasks that we have reviewed in
this chapter are not readily explained by it. It is also relevant to note that
the dual coding approach provides a more general and strategic defense
against the tacit cues and knowledge argument. The defense is that the the-
ory predicts different and sometimes contrasting effects under specified
experimental manipulations, effects that are difficult to explain in terms of
the experimenters' and subjects' beliefs. Examples are: the reversal of pic-
ture-word differences in symbolic comparison time with verbal and non-
Manipulation and Use of Representational Information 211
verbal attributes, the Stroop-like conflict effect for size comparisons with
pictures but not printed words, the reversal of the conflict effect when sub-
jects' judged the relative distance of pictured objects, and the reversal of
clock-comparison times for symbolic and mixed perceptual-symbolic con-
ditions when subjects used a computational strategy as compared to an
imagery strategy. Such systematic and predicted variations in effects are
comparable in principle to the different effects and relations observed in epi-
sodic memory tasks under conditions that differentially implicate verbal
and imaginal coding during task performance (see chap. 8).
Somewhat paradoxically, the above counterargument is reinforced by
negative evidence in that the experimenters' or subjects' expectations could
hardly account for our failure to obtain certain effects that we initially pre-
dicted on the basis of a dual coding analysis. We have seen that those effects
are challenging to the theory, but they require a response other than the tacit
knowledge interpretation just considered.
It is important to note, finally, that dual coding theory is not compro-
mised by evidence that the subjects' beliefs or tacit knowledge influence
their performance in some cognitive tasks. Such factors are easily inter-
preted in dual coding terms as nonverbal and verbal information about
objects and events and their behavioral affordances, information that is rep-
resented in the two symbolic systems and used when it is adaptive to do so.
The activation and use of such information implicates the same dual coding
processes as other representational phenomena that we have discussed, that
is, representational, referential, and associative processing, evaluative and
mnemonic functions, and so on, as described in chapter 4. Often the effec-
tive "belief is simply a verbal description that is evoked by the experimen-
tal conditions and that operates reflexively to modify performance on the
task. If that occurs, we could say that the task is "cognitively penetrable"
but that would not add to the explanation.
CONCLUDING COMMENTS
This chapter has reviewed some of the principle findings from studies con-
cerned with performance in tasks that require manipulation of mental rep-
resentations, or evaluation and computation of information associated with
such representations. As in the case of episodic and other semantic memory
studies reviewed in previous chapters, the findings are more consistent with
the empiricist idea that mental representations consist of modality-specific
structures, which include or can be operated on by modality-specific pro-
cesses, than they are with prepositional-computational or other abstract
conceptual approaches. More specifically, they are generally consistent with
the general assumption of the updated dual coding theory proposed in chap-
ter 4. The theory also encountered some troublesome findings that were
unpredictable from its assumptions and in one instance (symbolic color
212 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
We have already dealt with many aspects of language in the context of such
topics as memory for words or phrases, meaning and semantic memory, and
language-evoked imagery. This chapter treats language as a problem in its
own right, with emphasis on more extended behavioral segments than
words or phrases, and with particular attention to comprehension and pro-
duction of such segments. We begin with a theoretical orientation to the
topic and then turn to applications of the theory to the basic phenomena of
comprehension and production, as well as special problems associated with
figurative language. Bilingualism, also a special and complex topic, is treated
separately in the next chapter.
THEORETICAL ORIENTATION
Chapter 2 pointed out the complex relations between language and the con-
cept of representation. Language is itself a representational system that sym-
bolizes the perceptual and behavioral world, and plays an important role in
mediating our interactions with it. It is also used reflexively to symbolize
language itself. These representational and mediational functions of lan-
guage are enormously complex in their own right. The complexity is mul-
tiplied because representational theorists have found it necessary, or at least
compelling, to postulate mental representations for language. These mental
representations preserve the properties of language stimuli and reponses in
verbal-associative approaches to the topic. Largely because of the creative
nature of language behavior and the related logical argument against the so-
called terminal meta-postulate of classical associationism, the mental rep-
resentations for language became more abstract, tied in particular to the idea
of internalized generative rules. The prototype of this approach was Chom-
sky's (1965) transformational generative grammar which retained its basic
features in subsequent revisions, including his most recent theory of gov-
ernment and binding (Chomsky, 1982). Other linguistic approaches in the
1960s and seventies differed from Chomsky's mainly in their emphasis on
the semantic nature of the elements and rules of the representational system
(e.g., Fillmore, 1968; LakofT, 1971). The general characteristics of these lin-
213
214 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
system that includes only linguistic elements may require recursive rules to
generate such sentences, but a human speaker may not. Expressions of that
type have been learned and, given the basic descriptive vocabulary and a
set of prepositions and other relational terms, they can be generated pro-
ductively in any new situation because that situation contains the stimuli
for eliciting such responses.
The same general analysis can be applied to more extended linguistic con-
structions. Children in literate societies learn to categorize sentences as
affirmatives, negatives, interrogatives, and so on, because they have been
taught to do so. They have also learned to generate such sentences to verbal
instructions or transform one sentence type into another. In brief, they can
behave like transformational-generative grammarians. Again, however, the
cues for generating the different types of constructions in communicational
contexts are found in the situational and linguistic context. Younger chil-
dren and people in preliterate societies use various grammatical construc-
tions as well because they have learned to do so in such contexts when the
need arises, without necessarily knowing how to generate the different types
to instructions nor how to transform one type into another. Of course, a
transformational theory of grammar does not require the latter type of
understanding but the point here is the reverse, that productive use of dif-
ferent sentence types in the absence of intraverbal transformational skills
does not demand explanation in terms of a more abstract system of gram-
matical competence. Bowerman (1973) argued similarly that it is gratuitous
to interpret the language of young children as reflecting understanding of
such concepts as deep structure subject when the evidence does not justify
such interpretations.
Syntactic creativity can thus be explained partly by reference to changing
situational contexts together with changes in the attentional focus and
behavior of the speaker in those contexts. The explanatory potential of such
an approach is greatly enhanced by adding imaginal contexts to situational
ones. That is, imagery provides a private situational context for both the
creative production and understanding of concrete language in particular.
The apparent linguistic creativity in communicational situations arises from
a continuously shifting interplay of situational focus (where this is relevant),
intraverbal context, and imagery. The nonlinguistic perceptual and imaginal
factors free language from the finite-state limitations of associative models
precisely because we are not dealing here with fixed intraverbal associative
probabilities, but with contextual variables that can have their own inde-
pendent influence at any point during the flow of discourse.
The analysis of more abstract discourse depends on two general qualifi-
cations of the above. First, given initial learning of some syntactic construc-
tions in situational contexts, the syntactic learning can be extended to other
vocabulary even without the situational and imaginal support (for the
details of the argument and supporting evidence, see chap. 5). Second, the
creative productivity and understanding of abstract discourse depends rela-
218 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
LANGUAGE COMPREHENSION
they had understood a given sentence or when they had generated an image
to it. The main findings were, first, that imagery reaction times were signif-
icantly faster to concrete than abstract sentences although comprehension
time did not differ significantly; and second, comprehension and imagery
reaction times were more highly correlated for concrete sentences (.71) than
for abstract sentences (.60).
We interpreted these results to mean that comprehension is more depen-
dent on imagery in the case of concrete than abstract sentences. However,
no unidirectional causal dependency is assumed in the present analysis, so
the more appropriate phrasing is that imagery is more likely to be part of
the comprehension process, or that imagery and comprehension are rela-
tively more closely associated, in the concrete than the abstract case. The
temporal relations between the criterion responses for comprehension and
imagery can vary according to task demands, as evidenced by the finding
that, in one of our experiments, comprehension reaction times were gener-
ally faster than imagery reaction times even to concrete sentences, but
imagery was faster than comprehension in a second experiment that used
more complex concrete sentences. The different results in the two experi-
ments might simply reflect differences in the criterion for responding. We
suggested, for example, that subjects under the imagery set may have
responded to the complex sentences in the second experiment before read-
ing the entire sentence, whereas those under the comprehension set did not
respond until they had read the whole sentence. Concrete sentence process-
ing may have involved imagery under both instructions.
The relation between imagery value and comprehension speed has also
varied across experiments. Whereas we found no significant difference in
comprehension reaction time for concrete and abstract sentences, many
experiments have shown that concrete sentences are evaluated for truth or
meaningfulness faster than abstract sentences (Holmes & Langford, 1976;
Jorgenson & Kintsch, 1973; Klee & Eysenck, 1973). The concrete sentence
advantage has been found both when the verification task involved explicit
(paraphrase) semantic relations between stimulus sentences and verification
sentences and when it involved implicit (inference) relations (Belmore,
Yates, Bellack, Jones, & Rosenquist, 1982). On the other hand, Glass, Eddy,
and Schwanenflugel (1980) found no difference in verification latency for
sentences containing concrete and abstract words, and the decisions actually
took longer for high-imagery than for low-imagery sentences when imagery
value was defined by whether or not imagery was required to verify a state-
ment. Eddy and Glass (1981) later showed that the negative effect of sen-
tence imagery occurred only when sentences were presented visually, pre-
sumably because visual presentation interfered with imagery. The latter
observation bears on the modality-specificity of processing in comprehen-
sion tasks, to which we return below. The relevant point here is that the
effect of imagery value in comprehension tasks can vary from positive to
negative, depending on task variables and how imagery is defined.
220 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
anomalous. Such a reversal did not occur in the case of imagery ratings,
which remained higher for concrete than abstract sentences even when they
were anomalous. The dual coding interpretation is that the comprehension
of concrete sentences was affected by changes in the sensibleness of the ima-
ginal context aroused by sentence wording as well as by the wording changes
themselves, whereas comprehension of abstract sentences was affected only
by the changes in wording. Imagery ratings were less affected by anomaly
because the concrete content words could still evoke imagery, albeit of a
bizarre (nonsensible) kind. In brief, image bizarreness could account for
both the drastic reduction in sensibility and the relatively high image-arous-
ing value of anomalous concrete sentences.
An experiment by Marschark (1978, 1979) yielded another kind of evi-
dence for dual coding effects. Marschark presented passages auditorily in
such a way that the subjects could control the rate at which they heard each
word, and so that this word-by-word processing rate could be measured. The
passages consisted of high-imagery and low-imagery paragraphs that were
carefully matched on a variety of other attributes. The relevant result in the
present context was that, under instructions to comprehend the passages,
the processing time patterns were strikingly different for the different pas-
sages: Subjects spent relatively more time on the major content words of
high-imagery passages, and more time on syntactic aspects of low-imagery
passages. These results together with the results of a strategy questionnaire
completed by subjects after the experiment suggested that high-imagery lan-
guage was understood largely by visualizing its semantic content, whereas
low-imagery language was understood largely in terms of its intraverbal
patterning.
The inferences concerning imaginal and verbal processes in comprehen-
sion in the above studies were based on manipulation of the imagery value
of language materials and reported processing strategies. More direct evi-
dence for modality-specific differences in processing emerged from an exper-
iment by Klee and Eysenck (1973). Their participants listened to concrete
or abstract sentences presented concurrently with a visual- or verbal-inter-
fering task. The sentences were meaningful or anomalous, and the subjects
indicated which was which by pressing a key. The interesting result was a
significant interaction that was consistent with the dual coding hypothesis.
The comprehension latencies were longer with visual than verbal interfer-
ence for concrete sentences, and conversely, longer with verbal than visual
interference for abstract sentences. These were the results that Klee and
Eysenck expected from the hypothesis that visual imagery is used in com-
prehending concrete sentences and that image formation was disrupted by
the visual-interfering task, whereas verbal processing (e.g., arousal of verbal
associations) predominates in the case of abstract sentence comprehension
and this processing was disrupted by the verbal-interpolated task.
The Klee and Eysenck experiment has been criticized on methodological
grounds (Holmes & Langford, 1976) but without any direct demonstration
222 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
that the general pattern of results and conclusions are wrong. In fact, Eddy
and Glass (1981) and Glass, Millen, Beck, and Eddy (1985) obtained results
indicative of modality-specific (visual or visuospatial) interference effects on
the processing of sentences judged to require imagery for their verification,
thus supporting at least the image half of the Klee and Eysenck conclusions.
Sadoski (1983) also found evidence of modality-specific interference during
oral reading of parts of stories that evoked most imagery, namely, the story
climaxes (see further below).
The above experiments suffice to illustrate the dual coding approach to
comprehension. Imagery plays an essential role in the comprehension of
concrete, high imagery verbal material when comprehension depends on
knowledge about the concrete properties of objects, their actions, or their
spatial arrangements, knowledge that is directly represented only in the
imagery system. The contribution of imagery is supplemented by effects that
are attributable to verbal processes, including associative dependencies
among the words of an utterance and any further verbal associations
aroused by the wording. The effects of imagery and verbal processes are
additive, in both a positive and negative sense. Their combined effects are
positive to the extent that the verbal patterns correspond to high-probability
associative relations in the verbal-representational system and the evoked
imagery corresponds to sensible real-world scenes. The effects are negative
when the verbal patterns are anomalous and the aroused imagery is bizarre.
Such imagery processes are less probable in the case of abstract sentences,
so their comprehension depends relatively more on verbal processes alone.
In addition, comprehension of both types of material is affected by the gen-
eral verbal and nonverbal situational contexts in which they occur because
the target material and the context affect the pattern of verbal- and nonver-
bal-representational activity. Finally, individual differences in imagery and
verbal abilities and strategy preferences affect the nature of processing dur-
ing comprehension.
mation processing. That analysis and the results are also generally compat-
ible with dual coding assumptions.
close the gaps. The propositions must also be organized globally at the
macrostructure level, that is, they must be connected to the topic or theme
of the discourse or some portion of it, such as an episode. These macros-
tructures, too, are described in terms of abstract, connected propositions,
and their function in the model is to reduce the information in the text base
(the microstructure level) through deletion and different types of inferences
based on the gist of the text. The two structural levels are related by a set of
semantic-mapping rules called macrorules, which are applied under the con-
trol of a general schema. The latter is the formal representation of the read-
er's goals in reading, the clarity of which depend on such factors as the
degree to which the text is conventionalized and the degree to which the
reader reads with a special purpose in mind.
The investigations of the model have shown that highly conventionalized
story texts have well-defined, coherent structures when transformed into the
propositional descriptions. More important, the model has had considerable
success in predicting text comprehension as measured by tests of readability
and memorability (see Kintsch & van Dijk, 1978, for a summary). Such an
approach has also been used to construct structurally equivalent stories and
movies (Baggett, 1979), which were processed in similar ways by subjects in
a recall task.
The up-dated model proposed by van Dijk and Kintsch (1983) elaborates
on the above in various specific and general ways. A relevant specific change
is that coherence is now defined more generally in terms of semantic-prop-
ositional relations that take account of world knowledge. Such specific
changes are a consequence of a general elaboration of the model, which dis-
tinguishes three levels of text representation in memory, including verbatim
surface representation, a propositional textbase much as described above,
and a situational model. The last of these is "not part of the text represen-
tation proper but a model that the hearer or reader constructs about the
situation denoted by the text" (p. 337). The authors argue that situation
models are required to account for such linguistic and psychological phe-
nomena as reference, coreference, coherence, situational parameters, and
perspective.
The addition of the situational model to the general theory obviously ren-
ders it more similar to dual coding theory, which also includes situational
representations that can be experienced as imagery. There is a fundamental
difference, however: It turns out that van Dijk's and Kintsch's proposed rep-
resentational structure for situational models also has a propositional for-
mat (pp. 344-346). Thus, with reference to the representation of an acci-
dent, we have "at the top a predicate, filled with information about 'having
an accident,' and followed by a list of participants, for example, in such a
way that the agent role can be filled by the person him- or herself. . . . The
event is then localized in place, time, and conditions" (p. 345). The context
of their discussion makes it clear that the reference is to the format of the
situational model as constructed and used by the reader or hearer, and not
Language Comprehension and Production 227
simply to the theorists' descriptive format for the model (see my earlier dis-
cussion of the distinction in chap. 3). As we have repeatedly asserted, no
common representational format of this kind is assumed in dual coding
theory.
I believe that the van Dijk-Kintsch model and other propositional dis-
course models provide a useful descriptive approach to discourse structure
in terms of a common, abstract language, and to predictions when the struc-
tural description is combined with processing assumptions. The central
question here is whether they adequately describe the actual coding and pro-
cessing mechanisms involved, and whether their predictions are better than
what might be achieved by other approaches. The dual coding approach
would begin with an examination of the verbal-contextual and associative
structure of a text. Thus, the parallel to an analysis of argument repetition
or propositional (semantic) repetition would be the analysis of literal repe-
titions and associative relations between content words in the text. The
associative relations would presumably vary in remoteness. The overall ver-
bal cohesiveness of the text could then be indexed by some measure of ver-
bal-associative overlap (cf. Deese, 1965). A parallel to a hierarchical descrip-
tion might emerge from analysis of the referential generality of words in the
text. The text analysis could be supplemented by associative data obtained
from readers at different points of the text. The text and the activated asso-
ciates might even include discourse-descriptive associates such as theme,
plot, episode, and the like, depending on the subjects' prior experiences with
text analysis. This approach has a close linguistic precedent in the work of
Halliday and Hasan (1976), who described text cohesion in terms of con-
nections or ties between words in different sentences. Anaphoric preposi-
tions, repetitions, synonyms, and superordinate-subordinate relations,
among others, contribute to cohesiveness in their analysis.
The dual coding analysis of discourse processing would go beyond the
verbal level to include the imagery aroused by text material. Thus, the lin-
guistic bases for cohesion in the analyses by Kintsch and van Dijk or Hal-
liday and Hasan would now have nonlinguistic parallels in such reactions
as common referential images evoked by coreferential terms, synonyms,
and the like. Episodes would be reflected in the imaginal contexts or situa-
tions that are continuously or repeatedly evoked by associatively and con-
textually related (cohesive) wording. The overall theme or schema might be
represented partly by a relatively specific image that recurs in some form
throughout the text to recurrent verbal cues. In short, both verbal and ima-
ginal contexts and associations contribute to the reader's psychological orga-
nization of text including its overall integration or cohesiveness.
I have shown elsewhere (Paivio, 1983c) how this general approach and
specific hypotheses and assumptions of dual coding theory can be applied
to aspects of literary analysis. The precedents were analyses in which the
concept of imagery played a prominent role. For example, in her study of
Shakespeare's imagery, Caroline Spurgeon (1935) drew special attention to
228 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
the theme, events, and plot of the story, suggesting to Sadoski that it is a
thema factor that represents the essential meaning of the story. The results
and interpretation are consistent with the above analysis of the thematic,
symbolic, and retrieval (conceptual peg) functions of images in literary
works. Sadoski in fact concluded that the results are particularly supportive
of the conceptual-peg hypothesis and dual coding theory in general. The gen-
erality of the results and conclusions were confirmed in a replication study
(Sadoski, in press) that included several design modifications, including use
of an unillustrated text.
Sadoski's studies nicely illustrate how imagery and dual coding concepts
can serve as an alternative to propositional schema (or script) approaches
to text comprehension and memory. It would be easy to extend the research
in various ways designed to provide more specific tests of dual coding. For
example, measures of imaginal-referential ability, as defined in chapter 6,
might predict story climax imagery and other responses specified by
Sadoski. Such extensions would not be trivial because it could turn out that
there is something special about text-elicited imagery reactions that is not
tapped by tests that use lists of words or pictures as stimuli. The same argu-
ment applies as well to other extensions of dual coding operational proce-
dures to the text level.
LANGUAGE PRODUCTION
abstract nouns equated for familiarity, which subjects defined orally. Anal-
ysis of the definitions showed that the concrete words, relative to the
abstract ones, elicited longer definitions, with faster initiation of the defini-
tions, fewer silent pauses, and fewer nonfluencies of other types. In brief,
concrete words were generally easier to define (cf. O'Neill, 1972) and gen-
erated more fluent speech than the abstract words.
Reynolds and Paivio also obtained information on the role of verbal-asso-
ciative processes in the definitions task. The speakers were identified as high
or low on a prior verbal-associative productivity test in which they wrote
associations to stimulus words. The experiment showed that the definitions
of the high-associative productivity participants contained more words, had
faster starting latencies, and were more fluent than those of the low-produc-
tivity subjects. The definitions given by the high-productivity subjects were
also judged to be better definitions of the concepts. These differences are
particularly noteworthy because the two groups were originally distin-
guished on the basis of a written association test, whereas the experimental
task required oral production of natural, grammatical speech. Thus, the
results apparently reflected the influence of individual differences in rather
general verbal-productive skills.
The dual coding interpretation of the above findings is straightforward.
The concrete descriptive tasks require a high degree of referential exchange
between the verbal and imagery systems. Cartoons activate the image sys-
tem directly and concrete words do so indirectly. In either case, the descrip-
tions or definitions are based on perceptual or perceptual-memory infor-
mation, which activates relevant descriptive representations in the verbal
system. The relatively fluent speech presumably results from the simulta-
neous availability of complex images, appropriate to the task, combined
with verbal-associative processes. The fluency of more abstract interpreta-
tions and definitions presumably depends more exclusively on such prop-
erties of the verbal system as availability and length of sequentially orga-
nized verbal-representational chunks as measured, for example, by
associative-fluency tests.
The plausibility of the dual coding analysis was enhanced by a further set
of results. Segal (1976, described in Paivio, 1975b) presented subjects with
groups of two, three, or four unrelated abstract words, concrete words, or
object pictures with instructions to make up sentences using a given set of
items. For example, the subject might see the words house, apple, and pencil,
or pictures of their referents. The relevant result here concerns the latency
of sentence generation as measured by a key press when subjects "had the
sentence in mind" (which was followed by their writing the sentence). The
latencies were faster for concrete words than abstract words and still faster
for pictures than concrete words. The latter finding was a counterintuitive
prediction from dual coding theory because commonsense considerations,
as well as any theory that emphasizes linguistic processes, would lead one
to expect faster sentence construction when the words to be used are actually
234 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
given. The results suggest instead that pictures have the advantage because
they can be encoded relatively directly and quickly by the imagery system
into an organized scene, which can then be described via the referential
interconnections.
This completes the analysis of language comprehension and production,
as applied to language in general. The next section puts the emphasis on
figurative language in particular.
REPRESENTATIONAL PROCESSES IN
FIGURATIVE LANGUAGE
Metaphors and idioms of various kinds pose a special problem for theories
of language because they are commonly used and understood despite the
fact that they are literally anomalous. Proverbs are also problematic because
they are used in an extended, figurative sense, although many of them could
also be used literally—for example, it is literally true that "all that glitters is
not gold" but it is unlikely that it would be used in that literal sense except
in a discussion of "fool's gold." Of course, frozen idioms and familiar met-
aphors and proverbs may not present any special analytic difficulty because
their metaphorical meaning has been overlearned. The theoretical problems
arise when one considers novel figurative expressions, as we do here. We
begin with a general analysis of psychological issues and approaches, and
then move to the dual coding approach, emphasizing its implication for
comprehension, but with some attention as well to memory and production.
Students of metaphor have generally identified similarity, relation, and
integration as core concepts in the analysis of metaphor processing. The
topic and vehicle (the subject and predicate) of a metaphor share something
in common. The relation between these similar or shared elements as well
as the ones that are not shared contribute somehow to the appreciation for
and interpretation of the metaphor. Finally, the cognitive end-product of the
interpretation is some kind of novel, integrated representation. Theories of
metaphor processing differ in the way they conceptualize the representa-
tional elements, structures, and processes that are presumed to be the basis
of similarity, relational, and integrative reactions to a metaphor.
Three general classes of theoretical approaches to the problem can be
identified: (a) emphasizing perception and imagery, (b) verbal-mediating
processes, and (c) abstract representations and processes. The dual coding
approach combines the first two along with a set of specific assumptions and
hypotheses.
The perception-imagery approaches generally assume that topic-vehicle
similarity is perceptually based, entailing, for example, a transfer of sensory
experiences as in synesthctic metaphors (cf. Asch, 1958; R. Brown, 1958;
Osgood, 1963); or they assume that the resulting holistic meaning of meta-
phors is based on some kind of "abstractive seeing" as represented in imag-
Language Comprehension and Production 235
ery (Langer, 1948). Imagery was also given a prominent role in G. Miller's
(1979) analysis of metaphor. Verbal-mediational approaches (e.g., Koen,
1965) assume that similarity and relational reactions are essentially based
on verbal-associative overlap between topic and vehicle. The abstract rep-
resentational approaches analyze similarity of topic-vehicle relations in
terms of semantic component or feature overlap (e.g., Malgady & Johnson,
1976; Ortony, 1979; Osgood, 1963). Their analyses of topic-vehicle relations
also take account of dissimilarities in semantic representations, including
asymmetry in the position of common features in the defining feature sets
of the two terms (e.g., Ortony, 1979). Finally, some of these theorists have
proposed that the integrated representation that emerges during metaphor
comprehension is the overlapping feature representation that is evoked by
the topic and vehicle (Malgady & Johnson, 1976), or some kind of common
abstract representation that is more than the sum of the attributes of each
constituent (Honeck, Riechmann, & Hoffman, 1975; Verbrugge &
McCarrell, 1977). Models of metaphor processing based on such ideas also
include other assumptions that need not be reviewed here.
The dual coding approach is based on the general assumption that the
representational processes that mediate figurative language behavior are
modality-specific (verbal and nonverbal) cognitive reactions that are asso-
ciatively evoked by the metaphor and the context in which it is used. Thus,
it combines features of the imagery and verbal-associative approaches cited
above (a similar dual process approach has been proposed recently by Har-
nad, 1982). Earlier (Paivio, 1979), I suggested five specific ways in which
imaginal and verbal processes could jointly contribute to metaphor com-
prehension and production: (a) dual coding enhances the probability of find-
ing a common ground, that is, a connection between topic and vehicle, in
long-term memory; (b) the synchronous or integrated nature of imagery
enables large amounts of potentially relevant information to become avail-
able quickly, if at least one term in the metaphor is high in image-arousing
value; (c) imagery ensures processing flexibility because it is relatively free
from sequential constraints; (d) topic and vehicle are retrieval cues for rel-
evant information; and (e) verbal processes, because of their sequential
nature, keep search and retrieval on track; that is, the metaphorical terms
themselves and the verbal associations they arouse constrain the search and
retrieval process more than imagery does, precisely because imagery is rela-
tively free from sequential constraints and, therefore, is more likely to lead
to irrelevant flights of fantasy.
These points were elaborated on in the original context (Paivio, 1979) and
here I will comment only on two issues related to them, one arising from
the research literature on metaphor and the other from a test of a hypothesis
associated with the proposed retrieval function of metaphorical terms.
The first issue concerns the role of imagery in the processing of figurative
language. Honeck et al. (1975) found that memory for proverbs was better
when cued by related interpretations than by unrelated ones when the prov-
236 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
erbs were high in imagery value but not when they were low in imagery.
Despite that observation, the authors preferred an abstract conceptual-base
interpretation of comprehension and recall of proverbs, partly because
another experiment showed that subjects recognized interpretations of prov-
erbs better after instructions to encode them for their intended meaning
than after instructions to visualize their literal meanings. The present anal-
ysis of the issue simply follows the argument already presented in the sec-
tion on language comprehension. Comprehension is a complex and multi-
level process, generally, and it must be especially so in the case of novel
figurative expressions. Imagery is likely to play a role in comprehension,
especially when the language includes concrete terms that readily evoke
imagery, and its arousal might facilitate performance in a criterion test of
comprehension but it need not always do so. The dissociation was demon-
strated in the experiment by O'Neill and Paivio (1978) described earlier, in
which anomaly had effects on comprehensibility and imagery ratings: Inter-
changing content words from different meaningful sentences reduced the
sensibleness of concrete strings more than of abstract strings, but imagery
ratings were less disrupted by anomaly. The interpretation was that concrete
terms could still evoke imagery even in anomalous contexts, but that the
pattern of imagery may be bizarre or otherwise unconducive to a meaning-
ful interpretation.
The parallel argument in the case of figurative expressions is that imagery
could interfere with a metaphorical interpretation because the imagery is
irrelevant or inappropriate. The possibility is illustrated by a study by Bil-
low (1975) in which the presentation of pictures along with metaphors
sometimes interfered with metaphor interpretation by children, perhaps
because the pictures added irrelevant detail. Imagery could be similarly mis-
leading because it biases a literal interpretation rather than a figurative one.
Such an effect would be especially likely in the case of proverbs like All that
glitters is not gold, which can be interpreted literally as well as figuratively,
but such garden-path imagery is possible with any figurative expression.
Consider the following example: As a young child, one of our daughters was
chattering away in a charming manner and her mother said, "Won't
Grandpa get a kick out of that mouth!" Whereupon the girl began to sob
and imploringly said, "I don't want Grandpa to kick me in the mouth!"
Imagery apparently facilitated comprehension, but not of the intended idi-
omatic message.
Concerning the retrieval function of topic and vehicle, the dual coding
proposition is that high imagery value of both terms facilitates retrieval of
imaginal and (indirectly) verbal-referential associations from long-term
memory, either of which could provide a common ground for interpreta-
tion. In effect, the topic and vehicle can be viewed as conceptual pegs for
semantic memory information. I suggested further that the imagery value
of the metaphorical vehicle (predicate) would be especially important on the
assumption that processing begins and is guided by the vehicle because its
Language Comprehension and Production 237
ticipants generally said that they first thought about (imaged) an eclipse and
then thought about what it might have to do with metaphor. But their intro-
spective analysis is misleading because the metaphor was presented orally,
so they would have heard and presumably understood the topic before hear-
ing the vehicle. Their semantic search process may have begun with the
vehicle, but only in light of its relation to the topic.
The analysis can be extended to metaphor comprehension and produc-
tion in natural communicational situations. When a speaker uses a meta-
phor, it is always in a specific situational and verbal context. That context
constrains the choice of a familiar metaphor or the production of a novel
one so that it will be relevant to the topic of conversation. Similarly, the
listener's interpretation is constrained by the same context. The ongoing
process in both parties is associative, including the associative pattern of the
conversational content as a whole, and the associations it selectively arouses
in the speaker. However novel, the generated metaphor is probabilistically
determined by the context and the speaker's verbal- and nonverbal-associ-
ative habits. The listener's interpretation is constrained by the context, the
metaphor itself, and his or her associative habits.
The communicational situation contrasts with most experimental studies
of metaphor comprehension and memory, in which metaphors are typically
presented in isolation, except for the context of other metaphors. The inter-
pretation of each metaphor is unconstrained by a relevant communicational
context. This may be why there is so much variability in the interpretation
of metaphors by subjects in psychological studies. Such variability would
not be conducive to the communicational function that Ortony (1975)
emphasized in his analysis of metaphor but, fortunately, it is likely that the
variability would be reduced by the communicational context itself. It is
clear in any case that context contributes to the understanding of novel met-
aphors (Gildea & Glucksberg, 1983).
This concludes our selective analysis of representational processes in rela-
tion to language comprehension and production. We turn next to an exten-
sion of the dual coding approach to bilingualism.
11
Bilingual Cognitive Representation
The bilingual mind presents some unique problems for students of cogni-
tion. Persons who have mastered two (or more) languages must have two
distinct representational subsystems of some kind, since they are able to
deal separately and meaningfully with different acoustic and response pat-
terns. (Actually, they must have more than two subsystems if they also read
and write in both languages, but I will simplify the present discussions by
ignoring the further analytic complexities that would arise if we were to deal
fully with the different sensorimotor components of bilingual language skills
as outlined in chapter 4.) Moreover, bilinguals must have some way of
switching efficiently from one linguistic code to the other in bilingual con-
texts. This means that bilingualism entails productive representational sys-
tems corresponding to the units and structures of each language, and func-
tional interconnections between them. That much is relatively
uncontroversial among cognitive theorists interested in bilingualism. What
is controversial is the interpretation of the cognitive processes implicated in
bilingualism: Does the ability to speak and understand two languages mean
that one has two ways of remembering, knowing, and thinking? Or are the
two language systems functionally connected to a common cognitive or con-
ceptual system?
The contrasting positions, as defined originally by Kolers (1963), have
been described variously as independence versus interdependence, language
dependent versus language independent, and separate versus shared-mem-
ory and cognitive systems. The independence-interdependence contrast will
do for our purposes. The independence position implies that the bilingual
has two functionally independent cognitive subsystems (including memory
stores) associated with the two languages. The interdependence position is
that the separate linguistic systems are functionally connected to a common
conceptual system, including a shared-memory store. The latter view, it
should be noted, is entirely consistent with common coding or propositional
approaches to cognition in general (e.g., see Rosenberg & Simon, 1977).
The contrasting views and their empirical implications have been dis-
cussed in detail elsewhere (e.g., Kolers, 1963; Kolers & Gonzales, 1980;
McCormack, 1977; Paivio & Begg, 1981, chap. 13; Paivio & Desrochers,
1980; Paradis, 1980). Here, I simply list some of the major research findings
that have been interpreted as support for one position or the other, and then
239
240 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
describe a dual coding model of bilingual memory and cognition and show
how it deals with such findings and other issues in bilingualism.
The independence position is supported by the following observations: (a)
the bilingual's word associations to translation-equivalent words in the two
languages differ more than would be expected from the interdependence or
common conceptual view; (b) language switching takes time in production
tasks and some comprehension tasks; (c) bilinguals are able to remember
the language in which a word was presented in a mixed language list more
accurately than would be expected on the basis of chance; (d) changing the
language of a set of words produces a release from proactive inhibition in a
Brown-Peterson short-term memory task; (e) additive memory effects con-
sistent with the idea of independent memory codes have been obtained in
free recall tasks using bilingual repetitions or bilingual encoding of items,
and (f) priming effects sometimes do not transfer from one language to the
other.
The following results have been interpreted as more consistent with an
interdependence or shared-system position: (a) similar associations are
given to stimulus words in a bilingual's two languages too often to support
an absolute independence position; (b) positive transfer effects occur in a
variety of verbal learning tasks when the word lists are switched from one
language to another for bilinguals; (c) free recall of bilingual lists by bilin-
guals shows clustering of items by conceptual category but not language; and
(d) translation and picture-naming reaction times are comparable, suggest-
ing that both are mediated by the same amodal conceptual system.
The most relevant of the issues and contrasting findings will be discussed
in more detail following a review of the present theoretical approach.
The bilingual dual coding model (Paivio & Desrochers, 1980) is in one sense
a specific version of the independence approach to bilingual cognition, but
it also includes a common representational system that provides a basis for
interpreting some findings that appear to support the interdependence
hypothesis. Overall, the model provides a comprehensive account of both
sets of findings summarized above and has unique implications that go
beyond those that arise from the independence or interdependence positions
separately considered. The theory includes all of the general assumptions
presented in chapter 4 and adds specific ones concerning the relations
between verbal representational systems corresponding to the two languages
and of each of those to the nonverbal system. The theory is schematically
modeled in Figure 11-1.
Bilingual Cognitive Representation 241
Figure 11-1. Schematic representation of the bilingual dual coding model showing
for languages L1 and L2 the corresponding verbal systems (V1 and V2) and their con-
nections with each other and with the imagery (I) system. From "A dual coding
approach to bilingual memory" by A. Paivio and A. Desrochers, 1980, Canadian
Journal of Psychology, 34, p. 391. Copyright © 1980 by Canadian Psychological
Association, Reprinted by permission.
sponding to the bilingual's two languages (L1 and L2) have referential inter-
connections to the image system (V1-I and V2-I in Figure 11-1) that are
partly shared and partly independent. That is, the verbal translation equiv-
alents in L1 and L2 may or may not activate the same nonverbal represen-
tational information, depending on the way the two languages have been
acquired. This assumption translated into the familiar idea that translation
equivalents do not necessarily have identical referential meanings.
We shall see presently that the assumptions have unique implications for
some basic issues in the psychology of bilingualism. One issue that is rele-
vant at this point concerns the translation process. The implication is that
the image system provides an indirect access route from one language to the
other. Under some circumstances and for some words, translation can be
mediated in that a logogen in V1 activates referential imagens which in turn
activate referential logogens in V2. In other cases, translation might occur
more directly, as suggested by the following set of assumptions.
between the bilingual's linguistic systems and their conceptual systems. Psy-
cholinguistic researchers (e.g., Lambert, Havelka, & Crosby, 1958; Osgood
& Ervin, 1954) subsequently emphasized the compound-coordinate dichot-
omy. Compound bilinguals were presumed to have good control of their two
languages but these are connected to a single, fused conceptual system. The
English word bread and the French word pain, for example, would have
identical meanings. Coordinate bilinguals, on the other hand, were assumed
to function like unilinguals in each of their languages, since the two concep-
tual systems that are acquired through each language are clearly differen-
tiated. Thus, for the French-English coordinate bilingual, the words bread
and pain would have somewhat different meanings, stemming from distinct
experiences with different kinds of bread. Conversely, objects might be ver-
bally distinguished in different ways by the two types of bilinguals.
Weinreich's classification system has been criticized on the grounds that
it has been difficult to define the categories operationally in terms of lan-
guage-acquisition experience and that empirical studies have produced only
mixed support for the distinction. Taking such criticisms into account,
Lambert (1969) proposed a modified operational definition in terms of early
versus late bilingualism, in which compounds are those who have been
brought up in a bilingual environment from infancy on, whereas coordi-
nates are those who had learned their second language later than the first,
usually after ten years of age and usually outside of the family setting. The
distinction was supported by the observation (Lambert, 1969, pp. 108-109)
that coordinate bilinguals, so defined, showed less interference on a bilin-
gual version of the Stroop test than did compound bilinguals, as though the
former had greater functional separation of the two languages.
The present approach to the problem begins with the general view that it
is more useful to think of the compound-coordinate distinction as a matter
of degree rather than extreme types. In dual coding terms, bilingual verbal
systems have multiple connections to an independent, nonverbal-represen-
tational system, some connections converging on a common set of imaginal
representations (reflecting a "compound" aspect of bilingual memory), and
others activating relatively independent sets (reflecting a "coordinate"
aspect). For some individuals and some concepts, the converging connec-
tions might predominate, so that bread and pain, for example, might elicit
images of the same kind of bread; for others, the independent connections
might predominate, resulting in images of different kinds of bread to the two
words. Individuals also could differ in the number and strength of direct
associations between translation equivalents in ways not easily encom-
passed by the compound-coordinate distinction. The different associative
patterns would be determined by linguistic and nonlinguistic experiences to
which the bilingual had been exposed during language learning.
The relevant empirical evidence is sparse and bears mainly on imagery
reactions to a bilingual's two languages. Bugelski (1977) described a personal
observation, which he also confirmed with other bilinguals. Bugelski had
246 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
and translate words. The critical finding from both experiments was that it
took no longer to name a picture in L2 than to translate L1 words into L2.
This finding is inconsistent with the word-association hypothesis described
by Potter et al. (1984), according to which access to and from an L, word is
exclusively via the first language, so that picture naming in L2 would require
that the picture first be named (covertly) in L1 and then translated into L2.
This process would take more time than translating a printed word into L2
because picture naming takes longer than reading a printed word. Note,
however, that the bilingual dual coding model does not assume that picture
naming in L2 must be mediated by L|. To the extent that L2 names had been
learned in the context of their referents (objects, pictures, images), the bilin-
gual would develop direct referential interconnections between imagens and
V2 logogens. There would be no reason, then, to expect that picture naming
in L2 would take longer than translating a printed word into L2. Longer nam-
ing reaction times would be expected only if L2 had been learned exclusively
through direct word-word translation, which is unlikely to be the case in
ordinary language-learning situations. Accordingly, contrary to what was
suggested by Potter et al. (1984, p. 34), their results are not difficult to rec-
oncile with dual coding theory.
Our final research examples provide data that are inconsistent with any
strong form of the interdependence-conceptual coding hypothesis, whereas
they are consistent with the independence hypothesis of bilingual semantic
memory and with dual coding theory. Lachman and Mistler-Lachman
(1976) had German-English bilinguals name pictures of objects in each of
their languages. The same pictures were named on two trials so that some
pictures were named twice in the same language and some were named once
in one language and once in the other. The relevant finding was that naming
latencies on trial 2 were significantly faster for pictures named in the same
language than for pictures named in the other language. According to the
Lachmans, the result suggests that the internal processes necessary for
accessing visual-conceptual content of pictures on the one hand and lin-
guistic information on the other are at least partly independent. Their pre-
ferred interpretation is in terms of a model of object naming proposed by
R. Lachman (1973), which includes a visual memory component for dealing
with identifiable visual patterns, a semantic memory component that links
the visual pattern to its conceptual infrastructure and knowledge of the
world, and a lexical storage component.
Lachman's model is similar to dual coding if we interpret the semantic
memory component of the former in terms of associative structures within
the imagery system. However, we need not resort to the associative level
nor to its analogue in the Lachman model to explain the results. It suffices
instead to assume that referential responding in one language increases the
availability of that response on a subsequent trial, but would not similarly
augment referential responding in the other language because the verbal-
representational systems for the two languages are independent. Cross-Ian-
Bilingual Cognitive Representation 249
Figure 11-2. Incidental free-recall scores for English words that bilingual subjects in
Experiment 1 had generated by naming pictures, translating French words, and copy-
ing English words; and for presented English words that subjects in Experiment 2
had coded by sketching the referent, translating, or copying. From "Dual coding and
bilingual memory" by Paivio and Lambert, 1981, Journal of Verbal Learning and
Verbal Behavior. Copyright © 1981 by Academic Press. Reprinted by permission.
theories were considered in the discussion and found wanting for logical and
empirical reasons.
A variety of other studies are directly relevant to dual coding theory or
can be reinterpreted in its terms. Saegert and Young (1975) paired Spanish
and English translation equivalents with different stimuli in the same
paired-associates list, so that bilingual subjects had to remember which con-
cept went with each stimulus as well as the language of the concept. In addi-
tion, half of the pairs were concrete nouns and half were abstract nouns.
Saegert and Young reasoned that the concrete items could be conceptualized
in a nonlinguistic (imaginal) form and that this would enhance the proba-
bility of translation errors because subjects would be confused about which
language code, Spanish or English, was appropriate for a given stimulus
when the association had been image mediated. Such confusions would be
less likely in the abstract case because they are more likely to be processed
in terms of their verbal representations alone. The results were consistent
with these predictions.
In a conceptually related study, however, Winograd et al. (1976) obtained
the opposite results in that they found memory for input language to be
poorer with abstract words than with concrete words. The discrepant results
252 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
are probably due to procedural differences. Saegert and Young used an asso-
ciative learning task that was designed to maximize the probability of con-
fusion errors. Winograd et al. (1976) used a free-recall task, which is gener-
ally less likely to produce confusion errors. Still, the task difference would
not explain why memory for input language was better with concrete than
abstract items in the Winograd et al. (1976) study. The authors suggested two
image-based interpretations. Their "cultural imagery" hypothesis is equiv-
alent to one of the dual coding interpretations of coordinate bilingualism
discussed earlier: Bilinguals have different images associated with transla-
tion equivalents in their two languages, so the images themselves contain
clues to the language of the concrete words from which they were generated.
The second suggestion was that the images associated with concrete words
may function as effective retrieval cues for phonological and other features
of the words themselves. Such interpretations are yet to be investigated.
Bilingual dual coding theory also provides a basis for reinterpreting some
findings that have been taken as evidence for a common memory store. Sev-
eral studies have shown positive transfer effects in a variety of verbal learn-
ing tasks when the word lists are switched from one language to the other
for bilinguals (e.g., Lopez & Young, 1974; MacLeod, 1976; Young & Saegert,
1966). The effect has been taken to mean that transfer is mediated via com-
mon memory representations for the two languages. Dual coding suggests
the following reinterpretation. To the extent that the studies used concrete
words (as they generally have), positive transfer effects would be expected
because the translation equivalents in the two languages would tend to
arouse common referent images. Moreover, direct verbal associations could
also produce positive transfer if we assume that bilingual subjects some-
times translate words covertly during first- or second-list learning. When
such translations occur during first-list learning, they would provide a head
start for learning items presented in that language in the second list. The
reverse translations during second-list learning could be used to check the
correctness of the recall attempts against memories of the already learned
first-list responses.
technique (which is designed for number-cued retrieval) may have been dis-
advantaged in the experiment. Nonetheless, the effectiveness of Ham-
moud's innovative associative-field procedure is quite encouraging. Theo-
retically, the technique is designed to promote the development of
interconnections between L2 target items and image compounds in which a
target's referent is embedded in a context of associated images relevant to
both L1 and L2. The technique could be further extended to promote the
development of rich intraverbal networks by including the associates them-
selves as to-be-learned L2 items.
The preceding discussion dealt only with the learning of a second lan-
guage vocabulary. Vocabulary learning is an important goal in itself—far
more important and complex than is generally conceded by teachers of for-
eign languages. Nonetheless, second language learning obviously entails the
learning of a grammatical system as well, and the question that arises in the
present context is whether dual coding theory and related empirical proce-
dures have anything to contribute to that goal.
The special relevance of the theory is that it draws attention to the impor-
tance of nonverbal-situational, cognitive, and behavioral contexts in the
acquisition of all language skills, including syntax. This nonverbal-contex-
tual emphasis is generally consistent with other current approaches that
stress the role of experiential and semantic factors in language acquisition
(see chap. 5, this volume; Paivio & Begg, 1981, chap. 10). More specifically,
in dual coding terms, the development of grammatical skills involves for-
mation of referential interconnections, not only between representations
corresponding to objects and their names, but also between the abstract and
dynamic attributes of objects (e.g., relations, transformations, actions) and
their corresponding verbal descriptions. For example, the propositional
relation in the sentence, "the pencil is on the book," maps onto a corre-
sponding real or imaginal situation. Learning to understand and produce
such expressions in a first or a second language accordingly requires expe-
riential contiguity between the verbal expression and the situation as per-
ceived or imagined, at least during the initial stage of learning. Later, such
structural (grammatical) skills can be strengthened and expanded (general-
ized) through intraverbal experience alone—that is, new instances may be
learned by reference to already developed intraverbal structures.
The empirical implication is that grammar learning should be facilitated
by the use of appropriate nonverbal referent situations, pictures, or imagery.
Some relevant evidence is available. Recall from chapter 5 that Moeser and
Bregman (1973) investigated the learning of a miniature artificial language
under conditions in which perceptual referents were provided or were
absent. They found that learning was best when sentences constructed from
nonsense words were presented along with pictures in which the syntactic
constraints of the language were also mirrored in the logical constraints of
the pictures. The authors concluded that semantic referents and imagery are
necessary for the initial learning of syntax. Consistent with the dual coding
Bilingual Cognitive Representation 257
view just presented, they also found that subsequent learning of the syntac-
tic class membership of new words could be learned in a purely verbal
context.
Another relevant example is the total physical response strategy for second
language learning as studied by Asher (e.g., 1972). The strategy is aimed at
developing listening skills by having learners act out responses to com-
mands. Thus, it is essentially a pragmatic learning strategy in which lan-
guage is studied in the context of nonverbal behaviors and appropriate sit-
uations. A number of second-language learning experiments (e.g., Asher,
1972) have shown that the strategy can be quite effective in comparison with
some other standard second-language learning techniques, but its effective-
ness needs to be studied further under carefully controlled experimental
conditions and in comparison with other experimental strategies, including
imagery mnemonics.
With the exception of Desrochers's (1982, 1983) promising application of
the hook technique to the learning of French grammatical gender, imagery-
based mnemonic strategies have not yet been applied systematically to the
learning of grammatical skills. Other possibilities are suggested by my own
use of the hook technique in language study. For example, I have used it to
rehearse phrase structure, verb forms in sentence contexts, and idiomatic
expressions in French. I found that I could represent the grammatical gender
of nouns and the appropriate ordering of adjectives and nouns in the struc-
ture of mnemonic images, with a high rate of success in recalling long lists
of phrases using the numbered hooks as retrieval cues. These personal
observations are not a substitute for the experimental studies of the general
problem, but they do indicate that such experiments are feasible.
In summary, we have considered a bilingual version of dual coding theory
that has implications for the performance of bilingual individuals in a vari-
ety of semantic memory and episodic memory tasks that require the indi-
vidual to respond selectively to pictorial or verbal stimuli. The theory also
leads to a strong emphasis on the role of situational contexts and imagery
in second language learning. In particular, the theory suggests that language-
learning strategies based on the systematic use of referent objects, pictures,
activities, and mental imagery would be especially effective in promoting
learning. I have interpreted the available research evidence to be generally
supportive of the approach but there are discordant notes as well. Moreover,
the research has only scratched the surface of the fundamental issues in this
domain.
12
Neuropsychological Evidence
258
Neuropsychological Evidence 259
hemispheres has been severed. The intact brain studies are possible because
sensory input to the two hemispheres is lateralized. Auditory information
from each ear reaches both sides of the brain, but the contralateral input is
stronger or more efficient than ipsilateral, so that right-ear input is processed
more efficiently by the left hemisphere than by the right hemisphere, and
vice versa for left-ear input. The visual pathways involve crossover of half
of the sensory neurons from each retina so that an object seen to the right
of the central fixation point (the right-visual hemifield) excites visual receiv-
ing areas in the left-visual cortex, and, conversely, for the left-visual field.
Tactual information from the left and right hands is similarly processed
relatively more efficiently by the contralateral hemisphere. Reciprocally,
motor control is also contralateral, so that muscles on the right side of the
body are controlled by the left hemisphere, and vice versa.
These neuroanatomical arrangements make it possible to present material
selectively to either hemisphere for perceptual recognition or other kinds of
cognitive processing. Dichotic listening tasks, in which each ear simultane-
ously receives different information, have been most common in the case of
audition, although asymmetries are also revealed by presentations to one
ear at a time. Visual studies have primarily relied on tachistoscopic presen-
tation in which items are flashed briefly to one side of the fixation point, so
that the stimulus has disappeared before the eyes have time to move. Tac-
tual tasks entail presentation of "feelable" materials to one hand at a time.
The functions of different regions within each hemisphere have been
inferred primarily from the results of studies of patients with focal lesions
in different parts of one hemisphere or the other, resulting from brain injury
or surgery. The best controlled studies have used patients with well-defined
lesion resulting from surgery performed to relieve such problems as severe
epileptic seizures. Some (mostly confirmatory) evidence has also emerged
from studies in which regional activity in the normal brain has been inferred
from patterns of electrical activity as measured by the EEG and regional
changes in cortical blood flow revealed by radioactive isotopes.
The above summary provides sufficient background for present purposes.
Readers wishing more detailed information on methodology can find it in
the sources cited earlier. We now turn to the highlights of research findings
that bear on the relevant theoretical issues.
(1981) interpreted these and other results from two experiments to be con-
sistent with predictions from dual coding theory. However, we are left some-
what uncertain concerning hemispheric differences in memory for common
objects, given the procedural differences that accompanied the different pat-
tern of results in Jaccarino's and Whitehouse's studies.
To summarize the effects of stimulus materials, we find consistent evi-
dence for a selective right-hemisphere role in memory for geometric forms,
faces, and nonsense figures, and less consistent evidence for a similar asym-
metry in the case of memory for common objects. The pattern is similar to
the one that emerges from perceptual recognition studies, in which geomet-
ric forms, etc., are recognized better by the right hemisphere, whereas com-
mon objects are recognized equally well by each hemisphere. Thus, both
hemispheres may be able to deal efficiently with familiar objects in episodic
memory tasks as well as in a task (perceptual recognition) that is dependent
on the availability of representations in semantic memory. I will discuss the
implications of that point further after considering some additional data.
The above generalizations concern effects of stimulus materials. Hemi-
spheric asymmetries have also been obtained with verbal and imagery tasks.
Jones-Gotman and Milner (1978) compared a group of right-temporal
lobectemy patients and matched controls on paired-associate learning of
separate lists of concrete and abstract word pairs. The subjects were
instructed to use mediating images to learn the concrete pairs and sentences
to link the abstract pairs. The results were that the right-temporal patients
recalled significantly fewer responses than the control group with the image-
linked concrete pairs, but the two groups performed equally well with the
sentence-linked abstract pairs. The authors concluded that the right-tem-
poral deficit found for concrete pairs must be attributed to the visual com-
ponent of the imagery mnemonic. Thus, although the material was verbal,
the right-hemisphere memory deficit under imagery instructions was similar
to the selective deficit in memory for nonverbal materials typically observed
with such patients. The right-hemisphere deficit also contrasts with the
observation that left-temporal lobectomy patients perform more poorly
than controls in memory tasks using verbal material (whether concrete or
abstract) in the absence of imagery instructions. These and other findings
described in the reviews cited earlier (e.g., Bryden, 1982) suggest that the
hemispheric asymmetries reflect the manner in which materials are pro-
cessed rather than differences in the type of material per se, although stim-
ulus materials obviously affect the probability that verbal and nonverbal
representations and processes will be activated and thereby affect memory
performance.
What about the left-temporal lobe and imagery instructions? Earlier
research by Jones-Gotman (Jones, 1974) showed that patients with lesions
in the left-temporal lobe were able to improve their performance in a verbal
paired-associate learning task when they were instructed to use imagery
mnemonics. Thus, they were able to compensate partly for their verbal
Neuwpsychological Evidence 263
The structural and processing levels that are postulated in dual coding the-
ory correspond closely to some traditional distinctions in the neuropsycho-
logical literature (e.g., Luria, 1973), which have been based on particular
neurological syndromes and which continue to be supported by recent
observations. We deal briefly with the representational level and then more
fully with the correlates of the other two levels.
Recall that representational processing refers to the activation of logogens
or imagens by corresponding verbal and nonverbal stimuli. The operational
behavioral specification of such processing is the recognition of a stimulus.
Neurologically, such representational processing implicates sensory path-
ways from the relevant receptors to the representational sites in the cortex.
The neuropsychological evidence for representational processing is the
selective failure to recognize specific classes of stimuli that follows damage
to the representational sites or the pathways leading to them. For example,
lesions of the parieto-occipital regions of the left hemisphere may impair the
recognition of written language without similarly affecting object recogni-
tion and, conversely, lesions in corresponding zones of the right hemisphere
can lead to selective impairments in face recognition, the ability to draw,
and so on (Luria, 1973, pp. 237-239).
Referential and associative interconnections can be inferred from func-
tional losses that occur when the brain damage leaves stimulus recognition
intact while impairing further processing by another system. These distur-
bances are commonly described as functional dissociations or disconnection
Neuropsychological Evidence 267
ority has also been shown from performance in perceptual closure and spa-
tial manipulation tests. Such asymmetrical effects occur for tactile as well as
visual tasks. The pattern recognition, closure, and manipulation tasks impli-
cate the right-parietal and temporo-occipital regions in particular.
In summary, the right-hemisphere functions are suggestive of represen-
tational and processing systems that are specialized for dealing with syn-
chronously organized structural information that is simultaneously availa-
ble for processing, or on which simultaneously (synchronously) functioning
processes operate. These functions are often contrasted with verbal, sequen-
tial, and analytic functions ascribed to the left hemisphere. The descriptive
contrasts have additional connotations as well, but their core component is
consistent with the synchronous-sequential functional contrast of dual cod-
ing theory.
REPRESENTATION OF EMOTION
The dual coding view as presented in chapter 4 was that affective and emo-
tional reactions become associated primarily with the nonverbal-represen-
tational system because they are learned in the context of nonverbal events.
Accordingly, learned affective reactions to stimuli are generally mediated by
imagens with high probability connections to primary affective systems. It
was also suggested, however, that words could acquire generalized affect-
arousing qualities analogous to referential meaning, in which the referential
reaction is a particular emotion. The analysis was based mainly on such data
as reaction time for comparisons of pictures and words on pleasantness (see
chap. 9). Here we consider relevant neuropsychological findings.
Bryden and Ley (1983) reviewed various kinds of evidence suggesting that
the right hemisphere is particularly involved in the perception and expres-
sion of emotion. Their own research using visual and auditory lateralized
presentation procedures suggested that the right hemisphere is superior to
the left in tasks requiring the subject to match emotional facial expressions,
categorize the emotional tone of musical passages, and judge the emotional
tone of sentences. A linkage with right-hemisphere imagery systems was sug-
gested by a priming study. Subjects first memorized a list of high imagery
or low imagery words that also varied in affective value. This procedure was
intended to induce the subjects to think about emotional material and
thereby produce activity in the right hemisphere. The subjects then partici-
pated in a face-recognition or dichotic listening experiment using affective
material. The results were that studying either positive or negative word lists
resulted in relative improvement in left-visual field (right-hemisphere) rec-
ognition of emotional facial expressions and in the left-ear (right-hemi-
sphere) recognition of dichotically presented emotional words. Moreover,
the right-hemisphere enhancement was greater when the memorized (prim-
272 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
ing) word list consisted of high imagery words than when it consisted of low
imagery words.
Bryden and Ley suggested that the priming results become quite explica-
ble if they are analyzed in terms of dual coding theory combined with
Zajonc's (1980) views concerning affective components of stimuli. Thus,
Study of a high-imagery list of emotional words leads to a representation of the
word list that includes not only verbal coding mechanisms that presumably are
represented in the left hemisphere, but also imagery-based and affective com-
ponents that are localized to the right hemisphere. Thus, relative to a neutral
word list, there is greater activity in the right hemisphere than in the left when
either high-imagery or highly emotional words have been presented. This
increased right-hemispheric activity makes the right hemisphere more receptive
to incoming stimuli, and consequently produces relatively better performance
in the left visual field or at the left ear, performance better than that which is
observed when word lists not having imagery or affective components are stud-
ied. (1983, p.38)
I would add only a cautionary note concerning the implication that
imagery is a right-hemisphere phenomenon. The evidence reviewed earlier
suggested that imagery activity could occur in either hemisphere. Accord-
ingly, the Bryden and Ley results should be interpreted to mean that affec-
tive imagery in particular is a right-hemisphere function. In any case, the
operational link between affect, imagery, and right-hemisphere efficiency is
consistent with aspects of the dual coding approach to emotion. The evi-
dence is less strong in regard to the possibility of direct affective arousal by
abstract verbal representations.
The evidence reviewed in this chapter provides considerable support for the
major assumptions of dual coding theory. The assumption of functionally
independent verbal- and nonverbal-representational and processing systems
is supported by material and task-specific functional asymmetries of the two
cerebral hemispheres. That the independent systems are nonetheless inter-
connected is supported by studies with split-brain patients and those with
lesions in certain brain areas who are able to recognize and remember
objects without being able to identify their names, or are able to use words
in verbal contexts without being able to associate them consistently with
their referents. Such data also constitute partial support for the distinctions
between representational, referential, and associative processing in that the
interconnections are inferred from impairments that specifically affect refer-
ential processing without affecting representational or within-system asso-
ciative levels of processing to the same degree. Some observations arc also
consistent with the assumption that the verbal-nonverbal symbolic distinc-
tion is orthogonal or partly orthogonal to sensory systems. More generally,
Neuropsychological Evidence 273
the data that support the orthogonality assumption indicate a high degree
of modality specificity in the representational and processing functions of
different brain regions.
How do theories of the propositional-computational type fare in light of
the neuropsychological evidence? Not very well at first sight, for it is difficult
to see how the assumption of a unimodal (or amodal) representational sys-
tem could account for the high degree of functional specialization of differ-
ent parts of the brain, correlated with distinctions in sensory as well as sym-
bolic modalities. There also seems to be no clear neuropsychological
evidence for a completely amodal representational system.
Still, propositional theories are so flexible that they can be accommodated
to the data. J. R. Anderson, for example, suggested that studies on hemi-
spheric specialization are indecisive because it can always be argued that
propositions encoding visual information or procedures for processing such
information are stored in the right hemisphere and propositions encoding
verbal information or relevant procedures are stored in the left hemisphere
(1978, pp. 271-272). However, such an argument amounts to redefining the
dual coding distinction in a way that makes the propositional view formally
equivalent to dual coding theory, which assumes representational and func-
tional (procedural) distinctions at the outset. The redefinition proposed by
Anderson is entirely terminological, without any special predictive or
explanatory consequences that would differentiate it from dual coding the-
ory unless the propositional version also includes assumptions about the
informational content and procedures associated with visual-spatial and
verbal propositional systems that differ from those associated with the pres-
ent (nonpropositional) dual coding theory. This has not yet been done in
any systematic way. Propositional theories have been based instead on the
assumption of an absence of distinctions in representational information
and procedures where dual coding draws sharp distinctions, as in tasks con-
trasting verbal and nonverbal stimuli or processing modes. The neuropsy-
chological evidence is clearly more consistent with the latter view than with
the former.
We end this final chapter and the book with a brief consideration of neu-
ropsychological theories as they pertain to cognition in general and dual
coding theory in particular. A number of specific hypotheses have been
mentioned, such as the functional distinctions between the two hemi-
spheres, the role of the hippocampus in episodic memory, the sequential
processing function associated with the region of the left hemisphere that
deals with motor and acoustic aspects of language stimuli and behavior, and
so on. Such hypotheses are directed at aspects of brain organization and
processing mechanisms but they are not general neuropsychological theories
274 Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach
TOWARD A NEUROPSYCHOLOGICAL
DUAL CODING MODEL
This chapter aimed primarily to review evidence relevant to dual coding
rather than to develop a neuropsychological dual coding model, but a ten-
tative outline of those theoretical aspects that implicate the cerebral hemi-
spheres can be suggested in a way that serves also to summarize the data.
The representational and processing levels of the two symbolic systems
along with organizational distinctions form the basis of the theory. Multi-
modal cognitive representations that store information about nonverbal
objects and events become established in posterior and central cortical areas
closely associated with the primary sensory systems. Their multimodal
character is a result of repeated and varied sensory and motor experiences
that create synchronously organized or integrated cortical representations in
which component information in any modality (visual, auditory, haptic,
olfactory, gustatory) can activate a larger holistic representation. Associa-
tion pathways also develop between different representations within and
between hemispheres, so that activation of one representation can activate
another with greater or lesser probability, depending on the nature of con-
textual sensory information. Such representations and associations develop
in both hemispheres, but one hemisphere (usually the right) becomes more
proficient in integrative, associative, and transformational activities involv-
ing those representations. Accordingly, posterior regions in particular play
a basic functional role in perceptual tasks dependent on the availability and
use of visual information and integrative processing of spatial information
in long-term memory. Activity in those cortical-representational systems
also forms the basis of consciously experienced visual imagery.
Neuropsychological Evidence 275
mental images and mental words are themselves neural events that can be
stored and retrieved (see the earlier discussion in chap. 8).
In contrast to the item-specific episodic memory functions of the tem-
poral lobes, the frontal lobes seem to be more crucial in memory for the
sequential order of discrete items, again with the hemispheres being func-
tionally differentiated in terms of the verbal-nonverbal contrast. This frontal
specialization for sequential memory may be a neuroanatomical conveni-
ence, representing an extension of the sequential organizational properties
of the motor cortex anterior to the central fissure.
This theoretical sketch emphasizes functions related to neuroanatomical
regions in the cortex. It says nothing about other structures that might play
a role in representational activity. It also passes over the representational
and processing functions of patterns of neuronal activity and biochemical
factors associated with different regions. A detailed neuropsychological the-
ory of cognitive representations and processes that incorporates all of the
available brain information remains to be written.
Referencess
Alba, J. W., & Hasher, L. (1983). Is memory schematic? Psychological Bulletin, 2, 203-231.
Algom, D., Wolf, Y., & Bergman, B. (in press). Integration of stimulus dimensions in percep-
tion and memory: Composition rules and psychophysical relations. Journal of Experi-
mental Psychology: General,
Allport, F. H. (1955). Theories of perception and the concept of structure. New York: Wiley.
Anderson, J. R. (1978). Arguments concerning representations for mental imagery. Psycholog-
ical Review, 85, 249-277.
Anderson, J. R. (1983). The architecture of cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Anderson, J. R., & Bower, G. H. (1973). Human associative memory. Washington, DC:
Winston.
Anderson, R. C, Goetz, E. T., Pickert, H. M, & Halff, H. M. (1977). Two faces of the concep-
tual peg hypothesis. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Mem-
ory, 3, 142-149.
Anderson, R. C., & Hidde, J. L. (1971). Imagery and sentence learning. Journal of Educational
Psychology, 62, 526-520.
Anderson, R. C., & McGaw, B. (1973). On the representation of the meanings of general items.
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 101, 301-306.
Anderson, R. C., & Ortony, A. (1975). On putting apples into bottles—-a problem in polysemy.
Cognitive Psychology, 7, 167-180.
Anderson, R. C., & Pichert, J. W. (1978). Recall of previously unrecallable information follow-
ing a shift in perspective. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 17, 1-12.
Anderson, R. E. (1976). Short-term retention of the where and when of pictures and words.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 105, 378-402.
Anderson, R. E. (1984). Did I do it or did I only imagine doing it? Journal of Experimental
Psychology: General, 113, 594-615.
Anisfeld, M., & Knapp, M. (1968). Association, synonymity, and directionality in false recog-
nition. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 77, 171-179.
Annett, J. (1982). Action, language and imagination. In L. Wankel & R. B. Wilberg (Eds.),
Psychology of sport and motor behavior. Edmonton, Alberta: University of Alberta Print-
ing Services.
Arnheim, R. (1969). Visual thinking. Berkeley & Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Arnold, M. B. (1960). Emotion and personality: Vol. 2. Neurological and physiological aspects.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Asch, S. E. (1958). The metaphor: A psychological inquiry. In R. Tagiuri & L. Petrullo (Eds.),
Person perception and interpersonal behavior. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Asher, J. J. (1972). Children's first language as a model for second language learning. The Mod-
ern Language Journal, 56, 133-139.
Atkinson, R. C. (1975). Mnemotechnics in second-language learning. American Psychologist,
30, 821-828.
Atkinson, R. C., & Shiffrin, R. M. (1968). Human memory: A proposed system and its control
processes. In K. W. Spencc & J. T. Spence (Eds.), The psychology of learning and moti-
vation: Advances in research and theory (Vol. 2). New York: Academic Press.
Attneave, F. (1974, July). How do you know? American Psychologist, pp. 493-499.
277
278 References
Attneave, F., & Pierce, C. R. (1978). Accuracy of extrapolating a pointer into perceived and
imagined space. American Journal of Psychology, 91, 371-387.
Babbit, B. C. (1982). Effect of task demands on dual coding of pictorial stimuli. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 8, 73-80.
Baddeley, A. D. (1978). The trouble with levels: A reexamination of Craik and Lockhart's
framework for memory research. Psychological Review, 85, 139-152.
Baddeley, A. D., Grant, S., Wight, E., & Thomson, N. (1974). Imagery and visual working
memory. In P. M. A. Rabbitt & S. Dornic (Eds.), Attention and performance (Vol. V).
London: Academic Press.
Baggett, P. (1979). Structurally equivalent stories in movie and text and the effect of the
medium on recall. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 18, 333-356.
Bahrick, H. P., & Bahrick, P. (1971). Independence of verbal and visual codes of the same
stimuli. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 91, 344-346.
Baker, L., & Santa, J. L. (1977). Context, integration, and retrieval. Memory & Cognition, 5,
308-314.
Bandura, A. (1977). Social learning theory. Englcwood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Banks, W. P. (1977). Encoding and processing of symbolic information in comparative judge-
ments. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation (Vol. 11). New
York: Academic Press.
Banks, W. P., & Flora, J. (1977). Semantic and perceptual processes in symbolic comparisons.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 3, 278-290.
Bartlett, F. C. (1932) Remembering. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Battig, W. F., & Montague, W. E. (1969). Category norms for verbal items in 56 categories: A
replication and extension of the Connecticut category norms. Journal of Experimental
Psychology Monographs, 80(3, Pt. 2).
Baum, D. R., & Jonides, J. (1979). Cognitive maps: Analysis of comparative judgments of dis-
tance. Memory & Cognition, 7, 462-468.
Baylor, G. W. (1972). A Treatise on the mind's eye: An empirical investigation of visual mental
imagery. Doctoral dissertation, Carnegie-Mellon University, Pittsburgh. (Ann Arbor,
MI: University Microfilms No. 72-12)
Beauvois, M. F. (1982). Optic aphasia: A process of interaction betwen vision and language.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 298, 35-47.
Beech, J. R., & Allport, D. A. (1978). Visualization of compound scenes. Perception, 7, 129-
138.
Begg, I. (1971). Recognition memory for sentence meaning and wording. Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 10, 176-181.
, I. (1972). Recall of meaningful phrases. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior,vior,
II, 431-439.
, I. (1973). Imagery and integration in the recall of words. Canadian Journal of Psychology,logy,
27, 159-167.
I. (1976). Acquisition and transfer of meaningful function by meaningless sounds. Cana-Cana-
dian Journal of Psychology, 30, 178-186.
Begg, I. (1978). Imagery and organization in memory: Instructional effects. Memory & Cogni-
tion, 6, 174-183.
Begg, I. (1982). Imagery, organization, and discriminative processes. Canadian Journal of Psy-
chology, 36, 273-290.
Begg, I., & Clark, J. M. (1975). Contextual imagery in meaning and memory. Memory & Cog-
nition, 3, 117-112.
Begg, L, & Paivio, A. (1969). Concreteness and imagery in sentence meaning. Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 8, 821 -827.
Begg, 1., & Robertson, R. (1973). Imagery and long-term retention. Journal of Verbal Learning
and Verbal Behavior, 12, 689-700.
Begg, I., & Sikich, D. (1984). Imagery and contextual organi/ation. Memory & Cognition, 12,
52-59.
References 279
Begg, I., Upfold, D., & Wilton, T. D. (1978). Imagery in verbal communication. Journal of
Mental Imagery, 2, 165-186.
Belmore, S. M., Yates, J. M., Bellack, D. R., Jones, S. N., & Rosenquist, S. E. (1982). Drawing
inferences from concrete and abstract sentences. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal
Behavior, 21, 338-351.
Beritoff, J. S. (1965). Neural mechanisms of higher vertebrate behavior (W. T. Liberson, Ed. &
Trans.). Boston: Little, Brown & Co.
Besner, D., & Coltheart, M. (1979). Ideographic and alphabetic processing in skilled reading of
English. Neuropsychologia, 17, 467-472.
Belts, G. H. (1909). The distribution and functions of mental imagery. New York: Teacher's
College, Columbia University.
Bever, T. G., Fodor, J. A., & Garrett, M. (1968). A formal limitation of associationism. In T.
R. Dixon & D. L. Horton (Eds.), Verbal behavior and general behavior theory. Engle-
wood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Biederman, I., Rabinowitz, J. C, Glass, A. L., & Stacey, E. W., Jr. (1974). On the information
extracted from a glance at a scene. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 103, 597-600.
Bierwisch, M. (1970). Semantics. In J. Lyons (Ed.), New horizons in linguistics. New York:
Penguin.
Billow, R. M. (1975). A cognitive developmental study of metaphor comprehension. Develop-
mental Psychology, 11, 415-423.
Binet, A. (1894). Psychologic des grands calculateurs et joueurs d'echec [Psychology of great
calculators and chess players], Paris: Hachette.
Bisiach, E., Capitani, E., Luzzatti, C., & Perani, D. (1981). Brain and conscious representation
of outside reality. Neuropsychologia, 19, 543-551.
Black, J. B., Turner, T. J., & Bower, G. H. (1979). Spatial reference points in language compre-
hension. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 18, 187-198.
Black, M. (1962). Metaphor. In M. Black (Ed.), Models and metaphors. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
Boles, D. B. (1983). Dissociated imageability, concreteness, and familiarity in lateralized word
recognition. Memory & Cognition, 11, 511-519.
Bousfield, W. K. (1953). The occurrence of clustering in recall of randomly arranged associates.
Journal of General Psychology, 49, 229-240.
Bower, G. H. (1967). A multicomponent theory of the memory trace. In K. W. Spence & J. T.
Spence (Eds.), The psychology of learning and motivation (Vol. 1). New York: Academic
Press.
Bower, G. H. (1970). Imagery as a relational organizer in associative learning. Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 9, 529-533.
Bower, G. H. (1972). Mental imagery and associative learning. In L. Gregg (Ed.), Cognition in
learning and memory. New York: Wiley.
Bower, G. H. (1981). Mood and Memory. American Psychologist, 36, 129-148.
Bower, G. H.. & Glass, A. L. (1976). Structural units and the redintegrative power of picture
fragments. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 2, 456-
466.
Bower, T. G. R. (1966). The visual world of infants. Scientific American, 215, 80-92.
Bower, T. G. R., & Paterson, J. G. (1973). The separation of place, movement, and object in
the world of the infant. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 15, 161-168.
Bowerman, M. (1973). Early syntactic development. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Braine, M. D. S. (1963). On learning the grammatical order of words. Psychological Review, 70,
323-348.
Brainerd, C. J. (1983). Working memory systems and cognitive development. In C. J. Brainerd
(Ed.), Recent advances in cognitive-developmental theory: Progress in cognitive develop-
ment research. New York: Springer-Verlag.
Brainerd, C. J., Dcsrochers, A., & Howe, M. L. (1981). Stages-of-learning analysis of picture-
word effects in associative memory. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learn-
ing and Memory, 7, 1-14.
280 References
Bransford, J. D., Stein, B. S., Vye, N. J., Franks, J. J., Auble, P. M., Mezynski, K. J., & Perfetto,
G. A. (1982). Differences in approaches to learning: An overview. Journal of Experi-
mental Psychology: General, 3, 390-398.
Bregman, A. S. (1977). Perception and behavior as compositions of ideals. Cognitive Psvchol-
ogy, 9, 250-292.
Bregman, A. S., & Campbell, J. (1971). Primary auditory stream segregation and perception of
order in rapid sequences of tones. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 89, 244-249.
Bremner, J. G. (1982). Object localization in infancy. In M. Potegal (Ed.), Spatial abilities. New
York: Academic Press.
Brewer, W. F. (1975). Memory for ideas: Synonym substitution. Memory & Cognition, 3, 458-
464.
Brewer, W. F., & Pani, J. R. (1984). The structure of human memory. In G. H. Bower (Ed.),
The psychology of learning and motivation: Advances in research and theory (Vol. 17).
New York: Academic Press.
Bridgman, P. W. (1927). The logic of modern physics. New York: Macmillan.
Broadbent, D. E. (1958). Perception and communication. London: Pergamon Press.
Brooks, L. R. (1967). The suppression of visualization in reading. The Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 19, 289-299.
Brooks, L. R. (1968). Spatial and verbal components of the act of recall. Canadian Journal of
Psychology, 22, 349-368.
Brooks, L. R. (1978). Nonanalytic concept formation and memory for instances. In E. Rosch
& B. B. Lloyd (Eds.), Cognition and categorization. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates.
Brown, I. Jr. (1979). Language acquisition: Linguistic structure and rule-governed behavior. In
G. J. Whitehurst & B. J. Zimmerman (Eds.), The functions of language and cognition.
New York: Academic Press.
Brown, R. W. (1958). Words and things. Glencoe, IL: The Free Press.
Brown, R. W. (1973). A first language: The early stages. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Bryden, M. P. (1982). Laterality: Functional asymmetry in the intact brain. New York: Aca-
demic Press.
Bryden, M. P. & Ley, R. G. (1983). Right-hemispheric involvement in the perception and
expression of emotion in normal humans. In K. M. Heilman & P. Satz (Eds.), Neuro-
psychology of human emotion. New York: Guilford.
Bucci, W. (1984). Linking words and things: Basic processes and individual variation. Cogni-
tion, 17, 137-153.
Bucci, W., & Frecdman, N. (1978). Language and hand: The dimension of referential compe-
tence. Journal of Personality, 46, 594-622.
Bugelski, B. R. (1970). Words and things and images. American Psychologist, 25, 1002-1012.
Bugelski, B. R. (197 la). The definition of the image. In S. J. Segal (Ed.), Imagery: Current cog-
nitive approaches. New York: Academic Press.
Bugelski, B. R. (1971b). The psychology of learning applied to teaching. Indianapolis: Bobbs-
Merrill.
Bugelski, B. R. (1974). The image as mediator in one-trial paired-associate learning: III.
Sequential functions in serial lists. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 103, 298-303.
Bugelski, B. R. (1977). The association of images. In J. M. Nicholas (Ed.), /mages, perception,
and knowledge. Boston: D. Rcidel.
Bugelski, B. R. (1982). Learning and imagery. Journal of Mental Imagery, 6, 1-192.
Caplan, D., & Chomsky, N. (1982). Linguistic perspectives on language development. In D.
Caplan (Ed.), Biological studies of mental processes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Caramazza, A., & Berndt, R. S. (1978). Semantic and syntactic processes in aphasia: A review
of the literature. Psychological Bulletin, 85, 898-918.
Carpenter, P. A., & Just, M. A. (1975). Sentence comprehension: A psycholinguistic processing
model of verification. Psychological Review, 82, 45-73.
References 281
Carr, T. H., McCauley, C, Sperber, R. D., & Parmelee, C. M. (1982). Words, pictures, and
priming: On semantic activation, conscious identification, and the automaticity of infor-
mation processing. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Perfor-
mance, 8, 757-777.
Carroll, J. B. (1962). The prediction of success in intensive foreign language training. In R.
Glaser (Ed.), Training and education research. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh
Press.
Carroll, J. B. (1976). Psychometric tests as cognitive tasks: A new "structure of intellect". In L.
B. Resnick (Ed.), The nature of intelligence. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Carroll, J. B. (1983). Studying individual differences in cognitive abilities: Through and beyond
factor analysis. In R. F. Dillon & R. S. Schmeck (Eds.), Individual differences in cogni-
tion (Vol. 1). New York: Academic Press.
Cartwright, D. (1959). Lewinian theory as a contemporary systematic framework. In S. Koch
(Ed.), Psychology: A study of a science (Vol. 2). New York: McGraw-Hill.
Case, R. (1978). Intellectual development from birth to adulthood: A neo-Piagetian interpre-
tation. In R. S. Siegler (Ed.), Children's thinking—What develops?. Hillsdale, NJ: Law-
rence Erlbaum Associates.
Chafe, W. L. (1970). Meaning and the structure of language. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Chafe, W. L. (1975). The recall and verbalization of past experience. In R. W. Cole (Ed.), Cur-
rent issues in linguistic theory. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Chase, W. G., & Clark, H. H. (1972). Mental operations in the comparison of sentences and
pictures. In L. Gregg (Ed.), Cognition in learning and memory. New York: Wiley.
Chevalier-Girard, N., & Wilberg, R. B. (1980). The effects of image and label on the free recall
of organized movement lists. In P. Klavora & J. Flowers (Eds.), Motor learning and
biomechanical factors in sport. Toronto: Canadian Society for Psychomotor Learning
and Sport Psychology.
Chi, M. T. H. (1976). Short-term memory limitations in children: Capacity or processing defi-
cits? Memory & Cognition, 4, 559-572.
Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic structures. The Hague: Mouton.
Chomsky, N. (1959). [Review of Verbal behaviorby B. F. Skinner]. Language, 35, 26-58.
Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chomsky, N. (1968). Language and mind. New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World.
Chomsky, N. (1982). Some concepts and consequences of the theory of government and binding.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Christian, J., Bickley, W., Tarka, M., & Clayton, K. (1978). Measures of free recall of 900
English nouns: Correlations with imagery, concreteness, meaningfulness, and frequency.
Memory & Cognition, 6, 379-390.
Clark, H. H. (1969). Linguistic processes in deductive reasoning. Psychological Review, 76,
387-403.
Clark, H. H. (1973). Space, time, semantics, and the child. In T. E. Moore (Ed.), Cognitive
development and the acquisition of language. New York: Academic Press.
Clark, J. M. (1978). Synonymity and concreteness effects on free recall and free association:
Implications for a theory of semantic memory. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Uni-
versity of Western Ontario, London.
Clark, J. M. (1983). Representational memory: Paivio's levels of meaning as experiential model
and conceptual framework. In J. C. Yuille (Ed.), Imagery, memory, and cognition:
Essays in honor of Allan Paivio. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Clark, J. M. (1984). Concreteness and semantic repetition effects in free recall: Evidence for
dual-coding theory. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 38, 591-598.
Clark, J. M., & Paivio, A. (1984, May). Associative mechanisms in cognition. Paper presented
at the annual meeting of the Canadian Psychological Association, Ottawa, Ontario,
Canada.
282 References
Clark, J. M., & Paivio, A. (1989). Observational and theoretical terms in psychology. American
Psychologist, 44, 500-512.
Clark, R. W. (1975). The life of BertrandRussell. London: J. Cape.
Collins, A. M., & Loftus, E. F. (1975). A spreading-activation theory of semantic processing.
Psychological Review, 82, 407-428.
Colpo, G., Cornoldi, C., & De Beni, R. (1977). Competition in memory between high and low
imagery value stimuli and visual stimuli: Temporal conditions for occurrences of inter-
ference effects. Italian Journal of Psychology, 4, 387-402.
Coltheart, M., Patterson, K., & Marshall, J. C. (Eds.). (1980). Deep dyslexia. London: Routledge
& Kegan Paul.
Conlin, D., & Paivio, A. (1975). The associative learning of the deaf: The effects of word imag-
ery and signability. Memory & Cognition, 3, 335-340.
Cooper, L. A. (1975). Mental rotation of random two-dimensional shapes. Cognitive Psychol-
ogy, 7, 20-43.
Cooper, L. A., & Shepard, R. N. (1973). Chronometric studies of the rotation of mental images.
In W. G. Chase (Ed.), Visual information processing. New York: Academic Press.
Cornoldi, C. (1976). Memoria e immaginazione. Bologna: Patron.
Cornoldi, C., & Paivio, A. (1982). Imagery value and its effects on verbal memory: A review.
Archivio di Psicologia Neurologia e Psichiatria, 2, 171-192.
Craik, F. I. M., & Lockhart, R. S. (1972). Levels of processing: A framework for memory
research. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 11, 671-684.
Craik, F. I. M., & Tulving, E. (1975). Depth of processing and the retention of words in episodic
memory. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 104, 268-294.
Crowder, R. G. (1976). Principles of learning and memory. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates.
Curry, F. K. W. (1967). A comparison of left-handed and right-handed subjects on verbal and
non-verbal dichotic listening tasks. Cortex, 3, 343-352.
D'Agostino, P. R., O'Neill, B. J., & Paivio, A. (1977). Memory for pictures and words as a
function of level of processing: Depth or dual coding? Memory & Cognition, 5, 252-256.
Dalrymple-Alford, E. C. (1968). Interlingual interference in a color naming task. Psychonomic
Science, 10, 215-216.
Das, J. P., Kirby, J., & Jarman, R. F. (1975). Simultaneous and successive syntheses: An alter-
native model for cognitive abilities. Psychological Bulletin, 82, 87-103.
Day, J. C., & Bellezza, F". S. (1983). The relation between visual imagery mediators and recall.
Memory & Cognition, 11, 251-257.
Deese, J. (1962). On the structure of associative meaning. Psychological Review, 69, 161-175.
Deese, J. (1965). The structure of associations in language and thought. Baltimore: Johns Hop-
kins Press.
Deffenbacher, K. A., Carr, T. H., & Leu, J. R. (1981). Memory for words, pictures, and faces:
Retroactive interference, forgetting, and reminiscence. Journal of Experimental Psy-
chology: Human Learning and Memory, '/, 299-305.
de Groot, A. M. B. (1983). The range of automatic spreading activation in word priming. Jour-
nal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 22, 417-436.
del Castillo, D. M., & Gumenik, W. E. (1972). Sequential memory for familiar and unfamiliar
forms. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 95, 90-96.
Dell. G. S., & Reich, P. A. (1981). Stages in sentence production: An analysis of speech error
data. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 20, 61 1-629.
den Heyer, K., & Barrett, B. (1971). Selective loss of visual and verbal information in STM by
means of visual and verbal interpolated tasks. Psychonomic Science, 25, 100-102.
Denis, M. (1979). Les images mentales [Mental images]. Paris: Presses Universitaires de
France.
Denis. M. (1982a). Imaging while reading text: A study of individual differences. Memory &
Cognition, 10. 540-545.
References 283
Ericsson, K. A., & Simon, H. A. (1984). Protocol analysis: Verbal reports as data. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Ernest, C. H. (1977). Imagery ability and cognition: A critical review. Journal of Mental Imag-
ery, 1, 181-216.
Ernest, C. H. (1980). Imagery ability and the identification of fragmented pictures and words.
Acta Psychologica, 44, 51-57.
Ernest, C. H., & Paivio. A. (1971). Imagery and verbal associative latencies as a function of
imagery ability. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 25, 83-90.
Eysenck, H. J. (1967). Intelligence assessment: A theoretical and experimental approach. British
Journal of Psychology, 37, 81-98.
Farah, M. J. (1985). Psychophysical evidence for a shared representational medium for mental
images and percepts. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 114, 91-103.
Farah, M. J., & Kosslyn, S. M. (1981). Structure and strategy in image generation. Cognitive
Science, 4, 371-383.
Fellz, D. L., & Landers, D. M. (1983). The effects of mental practice on motor skill learning
and performance: A meta-analysis. Journal of Sport Psychology, 5, 25-57.
Ferguson, G. A. (1954). On learning and human ability. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 8,
95-112.
Ferguson, G. A. (1956). On transfer and the abilities of man. Canadian Journal of Psychology,
10, 121-131.
Fernald, M. R. (1912). The diagnosis of mental imagery. Psychological Monographs (Whole
No. 58).
Field, T. (1982). Infancy. In R. Vasta (Ed.), Strategies and techniques in child study. New York:
Academic Press.
Fillenbaum, S., & Rapoporl, A. (1971). Structures in the subjective lexicon. New York: Aca-
demic Press.
Fillmore, C. J. (1968). The case for case. In E. Bach & R. T. Harms (Eds.), Universals in lin-
guistic theory. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
Fillmore, C. J. (1977). The case for case reopened. In P. Cale, & J. Sadock (Eds.), Syntax and
semantics. New York: Academic Press.
Finke, R. A. (1980). Levels of equivalence in imagery and perception. Psychological Review,
87, 113-132.
Finke, R. A. (1985). Theories relating mental imagery to perception. Psychological Bulletin, 98,
236-259.
Finke, R. A., & Shepard, R. N. (in press). Visual functions of mental imagery. In L. Kaufman
& J. Thomas (Eds.), Handbook of perception and human performance. New York: Wiley.
Fleishman, E. A., Roberts, M. M., & Friedman, M. P. (1958). A factor analysis of aptitude and
proficiency measured in radio-telegraphy. Journal of Applied Psychology, 42, 129-135.
Fleishman, E. A., & Rich, S. (1963). Role of kinesthetic and spatial-visual abilities in percep-
tual-motor learning. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 66, 6-11.
Flexser, A. J., & Tulving, E. (1978). Retrieval independence in recognition and recall. Psycho-
logical Review, 85, 153-171.
Fodor, J. A. (1965). Could meaning be an r,,,? Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior,
4, 73-81.
Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell.
Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Foltz, G., Poltrock, S., & Potts, G. (1984). Mental comparison of size and magnitude: Size
congruity effects. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cogni-
tion, 10, 442-453.
Forisha, B. D. (1975). Mental imagery verbal processes: A developmental study. Developmental
Psychology, 11, 259-267.
Foss, D. J., & Harwood, D. A. (1975). Memory for sentences: Implications for human associ-
ative memory. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 14, 1-16.
References 285
Fraisse, P. (1960). Recognition time measured by verbal reaction to figures and words. Percep-
tual and Motor Skills, 11, 204.
Fraisse, P. (1968). Motor and verbal reaction times to words and drawings. Psychonomic Sci-
ence, 12, 235-236.
Friedman, A. (1978). Memorial comparisons without the "mind's eye". Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 17, 427-444.
Friedman, A., & Bourne, L. E., Jr. (1976). Encoding the levels of information in pictures and
words. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 105, 169-190.
Friedman, W. J. (1983). Image and verbal processes in reasoning about the months of the year.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 9, 650-666.
Frost, N. (1972). Encoding and retrieval in visual memory tasks. Journal of Experimental Psy-
chology, 95, 311-326.
Fry, P. S. (Ed.). (1984). Changing conceptions of intelligence and intellectual functioning: Cur-
rent theory and research. International Journal of Psychology, 19, [Special issue], 457-
474.
Gage, D. F., & Safer, M. A. (1985). Hemisphere differences in the mood state-dependent effect
for recognition of emotional faces. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Mem-
ory, and Cognition, II, 752-763.
Gallon, F. (1883). Inquiries into human faculty and its development. London: Macmillan.
Garner, W. L., Hake, H. W., & Eriksen, C. W. (1956). Operationism and the concept of per-
ception. Psychological Review, 63, 149-159.
Garner, W. R. (1974). The processing of information and structure. Potomac, MD: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Garrett, M. F. (1975). The analysis of sentence production. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), Psychology
of learning and motivation (Vol. 9). New York: Academic Press.
Gazzaniga, M. S., & LeDoux, J. E. (1978). The integrated mind. New York: Plenum Press.
Gernsbacher, M. A. (1984). Resolving 20 years of inconsistent interaction between lexical
familiarity and orthography, concreteness, and polysemy. Journal of Experimental Psy-
chology: General 113, 256-281.
Geschwind, N. (1965). Disconnexion syndrome in animals and man. Brain, 88, 237-294, 585-
644.
Gibson, E. J. (1969). Principles of perceptual learning and development. New York: Appleton-
Century-Crofts.
Gibson, J. J. (1966). The senses considered as perceptual systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton-Mifflin.
Gildea, P., & Glucksberg, S. (1983). On understanding metaphor: The role of context. Journal
of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 22, 577-590.
Gillund, G., & Shiffrin, R. M. (1984). A retrieval model for both recognition and recall. Psy-
chological Review, 91, 1-67.
Glanzer, M., & Duarte, A. (1971). Repetition between and within languages in free recall. Jour-
nal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 10, 625-630.
Glass, A. L., Eddy, J. K., & Schwanenflugel, P. J. (1980). The verification of high and low imag-
ery sentences. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 6,
692-704.
Glass, A. L., Millen, D. R., Beck, L. G., & Eddy, J. K. (1985). Representation of images in
sentence verification. Journal of Memory and Language, 24, 442-465.
Glucksberg, S. (1984). Commentary: The functional equivalence of common and multiple
codes. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 23, 100-104.
Glucksberg, S., Trabasso, T., & Wald, J. (1973). Linguistic structures and mental operations.
Cognitive Psychology, 5, 338-370.
Goldman-Eisler, F. (1961). Hesitation and information in speech. In C. Cherry (F,d.), Infor-
mation theory. London: Butterworths.
Goldman-Eisler, F. (1968). Psycholinguist ics: Experiments in spontaneous speech. New York:
Academic Press.
286 References
Goodale, M. A. (1983). Vision as a sensorimotor system, in T. E. Robinson (Ed.), Behavioral
approaches to brain research. New York: Oxford University Press.
Goodnow, J. J. (1977). Children's drawing. London: Open Books.
Gordon, R. (1949). An investigation into some of the factors that favour the formation of ster-
eotyped images. British Journal of Psychology, 39, 156-167.
Graesser, A. C., Gordon, S. E., & Sawyer, J. D. (1979). Recognition memory for typical and
atypical actions in scripted activities: Tests of a script pointer plus tag hypothesis. Jour-
nal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 18, 319-332.
Greenwald, A. G. (1970). Sensory feedback mechanisms in performance control. Psychological
Review, 77, 73-99.
Griffin, D. R. (1976). The question of animal awareness. New York: Rockefeller University
Press.
Groninger, L. D., & Groninger, L. K. (1982). Function of images in the encoding-retrieval pro-
cess. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 8, 353-358.
Groninger, L. D., & Groninger, L. K. (1984). Autobiographical memories: Their relation to
images, definitions, and word recognition. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learn-
ing, Memory, and Cognition, 4, 745-755.
Guenther, R. K. (1980). Conceptual memory for picture and prose episodes. Memory & Cog-
nition, 8, 563-572.
Guilford, J. P. (1967). The nature of human intelligence. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Guilford, J. P. (1974). Rotation problems in factor analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 81, 498-
501.
Guilford, J. P. (1982). Cognitive psychology's ambiguities: Some suggested remedies. Psycho-
logical Review, 87, 48-59.
Guilford, J. P., & Hoepfner, R. (1971). The analysis of intelligence. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Haber. R. N. (1979). Twenty years of haunting eidetic imagery: Where is the ghost? The Behav-
ioral and Brain Sciences, 2, 583-629.
Haber, R. N., & Haber, R. B. (1964). Eidetic imagery: I. Frequency. Perceptual and Motor
Skills, 19, 131-138.
Hall, C. R. (1980). Imagery for movement. Journal of Human Movement Studies, 6, 252-264.
Hall, C. R. (1985). Individual differences in the mental practice and imagery of motor skill
performance. Canadian Journal of 'Applied Sport Sciences, 10:4, 17S-21S.
Hall, C. R., & Buckolz, E. (1983). Imagery and the recall of movement patterns. Imagination,
Cognition, and Personality, 12, 251-260.
Halliday, M. A. K., & Hasan, R. (1976). Cohesion in English. London: Longman.
Hamers, J. F., & Lambert, W. E. (1972). Bilingual interdependencies in auditory perception.
Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, II, 303-310.
Hammoud, R. (1982). Utilisation de I'image mental et du champ dissociations dans I'enseigne-
ment du vocabulaire arabe a des debutants adultes francophones [Use of mental imagery
and associative fields in the teaching of Arabic vocabulary to adult francophone
beginners]. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Laval University, Quebec, P.Q., Canada.
Hampson, P. J., & Duffy, C. (1984). Verbal and spatial interference effects in congcnitally blind
and sighted subjects. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 38, 411-420.
Hanley, G. L., & Levine, M. (1983). Spatial problem solving: The integration of independently
learned cognitive images. Memory & Cognition, 11, 415-422.
Harnad, S. (1982). Metaphor and mental duality. In T. W. Simon & R. J. Scholes (Eds.), Lan-
guage, mind, and brain. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Harris, P. L. (1975). Development of search and object permanence during infancy. Psycholog-
ical Bulletin, 82, 332-344.
Harris, P. L, (198.3). Infant cognition. In P. H. Musscn (Fd.), Handbook of child psychology:
Vol. 11. Infancy and developmental psychobtology. New York: Wiley.
Hasher, L., Ricbman, B., & Wren. F. (1976). Imagery and the retention of free-recall learning.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 2, 172-181.
References 287
Hatakeyama, T. (1981). Individual differences in imagery ability and mental rotation. Tohoku
Psychologies Folia, 40, 6-23.
Hayes-Roth, B. (1977). Evolution of cognitive structures and processes. Psychological Review,
84, 260-278.
Hayes-Roth, B., & Hayes-Roth, F. (1977). The prominence of lexical information in memory
representations of meaning. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 16, 119-
136.
Head, H. (1920). Studies in neurology. New York: Oxford University Press.
Healy, A. F. (1975). Coding of temporal-spatial patterns in short-term memory. Journal of Ver-
bal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 14, 481-495.
Healy, A. F. (1977). Pattern coding of spatial order information in short-term memory. Journal
of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 16, 491-437.
Hebb, D. O. (1949). The organization of behavior. New York: Wiley.
Hebb, D. O. (1961). Distinctive features of learning in higher animal. In J. F. Delafresnage
(Ed.), Brain mechanisms and learning. New York: Oxford University Press.
Hebb, D. O. (1980). Essay on mind. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Hebb, D. O., Lambert, W. E., & Tucker, G. R. (1971). Language, thought, and experience. The
Modern Language Journal, 55, 212-222.
Heidbreder, E. (1946). The attainment of concepts: I. Terminology and methodology. Journal
of General Psychology, 35, 173-189.
Hermelin, B., & O'Connor, N. (1982). Spatial modality coding in children with and without
impairments. In M. Potegal (Ed.), Spatial abilities. New York: Academic Press.
Hilgard, E. R. (1977). Divided consciousness: Multiple controls in human thought and action.
New York: Wiley.
Hintzman, D. L., & Block, R. A. (1971). Repetition and memory: Evidence for a multiple-trace
hypothesis. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 88, 297-306.
Hintzman, D. L., & Ludlam, G. (1980). Differential forgetting of prototypes and old instances:
Simulation by an exemplar-based classification model. Memory & Cognition, 8, 378-
382.
Hintzman, D. L., O'Dell, C. S., & Arndt, D. R. (1981). Orientation in cognitive maps. Cognitive
Psychology, 13, 149-206.
Hockett, C. F. (1963). The problem of universals in language. In J. H. Greenberg (Ed.), Uni-
versals of language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hoffman, R. R., & Nead, J. M. (1983). General contextualism, ecological science, and cognitive
research. The Journal of Mind and Behavior, 4, 507-560.
Hoffmann, J., Denis, M., & Ziessler, M. (1983). Figurative features and the construction of
visual images. Psychological Research, 45, 39-54.
Hollan, J. D. (1975). Features and semantic memory: Set-theoretic or network model? Psycho-
logical Review, 82, 154-155.
Holland, P. C. (1983). Representation-mediated overshadowing and potentiation of condi-
tioned aversions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 9, 1-
13.
Holmes, V. M., & Langford, J. (1976). Comprehension and recall of abstract and concrete sen-
tences. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 15, 559-566.
Holyoak, K. J. (1977). The form of analog size information in memory. Cognitive Psychology,
9, 31-51.
Holyoak, K. J., Dumais, S. T., & Mover, R. S. (1979). Semantic association effects in a mental
comparison task. Memory & Cognition, 7, 303-313.
Honeck, R. P., Riechmann, P., & Hoffman, R. R. (1975). Semantic memory for metaphor: The
conceptual base hypothesis. Memory & Cognition, 3, 409-415.
Horn, J. L., & Knapp, J. R. (1973). On the subjective character of the empirical base of Guil-
ford's structure-of-mtcllect model. Psychological Bulletin, 80, 33-43.
Horowitz, L. M., & Prytulak, L. S. (1969). Rcdintegrativc memory. Psychological Review, 76,
519-531.
288 References
Howe, M. L. (1985). The structure of associative memory traces. Canadian Journal of Psy-
chology, 39, 34-53.
Hubel, D. H., &'Wiescl, T. N. (1962). Receptive fields, binocular interaction, and functional
architecture in the cat's visual cortex. Journal of Physiology, 160, 106-154.
Hudson, J., & Nelson, K. (1984). Play with language: Overextensions as analogies. Journal of
Child Language, 11, 337-346.
Huey, E. B. (1908). The psychology and pedagogy of reading. New York: Macmillan. (Reprinted
1968, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press)
Hunt, E. B. (1978). Mechanics of verbal ability. Psychological Review, 85, 109-130.
Hunt, E. B., Frost, N., & Lunneborg, C. (1973). Individual differences in cognition: A new
approach to intelligence. In G. Bower (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation
(Vol. 7). New York: Academic Press.
Hunt, J. McV. (1961). Intelligence and experience. New York: Ronald.
Hunter, W. S. (1913). The delayed reaction in animals and children. Behavior Monographs, 2,
(Serial No. 6).
Huttenlochcr, J. (1968). Constructing spatial images: A strategy in reasoning. Psychological
Review, 75, 550-560.
Huttenlocher, J., & Kubicek, L. F. (1983). The source of rclatedness effects on naming latency.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 9, 486-496.
Intons-Peterson, M. J. (1983). Imagery paradigms: How vulnerable are they to experimenters'
expectations? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance,
9, 394-412.
Intraub, H., & Nicklos, S. (1985). Levels of processing and picture memory: The physical supe-
riority effect. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition,
11, 284-298.
Irwin, D. L, & Lupkcr, S. J. (1983). Semantic priming of pictures and words: A levels of pro-
cessing approach. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 22, 45-60.
Jaccarino, G. (1975). Dual-coding in memory: Evidence from temporal lobe lesions in man.
Unpublished Master's thesis, McGill University, Montreal.
Jacoby, L. L. (1978). On interpreting the effects of repetition: Solving a problem versus remem-
bering a solution. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 17, 649-667.
Jakobson, R., Fant, G. M., & Halle, M. (1951). Preliminaries to speech analysis. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
James, C. T., Thompson, J. G., & Baldwin, J. M. (1973). The reconstructive process in sentence
memory. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 12, 51 -63.
Janssen, W. H. (1976). Selective interference in paired-associate and free recall learning: Mess-
ing up the image. Acta Psychologica, 40, 35-48.
Jenkins, J. J., & Palermo, D. S. (1964). Mediation process and the acquisition of linguistic struc-
tures. In U. Bellugi & R. W. Brown (Eds.), The acquisition of language: Monographs of
the Society for Research in Child Development, 29, 141-169.
Jenkins,.!. J., & Russell, W. A. (1952). Associative clustering during recall. Journal of Abnormal
and Social Psychology, 4 7, 818-821.
Johnson, M. K. (1983). A multiple-entry, modular memory system. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), The
psychology of learning. New York: Academic Press.
Johnson, M. K., Kalian, T. L., & Raye, C. L. (1984). Dreams and reality monitoring. Journal
of Experimental Psychology: General, 113, 329-344.
Johnson, M. K., & Raye, C. L. (1981). Reality monitoring. Psychological Review, 88, 67-85.
Johnson, P. (1982). The functional equivalence of imagery and movement. Quarterly Journal
of Experimental Psychology, 34A, 349-365.
Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1972). The three-term series problems. Cognition, I, 57-82.
Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1983). Mental models. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Jolicoeur, P., & Landau, M. J. (1984). Effects of orientation on the identification of simple
visual patterns. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 38, 80-93.
References 289
Jones, M. K, (1974). Imagery as a mnemonic aid after left temporal lobectomy: Contrast
between material-specific and generalized memory disorders. Neuropsychologia, 12, 21-
30.
Jones-Gotman, M., & Milner, B. (1978). Right temporal lobe contribution to image-mediated
memory. Neuropsychologia, 16, 61-71.
Jonides, J., Kahn, R., & Rozin, P. (1975). Imagery instructions improve memory in blind sub-
jects. The Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 5(5), 424-426.
Jorgenson, C. C, & Kintsch, W. (1973). The role of imagery in the evaluation of sentences.
Cognitive Psychology, 4, 110-116.
Just, M. A., & Carpenter, P. A. (1976). Eye fixations and cognitive processes. Cognitive Psy-
chology, 8, 441-480.
Kammann, R. (1968). Associability: A study of the properties of associative ratings and the role
of association in word-word learning. Journal of Experimental Psychology Monographs,
78 (Whole No. 4, Pt. 2).
Katz, A. N. (1978). Differences in the saliency of sensory features elicited by words. Canadian
Journal of Psychology, 32, 156-179.
Katz, A. N. (1983). What does it mean to be a high imager? In J. C. Yuille (Ed.), Imagery,
memory, and cognition: Essays in honor of Allan Paivio. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erl-
baum Associates.
Katz, A. N., & Denny, P. (1977). Memory-load and concreteness in the order of dominance
effect for verbal concepts. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 16, 13-20.
Katz, A. N., & Paivio, A. (1975). Imagery variables in concept identification. Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 14, 284-293.
Kaufmann, F. (1980). Imagery, language, and cognition. New York: Columbia University
Press.
Keil, F. C. (1981). Constraints on knowledge and cognitive development. Psychological Review,
88, 197-227.
Kelley, H. P. (1964). Memory abilities: A factor analysis. Psychometric Monographs (Whole
No. 11).
Kellogg, G. S., & Howe, M. J. A. (1971). Using words and pictures in foreign language learning.
Alberta Journal of Educational Research, 17, 87-94.
Kerr, N. H. (1983). The role of vision in "visual imagery" experiments: Evidence from the
congenitally blind. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 112, 265-277.
Kerst, S. M., & Howard, J. H., Jr. (1977). Mental comparisons for ordered information on
abstract and concrete dimensions. Memory & Cognition, 5, 227-234.
Kerst, S. M., & Howard, J. H., Jr. (1978). Memory psychophysics for visual area and length.
Memory & Cognition, 6, 327-335.
Kieras, D. (1978). Beyond pictures and words: Alternative information-processing models for
imagery effects in verbal memory. Psychological Bulletin, 85, 532-554.
Kimura, D. (1982). Left-hemisphere control of oral and brachial movements and their relation
to communication. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 298, 135-
149.
King, D. L. (1973). An image theory of classical conditioning. Psychological Reports, 33, 403-
411.
Kintsch, W. (1974). The representation of meaning in memory. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erl-
baum Associates.
Kintsch, W., & van Dijk, T. A. (1978). Toward a model of text comprehension and production.
Psychological Review, 85, 363-394.
Kirby, J. R., & Das, J. P. (1976). Comments on Paivio's imagery theory. Canadian Psycholog-
ical Review, 17. 66-68.
Kirsner, K., Smith, M. C., Lockhart, R. S., King, M. L., & Jain, M. (1984). The bilingual lexi-
con: Language-specific units in an integrated network. Journal of Verbal learning and
Verbal Behavior, 23, 519-539.
290 References
Kiss, G. R. (1973). Grammatical word classes: A learning process and its simulation. In G. H.
Bower (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation. New York: Academic Press.
Kiss, G. R. (1975). An associative thesaurus of English: Structural analysis of a large relevance
network. In A. Kennedy & A. Wilkes (Eds.), Studies in long term memory. New York:
Wiley.
Klee, H., & Eysenck, M. W. (1973). Comprehension of abstract and concrete sentences. Journal
of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 12, 522-529.
Klix, F. & Metzler, P. (1982). Structural coding of pictures in human memory and its relation
to the representation of concepts. In F. Klix, J. Hoffman, & E. van der Mier (Eds.), Cog-
nitive research in psychology. Berlin: Verlag der Wissenschaften.
Koen, F. (1965). An intra-verbal explication of the nature of metaphor. Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 4, 129-133.
Kolers, P. A. (1963). Interlingual word association. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal
Behavior, 2, 291-300.
Kolers, P. A. (1973). Remembering operations. Memory & Cognition, I, 347-355.
Kolers, P. A. (1978). On the representation of experience. In D. Gerver & W. Sinaiko (Eds.),
Language interpretation and communication. New York: Plenum Press.
Kolers, P. A., & Brison, S. J. (1984). Commentary: On pictures, words, and their mental rep-
resentations. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 23, 105-113.
Kolers, P. A., & Gonzales, E. (1980). Memory for words, synonyms, and translations. Journal
of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 6, 53-65.
Kolers, P. A., & Roediger, H. L. (1984). Procedures of mind. Journal of Verbal Learning and
Verbal Behavior, 23, 425-449.
Kolers, P. A., & Smythe, W. E. (1979). Images, symbols, and skills. Canadian Journal of Psy-
chology, 33, 158-184.
Kolers, P. A., & Smythe, W. E. (1984). Symbol manipulation: Alternatives to the computational
view of mind. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 23, 289-314.
Kolers, P. A., & von Griinau, M. (1976). Shape and color in apparent motion. Vision Research,
16, 329-335.
Kosslyn, S. M. (1973). Scanning visual images: Some structural implications. Perception & Psy-
chophysics, 14, 90-94.
Kosslyn, S. M. (1980). Image and mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Kosslyn, S. M. (1981). The medium and the message in mental imagery: A theory. Psycholog-
ical Review, 88, 46-66.
Kosslyn, S. M., Holtzman, J. D., Farah, M. J., & Gazzaniga, M. S. (1985). A computational
analysis of mental image generation: Evidence from functional dissociations in split-
brain patients. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 114, 311-341.
Kosslyn, S. M., Pinker, S., Smith, G. E., & Schwartz, S. P. (1979). On the demystification of
mental imagery. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 2, 535-581.
Kosslyn, S. M., & Pomerantz, J. R. (1977). Imagery, propositions, and the form of internal
representations. Cognitive Psychology, 9, 52-76.
Kroll, J. F., & Potter, M. C. (1984). Recognizing words, pictures, and concepts: A comparison
of lexical, object, and reality decisions. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior,
23, 39-66.
Krueger, T. H. (1981). Imagery pattern in creative problem solving: A study of visualizing. Las
Cruces, NM: Encina Press.
Kuiper, N. A., & Paivio, A. (1977). Incidental recognition memory for concrete and abstract
sentences equated for comprehensibility. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 9, 247-
249.
Lachman, R. (1973). Uncertainty effects on time to access the internal lexicon. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 99, 199-208.
Lachman, R., & Mistler-Lachman, J. (1976). Dominance lexicale chez les bilingues [Lexical
dominance in bilinguals]. Bulletin de Psvchologie [Special issue], 281-288.
References 291
Lakatos, I. (1963-1964). Proofs and refutations. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Sci-
ence, XIV, pp. 1-25, 120-139, 221-245, 296-343.
Lakoff, G. (1971). On generative semantics. In D. D. Steinberg & L. A. Jacobovits (Eds.),
Semantics. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Lakoff, G. (1977). Linguistic gestalts. In Papers from the thirteenth regional meeting. Chicago:
Chicago Linguistic Society.
Lambert, W. E. (1969). Psychological studies of the interdependences of the bilingual's two
languages. In J. Puhvel (Ed.), Substance and structure of language. Los Angeles: Univer-
sity of California Press.
Lambert, W. E., Havelka, J., & Crosby, C. (1958). The influence of language acquisition con-
texts on bilingualism. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 56, 239-244.
Lambert, W. E., & Paivio, A. (1956). The influence of noun-adjective order on learning. Cana-
dian Journal of Psychology, 10, 9-12.
Lang, P. J. (1979). A bio-informational theory of emotional imagery. Psychophysiology, 16,
495-512.
Langer, S. K. (1948). Philosophy in a new key. New York: Mentor Books. (Original work pub-
lished 1942)
Lay, C. H., & Paivio, A. (1969). The effects of task difficulty and anxiety on hesitations in
speech. Canadian Journal of Behavioural Science, I, 25-37.
Lazarus, R. S. (1984). On the primacy of cognition. American Psychologist, 39, 124-129.
Lederman, S. J., Klatzky, R. L., & Barber, P. O. (1985). Spatial and movement-based heuristics
for encoding pattern information through touch. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
General, 114, 39-49.
Leeper, R. (1935). A study of a neglected portion of the field of learning—The development of
sensory organization. Journal of Genetic Psychology, 46, 41-75.
Leeper, R. (1951). Cognitive processes. In S. S. Stevens (Ed.), Handbook of experimental psy-
chology. New York: Wiley.
Leight, K. A. & Ellis, H. C. (1981). Emotional mood states, strategies, and state-dependency in
memory. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 20, 251 -275.
Leuba, C. (1940). Images as conditioned sensations. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 26,
345-351.
Leventhal, H. (1980). Toward a comprehensive theory of emotion. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.),
Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 13). New York: Academic Press.
Levin J. R. (1982). Pictures as prose-learning devices. In A. Flammer & W. Kintsch (Eds.),
Discourse processing. Amsterdam: North-Holland.
Levine, M., Jankovic, I. N., & Palij, M. (1982). Principles of spatial problem solving. Journal
of Experimental Psychology: General, 111, 157-175.
Ley, R. G. (1983). Cerebral laterally and imagery. In A. A. Sheikh (Ed.), Imagery: Current
theory, research, and application. New York: Wiley.
Ley, R. G., & Bryden, M. P. (1983). Right hemispheric involvement in imagery and affect. In
E. Perecman & J. Brown (Eds.), Cognitive processing in the right hemisphere. New York:
Academic Press.
Light, L. L., & Berger, D. E. (1974). Memory for modality: Within-modality discrimination is
not automatic. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 103, 854-860.
Light, L. L., Berger, D. E., & Bardales, M. (1975). Trade-off between memory for verbal items
and their visual attributes. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning &
Memory, 104, 188-193.
Lockhart, R. S., Craik, F. I. M., & Jacoby. L. (1976). Depth of processing, recognition, and
recall. In J. Brown (Ed.), Recall and recognition. New York: Wiley.
Lockhead, G. R. (1972). Processing dimensional stimuli: A note. Psychological Review. 79,
410-419.
Lockhead, G. R. & Evans, N. J. (1979). Emmert's imaginal law. Bulletin of the Psychonomic
Society, 13, 114-116.
292 References
Loftus, E. F., & Loftus, G. R. (1980). On the permanence of stored information in the human
brain. American Psychologist, 35, 409-420.
Lohr, J. M. (1976). Concurrent conditioning of evaluative meaning and imagery. British Jour-
nal of Psychology, 67, 353-358.
Lopez, M., & Young, R. K. (1974). The linguistic interdependence of bilinguals. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 102, 981-983.
Lowes, J. L. (1927). The road to Xanadu. London: Constable.
Lupker, S. J. (1979). The semantic nature of response competition in the picture-word interfer-
ence task. Memory & Cognition, 7, 485-495.
Lupker, S. J., & Katz, A. N. (1981). Input, decision, and response factors in picture-word inter-
ference. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 7, 269-
282.
Lupker, S. J., & Katz, A. N. (1982). Can automatic picture processing influence word judg-
ments? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 8, 418-
434.
Luria, A. R. (1961). The role of speech in the regulation of normal and abnormal behavior. New
York: Liveright.
Luria, A. R. (1973). The working brain: An introduction to neuropsychology. New York:
Penguin.
MacCorquodale, K., & Meehl, P. E. (1954). Edward C. Tolman. In W. K. Esles, S. Koch, K.
MacCorquodale, P. E. Meehl, C. G. Mueller, W. N. Schoenfcld, & W. S. Verplanck
(Eds.), Modern learning theory. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
MacLeod, C. M. (1976). Bilingual episodic memory: Acquisition and forgetting. Journal of Ver-
bal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 15, 347-364.
MacLeod, C. M., Hunt, E. B., & Mathcws, N. N. (1978). Individual differences in the verifica-
tion of sentence-picture relationships. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior,
17, 493-507.
Macnamara, J. (1972). Cognitive basis of language learning in infants. Psychological Review,
79, 1-13.
Madigan, S. (1983). Picture memory. In J. C. Yuille (Ed.), Imagery, memory, and cognition:
Essays in honor of Allan Paivio. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Magiste, E. (1984). Stroop tasks and dichotic translation: The development of interference pat-
terns in bilinguals. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cog-
nition, 10, 304-315.
Malgady, R. G., & Johnson, M. G. (1976). Modifiers in metaphors: Effects of constituent phrase
similarity on the interpretation of figurative sentences. Journal of Psycholinguistic
Research, 5, 43-52.
Mandler, G. (1975). Mind and emotion. New York: Wiley.
Mandler, G. (1980). Recognizing: The judgment of previous occurrence. Psychological Review,
87, 252-271.
Mandler, J. M. (1983). Representation. In P. H. Mussen (Ed.), Handbook of child psychology:
Cognitive development (Vol 3). New York: Wiley.
Mandler, J. M. (1984). Stories, scripts, and scenes: Aspects of schema theory. Hillsdale, NJ: Law-
rence Erlbaum Associates.
Mandler, J. M., & Parker, R. E. (1976). Memory for descriptive and spatial information in
complex pictures. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory,
2, 38-48.
Marks, D. F. (1972). Individual differences in the vividness of visual imagery and their effect
on function. In P. Sheehan (Ed.), The function and nature of imagery. New York: Aca-
demic Press.
Marks, D. F. (1973). Visual imagery differences in the recall of pictures. British Journal of Psy-
chology, 64, 17-24.
Marmor, G. S. (1975). Development of kinetic images: When docs the child first represent
movement in mental images? Cognitive Psychology, 7, 548-559.
References 293
Mannor, G. S. (1977). Mental rotation and number conservation: Are they related? Develop-
mental Psychology, 13, 320-325.
Marrnor, G. S., & Zaback, L. A. (1976). Mental rotation by the blind: Does mental rotation
depend on visual imagery? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and
Performance, 2, 515-521.
Marschark, M. (1978). Prose processing: A chronometric study of the effects of imagibility.
Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Western Ontario, London.
Marschark, M. (1979). The syntax and semantics of comprehension. In G. Prideaux (Ed.), Per-
spectives in experimental linguistics. Amsterdam: John Benjamins B. V.
Marschark, M. (1983). Semantic congruity in symbolic comparisons: Salience, expectancy, and
associative priming. Memory & Cognition, 11, 192-199.
Marschark, M., & Hunt, R. R. (1985). On memory for metaphor. Memory & Cognition, 13,
413-424.
Marschark, M., Katz, A. N., & Paivio, A. (1983). Dimensions of metaphor. Journal of Psycho-
linguistic Research, 12, 17-40.
Marschark, M., & Paivio, A. (1977). Integrative processing of concrete and abstract sentences.
Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 16, 217-231.
Marschark, M., & Paivio, A. (1979). Semantic congruity and lexical marking in symbolic com-
parisons: An expectancy hypothesis. Memory & Cognition, 7, 175-184.
Mathews, N. N., Hunt, E. B., & MacLeod, C. M. (1980). Strategy choice and strategy training
in sentence-picture verification. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 19,
531-548.
May, J. E., & Clayton, K. N. (1973). Imaginal processes during the attempt to recall names.
Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 12, 683-688.
McClelland, D. C. (1961). The achieving society. Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand.
McCormack, P. D. (1977). Bilingual linguistic memory: The independence-interdependence
issue revisited. In P. A. Hornby (Ed.), Bilingualism: Psychological, social, and educa-
tional implications. New York: Academic Press.
McCune-Nicolich, L. (1981). The cognitive bases of relational words in the single word period.
Journal of Child Language, 8, 15-34.
McFarland, C. E., Jr., Frey, T. J., & Rhodes, D. D. (1980). Retrieval of internally versus exter-
nally generated words in episodic memory. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal
Behavior, 19, 210-245.
McGee, M. G. (1982). Spatial abilities: The influence of genetic factors. In M. Potegal (Ed.),
Spatial abilities. New York: Academic Press.
McGonigle, B., & Chalmers, M. (1984). The selective impact of question form and input mode
on the symbolic distance effect in children. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology,
37, 525-554.
McGuigan, F. ). (1978). Cognitive Psychophysiology: Principles of covert behavior. Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
McKennell, A. C. (1960). Visual size and familiar size: Individual differences. British Journal
of Psychology, 51, 27-35.
McNeil!, D. (1979). The conceptual basis of language. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates.
Mervis, C. B., & Pani, J. R. (1980). Acquisition of basic color categories. Cognitive Psychology,
12, 496-522.
Miller, A. I. (1984). Imagery in scientific thought: Creating 20th century physics. Boston:
Birkhauser.
Miller, G. A. (1956). The magical number seven plus or minus two: Some limits on our capacity
for processing information. Psychological Review, 63, 81-97.
Miller, G. A. (1962). Some psychological studies of grammar. American Psychologist, 17, 748-
762.
Miller, G. A. (1979). Images and models, similes and metaphors. In A. Ortony (Ed.), Metaphor
and thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.
294 References
Mills, L., & Rollman, G. B. (1979). Left hemisphere selectivity for processing duration in nor-
mal subjects. Brain and Language, 7, 320-335.
Mills, L., & Rollman, G. B. (1980). Hemispheric asymmetry for auditory perception of tem-
poral order. Neuropsychologia, 18, 41-47.
Milner, B. (1973). Hemispheric specialization: Scope and limits. In F. O. Schmitt & F. G. Wor-
den (Eds.), The Neurosciences: Third study program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Milner, B. (1980). Complementary functional specializations of the human cerebral hemi-
spheres. In R. Levi-Montalcini (Ed.), Nerve cells, transmitters, and behavior. Vatican
City: Pontificia Academia Scientiarum.
Minsky, M. (1975). A framework for representing knowledge. In P. Winston (Ed.), The psy-
chology of computer vision. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Mistler-Lachman, J. L. (1975). Queer sentences, ambiguity, and levels of processing. Memory
& Cognition, 3, 395-400.
Moar, L, & Bower, G. H. (1983). Inconsistency in spatial knowledge. Memory & Cognition, 11,
107-113.
Moar, I., & Carleton, L. (1982). Memory for routes. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psy-
chology, 34A, 381-394.
Moeser, S. D., & Bregman, A. S. (1972). The role of reference in the acquisition of a miniature
artificial language. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 11, 759-769.
Moeser, S. D., & Bregman, A. S. (1973). Imagery and language acquisition. Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 12, 91-98.
Moran, T. (1973). The symbolic imagery hypothesis: A production system model. Unpublished
doctoral dissertation, Carnegie-Mellon University.
Mori, K., & Moeser, S. D. (1983). The role of syntactic markers and semantic referents in learn-
ing an artificial language. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 22, 701-718.
Morris, P. E., & Hampson, P. J. (1983). Imagery and consciousness. New York: Academic
Press.
Morris, P. E., & Stevens, R. (1974). Linking images and free recall. Journal of Verbal Learning
and Verbal Behavior, 13, 310-315.
Morrow, D. G. (1985). Preposition and verb aspects in narrative understanding. Journal of
Memory and Language, 24, 390-404.
Morton, J. (1969). Interaction of information in word recognition. Psychological Review, 76,
165-178.
Morton, J. (1979). Facilitation in word recognition: Experiments causing change in the logogen
model. In P. A. Kolers, M. Wrolstead, & H. Bouma (Eds.), Processing of visible language
(Vol. 1). New York: Plenum Press.
Moscovitch, M. (1979). Information processing and the cerebral hemispheres. In M. S. Gaz-
zaniga (Ed.), Handbook of behavioral neurobiology: Vol. 2. Neuropsychology. New York:
Plenum Press.
Mowrer, O. H. (1960). Learning theory and the symbolic processes. New York: Wiley.
Moyer, R. S. (1973). Comparing objects in memory: Evidence suggesting an internal psycho-
physics. Perception & Psychophysics, 13, 180-184.
Moyer, R. S. & Bayer, R. H. (1976). Mental comparisons and the symbolic distance effect.
Cognitive Psychology, 8, 228-246.
Moyer, R. S., Bradley, D, R., Sorensen, M. H., Whiting, J. C, & Mansfield, D. P. (1978). Psy-
chophysical functions for perceived and remembered size. Science, 200, 330-332.
Moyer, R. S., & Dumais, S. T. (1978). Mental comparison. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), The psychol-
ogy of learning and motivation. New York: Academic Press.
Murdock, B. B., Jr. (1974). Human memory: Theory and data. Potomac, MD: Lawrence Erl-
baum Associates.
Murdock, B. B., Jr. (1982). A theory for the storage and retrieval of item and associative infor-
mation. Psychological Review, 89, 609-626.
Murray. D. J. (1982). Rated associability and episodic memory. Canadian Journal of Psychol-
ogy, 36, 420-434.
Ncisser. U. (1967). Cognitive Psychology. New York: Appleton.
References 295
Neisser, U., & Kerr, N. (1973). Spatial and mnemonic properties of visual images. Cognitive
Psychology, 5, 138-150.
Nelson, D. L. (1981). Many are called but few are chosen: The influence of context on the effects
of category size. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation, 15,
129-162.
Nelson, D. L., & Brooks, D. H. (1973). Functional independence of pictures and their verbal
memory codes. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 98, 44-48.
Nelson, D. L., Reed, V. S. & Walling, J. R. (1976). Pictorial superiority effect. Journal of Exper-
imental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 2, 523-528.
Nelson, K. (1974). Concept, word, and sentence: Interrelations in acquisition and development.
Psychological Review, 81, 267-285.
Nelson, K. (1977). The syntagmatic-paradigmatic shift revisited: A review of research and the-
ory. Psychological Bulletin, 84, 93-116.
Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-
Hall.
Nickles, T. (1982). Introductory essay: Scientific discovery and the future of philosophy of sci-
ence. In T. Nickles (Ed.), Scientific discovery, logic, and rationality. Boston: D. Reidel.
Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on
mental processes. Psychological Review, 84, 231-259.
Noble, C. E. (1952). An analysis of meaning. Psychological Review, 59, 421-430.
Norman, D. A., & Rumelhart, D. E. (1975). Explorations in cognition. San Francisco: W. H.
Freeman.
O'Connor, N., & Hermelin, B. (1972). Seeing and hearing and space and time. Perception &
Psychophysics, 11, 46-48.
O'Connor, N., & Hermelin, B. (1978). Seeing and hearing and space and time. New York:
Academic Press.
Oldfield, R. C. (1966). Things, words, and the brain. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psy-
chology, 18, 340-353.
Olson, D. R. (1970). Language and thought: Aspects of a cognitive theory of semantics. Psy-
chological Review, 77, 257-273.
Olson, D. R., & Bialystok, E. (1983). Spatial cognition: The structure and development of mental
representations of spatial relations. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Olson, D. R., & Filby, N. (1972). On comprehension of active and passive sentences. Cognitive
Psychology, 3, 361-381.
O'Neill, B. (1971). Word attributes in dichotic recognition and memory. Unpublished doctoral
dissertation, University of Western Ontario, London.
O'Neill, B. J. (1972). Denneability as an index of word meaning. Journal of Psycholinguistic
Research, 1, 287-298.
O'Neill, B. J., & Paivio, A. (1978). Semantic constraints in encoding judgments and free recall
of concrete and abstract sentences. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 32, 3-18.
Ortony, A. (1975). Why metaphors are necessary and not just nice. Educational Theory, 25,
45-53.
Ortony, A. (1979). The role of similarity in similes and metaphors. In A. Ortony (Ed.), Meta-
phor and thought. New York: Cambridge University Press,
Osgood, C. E. (1953). Method and theory in experimental psychology. New York: Oxford Uni-
versity Press.
Osgood, C. E. (1963). Language universals and psycholinguistics. In J. H. Greenberg (Ed.), Uni-
versals in language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Osgood, C. E. (1971). Where do sentences come from? In D. D. Steinberg and L. A. Jakobovits
(Eds.), Semantics: An interdisciplinary reader in philosophy, linguistics, and psychology.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Osgood, C. E. (1973). The discussion of Dr. Paivio's paper. In F. J. McGuigan & R. A. Schoon-
over (Eds.), The psyche/physiology of thinking: Studies of covert processes. New York:
Academic Press.
296 References
Osgood, C. E., & Ervin, S. (1954). Second language learning and bilingualism. In C. E. Osgood
& T. A. Sebeok (Eds.), Psycholinguistics. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology,
49, 139-146.
Osgood, C. E., Suci, G. J., & Tannenbaum, P. H. (1957). The measurement of meaning.
Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.
Owens, J., Dafoe, J., & Bower, G. (1977). Taking a point of view: Character identification and
attributionalprocesses in story comprehension and memory. Paper presented at the Con-
vention of the American Psychological Association, San Francisco.
Paivio, A. (1963). Learning of adjective-noun paired-associates as a function of adjective-noun
word order and noun abstractness. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 17, 370-379.
Paivio, A. (1965a). Abstractness, imagery, and meaningfulness in paired-associate learning.
Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 4, 32-38.
Paivio, A. (1965b). Personality and audience influence, in B. A. Maher (Ed.), Progress in exper-
imental personality research (Vol. 2). New York: Academic Press.
Paivio, A. (1966). Latency of verbal associations and imagery to noun stimuli as a function of
abstractness and generality. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 20, 378-387.
Paivio, A. (1968). A factor-analytic study of word attributes and verbal learning. Journal of
Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 7, 41-49.
Paivio, A. (1969). Mental imagery in associative learning and memory. Psychological Review,
76, 241-263.
Paivio, A. (1971). Imagery and verbal processes. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
(Reprinted 1979, Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates)
Paivio, A. (1972). Symbolic and sensory modalities of memory. In M. E. Meyer (Ed.), The third
Western symposium on learning: Cognitive learning. Bcllingham, WA: Western Wash-
ington State College.
Paivio, A. (1973). Psychophysiological correlates of imagery. In F. J. McGuigan & R. A.
Schoonover (Eds.), The psychophysiology of thinking. New York: Academic Press.
Paivio, A. (1974a). Language and knowledge of the world. Educational Researcher, 3, 5-12.
Paivio, A. (1974b). Spacing of repetitions in the incidental and intentional free recall of pictures
and words. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 13, 497-511.
Paivio, A. (1975a). Coding distinctions and repetition effects in memory. In G. H. Bower (Ed.),
The psychology of learning and motivation (Vol. 9). New York: Academic Press.
Paivio, A. (1975b). Imagery and synchronic thinking. Canadian Psychological Review, 16, 147-
163.
Paivio, A. (1975c). Neomentalism. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 29, 263-291.
Paivio, A. (1975d). Perceptual comparisons through the mind's eye. Memory & Cognition, 3,
635-647.
Paivio, A. (1976a). Concerning dual-coding and simultaneous-successive processing. Canadian
Psychological Review, 17, 69-72.
Paivio, A. (1976b). Imagery in recall and recognition. In J. Brown (Ed.), Recall and recognition.
New York: Wiley.
Paivio, A. (1977). Images, propositions, and knowledge. In J. M. Nicholas (Ed.), Images, per-
ception, and knowledge. The Western Ontario Series in the Philosophy of Science. Bos-
ton: Reidel.
Paivio, A. (1978a). Comparison of mental clocks. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
Perception and Performance, 4, 61-71.
Paivio, A. (1978b). Dual coding: Theoretical issues and empirical evidence. In J. M. Scandura
and C. J. Brainerd (Eds.), Structural/process models of complex human behavior. Leiden,
The Netherlands: Nordhoff.
Paivio, A. (1978c). Imagery, language, and semantic memory. International Journal of Psycho-
linguistics, 5, 31-47.
Paivio, A. (1978d). Mental comparisons involving abstract attributes. Memory & Cognition, 6,
199-208.
References 297
Sloman, A. (1971). Interactions between philosophy and artificial intelligence: The role of intu-
ition and non-logical reasoning in intelligence. Artificial Intelligence, 2, 209-225.
Smith, E. E., Shoben, E. J., & Rips, L. J. (1974). Structure and process in semantic memory: A
featural model from semantic decisions. Psychological Review, 81, 214-241.
Smith, E. E., & Medin, D. L. (1981). Categories and Concepts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Uni-
versity Press.
Smythe, P. C. (1970). Pair concreteness and mediation instructions in forward and backward
paired-associate recall. Unpublished doctoral thesis, University of Western Ontario,
London, Ontario, Canada.
Snodgrass, J. G. (1984). Concepts and their surface representations. Journal of Verbal Learning
and Verbal Behavior, 23, 3-22.
Snodgrass, J. G., Burns, P. M, & Pirone, G. U. (1978). Pictures and words and space and time:
In search of the elusive interaction. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 107,
206-230.
Snodgrass, J. G., & Vanderwart, M. (1980). A standardized set of 260 pictures: Norms for name
agreement, image agreement, familiarity, and visual complexity. Journal of Experimen-
tal Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 6, 174-215.
Solso, R. L. & Raynis, S. A. (1979). Prototype formation from imaged, kinesthetically, and
visually presented geometric figures. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Per-
ception and Performance, 5, 701-712.
Sperling, G. (1960). The information available in brief visual presentations. Psychological
Monographs, 74, (Whole No. 498).
Spurgeon, C. F. E. (1935). Shakespeare's imagery and what it tells us. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Staats, A. W. (1961). Verbal habit families, concepts, and the operant conditioning of word
classes. Psychological Review, 68, 190-204.
Staats, A. W. (1968). Learning, language, and cognition. New York: Holt.
Steckol, K. L., & Leonard, L. B. (1981). Sensorimotor development and the use of prelinguistic
performatives. Journal of Speech and Hearing Research, 24, 262-268.
Stein, B. S., & Bransford, J. D. (1979). Constraints on effective elaboration: Effects of precision
and subject generation. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 18, 769-777.
Steinfeld, G. J. (1967). Concepts of set and availability and their relation to the reorganization
of ambiguous pictorial stimuli. Psychological Review, 74, 505-522.
Sternberg, R. J. (1980). Representation and process in linear syllogistic reasoning. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: General, 109, 119-159.
Sternberg, R. J. (1984). Toward a triarchic theory of human intelligence. Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 7,269-315.
Sternberg, R. J., & Weil, G. M. An aptitude-strategy interaction in linear syllogistic reasoning.
Journal of Educational Psychology, 72, 226-234.
Sternberg, S. (1967). Two operations in character recognition: Some evidence from reaction-
time measurements. Perception and Psychophysics, 2, 45-53.
Stremnes, F. J. (1973). A semiotic theory of imagery processes with experiments on an Indo-
European and a Ural-Altaic language. Do speakers of different languages experience dif-
ferent cognitive worlds? Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 14, 291-304.
Stremnes, F. J. (1979). The problem of the image: Can there be information in propositions?
Communications, 4, 259-275.
Stroop, J. R. (1935). Interference in serial verbal reactions. Journal of Experimental Psychology,
18, 643-661.
Suinn, R. M. (1983). Imagery and sports. In A. A. Sheikh (Ed.), Imagery: Current theory,
research, and application. New York: Wiley.
Tapley, S. M., & Bryden, M. P. (1977). An investigation of sex differences in spatial ability:
Mental rotation of three-dimensional objects. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 31, 122-
130.
304 References
Tatum, B. C. (1976). Stimulus imagery effect in associative learning: Differentiation or media-
tion? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 2, 252-261.
Taylor, I. (1971). How are words from two languages organized in a bilingual's memory? Cana-
dian Journal of Psychology, 25, 228-239.
te Linde, J. (1982). Picture-word differences in decision latency: A test of common-coding
assumptions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition,
8, 584-598.
te Linde, J., & Paivio, A. (1979). Symbolic comparisons of color similarity. Memory & Cogni-
tion, 3, 635-647.
Terrace, H. S. (1985). In the beginning was the "name." (1985). American Psychologist, 40,
1011-1028.
Thorndyke, P. (1977). Cognitive structures in comprehension and memory of narrative dis-
course. Cognitive Psychology, 9, 77-110.
Tolman, E. C. (1948). Cognitive maps in rats and men. Psychological Review, 55, 189-208.
Triesman, A. (1979). The psychological reality of levels of processing. In L. S. Cermak & F. I.
M. Craik (Eds.), Levels of processing in human memory. Hillsdale, N.I: Lawrence Erl-
baum Associates.
Tulving, E. (1972). Episodic and semantic memory. In E. Tulving & W. Donaldson (Eds.),
Organization of memory. New York: Academic Press.
Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of episodic memory. New York: Oxford University Press.
Tversky, A. (1977). Features of similarity. Psychological Review, 84, 327-352.
Tversky, B. (1969). Pictorial and verbal encoding in a short-term memory task. Perception &
Psychophysics, 6, 225-233.
Tversky, B. (1981). Distortions in memory for maps. Cognitive Psychology, 13, 407-433.
Tversky, B., & Flemenway, K. (1984). Objects, parts, and categories. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: General, 113, 169-193.
Underwood, B. J. (1965). False recognition produced by implicit verbal responses. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 70, 122-129.
Underwood, B. J. (1969). Attributes of memory. Psychological Review, 76, 559-573.
Underwood, B. J. (1975). Individual differences as a crucible in theory construction. American
Psychologist, 30, 128-134.
Underwood, B. J., & Schulz, R. W. (1960). Meaningfulness and verbal learning. Chicago:
Lippincott.
van Dijk, T. A., & Kintsch, W. (1983). Strategies of discourse comprehension. New York: Aca-
demic Press.
van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. New York: Oxford University Press.
Vanderwart, M. (1984). Priming by pictures in lexical decision. Journal of Verbal Learning and
Verbal Behavior, 23, 67-83.
Verbrugge, R. R., & McCarrell, N. S. (1977). Metaphoric comprehension: Studies in reminding
and resembling. Cognitive Psychology, 9, 494-533.
Wallace, B. (1984). Apparent equivalence between perception and imagery in the production
of various visual illusions. Memory & Cognition, 12, 156-162.
Warren, M. W. (1977). The effects of recall-concurrent visual-motor distraction on picture and
word recall. Memory & Cognition, 5, 362-370.
Warren, R. M., Obusek, C. J., Farmer, R. M., & Warren, R. P. (1969). Auditory sequence:
Confusion of patterns other than speech or music. Science, 164, 586-587.
Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20, 158-
177.
Weber, R. J., & Harnish, R. (1974). Visual imagery for words: The Hebb test. Journal of Exper-
imental Psychology, 102, 409-414.
Weinreich, V. (1953). Languages in contact. New York: Linguistic Circle of New York.
Wcxler, K., & Culicover, P. W. (1980). Formal principles of language acquisition. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Whitehousc, P. J. (1981). Imagery and verbal encoding in left and right hemisphere damaged
patients. Brain and Language, 14, 315-332.
References 305
Abelson, R., 27 Begg, L, 86, 104, 142, 148, 150, 154, 159,
Alba, J. W., 28, 149 168-71, 218, 220, 223, 229, 232, 239, 256,
Algom, D., 179 258
Allport, D. A., 71 Bellack, D. R., 219
Allport, F. H., 120 Bellezza, F. S., 169, 170
Anderson, J. R., 11, 41, 43, 44, 46, 48, 49, Belmore, S. M., 219
52, 81, 125, 129, 159, 163, 171, 196, 214, Berger, D. E., 150
273 Bergman, B., 179
Anderson, R. C, 132, 154, 167, 171, 224 Beritoff, J. S., 86, 274
Anderson, R. E., 151, 173 Berndt, R. S., 268-69
Anisfeld, M., 148 Besner, D., 191
Annett, J., 208 Belts, G. H., 101, 117
Antrobus, J. S., 208 Bever, T. G., 11
Arndt, D. R., 204-5 Bialystok, E., 46
Arnheim, R., 201 Bickley, W., 159
Arnold, M. B., 80, 274 Biederman, I., 165
Asch, S. E., 234 Bierwisch, M., 29
Asher, J. J., 257 Billow, R. M., 236
Atkinson, R. C, 38, 253 Binet, A., 37
Attneave, F., 59, 178 Bisiach, E., 264
Auble, P. M., 145 Black, J. B., 225
Black, M., 237
Blackmore, M., 150
Babbit, B. C., 160 Bleasdale, F., 143, 148
Baddeley, A. D., 70, 145, 156 Block, R. A., 181
Baggett, P., 226 Boles, D. B., 127, 261
Bahrick, H. P., 158 Bourne, L. E. Jr., 132
Bahrick, P., 158 Bousfield, W. K., 38, 70
Baker, L., 169 Bower, G. H., 11, 24, 39, 41, 43, 44, 48, 80,
Baldwin, J. M., 231 81, 129, 141, 159, 166, 171, 203, 214, 224-
Bandura, A., 86 25
Banks, W. P., 184, 189, 192 Bower, T. G. R., 88
Barber, P. O., 204 Bowerman, M., 217
Bardales, M., 150 Bradley, D. R., 178
Barresi, J., 246, 251-52 Braine, M. D. S., 92, 216
Barrett, B., 156 Brainerd, C. J., 84, 168
Bartlett, F. C., 27, 28, 38, 70 Bransford, J. D., 70, 145
Battig, W. F., 122 Bregman, A. S., 19, 27, 28, 42, 94, 175, 256
Baum, D. R., 180, 181 Bremner, J. G., 88
Bayer, R. H., 180 Brewer, W. F., 140, 154
Baylor, G. W., 50 Bridgman, P. W., 13
Beauvois, M. F., 267-68 Brison, S. J., 139
Beck, L. S., 222 Broadbent, D. E., 38
Beech,.!. R., 71 Brooks, D. H., 158
307
308 Author Index
Osgood, C. E., 22, 24, 29, 37, 51, 121, 231, Pylyshyn, Z. W., 5, 6, 9, 13, 44-48, 50, 155,
234, 235, 245 197, 209
Ovcrbey, G., 174
Owens, J., 224 Rabinowitz, J. C., 165
Rapoport, A., 125
Paivio, A., vii, 3, 10, 11, 13, 23, 26, 28, 36, Ratcliff, R., 125, 146
39, 44, 53, 56, 58-60, 64, 69, 71, 79, 81, Raye, C. L., 151
87, 93, 94, 99, 101-2, 106-7, 112-13, 117- Raynis, S. A., 89
19, 123, 125-28, 130, 132-33, 137, 143, Reed, H. B., 74
146-47, 151, 154-55, 157-64, 166-68, Reed, S. K., 210
170-72, 174, 180-87, 189-95, 197, 201-2, Reed, V. S., 152
206-8, 218, 220, 223, 227, 229, 232-33, Reese, H. W., 39
235-37, 239-41, 250-54, 256, 258, 261, Reich, P. A., 229
264, 270 Rescorla, R. A., 86
Palermo, D. S., 65, 92, 122, 216 Reynolds, A., 232-33
Palij. ML, 203, 205 Reynolds, J. H., 165
Palmer, S. E., 17, 18, 20, 29, 31, 44 Rhodes, D. D., 150
Pani, J. R., 27, 140 Rich, S., 101, 188
Paradis, M., 239 Richardson, A., 207
Parker, R. E., 165 Richardson, J. T. E., 39, 116, 154-56, 159,
Parkins, E. J., 274 166
Parmelee, C. M., 136 Riebman, B., 142
Paterson, J. G., 88 Riechmann, P., 235
Patterson, K., 261 Rips, L. J., 125
Pellegrino, J. W., 100, 132, 156 Roberts, M. M., 101
Perani, D., 264 Roberts, W. A., 203
Perfetti, C. A., 104 Robertson, R., 142
Perfetto, G. A., 145 Robins, C, 197
Peterson, L. R., 166 Rock, L, 19, 166
Peterson, M. J., 142, 159, 173, 178 Roediger, H. L. 111, 13,36
Philipchalk, R. P., 86, 172 Rogers, T. B., 79, 101
Piagct, J., 27, 42, 73, 84, 90, 93 Rohwcr, W. D. Jr., 39, 70
Piattelli-Palmarini, M., 84 Roitblatt, H. L., 22
Pichert, J. W., 224 Rollman, G. B., 269
Pickert, H. M., 167 Rosch, E., 27, 132, 228
Pierce, C. R., 178 Rosenberg, S., 145, 232, 239
Pierson, L., 206 Rosenfeld, J. B., 223
Pike, R., 146 Rosenquist, S. E., 219
Pinker, S., 44, 85, 179 Rosenthal, T. L., 87
Pirone, G. U., 172 Rosinski, R. R., 132, 134
Podgorny, P., 178 Rowe, E. J., 28, 167, 172
Poltrock, S., 191-92 Royce, J. R., 97
Pomerantz, J. R., 10, 44 Rozin, P., 169
Posner, M. L, 26, 74 Rubin, D. C, 159
Postman, L., 142 Rucker, R., 7
Potter, M. C., 128, 131, 134, 136, 138, 139, Rugg, H., 201
247-48 Rumelhart, D. E., 214, 225
Potts, G., 191-92 Runquist, W. N., 150, 152
Powell, G. D., 174 Russell, W. A., 38
Premack, D., 22 Russo, J. E., 151
Prentice, J. L., 232 Ryan, E. B., 247
Pressley, M., 91, 116, 253-54
Preston, M. S., 247 Saddler, C. D., 167
Pribram, K. H., 274 Sadoski, M.. 222, 228-29
Prytulak, L. S., 168 Saegert, J., 251-52
Author Index 313
Abilities, 96-119, 185-89, 193. See also Availability of information, 60-61, 71, 121,
Individual differences; Individual 126, 165, 203, 205
Differences Questionnaire; Structure-of-
intellect model Behaviorism, 4, 11, 24, 33-35, 37
associative, 107-8 Bilingualism, 57, 239-57. See also Second
dual coding theory of, 97-119 language learning
evaluative, 112-15 between vs. within language relations,
vs. habits, 99-100 242-44
imagery, 14, 99-101, 104, 106, 109-12, common coding theory, 239-40, 247-48,
185-88 252
imagery vividness, 117-19, 220 compound vs. coordinate, 244-46
mnemonic, 115-17 dual coding theory of, 240-44, 247-49,
organizational and transformational, 108- 252-57
12 and episodic memory, 240, 249-52
referential, 104-6 independence vs. interdependence, 239-
sensory specific, 101-2 40, 246-48
spatial, 100-101, 110, 187-88 and language switching, 244
verbal vs. nonverbal, 100-102 and semantic memory, 244-49
Abstract representations. See Propositions; translation vs. naming effects, 247-51
Representations Bizarreness of imagery, 166, 221, 236
Accessibility of information, 60, 205 Blindness, 157-58, 169, 197
Activation processes, 67-69, 121-26, 243- Block visualization task, 34, 110, 205
44, 247 Brain. See Cerebral hemispheres;
Analogue representations, 16-17, 49, 180- Neuropsychology
84, 189, 192-93, 196-98, 203-5
Analogy, extension by, 94 Categories, representation of, 26-27, 65, 132
Aphasia, 194, 265-69, 272 category decision latencies, 131-32
Articulatory processes, 143, 175, 181 category instance norms, 122
Artificial intelligence, 214. See also Cell assembly theory, 25-26, 37, 73, 274
Computation Cerebral hemispheres, 258-66
Associationism, 11 and emotion 271-72
Associations, word. See Verbal associations imagery and, 262-64, 269-71
Associative fluency, 107, 186-87 and lateralization of sensorimotor
Associative models, 43, 217 systems, 259
Associative overlap (feature overlap), 129- memory and, 261-63
30, 171, 227, 235 perceptual recognition and, 260-63
Associative processing, 69-70, 76, 107-8, Chunking, 165
127-30, 143-46, 242-44, 247, 268-69 Code independence/additivity hypothesis,
Associative-relatedness judgments, 133, 138 142, 150-52, 158-64, 228, 249-51,
Attributes, 24, 141, 192-93, 256. See also 266
Features Cognitive maps, 61, 203-5
Auditory-motor representations, 143, 274 Coherence (cohesion), 225-27
Auditory streaming, 175 Color processing, 64, 174-75, 194, 267-68
315
316 Subject Index
Mental practice and motor skills, 81, 207-9 Organizational processes, 38, 70-71, 108-9,
Mental rotation, 21, 93, 196-98, 264 142-45, 164-75. See also Sequential
apparent movement in, 197 organization and processing;
in cognitive maps, 204 Synchronous organization and
individual differences and, 197 processing
motor processes in, 197
verbal processes in, 197-98 Paired-associate learning, 144-47, 152-55,
Metaphor, 234-38 166-71
Meta-theory, 3-15 Parallel processing. See Synchronous
constructive empiricism, 15 organization and processing
and dual coding theory, 81-83 Paralogic, 9
formal vs. informal approaches, 6-10 Pattern perception, 26-28
observational vs. theoretical terms, 10-11 Perception/imagery, functional similarities,
operational concepts, 13-15 177-80
rationalist vs. empiricist views, 4-6 Perceptual memory representations, 144
terminal meta-postulate, 11-13 Perceptual recognition, 35, 103, 126-27
Mnemonic techniques, 71, 91, 116, 174, Phonemic features, 28
253-57 Phonemic memory code, 143
Modality-specific interference, 155-57 Picture naming, 123, 131. See also
Modality-specific representations and Referential processing
processes, 40, 54-58, 189, 266, 275 and bilingualism, 240, 247-51
abilities, 102 dual coding theory, 63
in bilingualism, 240-44 frequency effects, 128
in episodic memory, 75, 141-46, 149-58 individual differences, 104-6
in figurative language, 235 interference from words, 134
in sentence comprehension, 219, 221-22 neuropsychology of, 267-69
in symbolic comparisons, 187-89 Pictures and cerebral hemispheres, 260-61,
Modularity, 56, 214 267
Mood and recall, 80 Picture-sentence comparisons 222-24
Motivational functions, 78-80, 208 Picture vs. word effects, 261
Motor processes, 72-73, 81, 197, 205, 207-9, in associative-relatedness judgments,
269 133
Movements, memory for, 161-63 in episodic memory, 91, 160, 164, 171-72
Multidimensional scaling, 179 in language production, 233
priming and, 135-38
Nativism, 42-43, 56, 84-85 in semantic memory, 123, 131-39
Neomentalism, 37 in symbolic comparisons, 132, 181-85,
Network models, 122 187-88, 192-96
Neuropsychology and representation, 258- Pragmatism, 15
76. See also Cerebral hemispheres Priming effects, 135-38
dual coding theory of, 272-76 bilingualism and, 240, 249
emotion and, 271-72 and criticisms of dual coding theory, 137-
and functional interconnections, 266-69 38
methods of study, 258-59 of emotion by imagery, 271-72
sensorimotor vs. symbolic modalities, expectancy in symbolic comparisons, 189-
264-66 90
and sequential vs. synchronous processes, in metaphor comprehension, 237
269-71 of perceptual responses, 178
and verbal/nonverbal independence, 259- picture vs. word effects, 135-36
64 Problem solving, 34, 201-3
imagery and verbal processes in, 201-3,
Object permanence, 88 207
Operationism and dual coding theory, 13- in logic and science, 6-9, 207
14, 82-83 Procedural memory, 140
320 Subject Index