Christopher Falzon - Ethics Goes To The Movies - An Introduction To Moral Philosophy-Routledge (2018)
Christopher Falzon - Ethics Goes To The Movies - An Introduction To Moral Philosophy-Routledge (2018)
Key Features
Christopher Falzon
First published 2019
by Routledge
52 Vanderbilt Avenue, New York, NY 10017
and by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2019 Taylor & Francis
The right of Christopher Falzon to be identified as author of this work
has been asserted by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the
Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or
utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now
known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in
any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing
from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or
registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation
without intent to infringe.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
A catalog record for this title has been requested
ISBN: 978-1-138-93819-9 (hbk)
ISBN: 978-1-138-93820-5 (pbk)
ISBN: 978-1-315-67580-0 (ebk)
Typeset in Times New Roman
by Deanta Global Publishing Services, Chennai, India
Contents
Acknowledgments vii
Filmography 273
Glossary 277
Bibliography 288
Index 300
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank my colleagues William Herfel, Joe Mintoff, Michael Newton,
Timothy O’Leary, Sarah Rice and Tim Stanley who were kind enough to read
through various chapters and to give me the benefit of their special expertise; Tim
Madigan and an anonymous reviewer for their tremendously helpful comments
on the text as a whole; Penny Craswell for casting her expert eye over the text and
saving it from all sorts of inelegancies; and Andy Beck, my editor at Routledge,
for his ongoing support and patience. This book is dedicated to Penny Craswell,
who has also been very patient.
Introduction
Rear Window Ethics
‘We’ve become a race of peeping Toms. What people ought to do is get outside
their own house and look in for a change. Yes, sir. How’s that for a bit of home-
spun philosophy?’ So says visiting insurance nurse Stella about the activities of
her charge, L.B. ‘Jeff’ Jefferies, in Hitchcock’s classic Rear Window. Wheelchair-
bound with a broken leg, cooped up with nothing to do, he has taken to passing the
time by staring out of the rear window of his apartment, watching the neighbours
in his block go about their lives. As is well-known, Rear Window unfolds as a
murder mystery as Jeff tries to work out if the bedridden woman across the way
has been murdered by her husband. But the film also includes some reflection on
what Jeff himself is doing in the film. Stella is sure that there’s something prob-
lematic about Jeff’s obsessive neighbour-watching. She thinks that those who
indulge in such activity really ought to stop and think about what they are doing.
Even Jeff comes to wonder about his activity, at least for a moment. As he says
later to his girlfriend Lisa, who has her own concerns, ‘I wonder if it’s ethical to
watch a man with binoculars, and a long-focus lens … Do you suppose it’s ethical
even if you prove he didn’t commit a crime? As Lisa says, it’s a question of ‘rear
window ethics’.
So, ethical reflection is coming into this film at a number of levels. Stella
and Lisa wonder about the ethics of Jeff’s behaviour, as does he. In addition, the
viewer may have their own thoughts about Jeff’s activity. Is all this surveillance
justified in the interests of solving a crime or is that simply an excuse to look? Is
Jeff a detective or a pervert, or perhaps a bit of both? And these are interesting
questions for the viewer to consider since Rear Window can readily be seen as
offering a metaphor for cinema and movie-watching. The scenes in the apartment
windows are like silent movies. Jeff himself is very much like a moviegoer, the
immobilised watcher who watches, unseen, in the dark. For their part, the mov-
iegoer is able to secretly go places and watch things that they would not ordinarily
be able to in real life. In considering the ethics of Jeff’s activities, the viewer is
also in a position to think about the ethics of their own movie-watching activity.
Is watching movies a form of voyeurism? Can it amount to the violation or exploi-
tation of those being watched? These concerns and questions notwithstanding,
2 Introduction
everyone involved in Rear Window is completely absorbed in the activity they
are raising questions about. Whatever his misgivings, Jeff can’t tear himself away
from the window; and despite their initial concerns, Stella and Lisa are quickly
drawn into Jeff’s surveillance activities. And so, of course, are the film’s view-
ers. As Pauline Kael pointed out many years ago, it is precisely ‘the opening into
other, forbidden or surprising kinds of experience’ that draws viewers to the mov-
ies in the first place (Kael 1970, 105).
If what the film is showing us provokes ethical questions and concerns in char-
acters and viewers alike, the viewer is also, uniquely, in a position to use the film
to explore these ethical views and concerns, to interrogate them in the light of
the film experience. This book is a more extended and systematic version of that
exercise. It is an introduction to ethical thinking, in particular the kind of system-
atic ethical thinking that has been undertaken for centuries by philosophers. And
it makes use of some recent and not-so-recent films to illustrate and explore some
of the key theories, arguments and problems that have emerged in the history of
ethics. I should say that using film for the purpose of exploring various aspects
of philosophy is not an especially novel thing to do. Films, along with television,
have enjoyed a good deal of popularity in recent years as an avenue for talking
about philosophical positions and issues. There are many books that have gone
down this avenue, including a number of excellent introductions to ethics. What
this book does that might be new is to take this approach in relation to an entire
history of ethical thinking.
Considering ethical thinking historically means that there is a progression
of ideas to consider, and a natural logic to the ordering of the ideas, since later
accounts respond to, contend with or distance themselves from earlier ones. But
we are not simply visiting a dusty museum of superseded thoughts. The history
of ethical thinking is also a history of the present, insofar as these ideas continue
to speak to and inform contemporary ways of thinking. And films are a useful
medium to employ in exploring the contemporary relevance of these ideas because
films are inevitably contemporary in their content and references. This is not to
forget all the changes in context, outlook and style that have occurred over the last
hundred years or so of film history. For all that, film remains a modern art. Even
history films have to speak to and resonate with modern audiences, which is why
they can so readily introduce anachronistic elements into their portrayals of his-
torical figures and events. A film like Agora, for example, might be seen as reading
the early modern confrontation between science and dogmatic religion back into
the confrontation between classical antiquity and a rising Christianity. Even in this,
the film is providing a measure of how certain ideas and viewpoints have become a
part of contemporary ways of thinking. And in using films to talk about views that
have emerged in the history of ethical thinking, one has a measure not only of how
far these historical views continue to speak to contemporary experience, but also
how these views have entered into and become part of that experience.
This is not to reduce the films being discussed here to no more than means for
talking about ethics. First, any use of films to talk about ethics is at the same time
a way of talking about the films. Seeing a character or their actions as providing
Introduction 3
an illustration or instantiation of some ethical view or concept is already a way of
thinking about what is going on in the film. Moreover, ethical views or ideas may
be invoked or alluded to in the film by the characters themselves in talking about
other characters or themselves. This makes talking about these views very much
a matter of talking about the film. Beyond this, the film is going to be more than
just a means for discussing ethics simply because talking about a film in terms of
its philosophical or ethical relevance can never really exhaust what is going on in
the film. A film is not an ethical treatise, a philosophical work. It has a life of its
own and there will always be more going on in it than the illustration or instantia-
tion of ethical views. There will be the story to get on with, and lives to portray,
and non-philosophical concerns, artistic, dramatic or comic concerns are going to
come into play in terms of what is being presented.
By the same token, that a film has a life of its own, and will be governed
significantly by non-philosophical concerns, is not incompatible with a film hav-
ing philosophical or ethical content. It would be odd to argue that films, simply
by virtue of having non-philosophical concerns, are unable to engage with such
content. Indeed, this can be expressed more positively: that a film is irreducible to
any philosophical or ethical ideas it might illustrate or instantiate arguably means
that there is room in film for a critical engagement with these ideas. Certainly, a
film may be set up to do little more than promote a certain viewpoint or way of
thinking. There are plenty of didactic, moralistic and propagandistic films of this
sort. But films can also reflect on and challenge the perspectives and positions
they portray in various ways, through playfulness, irony, even downright subver-
sion (see Stam 2000, 139; Wilson 1986, 13). And it can be very much part of their
artistry, drama or comedy that they do so.
So, the suggestion is that reflection on philosophical or ethical ideas might
take place through the workings of a film, which is able to portray these ideas in
various lights, positive or negative. The philosophical text is not the only context
in which such critical reflection can take place. Admittedly, this book does not
go too far down this path. That is, it does not seek to explore how a film might be
philosophical or ethical in its own right, without in any way serving to illustrate
or engage with philosophical or ethical positions in the literature. No doubt, like
Hitchcock’s notion of pure cinema, there is pure film-philosophy, pure cinematic
ethics. This is not the concern of the present book. The overriding purpose here
remains that of introducing ethical positions from the history of ethical thinking,
so the films remain to that degree subordinated to the philosophy. Nonetheless,
films are not subordinate insofar as they have resources to reflect on any ethical
views they might be thought to illustrate or instantiate, to interrogate them even
as they portray them. These ideas are not only concretely illustrated in the films
but also, in being refracted through the lens of cinematic experience, are able to
be studied from a number of different angles.
The aim here as mentioned is to use films to talk about an entire history of
ethics. That a historical film can readily introduce anachronistic elements into its
picture of the past reminds us that any history is going to be, to some extent, a
‘history of the past in terms of the present’. One can safely assume that the history
4 Introduction
of ethical thinking is far messier than what is being portrayed in this book, which
is a more or less smooth and continuous progression from ancient thinking to
recent ethical thought. But in the end, the same could probably be said of any his-
tory. This does not necessarily make the history wrong, only necessarily partial. It
should just be kept in mind that the history of ethics being presented here is not the
whole story. Apart from anything else, there are some glaring omissions, such as
Emotivism and other ethical views from twentieth-century analytic philosophy; as
well as the moral views of Pragmatist figures like John Dewey. Most obviously,
it is very much a story of one tradition of ethical thinking only, namely, Western
ethical thinking. It has nothing to say about non-Western ethics. And with regard
to the discussion of religious ethics, the religion is restricted to the Christianity
that happened to become dominant in the West in the medieval period.
What Is Ethics?
I have been referring rather vaguely to ethical thinking and to unspecified ethical
theories, positions, views and ideas that we will be exploring. Before proceed-
ing any further, it will be useful to consider what might be understood by the
notion of ethics. No special distinction is being made between ethics and morality
here. One term comes from the Greek (ethos) and the other from Latin (mores),
meaning customs, manners or social norms. And while there are of course ethical
theories, and a history of such theories, ethics is not something we encounter first
as abstract theory, ‘moral philosophy’, a branch of philosophy. Rather it is in the
first instance something utterly practical, very much part of everyday life. One
does not need to be a philosopher to be acquainted with it. Living a life is enough.
Ethics here is thinking about how we should live that life and what sort of person
we ought to be. And the ethical dimension of everyday life is the more or less
organised framework of norms, values and commitments that embody our sense of
how we ought to live, the sort of life we aspire to, in terms of which we ordinarily
think about what to do, make our decisions and act.
A life without such a framework, in which we just did whatever we were
moved to do by immediate wants and desires, would be at the very least an under-
developed one. Very young children might qualify. They are not yet responsible
moral agents, able to play a role in the dramas of life. But while some adults do
of course act childishly, a framework of norms and values is not something moral
agents can easily do without. We cannot lead our lives without making choices
that show we think that some things are more important than others. Ordinarily,
we are committed to being a certain sort of person, to living a certain kind of life;
and this requires us to adhere to a framework of justification and criticism, the
‘horizon of evaluation’ in terms of which we reflect and weigh up the choices
and actions we undertake. This set of commitments and values is central to who
we are, our ‘identity’. Such an orienting framework is necessary if we are to be
agents at all. To lose it would not amount to a liberation but a terrifying experi-
ence of disintegration. It would be precisely an ‘identity crisis’, a breakdown, a
catastrophic loss of orientation. In such a state, we would no longer know where
Introduction 5
we stood, how to choose, what actions to pursue and we would be crippled as
agents (see Taylor 1985a, 34–35).
Thus, ethics, understood as a set of values or ideals concerning how to live that
goes beyond mere survival, is not an optional extra but an essential part of being
a functioning human being, a responsible moral agent. It defines who one is and
where one stands in the world, and at the same time, what one aspires to or tran-
scends oneself towards. Whatever particular form it takes, ethics always involves
some form of self-transcendence or self-overcoming. We can equally say that it
is a distinguishing mark of human beings that they are the creatures for whom the
ethical question can arise: how should I live? What kind of life do I want? (Malik
2014, 184). While this is the kind of question one might associate particularly
with twentieth-century existentialism, it would be better to say that existentialism
is the philosophy especially concerned with asking this distinctively human ques-
tion. It is also the question that was especially important to the Greeks, right at the
beginning of systematic moral reflection. Socrates, in Plato’s Republic says that
‘we are discussing no small matter, but how we ought to live’. It is not perhaps the
kind of question that can be associated so readily with modern moral philosophy
to the extent that the latter has been a highly theoretical exploration of grounds or
basic principles underlying moral judgements.
So, ethics is not in the first instance a matter of philosophical theory, but some-
thing to be lived. As James Griffin suggests, ethics in this sense of a lived ethics
appears early in the life of a culture (Griffin 2015, 1). As a culture develops, roles
are established that involve adherence to particular norms of behaviour. And indi-
viduals are inculcated into that culture, developing as individuals in the process
insofar as they imbibe its norms in the course of socialisation. They are then able to
take part in that society, play various roles within it, participate in its dramas. This
is not to say that life is simply the slavish reproduction of pre-existing formulae, of
the customary ways of doing things that we may have absorbed from our culture.
Otherwise, morality would never change or evolve. But nor however are we ever
completely our own creation, however much we might like to imagine ourselves so.
We inevitably acquire some kind of ethical framework for living from our culture
in the course of growing up, in the process of becoming who we are. However, this
ethical apparatus is also something that gets put to the test in the course of living,
sometimes being modified or even coming completely undone in the process.
What about the various philosophical theories of ethics, the history of which
is the subject of this book? These ethical theories are not entirely distinct from
lived ethics, but rather, parasitic upon it. What usually happens is that philoso-
phers come along and try to provide lived ethics with foundations, to discern
what characterises or underpins moral judgements, to bring ethics under a set of
simple rules or principles. What these days is known as normative ethical theory
aims to produce some kind of coherent, systematic account of what makes moral
judgements correct, in terms of some fundamental principle that defines a feature
common to all correct moral judgements. On the basis of some such principle,
philosophers have been inspired to justify, affirm and also criticise, even try to
reform, existing values, norms and ways of behaving.
6 Introduction
But it is important to stress that ethics does not wait for philosophers to provide
it with theoretical foundations. That sort of theorising happens after the event,
the event being the moral training that starts in early childhood. Equally, a con-
nection to life is necessary even for the most general ethical theory. Sometimes
these theories claim to rely on intuitions about the nature of the good, access to
divine revelation or the deliverances of pure reason in order to arrive in an a priori
manner at principles that can provide a foundation for lived ethics. But however
it might be arrived at, a general theory of ethics without any intrinsic reference to
life would be empty and irrelevant. Equally, no matter how abstract, ethical theo-
ries generally involve some idea of how to live, bound up with a broad conception
of what it is to be a human being and also of the larger world in which one exists.
Even a highly theoretical account like that of the eighteenth-century philosopher
Kant in the end exhorts us to live a certain way, to be what we are, namely rational
beings whose reason lifts us above nature, and to never fall below that to become
a mere thing, pushed around by natural forces.
Nonetheless, it is an occupational hazard for theoretical accounts that in their
efforts to systematise lived ethics, or to subordinate it to simple rules or princi-
ples, life can end up being subordinated to theory, leaving us with an ethics that
is unliveable, and hence inhuman. How else could there emerge such improbably
superhuman figures as the entirely rational Kantian agent, or for that matter, the
god-like Stoic sage or the all-knowing utilitarian calculator? This inhumanity is
a problem for an ethical theory. As one commentator puts it, ‘if ethics retreats to
a fantasy world, providing dictates that could guide only the infinitely rational,
impartial, all-knowing agent, then it loses its interest and value to our societies’
(Hayward 2017). It is an at least necessary condition for any conception of how
we ought to live that it is physically and psychologically possible for human
beings to live in the way prescribed.
It is true that ethics involves the aspiration to certain ideals of behaviour. To
that extent it is a form of transcendence, of going beyond or overcoming one-
self. And every person who aspires to be a certain sort of person, to live a certain
life, engages in this transcendence. This is why a moral agent cannot be reduced
to a thing, and ethics cannot be exhaustively accounted for in purely objective,
scientific terms. But nor can we entirely transcend our bodies, become pure
subjects. The physical and psychological capacities of human beings always
have a bearing on ethical life. Perhaps some people can rise higher than others,
so we cannot judge what human beings are capable of just by what the ‘ordi-
nary person’ can manage. But whatever the case, none of us can aspire to what
is physically or psychologically beyond human beings as such. This suggests
that the constraints on ethics are ultimately practical. Ethics should concern
itself with what falls within the limits of human capacity (see Hayward 2017).
A theory-driven ethics that is not ultimately grounded in human life and what
human beings are capable of achieving is not only of no positive use or value.
It can indeed be positively dangerous. It can become a tool for terrorising life,
a basis for tormenting or brutalising people insofar as they fall short, as they
inevitably must, of the impossible ethical ideal.
Introduction 7
Film as Experimental
If ethical positions have a fundamental connection to the practical, and to what
people are capable of doing in practice, they are not immune from being put to the
test of experience, the practical experience of living. For a lived ethics, merely to
live is to put oneself to the test. And what is being put to the test in these ‘experi-
ments in living’, to borrow a notion from John Stuart Mill, is not some hypothesis
or theory, but we ourselves, as defined by the values or ideals that constitute our
identity as moral agents.
Most straightforwardly, we can be put to the test as moral agents simply by
encountering challenging circumstances, which concretely pose the question of
whether we are able to live up to our defining ideals in practice. These are not
experiments concerned with exploring human biology or psychology, but with
human beings as moral subjects; though once again, human biology and psychol-
ogy have a role to play since they provide the capacities we have to work with as
moral beings and the ultimate constraints on the sort of person we can be. Further,
if even general ethical theories and positions have to have some connection to the
practical and can only require of people what they are capable of doing if they
are going to be meaningful, they are similarly not immune from the test of expe-
rience. If an ethical theory was to formulate an ideal of conduct that could only
be attained by a superhuman being, and which no ordinary human being could
live up to in practice, that would be a significant problem for the theory. To that
extent, even abstract moral theories are at risk of disconfirmation in the light of
experience and the experiment of trying to live the theory in practice affords us
the opportunity to reflect on the theory in question.
Experiments in living are intrinsically dangerous in the sense that they expose
us to the possibility of failure. Most straightforwardly, there is the risk of falling
short of our defining ideals in practice. The stakes in such experiments are not
simply epistemological. Failure to conform to expectations represents not just dis-
confirmation but self-betrayal, an occasion for guilt, embarrassment and humili-
ation – not to mention an opportunity for lying and self-deception as one tries to
preserve one’s conception of oneself, and one’s estimation in the eyes of others.
The connections between experiment, experience and danger are reflected in the
very language we use. Experiment and experience once meant the same thing, and
they share the Latin root expereri (to try, to test), which is itself linked to the word
for danger (periculum).
We can, however, envisage experiments in living in which we are removed
from the lives being lived and the risks this experimentation entails. We can
envisage hypothetical scenarios, fictional stories or narratives, which provide an
occasion for reflecting in an extended way on possible forms of life and views
about how one should live. Being fictional here does not amount to being false,
only to that which is ‘fictioned’, that is, fabricated or constructed (see O’Leary
2009, 86–88). This is one way of thinking about the function of the fictive arts,
including films as a contemporary art form. Like novels and plays, films can be
seen as offering experimental scenarios in which moral agents, ideals and views
8 Introduction
of life can be explored and tested. Narrative film seems particularly well-placed
to run such virtual experiments. It is an art form that engages directly with expe-
rience, that confronts the viewer in a visceral way, as well as being able to por-
tray relatable characters with some structure of values, ideals and commitments,
experimental subjects able to be put to the test.
With respect to ethical theories, these as noted must also have some connec-
tion with the practical. They have to be able to be lived in practice. So even a
highly theoretical account like Kant’s exhorts us to live a certain way, to live up
to a certain ideal of conduct, to be a certain kind of character. As such, through
characters, actions and lives that illustrate or embody them, ethical theories can
be concretely portrayed in film; and we can also ask critical questions about them.
The question might be posed for example as to whether it is possible in practice
for human beings to live up to the ideal of how to live, or be the kind of ideal char-
acter, that is envisioned in the theory. Or we might consider how far a complex
human and moral reality that is being portrayed in the film can be captured by the
theory. And it may be that the theory is going to be found wanting or inadequate
when put to the test of experience in these ways.
Of course, a film can also be questioned in connection with the ideas and posi-
tions that it portrays. Insofar as the film invokes a theoretical view or position, the
position may be misconstrued or oversimplified. As an instance, Nietzsche, part
of whose ‘posthumous life’ has been in the movies, and one of the few philoso-
phers to make regular appearances there, is regularly misrepresented. Aside from
this, a film may portray undeveloped characters and contrived, unrealistic scenar-
ios. It may recycle well-worn cinematic conventions and stock characters, so that
in the end it only references other films, a movie universe with movie heroes and
villains. Or it may uncritically take on and amplify conventional views circulat-
ing through the culture that offers a mythological or ideologically distorted view
of the world or of ourselves. In this role, the film acts as no more than a means of
perpetuating these views and is essentially part of the problem. But while films
may be constructed to do no more than confirm, reproduce and reinforce prevail-
ing myths, they are also able to invoke aspects of our experience that resist and
go beyond such representations, reminding us that experience that is richer, more
diverse or more complex than these representations allow. In so doing, they can
challenge not only those cultural myths but also film’s sometime complicity in
perpetuating them. This is the experimental film as both cultural critique and cin-
ematic self-critique.
Film understood as experimental, in this broad sense of offering a narrative
through which characters, ethical positions or forms of thinking can be critically
examined, explored and tested, has affinities with the thought experiments found
within philosophical texts. These too are fictional narratives, hypothetical scenar-
ios offering a mode of critical reflection. That is an aspect that some film philoso-
phers have emphasised, arguing that it makes sense to think of some fiction films
as working in ways that philosophical thought experiments do, questioning exist-
ing views, posing counter-examples, exploring what is essential to a concept and
Introduction 9
so on; and in that regard, as not only capable of illustrating philosophical ideas
and themes, but of ‘doing philosophy’ (Wartenberg 2007, 67). However, there are
also some significant differences between film and philosophical thought experi-
ments, one being that film is more emphatically invested in experience. Whereas
the philosophical thought experiment is austere and sketchy, the film narrative is
richly detailed. Where philosophical experiments focus on concepts rather than
people, and don’t engage the audience, cinematic narratives give access to con-
duct, characters and extended stories involving the audience in their characters’
lives and fate. And unlike even literary narratives, films do not merely describe
but show things in detail, especially faces, gestures and conduct, communicating
their significance directly.
These differences have led some to argue that there are too many disanalo-
gies for film to be understood as philosophising or reflecting in this way (see
Wartenberg 2011, 19–21). But rather than trying to judge film in terms of the
narrow model of the philosophical thought experiment, it seems more fruitful to
argue that the differences film as film brings to the table, particularly the ability to
show experience in a richly detailed way, enhance its capacity to engage in narra-
tive experimentation, to invoke challenging experiences, in ways that go beyond
what is possible within the philosophical text. As Damien Cox and Michael
Levine put it, through its relative richness of detail, film can ‘sometimes provide
nuanced investigation of fundamental features of experience well beyond the ordi-
nary achievements of written philosophical texts, and in doing so robustly refute
hollow and simplistic ways of understanding life’ (Cox and Levine 2012, 12).
In other words, film precisely as film is well placed to present experimental sce-
narios in which moral theories and forms of understanding can be put to the test of
experience. And the experiment in question is not the abstract thought experiment
but the concrete experiment in living.
In Jonathon Glazer’s 2013 Under the Skin, a remarkable and rather d isturbing
scene unfolds in a quiet, understated way. On a beach, a woman watches a
swimmer emerge from the ocean and walk towards her. The two of them are
alone except for a family further down the beach. The family’s dog is swim-
ming in the rough surf. Suddenly there is the sound of screaming. The dog is
in trouble. A woman is in the water, swimming out, trying to rescue the dog.
Now she is also in trouble. Her husband dives in after her, their baby left on the
beach. The swimmer runs back into the ocean to rescue the husband, who once
brought back to the beach immediately breaks free and goes back into the water
to try to save his wife. The woman with whom the scene began has a different
reaction. She watches the tragedy unfold impassively, with complete indiffer-
ence. Then she walks down to the swimmer, who has returned to the beach and
is lying exhausted on the sand. She picks up a rock and strikes him with it, and
then drags him off the beach, leaving the crying baby to its fate, which is very
likely death from exposure.
The film’s premise is that the woman, played by Scarlett Johansson, is in
reality an alien in a woman’s skin, here to hunt humans, men in particular
(Figure 1.1). The alien predator amongst us is the basis for any number of films.
But what is interesting about Under the Skin is that it seems to depict a genu-
inely alien perspective on the human world. And what characterises the alien-
ness of this perspective is that it is one of absolute amorality, portraying how
things might look if one had no moral concerns at all. The drowning family is of
no concern. The swimmer who heroically tried to rescue them is no more than
a convenient source of food. The baby is a mere detail in the background and
can be left to die. It may be that such amorality is so foreign to ordinary ways
of thinking that it is only really intelligible from the perspective of an alien. But
we can turn this around, look on ourselves as the alien beings for a moment, and
ask why it is that these beings should view things in moral terms. What’s in it
for us? Why should we ‘do the right thing’ rather than just what happens to be
in our interests?
16 Excess and Obsession
Figure 1.1 The alien on the prowl in Under the Skin (Jonathon Glazer, 2013. Credit: A24/
Photofest).
Why Be Moral?
‘Why be moral?’ is perhaps the ultimate metaethical question. Philosophical
thinking about ethics is typically divided into two areas. Normative ethics is con-
cerned with producing theories about what we ought, morally speaking, to do,
theories that allow us to make substantive moral judgements. Metaethical reflec-
tion asks general questions about the nature of the moral judgements we make and
perhaps the biggest metaethical question is why be moral at all? What reasons are
there for me personally to be moral, even when it does not appear to be in my indi-
vidual interest to do the right thing? And why should people in general be moral,
i.e., why should a society adopt the institution of morality?
In the first instance, it might be thought that we are only moral beings because
if we do not do the right thing, we will be found out and punished. But suppose we
could do whatever we wanted and be sure of getting away with it? What reasons
could we have then for being moral? This is a question that was posed very early in
the history of philosophy by the Ancient Greek philosopher Plato (c.428–347 bce),
in one of his dialogues, The Republic. And he posed the question through a story,
the story of the ring of Gyges, about a shepherd who discovers a ring that enables
him to become invisible. With this power, he is able to seduce the queen, plot with
her to kill the king and take over the kingdom, becoming wealthy and powerful
in the process. He can do all of this without fear of detection or punishment. So
he is in a position to pursue and satisfy all his desires, regardless of moral con-
straints, and he does very well indeed out of it. This raises the question – what
reason could Gyges possibly have for not doing what benefits him, doing what
is in his interests? Why should he bother, under these circumstances, to do the
right thing? As Plato phrases it, why would anyone bother to remain within the
Excess and Obsession 17
boundaries of moral behaviour ‘when he is able to take whatever he wants from
the market-stalls without fear of being discovered, to enter houses and sleep with
whomever he chooses, to kill and release from prison anyone he wants, and gen-
erally to act like a god among men’ (Plato 1993, 260c; using the standardised
pagination for works by Plato)?
The tale of Gyges continues to resonate 2000 years later, although the media
available for storytelling has changed somewhat in the meantime. Fast forward
to the present, and we have a story that would make a reasonable plot for a film,
and that film could be taken to raise similar questions about why one should
bother to act morally. In contemporary cinematic stories, it is likely to be scien-
tists rather than shepherds who discover the secret of invisibility, but this does not
stop events taking a familiar path. Whatever noble aspirations the scientists might
have had at the beginning, once they have this power their aspirations typically
give way to various sorts of wickedness as soon as they realise how much they
can get away with. Films with this theme range from the classic The Invisible Man
(Jack Griffin, 1933), where the chemist (Claude Rains) who has discovered the
invisibility formula resolves to dominate the world through a reign of terror, to the
more recent remake, Hollow Man (Paul Verhoeven, 2000), where the wickedness
that ensues, including voyeurism and murder, is presented in meticulous detail.
You might want to take an optimistic view of these scenarios, highlighting
various mitigating circumstances. Perhaps the scientist behaves badly because
the process that makes them invisible also drives them crazy, as in the original
Invisible Man film. Or perhaps they were simply bad people to begin with, as
in the later version where the main character, Sebastian Caine (Kevin Bacon),
is shown to have questionable traits like overweening arrogance long before
the invisibility process that turns him into a monster. Given this, perhaps the
bad behaviour of the character who discovers invisibility is not a reflection of
human nature as such, but only the nature of the particular individual involved
or as a result of the invisibility process. This also seems to be the case with
the ring of invisibility that features in Peter Jackson’s The Lord of the Rings
(2001–2003) and The Hobbit (2012–2014) films. In these sagas, based on the
J.R.R. Tolkien novels, we do not simply have a magical ring that confers invis-
ibility, as in the Gyges story, but one that exerts an evil force that corrupts
the wearer. Here once again we can blame any bad behaviour on the invis-
ibility process.
But even if we were to accept this, there are other kinds of invisibility where
these considerations don’t arise, and yet the question of why one should bother to
be moral remains. Why do the right thing, for example, if you found that your day
was mysteriously repeating over and over, with the actions of the previous day
erased each time, so that only you remembered them, meaning that you could do
whatever you liked without any real consequences? This is the predicament that
weatherman Phil (Bill Murray) finds himself in Groundhog Day (Harold Ramis,
1993). Although the character is certainly grumpy and cynical, he is not an espe-
cially bad person, even when he has the opportunity to be so. Nonetheless, under
those circumstances, the question inevitably arises – why not be as gluttonous,
18 Excess and Obsession
lecherous or villainous as you like? Phil’s first response to his situation is very
much like that of a modern-day Gyges. He proclaims: ‘I’m not going to live by
their rules any more’, meaning the rules of ordinary, well-behaved citizens, and
sets out on a night of mayhem.
If Groundhog Day relies on a fantasy device to achieve its state of figurative
invisibility, there are more down-to-earth forms one can consider. What if, like
the perfidious eye doctor in Woody Allen’s Crimes and Misdemeanors (1989),
you have the wealth and social standing to cover up any crimes you might com-
mit, including adultery, fraud, even murder? Or if, in the criminal world, you have
the kind of power that allows you to act with complete impunity, doing whatever
you like without having to worry about public scrutiny or legal prosecution, like
the gangsters Tony Montana in Scarface (Brian de Palma, 1983) or Henry Hill in
Goodfellas (Martin Scorsese, 1990). Or suppose you have the kind of financial
clout that allows you to do much the same in the business world, like the busi-
nessmen Gordon Gekko in Wall Street (Oliver Stone, 1987) or the Jordan Belfort
character in The Wolf of Wall Street (Martin Scorsese, 2013). These characters
all raise the question of the moment. Why abide by moral constraints if you have
nothing to lose by doing whatever is in your immediate interests? Why not take
the opportunity to fulfil every wish, no matter how extreme?
If these are all Gyges-like scenarios that have been portrayed and explored in
various films, it is worth adding that film itself might be seen as offering the pros-
pect of unlimited wish-fulfilment for the moviegoer, the satisfaction of any desire
without danger to oneself. Every movie is a virtual world, a hypothetical situation
in which anything that one desires can potentially be realised, at least in visual
terms. Any scenario is possible, and more importantly, can be safely enjoyed by
the film-goer, watching invisibly in the dark. Those in the movie audience, it
turns out, are the original invisible men and women. Naturally, the representative
power of cinema being what it is, the idea of film as an avenue for wish-fulfilment
for the viewer has itself been represented in film, as early as Sherlock Jr (Buster
Keaton, 1924). In the film, Keaton, a lowly film projectionist and hopeless would-
be amateur detective, falls asleep and dreams of entering the film he has been
projecting. Here, he becomes Sherlock Jr, the greatest detective in the world.
Having said that, it is not clear that we always wish for the unlimited satisfac-
tion of our desires, the absence of any moral constraints; or indeed that we look
to films only to gratify our desires, wishes and fantasies. The prospect of there
being no moral constraints, no consequences for transgression, might in fact be a
profoundly disturbing prospect. We might desperately wish for there to be a moral
universe, like the rabbi, Ben (Sam Waterston), in Crimes and Misdemeanours,
who insists that without some kind of moral order that acts of wickedness violate,
the world would be a dark, meaningless and terrifying place. A moral universe
can certainly be portrayed within film, a world where good prospers, and even
if it experiences some reverses along the way, will ultimately prevail over evil;
and where those who do wrong, even if they fail to see the light and join the side
of good by the last act, are at least going to be found out and punished by the
end. There are many films in which an essentially moral world is reassuringly
Excess and Obsession 19
confirmed in these ways. Indeed, this is pretty much the standard Hollywood
scenario. And there is clearly an appetite for such films, even if part of their
appeal might be the pleasure of seeing the bad guys violating all moral norms and
standards, indulging in all the forbidden appetites, before being inevitably and
properly called to account for their transgressions.
We know however that in real life things don’t always work out this way,
that good does not always prevail and that the bad guys don’t always get their
comeuppance. Indeed, like Gyges, they often do very well. And there are plenty
of ‘realistic’ films that serve to remind us precisely of this. In so doing, they raise
with renewed force the question of why one should be moral. One of the pleas-
ures of Crimes and Misdemeanors is that it is quite conscious of its distance from
the Hollywood moral universe. The main character, the ophthalmologist Judah
Rosenthal (Martin Landau), contrives after some agonising to have his mistress
killed when she threatens to expose their affair and ruin his comfortable life; and
in the end he gets away with it, even prospers by it. It’s a stark repudiation of the
conventional Hollywood story and the film itself comments on this. At the end of
the film, the murderous eye doctor meets the director, playing a failed filmmaker,
at a wedding, and recounts his story in the guise of a possible film plot. Allen’s
character replies that it would be a better story if the murderer was wracked with
guilt and driven to give himself up. The doctor’s reply is that this is what hap-
pens in the movies, not in real life: ‘If you want a happy ending, you should
go see a Hollywood movie’. The film’s ending is astonishingly bleak, and if on
one level it might be regarded as offering a gloomy, pessimistic view of human
nature, it might just as easily be seen as presenting a realistic one, stripped of all
comforting illusions.
A similarly pessimistic, or realistic, vision is evident in Roman Polanski’s neo-
noir Chinatown (1974), which revives forties film noir themes but gives them a
darker twist. In classic film noir like John Huston’s The Maltese Falcon (1941),
society might be corrupt and evil, and the private investigator who brings it to
light may themselves be flawed, but in the end, they usually manage to bring
about some degree of justice. In Chinatown, there is no triumph of any sort. When
LA private eye Jake Gittes (Jack Nicholson) stumbles on a network of graft, mur-
der and incest, presided over by evil businessman Noah Cross (played by John
Huston, no less), neither he nor the police have the power to do anything about it.
Worse, Gittes himself ends up causing the death of the woman he is trying to pro-
tect from Cross’s predations and Cross escapes any punishment. In a similar way,
the classic western undergoes a reality check in No Country for Old Men (Joel
and Ethan Coen, 2007). The decent western hero who fights for what is right, and
who traditionally triumphs over evil through perseverance and resourcefulness,
appears here in the figure of sheriff Ed Bell (Tommy Lee Jones). However, Bell
finds himself ‘over-matched’ by the new, brutal forms of drug-related crime he
is confronting. He is unable to protect ‘his people’, cowboy-adventurer Lewellyn
Moss (Josh Brolin) or his wife Carla Jean (Kelly Macdonald), from retribu-
tion, after Moss happens upon a large amount of money from a drug deal gone
wrong. And he is unable to bring to justice the chief agent of that retribution, the
20 Excess and Obsession
terrifying hitman Anton Chigurh (Javier Bardem). In the end, all sheriff Bell can
do is escape into retirement from an evil that he cannot defeat.
As a final variation on this theme, David Lynch’s Blue Velvet (1989) simul-
taneously foregrounds a standard Hollywood story of good triumphing over evil
and subverts it. On the face of it, the film is a conventional story of evil being
properly punished, as clean-cut hero Jeffrey (Kyle McLachlan) manages in the
end to defeat sadistic gangster Frank Booth (Dennis Hopper). But the hero finds
he has affinities with the evil Frank, being similarly drawn to nightclub singer
Dorothy Vallens (Isabella Rossellini) who represents the prospect of illicit, per-
verse sex. Moreover, the ‘good world’ that Jeffrey leaves and to which he even-
tually returns, represented in the picture-perfect images of the town with which
the film begins and ends, is shown to be an impossible idealisation, a comforting
veneer that hides a much darker reality that is always just below the surface.
Under the manicured lawns, there are hideous insects. If we are going to be real-
istic, we need to acknowledge that wrongdoing is not always found out and pun-
ished, that people can and do get away with evil, and often do very well out of it.
So, is it true that the only reason people adhere to moral standards is because of
fear of being caught and punished otherwise? Or can we give a better answer to
the question of why we should be moral?
One response might be that even if we can avoid external scrutiny and
punishment, we will suffer punishment at our own hands for evil deeds, through
guilt and remorse. On this view it is our conscience that keeps us behaving ethically.
We have an internal moral sense, whether this is something inbuilt or inculcated in
us through our upbringing. However, even if conscience is a psychological reality,
it is certainly possible to imagine it absent. Lack of conscience, the absence of any
moral constraints on one’s actions and a willingness to do whatever furthers one’s
interests, is the familiar mark of the movie psychopath. But it might also be argued
that despite the prevalence of such figures in film, this conscience-less, amoral kind
of outlook is in reality relatively rare in individuals. It is a strange way of being,
marking the conscienceless individual as ‘other’, not like the ordinary human being,
and more appropriately embodied as the mysterious viewpoint of an alien, as in
Under the Skin. It is an outlook, however, that might be more prevalent at the insti-
tutional level. The documentary The Corporation (Mark Achbar, Jennifer Abbott,
2003) makes the case that were the modern corporation a legal person, an actual
person, the kind of person it would typically be is one that is utterly self-interested,
deceitful, callous, without guilt, willing to break social rules for its own ends – in
short, a psychopath. The amoral corporation is itself a familiar character in films,
from Alien (Ridley Scott, 1979) to Robocop (Paul Verhoeven, 1987). But typically
in these films, the corporation is pitted against human characters that we can iden-
tify with. Those characters who act in its name have sold their souls and ceased to
be human. In the case of Alien this is quite literally so, since the ‘company man’, the
villainous Ash (Ian Holm), turns out to be an android.
At the same time, there is perhaps something a little convenient about this
relegation of evil to the alien psychopath or the inhuman corporation. The very
notion of ‘evil’, as immoral behaviour that seems so bad that it can only come
Excess and Obsession 21
from some conscienceless other, may be a convenient way of distancing our-
selves from actions that after all are in the last analysis committed by human
beings like us (see Morton 2004, 4–5, 93–94). It is far more disturbing to think
that terrible things might be done by people we can relate to, people who are
not monsters or sadists but to all intents and purposes ordinary individuals. The
controversy over twentieth-century philosopher Hannah Arendt’s notion of the
‘banality of evil’ was precisely of this nature. Arendt introduced the notion in
her book Eichmann in Jerusalem, based on her coverage of ex-Nazi Eichmann’s
1961 trial in Jerusalem. The controversy was over the idea that a participant in the
Holocaust, a mid-level administrator responsible for organising transportation of
Jews to Nazi death camps, might not be crazy, or a monster, but a normal person,
indeed a nobody, a mediocrity. Margarethe von Trotta’s Hannah Arendt (2012)
depicts Arendt (played by Barbara Sukowa) covering the Eichmann trial and the
subsequent furore over her book. In it, she is presented defending her position
in a climactic public lecture: ‘I wrote no defense of Eichmann, but I did try to
reconcile the shocking mediocrity of the man with his staggering deeds. Trying to
understand him is not the same thing as forgiveness’.
It might be imagined that one’s conscience would stop them from participating
in such horrors. It is easy to think that there is some kind of moral instinct in us
that would have compelled us to do the right thing, had we been German citizens
during the Nazi period. Arendt herself reports that Eichmann had the opportunity
to see the death camps in operation and was repelled by them, but soon after
began his duties administering transportation. He had a conscience, she suggests,
but it ‘functioned in the expected way for about four weeks, whereupon it began
to function the other way around’ (Arendt 2006, 95). For Arendt, this turnaround
is the real root of Eichmann’s evil. It amounts to him ceasing to think for himself
or to see the world beyond the dictates of Nazi policy. In so doing, he ceased to
see things from the standpoint of other people and to adopt a moral understand-
ing of what he had done to them. Giving himself to the movement, his guiding
principles became efficiency and obedience in the name of the great cause. One’s
conscience can no doubt always be recalibrated in this way, so that one overcomes
one’s ordinary repugnance to crime in order to perform what one understands to
be an important task requiring great courage.
Moreover, even those whose consciences function in the ‘expected way’ may
be less constrained by it than they imagine. This is what the eye doctor Judah
discovers in Crimes and Misdemeanors. Recounting his supposed movie plot to
Cliff at the end of the film, he indicates that while he suffered terrible guilt at first
over what he had done, to the point where he was on the verge of confessing to
the police, that guilt gradually diminished over time; and though he occasionally
has a bad moment, he has learned to live with what he has done. After all, as he
points out, people learn to live with all sorts of terrible sins. And apart from all
this, even if conscience does work as expected to prod us and keep us more or
less on the straight and narrow, we might still want to know why we should obey
our consciences, what reasons we might have for doing so. We need to look more
closely at the issue.
22 Excess and Obsession
Plato’s Moral Theory
This brings us back to Plato, who presents the original invisibility story, the story
of Gyges. The rest of the Republic is, in effect, Plato’s answer to the question
the story poses, of why we should be moral even if we can get away with being
immoral. In this, Plato wants to reject the view of morality and of human nature
that the story implies: that the only reason to abide by moral standards is to avoid
being caught and punished for transgressing them. Along with that, he rejects the
idea that we are essentially creatures driven by our desires, with morality being
merely an external constraint that limits their satisfaction. Plato acknowledges
that human beings have desires, but he does not think we are just creatures of
desire. He thinks that there are in fact different parts to our makeup. He points out
that we often experience mental conflicts and argues that these conflicts reflect
this internal complexity. Someone who is thirsty but knows the water is poisoned
both wants to drink the water and stops themselves from drinking, which sug-
gests to Plato that one part of the person just wants to drink, but another, differ-
ent part is more wisely and sensibly commanding them not to drink (see Plato
1993, 435c–441c). Move forward now to David Fincher’s Fight Club (1999),
and we see such internal compartmentalisation in dramatically exaggerated form.
The film’s unnamed narrator (Edward Norton), with a responsible job and a well-
furnished apartment, finds that a side of his personality at odds with his ordinary,
responsible self, has taken on a life of its own. He finds himself confronted by his
alter-ego, the anarchic and dangerous Tyler Durden (Brad Pitt), for whom jobs
and apartments are merely shackles to be thrown off at the earliest opportunity. If
Durden ultimately turns out to be a delusion on the narrator’s part, this only under-
scores that the split is really internal, between different parts of his personality.
The move from experiencing internal conflicts to imagining that there are liter-
ally different parts operating within ourselves is clearly not a large one. On the
basis of such conflicts, Plato argues that the self, or soul (a term that is without
religious overtones for Plato) has three distinct parts: a rational part, a desiring
element and a spirited part. Reason is the part of the soul that knows reality, calcu-
lates and makes decisions. Its proper role is to rule the desiring part. Desire is the
irrational, appetitive part of the soul, made up of instinctive cravings and urges. It
includes all the physical desires, such as hunger, thirst and sexual desire, as well as
the desire for money. Properly speaking, it should be regulated by reason. To this,
Plato adds a spirited part, which is manifested in feelings of self-disgust, shame,
courage, indignation and strength of will. The spirited part’s role is to provide
reason with the force it needs to govern desire. This picture provides the basis
for Plato’s view of morality. Being moral for Plato is not just a matter of submit-
ting to external constraints that stop you pursuing what is in your self-interest.
It certainly involves controlling and regulating your immediate desires, but by
themselves, these desires cannot be trusted to pursue what is in your interests.
You may want to do all sorts of things that you know, rationally, are bad for you,
like drinking the water you know to be poisonous. The rational part looks at the
overall picture, at what is good for the self as a whole and for each part. So, if I am
Excess and Obsession 23
really self-interested, I must be ruled by the rational part; I must have a properly
balanced soul, and, for Plato, having this inner balance is what it is to be moral.
What this means is that for Plato, being moral, instead of being opposed to self-
interest, is in fact very much in the interests of the self. It means having a well-
ordered soul, in which each part plays its proper role in the whole. The proper
role of the rational part is to govern the other parts of the soul; the spirited part’s
role is to provide reason with the force it needs to govern; and the appetitive part
should be controlled and regulated by reason. Moral goodness thus amounts to a
kind of mental health or well-being, which is clearly beneficial for its possessor.
It is also an enjoyable state to be in, and so Plato can argue that the moral life is a
happy one. With this picture of the moral human being, Plato introduces an influ-
ential conception of human nature, the idea of human existence as essentially a
struggle between reason and desire, a struggle that reason ought to win. For Plato
and many who come after him, reason is the ‘higher’ part of the human being and
desires are the primitive, irrational and chaotic ‘lower’ part. In these accounts, we
are typically identified most closely with our higher, rational part. While desires
are still seen as part of us, they are often seen as less central, to an extent alien to
us, an unfortunate accompaniment that is perhaps part of our animal heritage, and
certainly needing to be kept in check by the rational self. If the desiring side of our
makeup were allowed to have its way, our inner balance would be overthrown.
We would be enslaved to our appetites and passions, which without any constraint
would become tyrannical.
We can see more clearly how having such an inner balance amounts to being
a morally good person insofar as Plato relates this harmony to our having recog-
nisable virtues, morally admirable character traits. In the well-ordered state, we
would have the virtues of justice, courage, temperance and wisdom, which are
the central elements of Platonic morality. We would be wise because the ruling
element possesses knowledge of what is good for each part and for the whole;
temperate, or self-controlled, because desire and pleasure are tempered by the rule
of reason; and brave because the spirited part allows us to pursue the precepts of
reason and to overcome the distractions of pain and pleasure. Finally, we would
have the overall virtue of being just, where justice is understood not in the modern
sense of having equality of opportunity or outcome, but in terms of something’s
being well-balanced, each part playing its proper role in the whole. So understood,
being just for Plato is synonymous with being moral. Being moral in this way,
with the proper balance of reason, desire and courage, is also a prerequisite for
playing one’s proper role in society (443d-e). And having the proper balance of
parts, with each part playing its proper role, also characterises the just or good
society, the republic that gives Plato’s dialogue its title. The tripartite self becomes
a microcosm of the tripartite society, whose corresponding parts are the ruling
class, the workers and the soldiers. The just society is the one in which each social
group plays its proper role: that of the workers being to serve the rulers, the rulers
to control the workers and the soldiers to do the bidding of the rulers and enforce
their rule. Once again, justice has nothing to do with equality. It amounts to a
morality that consists in playing your proper part in the whole.
24 Excess and Obsession
Returning to the individual case, the relation between inner balance and moral-
ity is also illuminated when we consider the alternative, when we fail to have this
inner balance. Corresponding to the virtues are various vices, such as foolishness,
cowardice and self-indulgence, all of which are reflections of disharmony in the
soul, of injustice. As is often the case with this reason-centred sort of picture,
immorality is seen to arise above all if one’s desires and appetites escape the con-
trol of reason. If your desires are not under the control of your reason, if you lack
self-control, you won’t be able to pursue your true interests. You won’t be able to
do what is good for you overall, but instead will be subject to the psychological
tyranny of your desires, which will grow out of all proportion. You will be the
victim of your appetites, desiring ever more in the way of food, drink, material
goods, wealth and so on, falling prey to all manner of addictions and obsessions.
Others will suffer as well, since you will be driven to satisfy yourself at their
expense, for example, by seeking the unlimited sexual pleasure that can only be
had through force or deception. Given that morality amounts to a kind of mental
health or well-being, the immoral person is unbalanced, mentally disordered, and
the thoroughly immoral person is on the verge of being insane.
This is an influential conception of evil, or at least, morally bad behaviour.
Being self-indulgent, ruled by one’s appetites and blind to the needs of oth-
ers, is certainly a conventional way of thinking about what being a bad person
involves. The bad children in Willy Wonka and the Chocolate Factory (Mel
Stuart, 1971) are bad in precisely this way: Augustus and Veruca are greedy and
demanding, Violet and Mike are addicted to the point of obsession with chew-
ing gum and television. They have not improved in the Tim Burton remake,
Charlie and the Chocolate Factory (2005). Mike is now obsessed with video
games. Of course, they are only children, not yet being fully developed adults,
and so have the excuse of not yet being mature. A crucial part of this develop-
ment is learning to govern one’s desires, in the way that Charlie (Peter Ostrum,
and in the remake, Freddie Highmore), the one ‘good’ and also most grown-up
child does. At the same time, in their subjection to their appetites, these little
monsters have something in common with the classic movie monsters of early
cinema, the monsters that seem to personify unleashed desire beyond the con-
trol of reason. A defining mark of the monster is that it is utterly self-seeking,
wholly concerned with satisfying its appetites. There is the wicked Mr Hyde
of Jekyll and Hyde fame, the werewolf, the classic vampire, all grotesque fig-
ures that have been literally deformed by the appetites that consume them. The
cinematic vampire in particular provides an enduring image of a creature com-
pletely given over to its desires, although as we will see, there have also been
some interesting variations on the theme, including the vampire who strives to
manage and control their blood lust and to be good.
These movie monsters are inhuman, and generally speaking have to be hunted
down and destroyed. As always, it is convenient to ascribe wicked acts to some-
thing that is ‘other’, not like us. Yet they are not entirely alien to us. They all
relate in some way to the human psyche, or at least a certain understanding of it.
In particular, the monster can be taken to represent the dangerous desires within
Excess and Obsession 25
us that strive to escape our control and which we must struggle to keep in check
if we are not to find ourselves being taken over by them. Even the vampire, per-
haps the most alien of these figures, provides a metaphor for human addiction, for
being entirely given over to one’s appetites. In the case of the more complex and
reflective vampire who struggles to control their urges, there is an image of the
human struggle to master desire. These monsters may also be explicitly linked to
the human to the extent that they emerge out of us or take us over. Struggling to
prevent their emergence, or being taken over by them, once again dramatises the
Platonic picture of the individual as engaged in a battle to control their desires and
appetites, and of the consequences of losing control. The monster, all appetite,
unleashed on the world to commit every kind of mayhem in pursuit of its needs,
exemplifies the idea of immoral behaviour as being a matter of unchecked desire.
The Jekyll and Hyde story, popular in the thirties and early forties, but also pre-
sent in one form or another in a number of more recent films, points very clearly
to such a view of the self and of what constitutes immoral behaviour. The two
best known classic versions are those of Rouben Mamoulian (1932) and Victor
Fleming (1941). Both films open with Dr Jekyll (Fredric March and Spencer
Tracy respectively) holding forth on the ‘dual nature of man’, as composed in
Platonic fashion of good and evil parts chained together in the soul, constantly
battling one another. In the films, we see the dire consequences when Dr Jekyll
invents a potion to separate the two halves of his nature. The intention is to free
humans from their ‘evil side’ so that the good in people will be able to develop
unhindered. Instead, it is the evil side that is freed and Jekyll turns into the gro-
tesque, murderous Mr Hyde. In Mamoulian’s film (see Figure 1.2), the evil side is
explicitly characterised in terms of ‘elementary instincts inherited from an animal
past’. In both films, it is identified with desire and appetites, particularly those of
a sexual nature. It manifests itself in Dr Jekyll in the desires he struggles to repress
when, though engaged to be married to a ‘good woman’ (Rose Hobart and Lana
Turner respectively), he meets a ‘bad’ one, Ivy Pierson (Miriam Hopkins and
Ingrid Bergman).
Fleming’s 1941 version of the story is itself more ‘repressed’ than the ear-
lier 1932 film, more toned down in its sexual content. This no doubt reflects
the arrival in Hollywood of the Hays Code, the set of industry moral guidelines
designed to rehabilitate the industry’s image, which was enforced after 1934. Ivy
Pierson, a prostitute in Mamoulian’s version, becomes a barmaid in Fleming’s
remake, with the implication of prostitution being omitted. Ivy’s flirtation with
Jekyll is more overtly sexual in the earlier film than in the later one. Nonetheless,
the 1941 film still manages to smuggle in some surprisingly frank sexual imagery,
particularly in the Tracy Jekyll’s first transformation scene. One of the images
Fleming employs here is that of a horseman and his steeds, an image also used
by Plato. Jekyll experiences himself as a charioteer whipping two horses, which
dissolve into his fiancé e and the barmaid Ivy. But this is not a representation of
reason striving to control the other parts of the soul, as it is in Plato. The image
has in fact been subverted in the film to become a metaphor for the unleashing
of Jekyll’s desires for sexual possession and domination. For both films, desire,
26 Excess and Obsession
Stoicism
After Plato and Aristotle, two schools of ethical thinking became prominent,
Stoicism and Epicureanism. Both originated in Greek civilisation and underwent
further development during the Roman period. Both are eudaimonistic, arguing
that the aim of life is to attain happiness. Where Plato identifies happiness with
justice, and Aristotle with the integration of reason and feeling, these schools
identify it particularly with inner peace, tranquillity or contentment. And both
provide the individual with strategies for finding tranquillity and contentment in
a world that is often uncertain and beyond their control. Broadly, tranquillity in
both cases requires some form of detachment or withdrawal from the world, along
with a transformation of those inner emotions, feelings and desires that have the
power to disturb us. Finally, both schools thought that the virtues were essential
to attaining the life of happy tranquillity and contentment.
Stoicism was the most influential ethical doctrine in the ancient world before
the advent of Christianity. It originated with the Greek thinker Zeno of Citium
(334–262 bce), and was later developed in the Roman period by the Greek ex-
slave Epictetus (55–135), where it became the default ethical position for the
upper classes, all the way up to the emperor. Many of Epictetus’s ideas, formu-
lated in his Enchiridion (‘handbook’ or ‘manual’), are echoed in the Meditations
of the Roman Emperor Marcus Aurelius (121–180). Central to Stoicism was the
idea that we achieve happiness by ‘learning to live with the inevitable’. There is
a great deal in the world that we cannot control, that is fated to happen regard-
less of what we might want. The reasonable thing to do is to accept it, to ‘live in
agreement with nature’. While this might sound like a doctrine of resignation, the
Stoics put a positive spin on this to the extent that they understood the universe
to have an underlying ordering principle or logos, which accounts for its structure
and regularities. Like Aristotle, the Stoics could not believe that the structure and
regularities of the world could arise from undirected, random processes. Rather,
nature is a well-ordered system in which everything has its proper place and rela-
tion with its environment. This larger order is understood in entirely naturalistic
terms. Although the Stoics identify the logos with God, there is no appeal to an
otherworldly realm, in the manner of Plato. This is a God that is inherent in the
world, imbuing it with order and meaning. Logos is also identified with reason;
the world is a rationally ordered system.
Excess and Obsession 45
Since everything that happens is supposed to be, the rational thing for i ndividuals
to do is to accept this, to conform their will with the events that are destined to
occur in the universe, to train themselves to desire what the universe allows and
not pursue what it does not. To do so is to live in agreement with one’s own nature,
because for the Stoics, as for Plato and Aristotle, what distinguishes human beings
is that they have the capacity to reason. Like all living things, humans eat, grow
and reproduce, and, like animals, they have capacities for sense perception, desire
and locomotion, and take care of their offspring, but what is uniquely human is the
capacity for reason. In living in accordance with our nature as rational beings, we
will attain happiness. Stoicism is another eudaimonistic ethical theory, in which
the proper goal of human endeavour is happiness or flourishing, and in which the
happiest, most fulfilled human life is the one lived in accordance with our rational
nature. Acting rationally in the various areas of human conduct is equivalent to
abiding by moral virtues, which for Stoicism are the classic virtues of wisdom,
temperance, courage and justice. Wisdom is the virtue of feeling and acting ration-
ally, being in harmony with one’s nature. Feeling and acting rationally in situa-
tions where one might feel fear or be tempted by pleasure defines the virtues of
courage and temperance. Acting rationally with regard to other people is the virtue
of justice, living in harmony with others, wishing them to be happy and flourish.
All four virtues are conceived by Stoicism as being interdependent.
For Stoicism, then, in order to have a fulfilling life, we should pursue whatever
cultivates and preserves virtue. The virtues enable individuals to live contented,
fulfilled lives. Stoicism is however distinctive amongst ancient schools in insist-
ing that virtue is the only thing needed for happiness. Whereas for Aristotle, hav-
ing external goods like health, wealth, good looks, friends and the like is necessary
for full happiness, the Stoic view is that happiness does not depend in any way on
external circumstances, which we cannot control and which are a matter of luck.
We should be concerned only with what is in our control, namely our inner men-
tal judgements, opinions, attitudes, desires and actions. Everything else falls into
the class of ‘indifferents’; they neither contribute nor detract from the happy life.
The Stoics were not entirely dismissive of external circumstances. They argued
for a class of ‘preferred indifferents’, things like life, health, strength, prosperity,
friends and family and a good reputation. These promote the natural condition
of the person so it is usually rational to prefer them to ‘dispreferred indifferents’
like death, disease, pain, ugliness, weakness and poverty. However, even pre-
ferred indifferents remain indifferents. We should not be upset if we don’t have
these things, or if we lose them. Happiness lies in learning to be indifferent to the
external circumstances beyond one’s control, learning that one can be happy and
fulfilled regardless of our material circumstances.
As such, becoming virtuous, rational in feeling and action, involves radically
transforming our emotional life. For the Stoics, emotion or passion is a psychic
disturbance that is contrary to reason. We should act purely on the basis of reason,
not emotion. Even Plato, for all his hostility to desire and emotion, saw these as
part of the psyche, to be controlled by reason, not extirpated. Aristotle of course
thought that emotion and feeling had a place in the rational organism provided it
46 Excess and Obsession
was reasonable or appropriate to the situation. For Stoicism, a significant amount
of emotional life needs to be removed. One can have certain mild ‘rational’ emo-
tions, like joy, kindliness or cheerfulness, but we need to free ourselves from
disturbing emotions like distress, jealousy, pity, grief, worry, fear and panic;
appetite which includes yearning, anger and passionate love; and pleasure or
irrational elation over what seems worth choosing. All of these disturbing emo-
tions are based on mistaken judgements about the importance of external things
like wealth, health, good looks, a happy family life, and so on. We mistakenly
take these things to be important and become emotionally attached to them. But
although we cannot control them, we can control our judgements about them. We
can learn to be indifferent to our circumstances, to calmly accept them. Here, the
therapeutic aspect of Stoicism is evident. Stoicism recommends various exercises
to achieve this healthy indifference. We will thereby be cleansed of all the fears
and anxieties that ordinary people suffer, and attain apatheia, the state of freedom
from disturbing emotions. This for Stoicism is the happy, fulfilled life, the life of
virtue. The Roman Stoics, in particular, emphasised the tranquillity that will result
from the virtuous life.
Being stoic has come to mean being able to grit one’s teeth, suppress one’s
feelings and endure adversity without complaint. However, it is not so much
about suppressing as not having the relevant feelings, being indifferent. As John
Sellars argues, this is why we cannot really see Maximus (Russell Crowe), the
hero of Ridley Scott’s historical epic Gladiator (2000), as a Stoic figure. Though
a proté gé of Marcus Aurelius (played by Richard Harris), he does not inherit the
emperor’s Stoic outlook. After Aurelius’s successor Commodus has Maximus’s
wife and family killed, he is exiled, captured by slavers and trained to fight as
a gladiator. But rather than accepting his new circumstances, he plots to return
to Rome to kill Commodus (Joaquin Phoenix), in order to exact revenge. The
Stoic view is that one’s close relations are amongst the external things that are
not necessary for one’s happiness. What Maximus needs to do is free himself
from the passionate desire for vengeance, the disturbing emotion tied up with
his attachment to his family. The same can be said for the Bride (Uma Thurman)
in Kill Bill (Quentin Tarantino, 2003). She endures a great deal, but her actions
are driven by the desire for revenge against Bill and the assassination squad who
attacked her and left her for dead, and in the second part of the film, the additional
desire to rescue her daughter from Bill’s clutches. Getting to the point where the
mind only makes rational judgements about the importance of external objects
requires considerable mental discipline and that discipline requires a lifetime of
training and practice. Epictetus recommends various exercises to cultivate it: for
example, when we kiss our child, remember she is mortal and not something we
own, silently reflect on the possibility she may die tomorrow; as we go about our
day, periodically pause to reflect on the fact that we will not live forever and that
this day could be our last; and so on (Epictetus 2008, 222).
Thus, the vengeance-driven action hero, no matter how heroically enduring
they may be in the pursuit of their goal, does not qualify as a Stoic figure, since they
are too passionate, too attached to external things. A much more unprepossessing
Excess and Obsession 47
figure can come closer to the Stoic ideal, at least with respect to displaying the
right kind of attitude towards externalities that cannot be controlled. In Spielberg’s
Bridge of Spies (2015), set at the height of the Cold War, the Russian spy Rudolf
Abel (Mark Rylance), having been arrested by the US authorities, radiates an
extraordinary calm despite difficult circumstances. Each time he is asked by his
lawyer James Donovan (Tom Hanks) whether he is worried about the prospect of
being found guilty and going to the electric chair, he replies in a deadpan manner,
‘would it help?’ This is Stoic indifference in essence; it is pointless to worry about
what we cannot control. As noted, getting to the desired Stoic state of tranquil
indifference is not easy. If we lived in perfect accord with nature, behaved purely
rationally, we would be what the Stoics called a perfect wise man, a sage. Sages
are completely virtuous and do not suffer from any mistaken emotions. They do
not desire the things that people ordinarily regard as indispensable for happiness,
like prosperity, fame, romantic love, social success and so on. They recognise
that these external goods, over which non-Stoics suffer anxiety, fear, disappoint-
ment and desire, are not necessary for the good life; only virtue is required for
that. As a result, the sage acquires a kind of psychic invulnerability. They cannot
be harmed, no matter how dire their circumstances. They could lose everything,
wealth, friends, family, reputation, life, without compromising their happiness,
since they have everything they need for their happiness within them. As the
Stoics themselves recognised, few could be said to have reached this ideal, though
most saw Socrates as having come close. He demonstrated extraordinary equa-
nimity while on trial for his life and calm acceptance of his fate once condemned
to death. These qualities are eminently on show in Rossellini’s Socrates, which
is itself filmed in a calm, serene style, without melodrama, befitting its subject.
A potential criticism of Stoicism is that it focuses too much on acceptance of
external circumstances and on changing oneself, leading to passivity and inaction.
For the Stoics themselves, indifference does not mean inaction. Stoic detachment
is compatible with involvement in everyday life, in society. The Stoic can take
full part in life, marry and have a family, engage in politics, and so on. The atti-
tude of indifference towards externals does not preclude the energetic pursuit of
preferred indifferents, of things like prosperity, health, friends, life and so on. But
it remains the case that the Stoic should not be disappointed if they don’t achieve
these things or if they lose them. These things are not necessary for happiness;
only virtue is necessary for that and this is what we should focus our attention on
cultivating. Still, we might wonder if this is a sustainable position. It might be
thought that there is a conflict between the Stoic ideal of indifference to externals
and our unavoidable involvement in social affairs. Can we really pursue exter-
nal things without being emotionally attached to them, and without being disap-
pointed if we fail to achieve them, or lose them? By the same token, is it possible
to detach ourselves from our ordinary needs and concerns for family and friends,
for fame, prosperity, health and so on, and still be motivated to act?
Over and above this, the radical transformation in emotional life required
in order to become virtuous in the Stoic sense is perhaps only attainable by a
superhuman figure, someone far removed from ordinary humanity. As such, the
48 Excess and Obsession
Stoic ideal seems to be in conflict with the often-repeated insistence in ancient
ethics that the best human life is the one lived in accordance with human nature.
Lack of a rich emotional life is ordinarily more likely to be taken as a marker
of the inhuman, as in Invasion of the Body Snatchers (Don Siegel, 1956). There
the transformation is not effected through Stoic therapies but alien intervention.
The inhabitants of a California town are replaced by duplicates grown in pods,
their minds absorbed into the new bodies while they sleep, and their old bodies
destroyed. The replacements have the same memories, habits and mannerisms
as the original, but they no longer feel love, grief or hope. From a Stoic point of
view, one could see this as an improvement. Stoicism may not advocate the rejec-
tion of all emotion, but it does seem to want to remove a significant portion of
emotional life. Yet the film’s main characters, Miles and Becky, refuse the pod
peoples’ offer to join them precisely because it would mean giving up the ability
to love and have feelings. For them, as for the audience, there is something pro-
foundly inhuman about the absence of emotional life. It is what above all marks
the pod people as alien, even though they are in so many ways identical to the
individuals they have replaced.
Epicureanism
Epicurean thinking, the main rival to Stoicism, was founded by the Greek thinker
Epicurus (341–c270 bce), and later developed by the Roman poet Lucretius
(c98–c55 bce). Epicureanism is another eudaimonistic ethical theory, holding that
the goal of human endeavour is happiness or fulfilment. It is distinctive how-
ever in holding that the happy life for human beings is the life of pleasure, free
of any pain or suffering. This sort of ethical view is sometimes called ‘egoistic
hedonism’, the doctrine that the only thing intrinsically valuable is one’s own
pleasure, and that everything else is valuable only as a means of securing pleasure
for oneself. In this, Epicureanism departs from much of ancient ethics, which fol-
lows Plato, Aristotle and Stoicism in holding that happiness in the proper sense
requires us to rise above the pursuit of mere pleasure, mere desire-satisfaction,
in order to live a virtuous life. However, as we will see, Epicureanism is by no
means a straightforwardly hedonistic position, advocating a life of unbridled
excess. Epicurus recommends limiting one’s desires as the best means of secur-
ing pleasure for oneself.
This is an ethics that is once again based on human nature, but unlike much of
ancient ethics, human nature is understood as primarily pleasure-seeking rather
than rational. The Epicureans saw this view as supported by empirical observa-
tion, arguing that pleasure is the only thing that people do, as a matter of fact, value
for its own sake. This can be confirmed by observing infants who instinctively
seek pleasure and avoid pain, and it is just as true of adults, although they have
more complicated beliefs about what will bring them pleasure. The Epicureans
insisted that all activity, even apparently self-sacrificing behaviour performed
solely for the sake of virtue, is in fact directed towards getting pleasure for one-
self. Shocking though this view must have been for their contemporaries, it is far
Excess and Obsession 49
more plausible to a modern audience. As noted, a feature of modern thought since
the seventeenth century and Thomas Hobbes is the idea that human beings are
fundamentally self-interested creatures driven by desire, seeking the pleasurable
satisfaction of our desires. In embracing this doctrine, Epicureanism has a sur-
prisingly modern feel about it, although as we will see in Chapter Three, Hobbes
builds a rather different picture of morality on this basis.
Another feature of Epicureanism that has surprisingly modern resonances is
that it rests on an entirely materialist view of nature, as involving nothing but
the blind interactions of particles. This wholly materialistic vision of the world
will not reappear in Europe until the seventeenth century, when the foundations
for the modern scientific worldview are laid. It is also a departure from much of
ancient ethics. Certainly, Aristotle and the Stoics offer naturalistic accounts in
the sense that they don’t appeal to any otherworldly ordering principles, such
as Plato’s Forms. However, neither Aristotle nor the Stoics could quite accept
that the structured world could arise from undirected processes. They envisaged
ordering principles that are inherent in nature, Aristotle’s forms and the Stoics’
logos. For Epicureanism, there is no such internal ordering principle in nature; all
phenomena are the result of the random, fortuitous interactions of atoms. Thus,
for the Epicureans, there is nothing to imbue the world with order and meaning.
The universe is a chaotic, meaningless place, indifferent to human hopes and con-
cerns. There are gods, but they don’t intervene in human affairs. We are alone in
the world and our only guide for how to act is our own pleasure. Epicureanism
tells us how to be happy in this world on the basis of a strictly materialist view of
nature, and a correspondingly down-to-earth view of human beings as creatures
who seek pleasure and want to avoid pain.
One might suppose that, given this view of human nature, and the ethical view
based on it, namely that pleasure is the only thing that is good in itself, what
Epicureanism is counselling is unlimited pleasure-seeking, decadent sensual-
ism. This indeed was how Epicureanism was characterised by its bitter rivals
the Stoics, and later on by the Christians. And nowadays that is precisely what
‘epicurean’ has come to mean, the self-indulgent seeker of pleasurable delights,
devoted to sensual enjoyment, especially fine food and drink. On this view, the
modern heroes of Epicureanism would be those who have the power to indulge
all of their desires, like the avaricious gangsters of the Scarface variety or the
unapologetically hedonistic stockbrokers in The Wolf of Wall Street. In this view,
Epicureanism is nothing less than an ethics of conspicuous consumption, of cap-
italism’s consumerist culture. However, unlimited pleasure-seeking is very far
from what Epicureanism calls for. What Epicurus counsels is in fact something
quite austere and restrained, what might be termed ‘negative hedonism’. And
Epicureanism also offers a possible standpoint for the moral critique of modern
consumerism as trenchant as anything that might emerge out of Platonic thinking.
It’s true that, for Epicurus, the happy, fulfilled life is the pleasant life, and
virtues like courage and moderation are only valuable insofar as they are a
means to pleasure. And this is another significant departure from most ancient
ethical thinking, for which pleasure is usually something to be sacrificed for
50 Excess and Obsession
the sake of virtue, the only thing good in itself. Now, it is pleasure that is the
only good in itself. But if pleasure is the satisfaction of your desires, there are
at least two ways you can ensure that you are satisfied to the maximum degree.
You can strive to acquire the power to shape the world so you can get whatever
you want, like Tony Montana or Jordan Belfort. This, however, is a problematic
strategy, as the world does not always cooperate in satisfying us; and even if
we are successful, too much indulgence has its own painful consequences for
the body, as is all too clearly apparent to the bleary-eyed heroes of the cinema
of excess. Alternatively, you can limit your desires to simple ones that can be
easily satisfied. That way you will be able to be completely happy, completely
free of pain and suffering, regardless of your circumstances. This is the path
that Epicurus recommends. For him, the best sort of pleasure is the kind that
involves no pain. Happiness here can be best understood in negative terms, as
freedom from suffering, from the suffering caused by overindulgence and from
the frustration of not being able to satisfy one’s desires. The Epicureans called
it ataraxia, meaning peace of mind, serenity or tranquillity. This is not unlike
the Stoic goal of apatheia, unsurprisingly as the Roman Stoics appropriated the
notion from their Epicurean rivals.
So rather than promoting the unlimited pursuit of pleasure, the Epicurean
focus is on sensibly limiting ourselves to simple desires for things we cannot do
without, what Epicurus calls ‘natural and necessary desires’ for food, drink and
shelter, which can be easily satisfied, and without which, we would suffer. One
needs to be more cautious about ‘natural but unnecessary’ desires, such as a taste
for rich food when simple food will do. Habitually pursuing these unnecessary
things sets one up for pain and distress, because they can be hard to acquire which
will be frustrating and potentially harmful, like the rich food that gives you indi-
gestion. And one should altogether avoid ‘vain and empty’ desires, for political
power, money, fame, designer goods and the like. These desires are not natural to
human beings but are inculcated by society and involve false beliefs about what
we need. Not only are these things unnecessary for our survival, the more one has
of them, the more one wants, making the desire for them impossible to satisfy and
leading to endless frustration and discontentment. Thus, Epicureanism advocates
reducing your desires to a minimum core, which can then be easily satisfied. It
turns out that we don’t need much to be happy; a simple diet, basic accommoda-
tion and perhaps a few good friends will be enough. And in restricting ourselves
to simple pleasures, we will no longer dependent for our happiness on a world
that we cannot control, which we cannot rely on to cooperate in the satisfac-
tion of our desires. To this end. Epicureanism, alone among the ancient schools,
advocates actual withdrawal from involvement in social and political life. Plato
and Aristotle both view human beings as essentially social animals who flourish
best in a properly organised community. Even Stoicism, which advocates detach-
ment from an uncertain world understands this detachment to be compatible with
continued involvement in society. Not so Epicureanism. As Luke Slattery puts it
‘whereas the Stoic withdraws into a fortified self or inner citadel … the Epicurean
picks up his bags and quits the city’ (Slattery 2012, 4).
Excess and Obsession 51
Yet, as Slattery goes on to note, Epicureanism also contains the seeds of a
radical social and political critique. In advocating a life of simple pleasures,
Epicureanism emerges as implicitly critical of modern consumerism and its
requirement of endless consumption. From this perspective, the modern advertis-
ing that fuels consumption is a concerted effort to implant ‘natural but unneces-
sary’ and ‘vain and empty’ desires in people, to convince them that satisfying
these desires will make them happy and that the discontent or frustration that
is inevitably going to arise from the pursuit of these sorts of desires can only be
cured by yet more consumption. Epicurus insists that ‘it is not continuous drink-
ings and revellings, nor the satisfaction of lusts, nor the enjoyment of fish and
other luxuries of the wealthy table, which produce the pleasant life, but sober rea-
soning, searching out the motives for all choice and avoidance’ (Epicurus 2006,
454–455). Grotesque images of overindulgence in the ‘luxuries of the wealthy
table’ have provided a handy metaphor for the excesses of modern life in a number
of socially critical films. La Grande Bouffe (Marco Ferreri, 1973) protests against
consumerist hedonism, portraying a group of friends who decide to kill them-
selves in the most hedonistic way possible, eating their way through meal after
meal of increasingly exotic food. In The Cook, The Thief, His Wife and Her Lover
(Peter Greenaway, 1989), the greed of the entrepreneurial classes in the Margaret
Thatcher era is distilled into the figure of the thief, a brutal criminal who presides
over obscenely lavish banquets in a London restaurant.
The heroes of Epicureanism are those who are content with the simple pleas-
ures, though their conspicuous lack of interest in acquisition and consumption is
liable to mark them out as eccentric in the present context. Morgan Rempel has
argued convincingly that one character who might be thought to approach the ideal
of Epicurean sage is Jeffrey ‘The Dude’ Lebowski from The Big Lebowski (Joel and
Ethan Coen, 1998). He has achieved his tranquillity in the midst of contemporary
Los Angeles by giving up any desire for wealth, achievement, a partner or clean
clothing. He is content to spend his time bowling, smoking dope, living in his mod-
est apartment and driving an old car. From an Epicurean point of view, the key point
here is that The Dude is not happy despite his reduced circumstances, but because
of them (see Rempel 2012, 67ff). A similar tranquillity seems to be achieved by the
teenage runaways in Moonrise Kingdom (Wes Anderson, 2012). In their case, it
literally requires them to pick up their bags and quit the city. On the fictional island
of New Penzance, in the 1960s, 12-year-olds Suzy (Kara Hayward) and Sam (Jared
Gilman), who have fallen in love, pack their bags and run away from town to set
up camp together in the small cove they name Moonrise Kingdom. There they are
happy enough living in the tent Sam has brought, with Suzy’s six stolen books, a
portable record player, binoculars and each other’s company. Their innocent affec-
tion for one another adds to the tranquillity of the moment, which is only disturbed
when the frantic adults finally locate their campsite. The matter of love, however,
raises some new issues. Love is something that is potentially problematic from the
Epicurean point of view. The danger with romantic love for the Epicurean lies in the
way lovers can become obsessed with one another, in ways that profoundly threaten
any possibility of contentment and tranquillity.
52 Excess and Obsession
Two centuries after Epicurus, the Roman poet Lucretius, in his Epicurean
philosophical poem ‘On the Nature of Things’, argues against indulging in
romantic love. While ordinary sexual desire is relatively easy to satisfy, roman-
tic love for Lucretius is a psychological obsession that disorders the mind. It
drives people to ruin their reputations, neglect their duties and waste their money
lavishing gifts on their beloved. It is nourished by distorted perceptions of the
object of their affection. Their ordinary attributes are idealised, producing an
illusory image of perfection that no person can possibly live up to. The impos-
sible romantic ideal of a complete union with another who is a model of perfec-
tion only leads to unrealistic expectations and frustration for all concerned. As
long as you are afflicted with this sickness, you will have no peace or tranquil-
lity. Even if your beloved is absent, you will still be tormented by images of
them and have no peace (see Lucretius 1951, 162–167). This is the passionate,
consuming love celebrated by the romantic Marianne in Sense and Sensibility;
but for the Epicurean, it is a mental affliction that ruins happiness and peace of
mind. Lucretius suggests therapies through which we might rid ourselves of the
romantic sickness, should we be unlucky enough to contract it. For example, he
suggests that you should concentrate on the beloved’s faults of mind and body
so you no longer have an idealised, distorted image of them. More positively,
you should learn to love the imperfect. If you want to be happy, you need to
go for realistic love based on character and habitual affection, rather than blind
passion (Lucretius 1951, 170).
Seen as a love story, Hitchcock’s Vertigo (1958) portrays many of the patho-
logical features of love described by Lucretius. San Francisco detective John
‘Scottie’ Ferguson (James Stewart) has become romantically involved with
Madeleine Elster (Kim Novak). She is the apparently suicidal woman whose
husband has asked him to follow, and after Scottie saves her from a suicide
attempt, he inevitably falls for her. Their growing closeness dominates the first
part of the film. After her apparent suicide at the clock tower, however, Scottie
becomes tormented by her image, imagining that he sees her in their favourite
restaurant, in front of the apartment building where she lived and on the street.
When he meets a woman, Judy, who resembles her, he tries to transform her
into the ideal he obsesses over, demanding that she dress and wear her hair as
Madeleine did. Here the distorting idealisation of the other becomes akin to
the Pygmalion pattern in which the protagonist, usually male, tries to mould a
female to fit an ideal. The whole situation is complicated in that Judy really is
his lost Madeleine; her charade as the suicidal wife was part of his client’s plot
to get away with murdering his real wife. But having fallen in love with Scottie,
she hopes that he will now love her for herself. Unfortunately, she is caught up
in Scottie’s obsession. He can only love her if she becomes his ideal Madeleine,
a woman who was never real. From here the film spirals to its tragic conclusion,
the real death of Madeleine/Judy, driven by Scottie’s obsessive desire for an
impossibly idealised other.
Noel Carroll argues that Vertigo not only offers an analysis of love and its
pathologies, but also illuminates a distinction between normal and pathological
Excess and Obsession 53
love. All romantic love involves a degree of fantasy, an idealisation of the other,
in which the participants imagine themselves two parts of a larger whole. And
this idealisation is unproblematic, to the extent that it remains based in the other’s
reality and encourages them to bring out their best. It becomes pathological when
the fantasy takes over, and the other is no longer seen as they are in any respect
but becomes completely subject to distorting idealisation. In these terms, Carroll
sees the first part of Vertigo as portraying a normal form of love and the second
as lurching into the pathological variety (see Carroll 2007). From this perspec-
tive, Lucretius’s dismissal of all romantic love as a dangerous sickness could
be questioned as overemphasising its pathological forms. But even if we accept
this, he can still be seen as calling attention to a pathology that is an inherent pos-
sibility in love relationships. Vertigo itself shows how readily love can turn into
something obsessive and pathological, and how the potentiality of its doing so is
present right from the start. The impossible ideal of a perfect union with one’s
ideal soulmate that fuels such obsessions is itself promoted through the fairy-tale
images of romantic love peddled by Hollywood films (Stephens 2010, 86). But
even within the Hollywood system, films like Vertigo have drawn attention to the
more pathological aspects of romantic passion, and in so doing, have also raised
questions about Hollywood’s own pathological romanticism.
To that extent, Vertigo can be seen as offering a Lucretian critique of romantic
love as a sickness, ‘with its demand for perfect union and its tendency to con-
struct the loved one as an idealized fantasy figure’ (Wood 2002, 385). It also
offers a commentary on the idealised Hollywood notion of love and the cinematic
construction of women as impossible fantasy figures. It is worth noting that in
Lucretius’s account of the pathologies of love, while the lovesick party is clearly
male, and the object of their obsession female, there is nothing to say that this
necessarily has to be so. As far as Lucretius is concerned, the roles could in prin-
ciple be reversed. It could just as easily be a woman who has become obsessed
over an impossibly idealised male. And the obsessed woman can also be found
in Hollywood films. For instance, there is the delusional Evelyn Draper in Play
Misty for Me, whose obsession with disc jockey Dave Garver (Clint Eastwood)
tips over into crazed violence. This is a scenario that is repeated later on, almost
note for note, in Fatal Attraction. But it also says a good deal about Hollywood
that these stories of female obsession are told very much from the male perspec-
tive, in terms of male panic over the threat posed by women who are not compli-
ant, who refuse to go along with male requirements and obediently disappear if
they are no longer needed. This anxiety frames the representation of these women
as versions of the ‘monstrous feminine’.
Mulholland Drive (2001), David Lynch’s ‘love story in the city of dreams’,
offers a corrective here in that it tells the story of romantic obsession from the
point of view of Hollywood starlet Diane Selwyn (Naomi Watts). The object of
obsession, however, remains a woman, in a further departure from Hollywood
norms. Diane not only creates an impossibly idealised image of her girlfriend
Camilla Rhodes (Laura Harring) but an entire fantasy or dream world that appears
to occupy the first two-thirds of the film. In this dream, Diane recreates their
54 Excess and Obsession
relationship in an idealised form in which she is successful Hollywood new-
comer Betty, and Camilla, an amnesiac car accident victim, Rita, whom she is
helping to search for her true identity. The story unfolds as a sunny neo-noir,
with Betty as the detective and Rita as her ‘friend fatale’. The dream is happy, a
Hollywood movie-style romance, but there are intimations that it is unreal and a
different reality lies under the surface. This is so most wrenchingly in the ‘Club
Silencio’ scene, where the couple’s bliss is destroyed as it is somehow indicated
that their entire relationship is an illusion. Soon afterward the dream evaporates.
The last part of the film is Diane’s bleak reality as a failed starlet, bitter at having
been abandoned by Camilla, who got the lead role in the movie that would have
brought Diane fame, and who, after enduring multiple humiliations at Camilla’s
hands, Diane has had murdered. This is the grim place, the ‘boulevard of broken
dreams’ that Diane has tried to escape from in the dream, and from which she will
eventually escape more permanently by killing herself.
The preceding represents a straightforward reading of the film, which has
a complex structure. However, much of the complexity has to do with the
film’s subversion not only of the ideal images that it presents but of the distinc-
tion between ideal and real itself. There is no hard and fast division between
the beautiful dream and the unpleasant reality. The one bleeds into the other.
Even in the sunny, romantic part of the film, which is largely coherent, even
hyper-realistic, there are ugly and disturbing episodes, such as a confrontation
with the evil hobo who lurks behind the diner. In the final scene, the distinc-
tion between ideal and real collapses altogether, leaving us with two violently
opposed images: the dead body of Diane, who has just shot herself, over which
float images of the blissfully happy Betty and Rita from Diane’s dream (see
Vass 2000; Sinnerbrink 2005). Overall, Mulholland Drive, like Vertigo, is both
a story of romantic obsession in which reality is displaced by delusional images
of perfection that people cannot possibly live up to and a commentary on
Hollywood’s own contribution to the production of such fantasies, its construc-
tion of women as impossible fantasy figures. Mulholland Drive goes further in
criticising the Hollywood system itself, subverting Hollywood’s self-image as
the place of dreams, the ‘dream factory’, by pointing to the brutal mechanics
of a male-dominated industry and the exploitative reality that greets actresses
seeking to make it there. Diane’s dream is also the compensatory delusion of
someone who has been destroyed by the industry.
To return to Epicureanism, we can finish with some questions that arise in
connection with this ethical position. As we will see, similar concerns arise with
more recent forms of pleasure-based ethics. Regarding Epicureanism’s psycho-
logical hedonism, its view of human nature, is it really the case that we are pri-
marily motivated by the desire for pleasure? Can this view be maintained without
becoming trivial and unfalsifiable, as when we hold that even the most selfless
acts are ‘really’ performed because they give us pleasure? Questions can also be
raised about Epicureanism’s ethical hedonism, its view that pleasure is the only
worthwhile goal, the only thing that people should strive for, and the idea that
the happy life is above all the pleasant one. It might be argued that human beings
Excess and Obsession 55
characteristically value things over and above pleasure. They typically aspire to
certain virtues or ideals of character and feel badly if they fall short of these
ideals. As such, purely pleasure-based accounts of morality might not be able
to address the full range of moral experience. There are times, arguably, when
being moral might involve putting constraints on desire, and not simply in order
to ensure maximum satisfaction in the longer term; times when doing what we
ought to do might be at the expense of pleasure. Certainly, Plato, Aristotle and
Stoicism lined up against the Epicurean idea that a life of pleasure could consti-
tute a fully realised human life. Of course, even Epicureanism turns its back on
the life of pleasure to the extent that it counsels not unlimited pleasure-seeking
but restricting oneself to those desires that can be easily satisfied. Its peculiar
achievement is to fashion a pleasure-based morality of restraint. But it is not clear
that it can account for situations where being moral requires not merely restraint
of pleasure but downright suffering and pain.
Whatever the debates between the various ancient schools, by the third cen-
tury ad, in the declining period of the Roman empire, they were displaced by
Neoplatonism, a revived version of Plato’s ideas developed particularly by the
Roman thinker Plotinus (205–270). Plotinus construed the universe as an ‘ema-
nation’ of the One or God, a transcendental first principle that is above material
being, a higher reality, the notion being derived from Plato’s supreme Form of
the good. For Plotinus, the One can be apprehended by the human soul as a pres-
ence transcending all knowing. Itself absolutely perfect and good, it brings about
increasing imperfect forms of existence, with physical matter being the lowest
form. Because human beings are attached to the material, the physical body, they
are open to evil. In order to flourish, the soul or mind needs to purge itself of the
bodily, this purging to be achieved through the virtues. The happy life is very
much a matter of turning away from this world in order to contemplate and ulti-
mately return as a disembodied soul to higher unity with the One. Neoplatonism
also appropriated elements of Stoic ethics, to the extent that Stoic ethics teaches
us to get rid of disturbing passions.
Neoplatonism also looks forward to the Christian era. From our vantage
point in the present, we are perhaps apt to see the transition from the classical
to the Christian era as the triumph of dogmatic religion over the reason, criti-
cal reflection and independent scientific enquiry, which will only return with
the collapse of the medieval worldview. The film Agora (Alejandro Amená bar,
2009) might serve as an example. It deals with the final years of philosopher-
scientist Hypatia (c.370–415), director of the Neoplatonist school in Roman
Alexandria, murdered by a Christian mob led by fanatical monks. The film
portrays Hypatia as an independent thinker, affirming her known interest in
mathematics and astronomy, and imagining her to have anticipated key dis-
coveries the seventeenth-century scientific revolution such as the sun-centred
view of the solar system and the elliptical orbits of the planets. By contrast, the
Christianity that is coming into ascendancy demands unswerving belief in the
word of God as revealed in the scriptures and submission to the authority of
priests. The impression is of an abrupt transition into dogmatic religion. What is
56 Excess and Obsession
obscured here is the manner in which Christianity incorporated many classical
ideas into its developing worldview. In particular, many Neoplatonic ideas were
appropriated in the theology of Augustine, Christianity’s first great synthesiser.
Hypatia herself was by all accounts a Neoplatonist in philosophical matters,
her mathematical and astronomical investigations serving as a pathway to the
contemplation of the higher reality envisaged in the Neoplatonic account (see
Sharpe 2012, 35).
Hypatia is also said to have lectured on apatheia, freedom from the tyranny
of emotions that served to distract the mind from contemplation of the cosmos;
and she was widely known for her sage-like equanimity. We can see something
of this ideal of equanimity, familiar from Stoicism, in Amená bar’s film, which
imagines Hypatia being mercifully euthanised by her slave before the Christians
have a chance to murder her. Faced with the inevitable, she calmly assents to
this loving gesture. As Matthew Sharpe notes, the film itself employs a tech-
nique similar to that recommended by the Stoics to promote such philosophical
detachment and acceptance, namely trying to see things from the point of view
of nature as a whole rather than from one’s limited perspective, in order to
recognise how we are but small, temporary elements of a larger order beyond
our control. As the Stoic emperor Marcus Aurelius urges, assuming this point
of view will help us to attain the appropriate indifference towards our circum-
stances, their ‘calm acceptance’ (Marcus Aurelius 2006, 90; see Sellars 2006
126–127). The film encourages this larger point of view by placing the events
that it portrays within such a large perspective, its first shot beginning from
far out in space, then revealing the earth’s globe and moving in on ancient
Alexandria, and the last shot pulling back from the events in Alexandria to a
view from space (see Sharpe 2012, 42).
However, these events are to be viewed, the death of Hypatia provides a con-
venient marker for the end of the classical era and the beginning of the Christian
era, and it is to the moral thinking of the Christian era that we now turn.
Plot
Dr Henry Jekyll, a doctor in Victorian London, is certain that within each
person there is both good and evil, and that science offers the possibility
of freeing us from the evil side of our makeup. In Mamoulian’s version,
the film opens with Jekyll (Fredric March), heading off to give a lecture
to this effect to colleagues and friends. In Fleming’s version, the story
opens with a congregation at a church service, with Dr Jekyll (Spencer
Tracy) in attendance. The service is disturbed by a madman in the grip
of his evil side.
In the Mamoulian version, Jekyll arrives late for a dinner party at the
home of fiancé e Muriel Carew (Rose Hobart), daughter of Brigadier
General Sir Danvers Carew (Halliwell Hobbes). After the others have
left, Jekyll asks Danvers’ permission to bring forward their wedding date,
but Danvers refuses. In Fleming’s remake, Jekyll holds forth about the
dual nature of man at a dinner party hosted by a Mrs Marley. In attend-
ance is his fiancé , now called Beatrix Emery (Lana Turner) and her
father Charles Emery (Donald Crisp).
In the Mamoulian film, Jekyll, while walking home with his colleague,
Dr John Lanyon (Holmes Herbert), spots a prostitute, Ivy Pierson (Miriam
Hopkins), being attacked by a man outside her boarding house. He
drives the man away and carries Ivy up to her room. Ivy tries to seduce
Jekyll, but Jekyll fights temptation and leaves with Lanyon (Ian Hunter).
In Fleming’s version, Ivy (Ingrid Bergman) is a barmaid and singer, with
no implication of prostitution.
Jekyll develops a drug that releases the evil side in himself, becom-
ing Hyde. In the Mamoulian version, the physical transformation when
Jekyll transforms into Hyde is striking. In the Fleming version, there is less
physical change. The remainder of Fleming’s film largely follows the lines
of the Mamoulian version, which runs as follows. Hyde returns to Ivy’s
boarding house and offers to look after her financial needs in return for her
company but treats her cruelly. He remains at her boarding house until he
discovers that Muriel and her father are returning to London. He leaves
Ivy but threatens that he will be back. Guilt-ridden over Hyde’s treatment
of Ivy, Jekyll has his servant deliver money to her. Ivy goes to see Jekyll,
hoping he can free her from the abusive Hyde. She recognises Jekyll as
the man who saved her from the attack outside her boarding house. Jekyll
promises Ivy she won’t have to worry about Hyde anymore.
En route to a party at the Carews’ home to celebrate their return,
Jekyll changes spontaneously into Hyde. Hyde goes to confront Ivy
58 Excess and Obsession
about seeing Jekyll and murders her. He returns to Jekyll’s house but
his servant refuses to admit him. He writes a letter to his colleague
Lanyon from Jekyll, asking him to get chemicals and have them wait-
ing at Lanyon’s home. When Hyde arrives, Lanyon produces a gun and
demands Hyde take him to Jekyll. Hyde drinks the formula and turns
back into Jekyll. Jekyll decides he must call off the wedding to Muriel
for her own safety.
Jekyll goes to the Carews’ to tell Muriel he cannot be with her any-
more. After leaving, he changes into Hyde again, comes back into the
house and attacks Muriel. When her father intervenes, Hyde kills him
using Jekyll’s cane, then runs off towards Jekyll’s home lab to mix a new
formula to change himself back. Standing over Danvers’ body with the
police, Lanyon recognises Jekyll’s cane and agrees to take the police
to its owner. The police arrive at Jekyll’s lab looking for Hyde and find
only Jekyll, but Lanyon tells them that Jekyll is the man they are looking
for. Jekyll changes into Hyde before their eyes. He attacks Lanyon, then
tries to escape from the police but is shot. As he lies dead, he transforms
one last time back into Jekyll.
Key Scenes
1 Mamoulian’s version opens with an extended point-of-view shot that
arrives in front of a mirror, revealing the point of view to be that of Dr
Jekyll himself [1.10–4.37]. In this way, we in the audience are identi-
fied with him, and his nature with ours. Jekyll heads off to give a lec-
ture on human nature, in which the ‘soul of man’ is said to consist of
two sides, the ‘good’ side and the ‘bad’ or ‘evil’ side, engaged in an
eternal struggle [4.18–6.33]. In Fleming’s version, the good and evil
sides of the human being are portrayed visually, the story opening
with a church service, linking the good side with religion, interrupted
by a madman who is wholly given over to the evil side [1.20–4.25].
2 In Fleming’s version, the references to religion continue. Jekyll pre-
sents his view of the duality of human nature at the dinner party,
describing two parts, good and evil, ‘chained together in the soul’
where they constantly fight one another. This version is distin-
guished by religious references invoked by Jekyll himself: ‘we all
have an evil side … why, as Christians we admit that man is created
weak’. In response to Jekyll’s claims that science will free human
beings from their evil side, the bishop asks whether it is wise to tam-
per with the problem of good co-existing with evil in the human soul.
Instead he invokes the need for God’s grace to help human beings
Excess and Obsession 59
Plot
In Glasgow, a motorcyclist (Jeremy McWilliams) retrieves a dead woman
(Lynsey Taylor Mackay) from the roadside and puts her in the back of
a van. A woman (Scarlett Johansson) puts on her clothes. The woman
drives the van around Scotland, picking up men. She lures a man (Joe
Szula) into a house. As he undresses, following the woman into a dark
place, he is submerged in a black liquid.
At a beach, the woman tries to pick up a swimmer (Kryš tof Há dek),
who runs off to help a couple in trouble in rough sea. When he returns
exhausted and unsuccessful, the woman strikes his head with a rock,
drags him to the van and drives away, ignoring the couple’s baby. The
next day, the woman listens to a radio report about the missing fam-
ily. The woman then visits a nightclub and picks up another man (Paul
Brannigan). At the house, he follows her into the void and is submerged
in the liquid. Suspended beneath the surface, he sees the swimmer
floating beside him, alive but bloated. When he touches him, the swim-
mer’s body collapses and a red substance empties out through a trough.
The woman seduces a facially-disfigured man (Adam Pearson) but
lets him leave after catching herself in a mirror. The motorcyclist inter-
cepts the man and bundles him into a car, then sets out in pursuit of the
woman. In the Scottish Highlands, the woman abandons the van in the
fog. She walks to a restaurant and tries to eat a piece of cake but cannot
and spits it out. At a bus stop, she meets a man (Michael Moreland) who
offers to help her. At his house, they eat and watch television. Alone in
Excess and Obsession 61
her room, she examines her body in a mirror. They visit a ruined castle.
Back at his house, they kiss and begin to have sex, but the woman stops
abruptly and examines her genitals.
The woman wanders in a forest, meets a commercial logger (Dave
Acton) and finds a place to sleep. She awakes to find the man molesting
her. She runs into the wilderness but he catches and attempts to rape
her. He tears her skin, revealing the featureless body of the alien. As the
alien extricates herself from the skin, the man douses her in petrol and
burns her alive.
Key Scenes
1 As the alien sets out on her mission, to lure and entrap men, there
is an extended point-of-view shot in which we follow her through a
shopping mall, and later we view the world through the windows of
the van she is driving [10.10–13.25]. In this manner, we are identi-
fied with her point of view; but at the same time, it is a perspective
that seems strange because it is, unusually in cinematic terms, a
female gaze that objectifies men and reduces them to prey. In this
manner, the film conveys the sense of an alien perspective on the
world. This is also an ironic comment on gender relations: a woman
could only act like this and get away with it if she were an alien.
2 In the scene at the beach, the sense of an alien perspective on the
world is reinforced. The woman strikes the swimmer with a rock and
drags him to her van, leaving the baby of the couple the swimmer
had tried to save crying on the beach. The scene is shot in an objec-
tive, anthropological way. No particular attention is paid to the baby,
who is left in the background of the shot, a mere detail, reflecting
the woman’s own lack of interest in it [22.37–28.06]. In this scene,
a sense of the alienness of the woman’s perspective is conveyed
through its absolute amorality, so remote from ordinary human ways
of responding to such a situation.
3 There are now hints that the woman is no longer a pure predator.
She is presented walking in the street as if being watched rather than
watching. When she falls, passers-by gather around her to help her
up. This is followed by multiple scenes of people interacting on the
streets, eventually forming a golden aura around her face, as if she
is starting to be drawn to humanity, wanting to belong [44.40–47.48].
4 The woman picks up her last victim, a facially-disfigured man and,
though talking with him sympathetically, brings him to the house
for consumption. However, after examining herself at length in a
62 Excess and Obsession
mirror, she lets him go. We have so far seen portions of her face
in the van’s rear-view mirror, but this is the first time her entire face
appears in a reflected image. It does not seem to be a moment of
self-discovery, but rather the point where she tries to identify with
the woman she is in the eyes of others [59.44–1.01.55].
5 After this, her point of view is no longer dominant. She appears
increasingly as a figure in the landscape [1.04.40–1.07.13; also
1.09.08–1.10.13]. This also marks a shift in her relations with oth-
ers. She ceases to be a predator of men; instead, she becomes
their prey. Now, instead of picking up and luring men to her
house, she is picked up by a man, and invited to stay in his house
[1.13.25–1.14.09]. He is kind and wants to help her, but this could
also be seen as a form of male predation. Now she has to be
carried over puddles [1.19.15–1.19.48] and helped downstairs
[1.20.09–1.22.04]. Again, there is an ironic reference to gender
relations. To identify as a human female is to no longer be a preda-
tory subject but to become the object of prey.
6 There are further mirror scenes at the man’s house [1.14.07–1.14.10;
1.16.13–1.18.04]. The attempt to identify with the woman she is in
the eyes of others may represent a form of self-deception, insofar as
it constitutes an attempt to deny her own alienness. That alienness
continues to intrude. In the restaurant, she gags on a piece of cake
she tries to eat [1.07.23–1.09.07]; at the man’s house, she taps the
wrong rhythm to the music [1.14.44–1.15.37]; sex is incomprehen-
sible to her [1.22.19–1.26.36]. In the end, she is unable to lead this
human life and flees into the forest.
7 This only makes her more vulnerable to attack. After the preda-
tory logger tries to rape her, he discovers the alien under her skin
and runs off. She discards her human skin, fully revealing her alien
form. She spends some time contemplating her face, which she now
holds in her hands. This may constitute a final recognition that the
human female she wanted to identify with was only a mask, skin-
deep [1.37.47–1.39.30].
2 Sin and Self-Denial
Religious Ethics
At the end of Abel Ferrara’s The Addiction (1995), a young woman lies on a
hospital bed. She has asked for the blinds to be opened and is now waiting for
the sunlight to fall on her. Kathleen Conklin (Lili Taylor) is a vampire who
has come to be horrified by her addiction to blood and no longer wants to sub-
mit to it (Figure 2.1). As a vampire, she knows how to do away with herself.
Figure 2.1 Kathleen the vampire in The Addiction (Abel Ferrara, 1995. Credit:
October Films/Photofest).
64 Sin and Self-Denial
But Casanova (Annabella Sciorra), the vampire who originally bit her, has
entered the room and abruptly closes the blinds. ‘It’s not that easy’ she says. ‘To
find rest takes a real genius’. But now as Kathleen lies alone in the gloom, she
has another visitor. A priest enters and asks how she is. She whispers that she
wants to make a confession and asks for God’s forgiveness. The priest absolves
her, administers a communion wafer and she becomes still, in repose as we
hear her say ‘Amen’ in voiceover. She is seemingly released, at rest at last. In
the film’s final scene, we see Kathleen in a cemetery, leaving a flower on her
own grave and then walking off as the camera pans upwards to a sculpture of a
crucifix. Over this we hear her in voice-over, saying ‘To face what we are in the
end, we stand before the light. And our true nature is revealed. Self-revelation is
annihilation of the self’. With this scene, this grittily realist film’s narrative has
given way to imagery filled with intimations of the transcendental. In accepting
God, Kathleen has been annihilated as a vampire and has transcended her addic-
tion. Thus, the vampire returns to our discussion, only now in a form coloured
by religious considerations. It is the religious, specifically Christian, view of
ethics and human nature that is the subject of this chapter.
Divine Command
With the rise of Christianity, which emerged out of a first-century Jewish move-
ment to become the dominant worldview in the West, especially in the medieval
period, a new stream was injected into ethical thinking, a religious concep-
tion of morality that turned on a single transcendent deity existing in a realm
beyond this one. Gone is the profusion of rather worldly gods that populated
the ancient world. In the Christian view, the world is understood to be subject
to a supernatural ordering principle, itself personified as a divine being that
creates the world and is able to intervene in it. The focus in ethical thinking is
on how human beings are related to this divine being, which is greatly supe-
rior to them in power, goodness and wisdom, indeed all-good as well as all-
knowing and all-powerful. As has been noted, Christianity incorporated a great
many classical ideas into its worldview, particularly from Greek philosophy.
This notion of a transcendental being is informed by Plato’s Form of the Good,
the overarching Form in his unworldly sphere of perfect Forms. But where the
Good is an abstract ideal for Plato, the Christian God is personal. As with Plato,
for Christianity there is one universal, objective form of the good life. The
Christian God issues commands for the universe as a whole and human beings
in particular. Being good is a matter of obeying those commands, submitting to
them, bringing your will into line with God’s. Evil is turning away from God,
trying to determine your own fate and thinking that you are self-sufficient. Left
to your own devices, you will fall prey to the cruelty and evil that arises from
your own corrupted nature.
Even today there are many for whom morality seems impossible without a
Christian religious basis and for whom the modern ‘materialist’ or scientific view
of the universe consequently represents a profound problem. This is the position
Sin and Self-Denial 65
famously expressed by Dmitri Karamazov in Dostoevsky’s novel The Brothers
Karamazov, when the character proclaims that ‘Without God … everything is
permitted’ (Dostoevsky 1990, 589). Or, as expressed by Sonia (Diane Keaton) in
Woody Allen’s Russian novels parody Love and Death (1975), ‘let’s say there is
no God and each man is free to do exactly as he chooses, well, what prevents you
from murdering someone?’ It’s a question that as we will see, haunts a number of
the characters in his subsequent films. The more general concern being expressed
here is that not only would one have no motivation to be ethical if God did not
exist, but there would be no basis for the rules of morality. However, it should
already be apparent that, even if religious systems typically dispense morality,
morality does not necessarily depend on religion. In the West, ancient Greek and
Roman ethical positions justifying moral judgements developed prior to and inde-
pendently of Christianity, indeed of any religious standpoint. Epicureanism in
particular developed an ethical position on the basis of an aggressively materialist
view of the world, a reason perhaps for Christianity’s particular hostility towards
it. In the end, morality only depends necessarily on the Christian God to the extent
that one will only accept as morality a Christian conception of morality. In other
words, that is a view that presupposes what it is arguing for, a God-centred con-
ception of the world and morality.
In this God-centred understanding, emerging out of both the Jewish and
Christian traditions, God is envisaged as a lawgiver, handing down laws. The
Hollywood biblical epic provides a spectacular visual representation of this.
Moral laws are literally etched into stone by God from on high in The Ten
Commandments (Cecil B. DeMille 1956; see Mitchell 2009, 489). On this under-
standing, in order to guide us in the right way of living, God has formulated cer-
tain rules or commands, epitomised by the Ten Commandments, that we ought to
obey. We are not compelled to obey them, because we have been created as free
agents, and so we can know what we should do and yet choose not to abide by it.
It is up to us to decide whether to accept or reject these rules. Nonetheless, these
rules tell us how we ought to live. This is a rule-based or ‘deontological’ concep-
tion of morality, one characterised by universal moral laws. The virtue ethics of
the ancient world does not disappear. The ideal remains virtuous behaviour, but
whereas in ancient ethics the focus was primarily on living in accordance with
one’s nature, now right living becomes a matter of following external standards,
the divine commandments, conforming to the will of God, whether embodied in
the revelations of the bible, the authority of the church or the inner voice of one’s
conscience. Virtues are now the states of character that help us to do God’s will
(van Hooft 2006, 84). In terms of predecessors in ancient thought, this picture
is closest to Plato’s, insofar as for Plato the ultimate basis of morality is not to
be found in human nature but in the transcendental world of the Forms. It can
similarly be seen as a non-naturalist notion of ethics only now moral values are
dependent on a supernatural deity. To distinguish it, we can characterise this as a
‘supernaturalist’ conception of morality.
A more mundane version would have it that moral rules that evolved out of
ancient communal life came to be understood as having been laid down by God.
66 Sin and Self-Denial
But in the religious view at least, moral rules are God’s commandments. This
view has been spelt out as the ‘divine command’ theory of morality, for which the
morally right thing to do is whatever is commanded by God, and morally wrong
means that which is forbidden by God. This construction also provides us with
a new sort of reason to be moral. Plato’s Gyges story raises the question of why
we should be moral if we can commit immoral acts without any chance of being
observed and punished. On the religious account, even if we are invisible to those
around us, we can never ultimately escape being seen and judged. Judah, the doc-
tor in Allen’s Crimes and Misdemeanors, may have wealth and social standing to
arrange for his mistress’s murder and cover up his involvement, but he is haunted
by memories of his father and his religious upbringing. In particular he recalls his
father saying that God sees everything and that those who are righteous will be
rewarded while those who are wicked will be punished for eternity. We may thus
have a reason to do the right thing, constrained by the threat of divine punishment
or at least by the promptings of our own conscience – whether the latter is under-
stood as the voice of God within or internalised parental admonitions.
The idea that moral rules are an expression of God’s will is not, however,
without its problems. Apart from anything else, this view of morality depends on
a belief in God and the validity of the scriptures. If this belief is questioned, it is
undermined. So it is for the murderous doctor in Crimes and Misdemeanors. For
Judah, despite the residual religious orientation that derives from his upbring-
ing, and the internal struggles that he has to undergo as a result, he insists that
he is in the end a ‘man of science’, that there is no God watching and judging,
and that there is no divine punishment to contend with. The scientific view of
the world is understood here to undermine the religious perspective, with large
implications if religion is taken to be the basis for morality. Without it there is
only our conscience stopping us from acting purely in our own self-interest and
Judah finds that conscience is not as powerful a constraint on behaviour as one
might imagine. Here, we are back on the couch at the end of film, with Judah,
having gotten away with murder, telling his story to filmmaker Cliff in the guise
of a movie plot. Cliff suggests that a more believable scenario would be to have
the protagonist being driven by guilt to turn themselves in, an allusion to the plot
of Dostoevsky’s Crime and Punishment. Judah’s response is to dismisses this as
something that happens in the movies, not in real life. In reality, people can live
with all sorts of sins.
Allen’s more recent Match Point (2005) explores similar themes but with God
even more conclusively out of the picture. This time the character who gets away
with murder is Chris (Jonathan Rhys Meyers), an ex-tennis star. Having married
into a wealthy family, he, like Judah, does away with a mistress who is threat-
ening his privileged life. Here, the religious dimension has been more starkly
eclipsed. There are no troubling flashbacks to a religious upbringing. Early in the
film, over dinner, Chris relates dismissively how his father found religion when
he lost both his legs and insists that ‘scientists are confirming more and more that
all existence is here by blind chance’. Once again, the modern scientific view
of the world is seen as excluding a religious perspective, which is significant if
Sin and Self-Denial 67
morality is understood to be impossible without God. Nor is Chris greatly trou-
bled by guilt or remorse at what he has done. Conscience remains a weak force.
In a later dream sequence, he confesses to his victim Nola (Scarlett Johansson)
that he did feel guilt, but you can learn to push it under the rug and go on. Like
Judah in Crimes and Misdemeanors, he sees himself as having done what had to
be done to protect his interests, making pure self-interest the ruling determinant of
his behaviour. In another echo of the earlier film, Match Point makes a jokey ref-
erence to Dostoevsky’s Crime and Punishment with a shot early on of Chris read-
ing the book in bed, and, presumably perplexed by the protagonist Raskolnikov’s
actions, turning to a Companion to Dostoevsky for explanation.
Match Point can be taken to dramatise, even more emphatically than Crimes
and Misdemeanors, the Dostoevskian concern that without God everything is
permissible. Equally, it highlights the problem that to understand ethics as neces-
sarily based on religion makes one vulnerable as a moral being if one loses one’s
faith. But there also internal problems with the religious conception of ethics. In
its divine command form, in which the morally good thing to do is whatever is
commanded by God, it is not clear how we are to establish what God’s will actu-
ally is, what God in fact commands. The scriptures are not always consistent and
are open to interpretation, as are miracles, dreams and other signs that might be
invoked to support claims regarding God’s will. The problem becomes especially
acute if the will of God is invoked in order to justify what to ordinary observers
might seem to be evil, cruel or in other ways morally questionable acts. How
do we know that those who invoke this justification are not simply mistaken,
deluded, mentally ill or perhaps just finding a convenient rationalisation for what
they do? The more extreme the actions, the more likely we are to think that some-
thing like this is going on. The person themselves might be absolutely sincere in
their beliefs about what God is commanding them to do, but such claims not only
make it possible for them to justify extreme acts to themselves, as being in the
name of a higher power, but also serve to insulate their actions from critical exam-
ination. As Voltaire puts it in his 1764 Philosophical Dictionary, ‘What can you
say to a man who tells you he prefers obeying God rather than men, and that as a
result he’s certain he’ll go to heaven if he cuts your throat?’ (Voltaire 2011, 138)
A case in point, the biblical story of Abraham presents a picture of someone
who believes that he has divine justification (via angelic command) for killing
his son, however reluctant he might be to do so. For all his certainty, it would
be natural for others to suppose that this must be the belief of a delusional indi-
vidual, perhaps one suffering from a mental illness. This is certainly our natu-
ral assumption when presented with the homicidal father (Bill Paxton) in Frailty
(Bill Paxton, 2001), who one night informs his children that he has been visited by
an angel and given the mission of destroying demons disguised as human beings.
There is also an Abrahamic element here, in that he also indicates that the angel
told him that his older son, Fenton, is a demon as well, though he refuses to kill
him. We can sympathise with Fenton, who thinks that his father has ‘gone crazy’,
and that his younger brother, Adam, who claims to be sharing some of his father’s
visions, has been brainwashed by him. The film is able to exploit the audience’s
68 Sin and Self-Denial
presuppositions by eventually making it apparent that the father was in fact telling
the truth; and also revealing that the narrator of the story, which we were led to
believe was Fenton, was in fact Adam, who did indeed share the father’s visions.
At the same time, film has the advantage of being able to give the viewer God-like
access to the world it creates. In this case, we are given access to enough informa-
tion to know that the father is not crazy, that he really is on a mission from God.
For ordinary human beings, without any God-like access to the transcendental, it
remains unclear how we can ever know what the will of God might be, or whether
anyone who claims to be following God’s commands is indeed doing so.
By way of comparison, The Passion of Joan of Arc (Carl Theodor Dreyer,
1928) seems to bring us face to face with the religious mission that infuses the life
of the central character. The film follows Joan of Arc’s 1431 trial for heresy, her
interrogation, torture and eventual execution, based on a transcript of the actual
trial. Here there is a dramatic portrayal of someone who fervently believes them-
selves to be on a mission from God. Through stylistic means, particularly the
repeated, almost obsessive close-ups of actor Maria Falconetti’s expressive face,
what is communicated is the character’s absolute commitment to a religious expe-
rience, regardless of the consequences of doing so. In this way, the film conveys
the reality and certainty of religious experience, at least for the person directly
involved. Yet despite that, it remains the case that there is nothing approaching
certainty for the viewer here. In contrast to Frailty, what is absent is any ‘objec-
tive’ filmic validation of Joan’s belief, any revelation to the audience allowing us
to see that she was indeed acting in God’s name. The film does not portray the
transcendental and we are not given access to transcendental experiences them-
selves or even indirect evidence of them. The character can certainly be seen
as somehow communicating an experience of something beyond that cannot be
conveyed through words. Someone who already believes might be predisposed to
view what is being presented this way. Or we may simply see an extraordinary
evocation of religious fervour, as something akin to madness. And in the end, it
remains possible to ask whether we are gazing on the face of a saint or someone
who is simply insane.
So these are some of the problems with the divine command view to do with
what we can know of the basis for its moral claims, but a further kind of problem
has to with the very notion of moral goodness or rightness it involves. Inasmuch
as the belief that one is following God’s commands provides a justification for
the actions one undertakes, it is not an objection to what they are doing that their
action might seem evil or terrible. If it is commanded by God, it is morally right.
By definition, what is morally right is what God commands, and what is wrong is
what he forbids. Thus, the homicidal father in Frailty can quite rightly say he is
doing the morally good thing, however horrible it might appear to others, insofar
as it has been commanded by God. In principle anything, no matter how seem-
ingly reprehensible, is morally right provided God commands it. To that extent,
the problem is not so much that without God everything is permissible, as that
if there is a God, then anything is permitted. In practical terms, the person who
believes that God is on their side is capable of anything, in the name of the higher
Sin and Self-Denial 69
law. Belief in a higher justice will enable one to overcome the moral qualms
most would ordinarily feel about killing and other extreme acts (see Zizek 2012;
Ignatieff 2013).
We might protest that surely a good God would not command terrible things,
that there would be limits to what a genuinely good God would command. But
now we are in the realm of the Euthyphro problem, so-called because it was raised
by Plato in his dialogue Euthyphro. In the dialogue, Socrates and Euthyphro are
discussing piety, and Socrates asks whether the gods love the pious because it is
the pious or whether the pious is pious only because it is loved by the gods (Plato
2003, 10a). This is now our question: is something right because God commands
it or does God command it because it is right? The problem is, there are problems
with both alternatives. If something is right because God commands it, there is
no moral limit to what God can command. Frailty’s homicidal father insists that
‘destroying demons is a good thing. Killing people is bad’, but while he may want
to draw the line at doing away with people, were he to be commanded by God to
kill indiscriminately, he could not object on the grounds that such an action was
evil. God’s command would make it good. But if there is no reason why God
cannot command any act, including indiscriminate murder, this also means that
God’s commands are completely arbitrary. He has no more reason to command
an action than to forbid it. Moreover, the very idea that God is good is destroyed
on this view. If good and bad are determined by God’s will, then to say that God’s
commands are good is only to say that God’s commands are commanded by God,
which is an empty statement. Thus, while we might look for guidance to rules
of morality handed down by God from on high, if right and wrong are whatever
God determines them to be, they become a matter of arbitrary choice, and the firm
foundation God is supposed to provide for morality evaporates away.
The alternative is to drop the idea that an action is right because God
commands it and to hold instead that God commands an action because it is
right. In this view, God has the infinite wisdom to know what is right and
what is wrong, and in the light of this knowledge, commands the right con-
duct. This avoids the arbitrariness of the first option. However, this approach
has its own difficulties, severe ones because it seems to make a religion-based
conception of morality unnecessary. Now, God is no longer required in order
to make an action right or wrong, to justify moral judgements. There are
objective standards of right and wrong that are independent of God’s will,
that God himself has to adhere to. And as such, what is distinctively theologi-
cal about this account of morality seems to disappear. We have effectively
abandoned the divine command theory of morality.
Augustine
A key architect of the Christian world view, and Christian ethics in particular, is
Augustine (354–430 ad), bishop of Hippo, in what is now Algeria. Living in the
dying days of the Roman empire, around the same time as Hypatia, Augustine
articulates a unified doctrine for the emerging religion, drawing on both Plato and
70 Sin and Self-Denial
Neoplatonism. The two-level view of reality as material existence and a higher,
transcendental reality that these views share is transmuted into the idea of God
as a transcendent, immaterial reality existing eternally outside of space and time,
but also the source of everything that comes below. Against this background,
Augustine formulates a Christianised version of eudaimonistic virtue ethics,
bound up with a version of the divine command theory. Once again, all human
beings are understood to seek happiness, ‘beatitude’ in Augustine’s terms. Only
now, real happiness for a human being consists in enjoyment of God, which is
the reward for being virtuous in this life. God provides the rules we must adhere
to if we are to attain this reward and virtue consists in successfully following
the rules. Morality thus takes the form of conforming to the prescriptions of the
divine law, the unchanging and eternal ideals, articulated in the scriptures, that
are also imprinted on the human mind. As such, we have reasons to be moral over
and above the fear of divine punishment if we do not. Being moral, following the
rules, being virtuous in this life, is a condition for human happiness, the ultimate
happiness of being one with God in the next. Thus, as with ancient ethics, the goal
for human beings remains happiness, the fulfilled life. Only now that happiness
requires that we follow God’s commands and fulfilment takes the form of the
ultimate union with God.
Virtue here includes the classic virtues celebrated by the Greeks, wisdom, jus-
tice, courage and temperance or self-denial, but also virtues that are foreign to
Greek thinking but praised in the New Testament, namely faith, hope and charity.
Charity is an orientation towards the good or well-being of others. The addition
of these new virtues by Augustine is the point where altruism enters significantly
into moral thinking, though the term itself was not coined until the nineteenth
century by August Comte. It is not that ancient ethics was self-centred, concerned
only with the individual and their happiness. What seems new with Christianity
however, is the increasing importance of the ideal of selflessness, sacrificing one-
self, putting the needs and interests of others above one’s own, the altruism that
nowadays is practically synonymous with being moral. With Augustine, altruism
in the form of Christian charity is the preeminent virtue, the most important of a
number of forms of behaviour commanded by God, the pursuit of which will lead
to eternal salvation. For the moment, however, we are going to focus on another
aspect of Augustine’s moral picture, which is the supreme importance of self-
denial, the renunciation of desire.
One important thing that God’s rules commanded was to go against one’s feel-
ings, desires and appetites. They are too strongly attached to the things of this
world and this is an avowedly supernatural conception of morality. Being moral,
attaining Christian goodness and virtue, is very much bound up with rising above
the physical appetites, denying our love for sensual pleasures, rejecting attach-
ment to this world, in order to reach God in the next. Desire, which connects us
to the material world, stands in the way of goodness, and ultimately of salvation,
and needs to be overcome. We can see in this the reappearance, with Augustine
at the start of the Christian era, of Plato’s picture of human life as a struggle to
overcome and control desire. Augustine also takes from Plato the view that the
Sin and Self-Denial 71
self is an immaterial soul that can think, the ‘inner person’; and the idea of human
being as the combination of a rational soul and a mortal and earthly body. There
is, however, one important difference. For Plato, the good life depends on reason
having the dominant position. For Augustine, the most important feature of the
soul, ethically speaking, is not reason but the will, the ability to choose between
the lower goods, the objects of the bodily pleasures and appetites, or the higher
goods of virtue and God. In his autobiographical Confessions, Augustine details
his own addiction to bodily pleasures in his youth, before he overcame them with
his eventual conversion to Christianity.
Thus, being moral on this account requires us to overcome our desiring nature,
for the sake of ultimate union with God, in which the immaterial soul, finally free
of the body, will go to heaven. At the same time, Augustine is extremely pes-
simistic about the prospects for most of us managing to achieve this self-denial
and attain virtue. Whereas for the ancient world virtue was generally seen as
being within the power of human beings to achieve, albeit with difficulty, for
Augustine, it is virtually impossible. As far as the appetites are concerned, he has
a keen appreciation of human weakness of will. To say he is suspicious of desire
is an understatement. He seems to have been terrified of the pleasures of the flesh,
the physical desires that persistently refuse to be constrained by the will, which
he calls ‘concupiscence’. For him, desire is an internal compulsion that human
beings by themselves are too weak to overcome or break free from in order to
choose the good. Human beings are constantly attracted towards evil, the exces-
sive satisfaction of their lower desires for material things and pleasures. Why
do people find it so difficult to choose the good? For Augustine, it is a matter of
human nature. Human beings are inherently depraved, constitutionally inclined
towards indulging their physical desires.
This inherent human predisposition towards evil is in turn understood as a
sickness that is part of humanity’s ‘fallen’ condition. Human beings had inher-
ited the original sin of the first parents, Adam and Eve, who disobeyed God and
were thrown out of the Garden of Eden as a result. The biblical story, which had
been dismissed or treated as an allegory by earlier commentators, was turned by
Augustine into a founding myth. Or as one commentator puts it, Augustine ‘rescued
Adam and Eve from obscurity, devised the doctrine of original sin—and the rest
is sexual history’ (Greenblatt 2017). Before the fall, ‘though they [human beings]
carried about an animal body, they yet felt in it no disobedience moving against
themselves’ (Augustine 2015, 202). Now, the individual is ‘disobedient to himself’
(Augustine 1958, 313). Because of Adam and Eve’s original rebellion, every indi-
vidual is now plagued by rebellious appetites and passions. Now, says Augustine in
City of God, the individual is ‘disobedient to himself’ (Augustine 1958, 313). Their
will has been corrupted, they lack the capacity to choose the good, and are incapable
of obeying God’s laws without otherworldly assistance, in the form of the grace of
God. Virtue is only possible now as a gift from God. There may be saintly humans,
but they are only good by virtue of God’s grace, something that can be given but
cannot be earned. In the end, only a few will be saved; most will continue to sin and
end up in hell. In this manner, Augustine introduces the abiding religious notion of
72 Sin and Self-Denial
human beings as fundamentally corrupted by their physical appetites, constitution-
ally given over to the sin and evil that are associated especially with the pleasures
of the flesh. Much of this thinking was reaffirmed by the Protestant reformers in the
sixteenth century, of which we will see more later.
There are recognisable features of this Augustinian account in Fleming’s
Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde. This film has already been discussed as a representation
of Plato’s picture of human nature as a battle between reason and desire. Over and
above this, it also has distinct religious overtones, and indeed, features that are
characteristic of the Augustinian appropriation of Plato’s picture of human nature.
Human beings are presented as striving to be good, where this is identified with
Christian virtuousness as well as Victorian propriety; and there is also an evil side
in all of us, identified particularly with physical appetites, which are nonetheless
strangely attractive and constantly threaten to undermine our efforts to be good.
Spencer Tracy’s Dr Jekyll discusses his picture of human nature over the dinner
table in explicitly religious terms, insisting that ‘we all have an evil side … why,
as Christians we admit that man is created weak’. He envisages the soul as a bat-
tleground in which good and evil, chained together, fight for supremacy. This is
not to discount the modern sensibility that also runs through the film. The bishop
invokes the need for God’s grace to overcome our physical appetites, suggest-
ing that there is a ‘higher source’ from which human beings can find aid in their
struggle against evil. Dr Jekyll, more up to date, insists that human beings will be
assisted in choosing the good not by otherworldly grace but by this-worldly medi-
cal science. Science will free human beings from their evil side so that the good
can develop unhindered.
As indicated in the earlier discussion, the Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde films are
also modern to the extent that there is a readiness to see desire as having a legiti-
mate role in the human makeup and its excessive suppression as damaging. This
is evident in Mamoulian’s pre-Code version of the Jekyll and Hyde story. Fredric
March’s Jekyll clearly wants to marry his fiancé as soon as possible but is being
made to wait by her father. Frustrated, he is attracted to a prostitute, who flirts with
him in a remarkably erotic scene. He is still capable of expressing Victorian senti-
ments, saying of his impending marriage that he wants to be ‘clean, not only in my
conduct but in my innermost thoughts and desires’. Nonetheless, on first becom-
ing Hyde he rages against the constraints of propriety: ‘You hypocrites, deniers of
life. If you could see me now … what would you think?’ It might be thought that
the Fleming version is going to be more conservative, appearing as it does after
the enforcement of the Hays Code. Certainly, there is the overt religious content
and the object of Jekyll’s forbidden desire is now a barmaid. But it is clear that
Tracy’s Jekyll is also being frustrated by a repressive society, his fiancé’s strait-
laced father insisting in delaying his marriage and looking on disapprovingly at his
public displays of affection. The film also rather subversively co-opts both Platonic
and religious symbolism to depict unleashed desire. As Jekyll turns into Hyde for
the first time, there are the revealing hallucinatory images. As noted earlier, Plato’s
horseman and horses image of human nature appears as a coachman whipping
horses that turn into his fiancé and the barmaid, the image becoming a metaphor
Sin and Self-Denial 73
for Jekyll’s desires for sexual domination. There are also images of a whirlpool and
mud, images that Augustine uses in his Confessions to describe the sexual impulses
that dominated what to him was his debauched youth (see Augustine 1961, 41, 55).
Here we can also return to our discussion of The Addiction. The vampire, as
another monstrous embodiment of unconstrained desire, is given a thoroughly
Augustinian interpretation in this film. The scene described at the start of the
chapter is the culmination of a story that begins with Kathleen, an idealistic phi-
losophy student appalled by a world that could allow evils such as the Holocaust
and war crimes, being turned into a vampire and becoming everything she hates.
As a vampire, she cannot help committing evil acts and the film suggests that in
this she is really no different to the rest of humanity. All human beings have an
innate predisposition towards evil. We have seen the vampire as a representa-
tion of the Platonic conception of evil, in terms of being dominated by one’s
desires and appetites. Now, resurrected in a more religious register, the vampire
has become a metaphor for the evil at the very heart of a corrupt human nature. It
is a fateful addiction to evil that can only be overcome in the end through the sav-
ing grace of a Christian God. This gloomy Augustinian view of human nature is
summed up by the vampire Casanova who originally bit Kathleen, as she lectures
her in the hospital room: ‘we’re not evil because of the evil we do, but we do evil
because we are evil … What choices do such people have? It’s not like we have
any options’. It is the priest, the next visitor, who provides Kathleen with her only
way of escape. The focus of the film, then, is very much on human nature as fun-
damentally corrupted by the physical appetites, inherently given over to sin and
evil, and too weak to resist without divine assistance.
There is no sense here of physical desire being a legitimate part of our makeup.
In line with the Augustinian account, it remains something that we need to over-
come. For the early Church in general, desire is viewed with deep hostility, a sign
of corruption, an evil we must struggle against; or at the very least, a distraction
from higher spiritual concerns, keeping us tied to this world. Any moral improve-
ment that might be possible in this world involves denying or suppressing one’s
desires. Consequently, in early Church writings and practices, there is a strong
emphasis on asceticism, the extreme renunciation of worldly desires. Amongst
the more spectacular expressions of this was the ascetic saint Simeon Stylites,
who in the fifth century spent 37 years living on a platform atop a pillar in the
Syrian desert. We will have occasion to revisit the Christian ascetic atop his pillar
in the next chapter, with the help of Luis Bunuel’s Simon of the Desert (1965),
whose central character is loosely based on this historical figure. The film, while
not being unsympathetic to its central character, finds his exorbitant self-denial
irresistibly comic. Even if this extreme behaviour represents something of a high
point in the history of Christian asceticism, in the broader history of Christian
thought, goodness and virtue have always seemed to require a generous dose of
self-denial and privation. And here lies a problem. Particularly from a modern
point of view, this self-denial, like the authoritarian suppression of desire in Plato
that it echoes, is liable to come across as repressive and unhealthy, bordering
on self-mutilation.
74 Sin and Self-Denial
Nonetheless, the attitude persists, extending even to the modern Antipodes.
For the priests and brothers running the fifties Catholic boys’ boarding school
in The Devil’s Playground (Fred Schepisi, 1976), any unseemly desires in their
charges have to be identified and stamped out wherever possible. The most fanati-
cal amongst them, Brother Francine (Arthur Dignam), tells the boys, ‘your body
is your worst enemy … you must be on guard against your senses at all times’.
Naturally, he is also the one most tormented by the desires he is trying to forbid
in others, reduced to anguish in the mundane circumstances of a visit to the public
swimming pool and tormented at night by lurid dreams. Others on the teaching
staff talk more matter-of-factly about the strange requirements of their profession
and its probably futile efforts to stamp out what is surely a natural part of the
human makeup. Nonetheless, the institution is dedicated to teaching its charges
to suppress their desires. The hero, 13-year old Tom (Simon Burke) spends long
hours praying for guidance, terrified and ashamed by his ‘impure’ thoughts. In
the end, he runs away from the school, escaping not from his desires but from the
tyranny of the institution that demonises them.
This is not to discount the religious film that celebrates the satisfaction of
desires. In Babette’s Feast (Gabriel Axel, 1987), two sisters, Martine (Birgitte
Federspiel) and Philippa (Bodil Kjer), live in a small village in nineteenth-century
Denmark. They are members of a strict, puritanical Protestant sect founded by
their father and have lived lives marked by deep self-denial and sacrifice for
others. Now elderly, their father dead, they take in a Parisian refugee, Babette
(Sté phane Audran), to work as a housekeeper. When Babette wins the lottery, she
decides to spend it on a sumptuous banquet for the sisters and the other towns-
people. These people are initially scandalised by the prospect of this ‘satanic
Sabbath’, which represents to them the evil of indulgence. However, as the meal
itself proceeds, they cannot help taking enjoyment from it, and in the process
loosen up and become more human, able to express love and mercy. The film
might be seen as a critique of religious self-denial, which has clearly cost the sis-
ters a great deal and a reminder of the pleasures of this life. However, it could also
be read in religious terms as a film in which the episode of earthly satisfaction, the
feast, is invested with value as symbolising the ‘heavenly banquet’, a premonition
of the other-worldly fulfilment that will be a reward for the self-denial in this one
(see Wright 1997). Still, precisely by being reduced to a symbol of other-worldly
satisfaction, the feast is no antidote to religious self-denial in this world, no cure
for the Augustinian hostility towards physical desires.
A further issue from the modern point of view is the Augustinian representation
of human beings as not only corrupted by their physical desires, but also as having
limited prospects of overcoming this corruption. It seems that on this view moral
improvement is simply not possible by human means. It is only with divine assis-
tance that any improvement is going to be possible, and even then, only after death.
In The Addiction, the only people in the film who are able to resist the vampires
are the priest and a man handing out religious pamphlets. They have presumably
been lucky enough to be fortified by God’s grace. For those who have not been
so strengthened there is no hope of escaping evil and corruption. The vampires
Sin and Self-Denial 75
are representative of the rest of us, addicted by nature to evil, powerless to fight
against it. For the modern sensibility, this extreme pessimism about the prospects of
improvement is one of the most problematic features of the Augustinian view. The
idea that human beings are intrinsically depraved and corrupt seems to condemn
them to evil, leaving little hope of progress in this world or the next. Indeed, being
good seems so far out of reach of human beings as to make any aspiration to moral
goodness meaningless. If as the vampire Casanova says, we ‘do evil because we are
evil’, if we have no choice in the matter and if we are only made moral by God’s
grace, which may be given but not earned, we might wonder whether there is any
point in talking about morality at all (see Malik 2014, 71).
Finally, we have to return to the problem noted earlier, that evil might arise
not from being under the sway of one’s lower desires and instincts, but from the
virtuous, self-controlled individual who takes themselves to be acting in order to
please God. As with Plato’s account, rigorous self-control and the denial of desire
is perfectly compatible with evil behaviour. Self-control allows one to pursue
one’s tasks with especial single-mindedness, bringing about the suppression of
any feelings of compassion or sympathy that might otherwise moderate one’s
actions. This is another concern highlighted by early modern critics of religion
like Michel de Montaigne, the sixteenth-century philosopher-essayist. He fills his
essays with examples of people acting cruelly, not because of an excessive pursuit
of physical pleasures, but because they think they have a higher mandate for what
they do. In his essay ‘On Moderation’, he mentions the notion ‘which was uni-
versally embraced by all religions … which leads us to think that we can please
Heaven and Nature by our murders and our massacres’ (Montaigne 2003, 226).
Two hundred years later, Voltaire’s comments on the dangers of fanaticism in the
Philosophical Dictionary will express similar concerns.
The potential for murderous behaviour in this way of thinking is dramatised
in Darren Aronofsky’s Noah (2014). The film, essentially a revival of the old
Hollywood biblical epic, reimagines the biblical story of the flood, but it does so
in a grimly realistic way. It does not hold back from showing the flood itself as
an act of spectacular brutality, a genocidal act that does away indiscriminately
with innocent and guilty, young and old alike. More to the point, Noah (Russell
Crowe) himself comes across as a religious fanatic, inexpressive and driven, con-
vinced that the human race is inherently wicked and ought to die out. This attitude
extends to his own family; he does not want them to produce any offspring. In
keeping with this, when his adopted daughter Ila (Emma Watson) produces two
children he resolves to murder them, despite his family’s protests. He only refrains
from doing so at the last moment, and this is the point where he ceases to be a
vehicle of blind religious certainty and feeling and humanity reassert themselves.
There is a further suggestion here that religion might be not only unneces-
sary for but in some cases positively inimical to moral behaviour and that human
beings might have a better chance of behaving decently without it. In having Noah
contemplate killing his granddaughters, the film is not being particularly faithful
to the biblical story. Indeed, it is incorporating a version of the Abraham story
into the story of Noah. But the Abraham story can itself be seen as a testament to
76 Sin and Self-Denial
fanaticism and the willingness to murder even those closest to you in the name of
religious belief. In Abraham’s case, there is no saving intervention of feeling or
humanity. The protagonist would have gone through with the murder had he not
been stopped, and he is only stopped by divine intervention, the same intervention
that set the events in motion in the first place. Once again, it seems that with God
anything is permitted. In the extremity of his behaviour, Abraham will continue to
be of interest to later commentators on the human condition such as Kierkegaard
and Sartre, as we will see in Chapter Five.
Figure 2.2 The rabbi and the eye doctor in Crimes and Misdemeanors (Woody Allen,
1989. Credit: Orion/Photofest).
78 Sin and Self-Denial
were no such moral order, the rabbi insists, the world would be a bleak, empty,
meaningless place. At the same time, the eye doctor, as a self-described man of
science, cannot believe in such an order. Here is an impending problem for the
natural law account. It is radically at odds with the modern scientific conception
of nature, understood as a realm of mechanically interacting particles, empty of
value and purpose. And this is seemingly confirmed when Judah escapes punish-
ment for his crime.
Whether the recognition that there is no moral order to violate, that the uni-
verse is indifferent and meaningless helps Judah to come to terms with his crime
or in fact represents the real punishment for what he has done, is another question
(see Pappas 2004). Filmmaker Cliff suggests the latter when he meets the eye doc-
tor at the wedding that closes the film. As he remarks in response to Judah’s ‘great
story for a movie’, if the murderer succeeds in getting away with murder, then
surely ‘his worst beliefs are realized’. His punishment might be the very fact that
he is not punished. Perhaps acknowledging this, Judah certainly replies by saying
‘Well, I said it was a chilling story, didn’t I?’ Nonetheless, he does not in the end
seem overly concerned, getting up soon after to rejoin his wife and family, happy
enough to be able to return to his privileged life.
By the time we get to Allen’s Match Point, any idea of larger moral order has
disappeared in favour of the scientific view of nature as meaningless and indif-
ferent to human existence, which is actively opposed to a religious view from the
start. As the protagonist Chris remarks early on in the discussion over dinner, ‘it
seems scientists are confirming more and more that all existence is here by blind
chance. No purpose, no design … faith is the path of least resistance’. There is
constant reference to the role of chance and lack of design in the universe. By
implication, we can no longer speak of any God-given moral order in the uni-
verse. This, it would seem, leaves the behaviour of the participants to be dictated
entirely by their greed, lust and self-interest. From the point of view of his self-
interest, Chris is able to regard Nola’s murder as ‘necessary’. Yet even here there
are echoes of the lost moral order. After the murder, Chris muses that ‘it would
be fitting if I were apprehended and punished. At least there would be some small
sign of justice, some small measure of hope for the possibility of meaning’. But
no such punishment eventuates. There is evidently a large gap between the idea
of nature as morally structured and the scientific view. Aquinas may present us
with a naturalistic notion of morality, but the conception of nature involved is
quite unlike the modern scientific understanding. It is the Christianised version of
Aristotle’s notion of nature as imbued with value and purpose.
Let’s look more closely at Aquinas’s notion of a God-given moral order
inherent in nature. Aquinas thinks that we can look to our own nature for moral
guidance. Human beings have inbuilt purposes, fundamental tendencies or incli-
nations that they can rationally comprehend and articulate in the form of explicit
rules of conduct. This is the natural law that tells them how they ought to act. This
is not however to say that we should simply surrender ourselves to our desires
and feelings. Our inclinations, Aquinas thinks, remain subject to the corruption of
our sinful nature. Here he adopts Augustine’s doctrine of original sin to explain
Sin and Self-Denial 79
why human beings do not automatically follow the laws of their nature, though
without going quite as far as Augustine in regarding humans as completely cor-
rupted. Rather, we have to be critical about the inclinations we pursue. We first
have to recognise the ‘natural purpose’ of the inclination, through our reason, and
only act on it to the extent that that purpose is respected. Inclinations belong to
the natural law only insofar as they are ‘ruled by reason’, seeking what reason
determines to be their proper purpose, the one appropriate to our nature. Thus,
what Aquinas calls the sense appetites, ‘concupiscible’ appetites like love and the
desire for pleasure, and ‘irascible’ appetites like fear and the desire to shun pain,
are a legitimate part of our make-up, but they have to be pursued appropriately.
The good person is the one whose desires have been trained by reason to seek
their appropriate objects, with virtue being the settled disposition to so behave.
Habitually appropriate concupiscible appetite is the virtue of temperance, habitu-
ally appropriate irascible appetite is the virtue of courage, and so on.
Being virtuous thus amounts to conforming to the rule of reason, which directs
human beings to behave in accordance with their proper, God-given nature and
purposes. Aquinas’s account of virtue clearly builds on Aristotle’s picture. And
like Aristotle, Aquinas thinks that through virtuous behaviour we will attain our
ultimate goal or end. Where Aristotle identifies this supreme good with eudai-
monia, happiness, the good life here on earth, Aquinas like Augustine calls it
beatitude or blessedness, and for him perfect happiness, the ultimate end, is to be
found in possessing God, the most perfect being, the supreme and infinite good.
For Aquinas, knowing is a form of possessing, and so to possess God is to know
God, to have the intellectual and direct knowledge of God that we will attain in
the afterlife. In doing so, we will realise ourselves in the fullest way, and attain
beatitude. As Aquinas puts it in Summa Contra Gentiles, ‘man’s ultimate felicity
consists only in the contemplation of God’ (Aquinas 1956, 125).
Thus, for Aquinas, as for Augustine, the ultimate human goal, happiness,
consists in union with God; and the virtuous life is the means to this end. Like
Augustine, he does not think we can attain perfect happiness in this lifetime.
However, unlike his predecessor, Aquinas does think we can make some moral
progress in this world. We can achieve an imperfect happiness through the exer-
cise of the ‘cardinal virtues’, prudence, justice, courage and temperance, through
which we order our desires and appetites. But it remains the case that true hap-
piness will have to wait for the next world. And to get there we will also need to
have the ‘theological virtues’ of faith, hope and charity, which orient our activities
towards uniting with God in the next world. These virtues are not acquired by
education or practice, but only as a gift from God. Thus, even in Aquinas there
remains a role for God’s grace.
Before proceeding further, there are a couple of issues worth noting. First of
all, we might wonder if the moral ideal being presented by Aquinas is in fact an
inhuman one, one that is beyond the capacity of human beings to attain. Aquinas
holds that while we may make some moral progress and attain a degree of hap-
piness in this life, one can only achieve complete happiness and fulfilment in the
afterlife. And it might be thought that this is not a human conception of happiness,
80 Sin and Self-Denial
because it is not a happiness that one can attain as a human being. One has to
die, to cease being human, in order to attain it. This is the paradox that Kathleen
discovers at the end of The Addiction, that moral progress is only possible at
the cost of ‘annihilation of the self’. Secondly, and this is not unrelated, there
is some conflict in Aquinas’s account between the Christian doctrine of a non-
bodily soul able to survive death that he espouses and the Aristotelian picture that
he wants to build on. Aquinas accepts Aristotle’s idea of the soul as the form of
the body, organising the matter of the body and making it possible for the body
to exercise various capacities. But if so, how can mind and body come apart in the
way required in order to be able to talk of a soul capable of persisting after the
decay of the body? Aquinas says that the highest activities of the human soul,
the intellectual operations, are intrinsically independent of the body and can sur-
vive death, but it is hard to reconcile this view with the Aristotelian doctrine that
he appropriates.
These issues notwithstanding, the preceding picture provides the background
for Aquinas’s natural law view of morality. It is worth noting that natural law
for Aquinas is the basis not only of ethics but politics. With Aristotle, Aquinas
sees human beings as essentially social animals; human beings have a natural
inclination to live in society, and the fully human life to be part of a community.
Moreover, for Aquinas, natural law dictates that the best political regime is the
monarchy, the monarch’s rule of society mirroring the manner in which the uni-
verse is ruled by God. But staying with ethics for the time being, on the basis of
natural law, some ways of acting can be said to be morally right because they
are natural, in keeping with our nature, while others are wrong because they are
unnatural. But even though the basis for morality is now to be found in our own
nature and inclinations, there remains plenty of opportunity for the religious con-
demnation of desire, to the extent that the desires are understood to be directed
towards inappropriate objects. To follow those desires is to act contrary to our
nature. In this manner, for example, the natural law account has been used to sup-
port the longstanding religious tradition of condemning as immoral any sexual
activity not undertaken for the purpose of reproduction. It can be argued from the
natural law perspective that the proper, God-given purpose of sex is procreation.
Human beings have been given sexuality in order to reproduce, so anything that
frustrates the proper purpose of sexuality is unnatural and wrong, including con-
traception and homosexuality. Aquinas himself condemns ‘that two men should
seek sexual union, which especially is called a vice against nature’ for this reason
(Aquinas 1998, 647).
Naturally, this raises a number of questions. Natural law is not based on
nature as observed so much as nature as interpreted by reason, a human nature or
essence designed by God. Appealing to the fact that people happen to have certain
desires is not sufficient to deem them natural to human beings, in this sense. That
requires interpreting the desires that we have. We then have the problem of how
to determine which desires are proper to our nature. To put this a different way,
as Richard Norman notes, human beings in practice have all sorts of desires and
inclinations and are capable of pursuing all sorts of purposes. It is not clear how
Sin and Self-Denial 81
we can identify, out of all the possible purposes we can pursue, the ones that are
proper or natural to us. To take the case of sexuality, human beings can employ
their sexuality for many purposes, including sheer enjoyment. Why shouldn’t
that, rather than reproduction, be the natural purpose of sexuality? (see Norman
1998, 33). All of which is to say, the problem that moralities based on God’s will
have, that of determining what God’s will actually is, persists even if that will is
understood to express itself in the way our nature is designed.
It also seems that Aquinas is vulnerable to the kind of criticism that can be
applied to Aristotle when the latter says that some human beings, such as women
and ‘natural slaves’, are fitted by nature to obey those who are by nature masters.
Aquinas himself rejected the idea that slavery is justified by natural law, since
all men are equal by nature (Aquinas 1998, 651). There were no natural slaves,
though he also thought that slavery could be legitimate as a matter of human law.
However, he does argue in Part 1, Question 92, that women are naturally subject
to men, because in men, ‘reason predominates’. The general concern remains that
in making these claims about what is justified by nature, how do we know that
we aren’t in fact smuggling in a value judgement about how people ought to act,
a particular cultural view about the activities that people should engage in or the
roles they should play? Talk of certain roles being natural can be used to give
a specious justification for what are in fact historically emergent arrangements,
such as the place of women or the institution of slavery – although in fairness, the
argument can also run the other way. That is, one can also invoke natural law in
order to criticise particular social roles and practices. Both sides of the equation
are evident in Steven Spielberg’s Lincoln (2012), which features scenes in the
American Congress where different factions, battling over the question of slavery,
invoke natural law both in support of slavery and against it. In this context, anti-
slavery Republican Thaddeus Stevens (Tommy Lee Jones) gets one of the best
lines. To an opponent who suggests that ending slavery ‘affronts natural law’ and
is ‘insulting to God’, he responds with: ‘What violates natural law? Slavery, and
you, Pendleton, you insult God. You unnatural noise’.
Nonetheless, claims that certain roles or practices are proper to people, or par-
ticular groups of people, because they are natural, have to recognise that ‘natural’
is a morally loaded term here, not a matter of straightforwardly observable fact.
This is not to say that our nature has no bearing on notions of how we ought to
act. Even if we consider our nature in relatively neutral terms, as the biological
makeup and capacities distinctive of our species, this surely sets some limits to
what we can aspire to morally. If ethics concerns how we should live, it can-
not ignore the limits of what we as human beings are in fact capable of doing.
A complete disconnection between the two is played for comic effect in The Life
of Brian (Terry Jones, 1979). In comedy troupe Monty Python’s religious satire,
Brian (Graham Chapman), born just down the road from Jesus, joins a revolution-
ary group, the ‘People’s Front of Judea’, who are opposed to the Roman occupa-
tion. His fellow revolutionary Stan (Eric Idle) demands that the other members
recognise his right to have babies, a moral aspiration that as Reg (John Cleese),
the group’s commander points out, is somewhat undermined by his inability as
82 Sin and Self-Denial
a biological male to reproduce. A moral claim is meaningless if it is entirely
incompatible with one’s physical makeup and capacities. But even if we take into
account a requirement that moral aspirations have to be compatible with what
we are capable of doing, this does not get us very far in determining what those
aspirations should be. As already noted, the capacities we have can be exercised
in many different ways, so it is difficult to see them as providing any guidance as
to the right way to behave.
The idea that there are deep-seated desires or inclinations in people’s makeup,
natural tendencies towards ‘the good’, appears in Neil Jordan’s The Crying Game
(1992). At the end of the film, ex-IRA terrorist Fergus (Stephen Rea), explains
why he has nobly taken the rap for his lover Dil (Jaye Davidson) and gone to
jail. He tells the story of the scorpion who asks a frog to carry it across the river,
pointing out that if it were to sting the frog, they would both drown. Halfway
across, the scorpion does sting the frog, and to the frog’s protests, says ‘I can’t
help it, it’s in my nature’. One reading of this story is as a suggestion that behind
Fergus’s noble act of self-sacrifice there is a fundamental tendency or inclina-
tion towards the good in his nature. It outweighs even his own self-interest. This
reading is reinforced by Fergus’s behaviour earlier in the film, while he is still a
member of the IRA, the militant group fighting at the time against British rule in
Ireland. Despite strict IRA rules about dealing with captives, Fergus befriends
the kidnapped British soldier Jody (Forrest Whitaker) that he is supposed to be
guarding. And he is unable to shoot his prisoner when he tries to escape, as Jody
realises: ‘I know you won’t shoot me because you can’t help it. It’s part of your
nature to be a good person’. Indeed, his escaping prisoner is killed not by Fergus
but, perversely, by a British army truck out searching for him.
But though one might hope to see, in such fundamental tendencies and incli-
nations, a natural basis for moral behaviour, things are not so straightforward.
Even if there are fundamental tendencies in people’s behaviour, these are likely
to be more diverse than the religious moralist would want to allow. When a guilt-
stricken Fergus comes to London to find Dil, Jody’s girlfriend, and becomes
attracted to her, he gets a surprise when she turns out to be transgender. It would
seem that it is Dil’s deep-seated inclination to be a woman despite being born
biologically male. Moreover, Fergus finds that he is strongly inclined to continue
to pursue a relationship with Dil, despite some initial misgivings. As we’ve seen,
he eventually goes so far as to take the rap for her and go to prison because, as he
explains, like the scorpion, it is his nature to do so. But it is not clear that the par-
ticular inclinations being exhibited by Dil, and by Fergus in relation to Dil when
he gets over his shock, would be seen as by Aquinas as pointing in the direction
of moral behaviour. They would more likely be viewed as unnatural inclinations.
This indicates not only that fundamental inclinations are diverse, but also, once
again, that there is an element of interpretation involved in talk of desires and
inclinations being natural and unnatural.
Indeed, it is arguably a feature of the developed moral agent that they are not
simply moved by desires, but reflectively interpret or evaluate their desires and
impulses in the light of various norms or ideals of behaviour. These norms may
Sin and Self-Denial 83
in turn have been internalised from one’s culture in the process of growing up. As
such, it might be quite literally the case that in speaking of certain desires as being
reflective of our God-given nature, we are in fact presenting what are in fact par-
ticular cultural views about the activities that people should engage in or the roles
they should play. At the same time, as the characters in The Crying Game indi-
cate, individuals are far from being the mere products of ‘cultural programming’.
They can readily come to explore directions that are at odds with prevailing social
norms and which may not meet with mainstream social approval. And if nothing
else, this speaks to the plasticity of human nature, the degree to which a relatively
complex creature is able to take a wide variety of forms. On this understanding,
the story of the scorpion that Fergus tells at the end of the film is in fact ironic.
We do not have a relatively fixed nature that determines what we do or narrowly
limits what we might strive for. Fergus himself demonstrates this in his continu-
ing attachment to Dil, pursuing a direction that is at odds with his earlier sexual
orientation; as indeed does Dil, who is reinventing herself as a woman.
A further issue for Aquinas’s natural law account is, as already noted, that
the particular conception of nature that it depends on comes into question in the
modern era, with the rise of the scientific worldview. This is the scientific world
of Crimes and Misdemeanors and Match Point, which seems to exclude not only
God but also the idea that things in the world are designed by God with inbuilt pur-
poses. The natural law account comes under direct attack by the twentieth-century
existentialist Jean-Paul Sartre in his ‘Existentialism is a Humanism’ (Sartre
1975), where he argues that human beings could only be thought of as existing
for a purpose if they were the product of some divine artisan, in the same way that
an object of manufacture can be said to have a purpose since it has been made by
an artisan with a definite purpose in mind. If there is no God, human beings have
no such God-given nature or purpose. Sartre’s own view is that this amounts to
a liberation for human beings. He mentions the Dostoevskian idea that if there is
no God, everything is permitted, but he does not think that this means there is no
longer any morality, value or purpose. Rather, it means that human beings are free
to choose themselves and responsible for whatever morality they subscribe to and
purposes they pursue. From this perspective, what Dil and Fergus demonstrate
is the human being’s lack of any pre-given nature or essence. Rather than being
defined through biological maleness or heterosexual orientation, they are free to
determine themselves as they see fit. On that reading, the scorpion story turns out
to be a form of bad faith or self-deception on Fergus’s part, a way of denying his
freedom to himself, pretending that he cannot help doing what he does. But this
is to get ahead of ourselves. We will return to Sartre’s account in Chapter Five.
For all its potential criticisms, Aquinas’s natural law approach remains
dominant within Catholic moral thinking. Within Christianity, however, it was
opposed by the Protestant reformers of the sixteenth century, who instigated the
Reformation in protest to what they saw as the errors and decadence of the Catholic
church. Amongst other things, Protestantism returned to Augustine’s concep-
tion of the world as utterly fallen, of human beings as fundamentally corrupted
and completely dependent on God for the attainment of goodness. And against
84 Sin and Self-Denial
Aquinas’s rationalism, his belief that rational insight into our own nature can
provide the basis for Christianity’s moral prescriptions ‘the protestant reformers
followed Augustine in subordinating reason to will. Man in his inmost essence is
will, and can either rebel against the divine law, or humbly and obediently submit’
(Burtt 1951, 153). It is this gloomy Augustinian view, revived by Protestantism,
and exported to the new world, that finds expression in the nineties New York of
The Addiction, with its view of human beings as inherently sinful, addicted to evil
and weak. It is in this spirit that Casanova tells Kathleen, ‘We sin because we are
sinners. We do evil because we are evil. What choices do such people have? We
have no options’. In the end, the only chance Kathleen has of being able to reject
evil is with God’s help.
Plot
The film has two plot lines. Judah Rosenthal (Martin Landau) is a suc-
cessful ophthalmologist, a family man and pillar of the community, but he
has a secret. He is trying to end an affair that he has been having with
Dolores (Jessica Huston) for several years, but she is threatening to tell
his wife about the affair if he doesn’t keep seeing her. How he deals with
this, by arranging to have her killed via his brother Jack (Jerry Orbach),
is one subplot.
Cliff Stern (Woody Allen) is the film’s other protagonist. He is a pre-
tentious filmmaker who has been trying to make a documentary about
philosopher Lewis Levy (Martin Bergmann). Out of financial despera-
tion (and prompted by his wife), he agrees to make a film portrait of his
annoying brother-in-law Lester (Alan Alda), a successful TV producer
who represents everything Cliff despises. While working on this docu-
mentary, he falls for the film’s producer Halley Reed (Mia Farrow). Cliff’s
troubles at work, and his attempted affair with Halley, form the second
plot line.
The two plot lines finally come together during the wedding scene
at the end of the film, when Judah and Cliff meet. The character linking
them together is the rabbi Ben (Sam Waterston) who is Cliff’s brother-in-
law and Judah’s patient. They meet at the wedding reception for Ben’s
daughter and have a conversation on the couch.
Key Scenes
1 As Judah thinks about having his mistress killed, he has an imagi-
nary conversation with his patient, the rabbi, Ben. Ben: ‘I couldn’t
go on if I didn’t feel with all my heart that there’s a moral struc-
ture – with real meaning – with forgiveness and some kind of
higher power. Otherwise, there’s no basis to know how to live’.
Sin and Self-Denial 91
As he adds: ‘without the law, it’s all darkness’. Here the film invokes
a religious perspective on morality, close to the natural law idea
[38.26–41.53].
2 At the scene of the crime, Judah recalls his father Sol (David
S. Howard), who represents another religious perspective on ethics,
and why one should be moral, even if one can get away with murder.
On this view, God is watching all the time, judging. I act right when I do
what God wants me to do, and wrongly when I fail to do it. And God will
reward those who do good and punish those who do bad. Sol: ‘God
sees everything, and those who are righteous will be rewarded, while
those who are wicked will be punished for eternity’ [55.50–56.26].
3 Anguished over the murder of his mistress, Judah visits the house
he grew up in and remembers a family dinner where religion and
morality were discussed. At the dinner is his father Sol, and Aunt
May (Anna Berger), an atheist who considers all religion supersti-
tious nonsense. Her view is that if you look at the real world without
blinkers, you’ll see that God does not exist, there is no one watching
us and there is no moral structure in the world. Note Sol’s response:
he actually agrees with May that religion may not ultimately depend
on rational belief, but on faith; but he also thinks that having this
faith means that one will have a better life. As he says, if it comes
to a contest between God and truth, ‘I will always choose God over
truth’ [1.07.00–1.10.25].
4 Although Sol calls Aunt May a nihilist, someone who rejects all reli-
gious and moral principles that might give life a moral structure, she
seems rather to be espousing a moral relativism. As she says, ‘might
makes right’; morality is really a reflection of the interests of those
who are in power, and it can change as a result. Hence her response
to the dinner guest who asks ‘what are you saying, May? There’s
no morality in the whole world?’ May: ‘For those who want morality,
there’s morality. Nothing is handed down in stone’ [1.07.00–1.10.25].
5 A central theme in the film is the question – why should one be
moral, why should we abide by moral rules or constraints? The
question is effectively posed by the central character, Judah. He
engineers the murder of his mistress and is not punished; and
though he feels guilty to start with, he gets over his guilt and returns
to his life of comfort and privilege, as if nothing had happened. This
is the story he tells Cliff on the couch at the end of the movie, under
the guise of an idea for a movie plot. Cliff questions whether one
could live with such a crime, and imagines that a better plot would
92 Sin and Self-Denial
The Addiction
The Addiction is a 1995 vampire film directed by Abel Ferrara (The
Funeral, Bad Lieutenant, Pasolini) and written by Nicholas St. John. It
is filmed in gritty black and white. It portrays murder as the expression
of a basic human addiction to evil, which human beings are incapable of
overcoming by themselves. This is both the expression of a gloomy reli-
gious conception of human nature and a rejection of existentialist views
on the matter.
Plot
Kathleen Conklin (Lili Taylor), is an idealistic PhD student appalled by
a world that could allow evils such as the Holocaust and war crimes.
On her way home from an exhibition, she is attacked by the vam-
pire Casanova (Annabella Sciorra). Casanova tells Kathleen to order
her to go away, but she is unable to. Kathleen duly becomes a vam-
pire. She starts to attack others and drink their blood. She seduces
Sin and Self-Denial 93
Key Scenes
1 Kathleen is turned into a vampire, but by not ordering Casanova to
go away when asked to do so, she has also effectively invited it, indi-
cating that the evil is already part of her nature [04.23–07.23]. See
also the scene where Kathleen bites the anthropology student, who
remonstrates with her. Anthropology Student: ‘Look what you’ve
done to me! How could you do this? Doesn’t this affect you at all?’
Kathleen: ‘No. It was your decision … My indifference is not the con-
cern here. It’s your astonishment that needs studying’ [33.53–36.00].
See also the scene where she bites her friend Jean. When Jean asks
why Katherine is doing this, she replies: ‘You know, this obtuseness
is disheartening, especially in a doctoral candidate’ [41.05–44.20].
2 The older vampire Peina claims to be a Nietzschean superman,
living beyond good and evil: ‘You think Nietzsche understood some-
thing? Mankind has striven to exist beyond good and evil, from
94 Sin and Self-Denial
the beginning. And you know what they found? Me’. However, he
seems closer to a practitioner of ascetic self-denial: ‘You know how
long I’ve been fasting? Forty years … You can never get enough,
can you? But you learn to control it. You learn, like the Tibetans, to
survive on a little’. Or again: ‘My habit is controlled by my will – true,
my will initially formed by my addiction, but now strong enough to
control the conditions that dictate the fulfilling of my needs’ [45.39–
51.1]. He may however be deluding himself about his powers of
self-control, since he proceeds to imprison and feed off Kathleen.
3 Kathleen lays out the film’s central thesis: ‘I finally understand what
all this is, how it was all possible. Now I see, good lord, how we
must look from out there. Our addiction is evil. The propensity for
this evil lies in our weakness before it’. Kathleen becomes critical of
existentialist authors like Kierkegaard, who insist on human freedom
and ignore what drives our behaviour, an inherent propensity to evil
that is behind historical atrocities like the Holocaust: ‘Kierkegaard
was right – there is an awful precipice before us. But he was wrong
about the leap – there’s a difference between jumping and being
pushed. You reach a point where you are forced to face your own
needs, and the fact you can’t terminate the situation settles on you
with full force’ [55.30–56.22].
4 At the hospital, Kathleen, having asked for the blinds to be opened,
is now waiting for the sunlight to fall on her. But Casanova enters
the hospital room and abruptly closes the blinds. ‘It’s not that easy’
she says. ‘To find rest takes a real genius’. She proceeds to hold
forth in terms reminiscent of Augustine, quoting from theologian and
writer R.C. Sproul, to the effect that we are evil and weak to the
core: ‘R.C. Sproul said we’re not sinners because we sin, but we sin
because we are sinners. In more accessible terms, we’re not evil
because of the evil we do, but we do evil because we are evil. Yeah.
Now what choices do such people have? It’s not like we have any
options’ [1.09.12–1.12.40]
5 As Kathleen lies alone in the gloom, she has another visitor. A priest
enters and asks how she is. She whispers that she wants to make a
confession and asks for God’s forgiveness. The priest absolves her,
administers a communion wafer and she becomes still, in repose as
we hear her say ‘Amen’ in voiceover. The only way we can overcome
the evil at our core, it seems, is with God’s help [1.13.12–1.15.10].
6 In the film’s final scene, Kathleen, in a cemetery, leaves a flower
on her own grave, then walks off as the camera pans upwards to a
Sin and Self-Denial 95
In the final part of Luis Buñ uel’s comedy Simon of the Desert (1965), we find
ourselves in a crowded sixties New York nightclub, filled with frenzied pleasure-
seekers dancing the latest dance. The camera moves in on a couple sitting at a
table. The man is the film’s hero, Simon (Claudio Brook), modelled on Saint
Simeon Stylites, the early Christian ascetic who spent decades atop a column in
the desert. For most of the film, we have been in the fifth century, with Simon on
his column, as he tries to avoid the world’s temptations and develops ever-more
extreme ways of denying his physical appetites. But now he has been transported
into the modern world by the devil (Silvia Pinal), the woman who is sitting next
to him. Now outfitted as a beatnik, with a neatly-trimmed beard, and smoking a
pipe, he asks her what the name of the dance is. It’s the ‘Radioactive Flesh’, says
the devil. ‘It’s the latest dance, the final dance’. Although Simon understandably
wants to go home to his column, he is informed that he can’t: ‘It’s been re-let.
You’ll have to put up with things here’. Indeed, there is no going back. Simon’s
world doesn’t exist anymore. It is thoroughly foreign, not least because of its
celebration of religiously motivated gestures of extravagant self-denial. The mod-
ern world emerges with a rather different attitude towards appetite and pleasure.
Indeed, pleasure becomes the very cornerstone of the new world’s ethical think-
ing. It is to the emergence of this world, and the new ethics of pleasure that arises
with it, that we now turn.
Utilitarianism
The idea that emerges in both Helvetius and Holbach, that virtuous or morally
right actions are those that contribute to the happiness of the whole, is the basic
principle of utilitarian moral theory. However, it falls to Jeremy Bentham (1748–
1832) to clearly articulate this moral and political perspective. This he does in
An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. For Bentham, as for
Helvetius and Holbach, the starting point is the hedonistic view of human beings
as exclusively driven to seek pleasure and avoid pain. These determine how we
in fact act; but in addition, to use Bentham’s phrase, it is for pleasure and pain ‘to
point out what we ought to do, as well as to determine what we shall do’ (Bentham
2004, 65). The happiness principle is therefore also a standard of right action,
a moral principle that tells us how we ought to act, namely in such a way as to
maximise pleasure and avoid pain. By the same token, for Bentham, all we mean
by calling an act good or right is that it promotes pleasure. When we say that we
ought to do something, we mean that the act in question is useful in bringing about
pleasure or happiness, which is the only thing good in itself, intrinsically valuable,
on the utilitarian view.
At the same time, Bentham extends this principle beyond individual pleasure
and pain. It becomes the idea that the morally good action is the one that maxim-
ises pleasure and minimises pain for all affected by the proposed action. We ought
to act and live in such a way as to promote the greatest happiness for all those
affected by our actions, the greatest happiness principle. Bentham also called this
Pleasure, Happiness and Rights 111
the principle of utility. Utility is the tendency of an action to produce happiness
and the utilitarian principle can be formulated in terms of maximising utility in
this sense. Bentham does not really explain this transition from a concern with
individual happiness to that of the greatest number. He does not, for example,
argue that promoting the happiness of the whole is the best way of ensuring my
own happiness. He clearly believes that in pursuing our own happiness, we should
seek the general happiness of society as well, but he does not say why the latter
follows. And one can readily imagine scenarios where pursuing one’s own hap-
piness not only does not increase that of others, but positively requires that other
people be deprived of theirs. This scenario is explored in the scandalous eight-
eenth-century Laclos novel Liaisons Dangereuse, in which decadent aristocrats
take malicious pleasure in ruining the lives of innocents. This is a key theme in
Dangerous Liaisons (Stephen Frears, 1988), one of a number of cinematic adap-
tations of the novel. The film highlights that pleasure can be pursued not only
without regard for others, but through the active harming of them.
We will return to this film and the idea that a pleasure-seeking being, far from
being concerned with the welfare of others, might just as readily take pleasure
in their suffering. For the moment it can be noted that, although one might want
to speak in such cases of ‘evil’ kinds of pleasure, for Bentham, there is no such
thing. Pleasure cannot be evil. The idea of an evil pleasure only makes sense if
you introduce a non-utilitarian value that is irreducible to pleasure. For Bentham,
pleasure remains the only thing valuable in itself and the only thing that we have
to do morally speaking is to produce on balance the most pleasure. Of course, an
action may have a number of consequences. It may produce both happiness and
unhappiness. But for utilitarianism, an action can be right if it produces some
unhappiness, as long as on balance, overall, it produces the most happiness in
comparison with other actions. So the utilitarian position is that we ought to act
and live in such a way as to promote the greatest happiness for all those affected
by our actions. When faced with a choice between alternative actions, the right
action is the one that has the best overall consequences, produces the greatest
amount or happiness, for everyone concerned.
This principle of right action, the greatest happiness principle, is not only
a principle of morality. The title of Bentham’s book is An Introduction to the
Principles of Morals and Legislation. As with Helvetius and Holbach, Bentham
extended this principle from a moral criterion to a criterion for social policy and
legislation. Legislators too should be concerned with the happiness of the whole.
In the rules, they lay down, and the punishments they impose, they should always
aim at a favourable balance of pleasure over pain. Bentham argued that the best
social policies were those that distributed pleasures as widely as possible, and
reduced pain as much as possible. Utilitarian thinking also provided an impor-
tant justification for the state itself. Bentham rejected Hobbes’s idea that political
authority is created and justified in terms of a social contract, arguing that it is the
state that creates the possibility of binding contracts. For Bentham, the legitimacy
of the state depends on whether a law contributes to the happiness of its citizens.
Government is justified in terms of utility (see Binmore 2000). On this view, the
112 Pleasure, Happiness and Rights
proper role of the state is to promote the greater good, the maintenance of public
order, security and happiness.
Utilitarianism is certainly a very appealing view of morality. In keeping with
the broad outlook of the Enlightenment, it views morality as no less than the
attempt to bring as much pleasure and happiness into the world as possible.
Morality is understood in entirely secular terms, as a human creation that serves
human goals, above all the desire to be happy and to be spared misery and pain.
Equally, this understanding of morality dispenses with religious fictions. Morality
for Bentham is no longer a matter of pleasing God by following divinely ordained
laws and prohibitions It becomes a thoroughly rational business, insofar as reason
is understood in a scientific, calculative sort of way. Utilitarianism promises to
make all moral issues rationally decidable through the empirical calculation of
consequences. We decide what actions to perform by measuring how much hap-
piness various possible actions are likely to produce, determining which produces
the most happiness overall. Bentham also explicitly rejects the Christian idea of
morality as self-denial, which he characterises as the ‘principle of asceticism’,
and which he sees as the exact opposite of the goal embraced by utilitarianism –
it prescribes the minimisation of happiness and disapproves of any increase. He
suggests that it has taken a stronger religious form, in which its adherents make
the active pursuit of pain a duty, and a weaker, philosophical form, in which, for
the sake of reputation, grosser bodily pleasures are rejected and the other pleas-
ures are called something other than pleasure. And he suggests that if this princi-
ple of asceticism were to be applied in legislation, the result would be a ‘hell on
earth’ (Bentham 2004, 74).
For all its appeal, however, Bentham’s utilitarianism is not without its prob-
lems. It might be thought, for example, that it places an impossible burden of cal-
culation on human beings. In every situation, it requires agents to determine all the
possible things they could do, including not acting, and try to calculate what the
total consequences for each action would be. Even if we could manage these cal-
culations, there is the question of whether we can indeed speak straightforwardly
of there being more or less pleasure in these different situations. That is, we may
wonder whether pleasures do indeed only differ in terms of quantity. Thinking so
makes it possible to add and compare different pleasures in the required manner.
But it might be thought that, for example, the cerebral pleasures of poetry and the
raucous pleasures of party games are very different kinds of pleasure. Can such
different pleasures be compared or added to one another? Bentham thought so. He
came up with a ‘felicific calculus’, which was to measure pleasures along a num-
ber of dimensions, including intensity, duration, likelihood of recurrence amongst
others. The intent was to be able to provide a quantitative measure of different
pleasures, sufficient to allow them to figure in utilitarian calculations. Not many
have been convinced by Bentham’s work-around.
There are also issues concerning utilitarianism’s notion of the human being.
For some critics of the time, in saying that human beings have no higher end than
pleasure, that this is the sole ultimate value, utilitarianism seemed to be advocating
that we wallow in bodily gratification. This led them to label it a ‘pig philosophy’.
Pleasure, Happiness and Rights 113
This accusation assumes that human beings are capable only of pleasures that a
pig is capable of, that there is no difference in quality between a human being’s
pleasures and a pig’s. And indeed, in Bentham’s formulation of utilitarianism,
this is the case. He assumes that pleasures only differ in terms of quantity. This is
driven home in his famous phrase, that ‘all things considered, pushpin [a simple
party game] is as good as poetry’. Both give us pleasure. But if the moral thing
to do is to produce the greatest amount of happiness or pleasure in the world, and
if utilitarianism gives us no reason to prefer some types of pleasures over others,
it is consistent with that to spend the day wallowing in crude pleasures, drinking,
eating, playing party games and so on. A dissipated life could even be morally
superior to a life of cultural or artistic activity, if there were more pleasure to be
had from the former.
Bentham’s successor John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) found Bentham’s failure
to distinguish between different kinds of pleasure an embarrassment, opening
utilitarianism up to the ‘pig philosophy’ criticism. In Utilitarianism, he sought
to refine the utilitarian position. He did not want to give up the basic utilitarian
idea that the sole ultimate value is happiness, to be equated with pleasure and the
absence of pain. But he argued that some pleasures were higher or more worthy
than others (Mill 2004, 279). For Mill, pleasures differ from one another in qual-
ity as well as quantity; and the superior pleasures are those that most befit our
nature as human beings, utilising our distinctively human capacities for intelligent
activity. The higher pleasures of the mind and the soul, such as poetry, music,
intellectual enquiry, moral virtue and so on, were to be preferred to the lower,
bodily pleasures of food, drink and sex. And they should count for more in the
calculation of overall happiness than lower ones. A number of films, drawing on
George Bernard Shaw’s 1913 play Pygmalion, pursue the related idea that indi-
vidual self-improvement might be measured by the degree to which one leaves
behind the lower pleasures and acquires a taste for the higher ones. In the story
Eliza Doolittle, a working-class flower seller with basic tastes, is introduced to
the higher pleasures of Professor Higgins and his circle. Higgins, a professor of
phonetics, has wagered that he can turn Eliza into a ‘proper lady’ in a few months.
Films that draw on this story include Pygmalion (Anthony Asquith, Leslie
Howard, 1938) and the musical My Fair Lady (George Cukor, 1964). Educating
Rita (Lewis Gilbert, 1980) has a similar plot.
By introducing the distinction between higher and lower pleasures, Mill com-
mits to a richer conception of human being than Bentham. Mill’s human being
may still be dominated by the desire for pleasure, but some pleasures are higher
than others because they befit our distinctive nature as human beings. Mill is not
simply saying that we ought to cultivate these higher pleasures. He thinks we
will not be entirely happy, truly satisfied, fulfilled, if we do not. This notion of
happiness, as linked to fulfilment, recalls Aristotle’s, but there are some key dif-
ferences. Like Aristotle, Mill’s notion of happiness rests on a philosophical con-
ception of human nature, an ideal of what we can become. But for Aristotle, this is
the human being understood as the sort of being that is fulfilled through virtuous
activity. Virtuous activity may give us pleasure, but this is at best an accidental
114 Pleasure, Happiness and Rights
accompaniment, whereas for Mill happiness lies in higher pleasures themselves.
We are the sort of being that can only be fully satisfied by the higher pleasures
like poetry, music and other elevated cultural pursuits, and never entirely satis-
fied by lower pleasures such as food and drink. And this claim about the relative
importance of higher and lower pleasures is not just a philosophical one. Mill
holds that it will find empirical support. If people are faced with a choice between
the two kinds of pleasures, he thinks, they will prefer the higher over the lower
(cf. Mill 2004, 282).
It might be objected that many people pursue trivial and mindless pleasures
like getting drunk and playing party games and seem completely happy. Isn’t Mill
then ignoring what these people prefer? Mill’s answer is that people need to have
had a real experience of the two alternatives. There are many people whose expe-
rience has been confined to trivial and mindless pleasures, and who continue to
pursue them exclusively. Mill’s claim is that if they could experience some of the
more demanding enjoyments that human beings are capable of, they would come
to find those pleasures more rewarding, and prefer them over the lower. This
indeed is what happens in the Pygmalion story. In the My Fair Lady musical ver-
sion, for example, Eliza is initially only interested in the lower pleasures, warmth
and comfort, as she expresses in the song ‘All I want is a room somewhere’. After
Higgins teaches her to speak correctly and introduces her to the higher pleasures
of elevated society, she runs away, trying to return to her old life. She finds,
however, that she is now a stranger in her former home. Having experienced the
higher pleasures, she can no longer be content with a life where only the lower
ones are possible. This development is repeated in Educating Rita, where Rita
(Julie Walters), the Eliza character, is a working-class hairdresser trying to better
herself by studying at university. Having been exposed to the higher pleasures of
poetry and literature, she finds she now prefers them to the simple pleasures she
once enjoyed, like singing songs down at the pub.
Mill does concede that there are some who, having been able to appreciate
the higher pleasures, relapse into the pursuit of the lower ones. But he thinks
that such cases can be explained in social and psychological terms, as cases of
degeneration (Mill 2004, 281–282). Perhaps this is how we might view the Henry
Higgins character in Educating Rita, Rita’s university lecturer Professor Bryant
(Michael Caine). Bryant is a burnt-out, cynical character teetering on the edge of
alcoholism. Though an expert in literature and poetry, he has lost any passion for
his subject. He thinks that expertise in these things is no guarantee of happiness
and that the less refined pleasures, like getting drunk and having sex, have much
more to recommend them. As a result, he initially tries to discourage Rita from
pursuing her studies. Mill would presumably see him as not competent to judge
between different pleasures, and he certainly comes across as having lost his way.
However, a position that purports to find empirical support, in people’s prefer-
ences for its contention that there are higher, more fulfilling pleasures for human
beings, cannot go too far in this direction. Dismissing anyone who prefers what
Mill would consider a lower pleasure as an incompetent judge threatens to make
any appeal to what people prefer meaningless.
Pleasure, Happiness and Rights 115
Without any reference to people’s own preferences in these matters, the
Pygmalion relationship has the potential to be an oppressive one. This is not so
much because the Higgins character in the classic scenario is typically arrogant,
demanding and heartless. Rather, it is the prospect that all kinds of oppressive
disciplinary impositions upon a person might be justified in the guise of cultivat-
ing an appreciation of supposedly higher tastes and pleasures in them. What saves
the Higgins-Doolittle relationship from being abusive in this way, as opposed to,
say, the Scottie-Madelaine relationship in Vertigo, is that in the Higgins-Doolittle
case, as Noel Carroll puts it, ‘one has the feeling that he is bringing out the best
in her’ (Carroll 2007, 111). That is, Higgins really is working on behalf of Eliza’s
interests, directing her towards the superior pleasures that befit her nature as a
human being, that make use of the distinctively human capacities for intelligent
activity. And what gives support to this view, and reassures the viewer, is that
Eliza herself prefers, seeks out and wants to cultivate these superior pleasures.
She is keen to better herself, to develop as a person in doing so. In Educating
Rita, the matter seems to be beyond doubt. The teacher, Bryant, actively tries to
discourage his student from pursuing this path, but she will not be deterred. And
in the end, her unstoppable enthusiasm ends up reawakening his own interest in
literature and poetry.
A common criticism of Mill’s account is that the conception of higher and
lower pleasures does not reflect human nature so much as the class biases of the
author. What Mill calls the higher pleasures, poetry, music, opera and so on, are
really the pursuits of the upper classes, whereas the carnal and bodily pleasures
are the sorts of things the lower classes delight in. So perhaps this doctrine is
really an intellectual’s justification for the particular preferences, interests and
values of his social class over those of the lower orders. We might ask whether
different social strata can be so straightforwardly identified with the different
kinds of pleasure, but leaving that aside, class certainly plays a key role in all of
the Pygmalion films. The upper-class teacher meets the working-class student,
and a clear marker of the class difference in these films is the preference for higher
or lower pleasures, respectively. The critic who sees Mill’s idea of higher pleas-
ures as an elitist privileging of upper-class pleasures might counter this by arguing
that it is the ‘lower’, working-class pleasures that are in fact superior, being more
authentic, more ‘human’ than the artificial delights of the upper strata. Behind this
judgement, of course, lies a certain conception of human nature, and this counter-
claim might equally be questioned as reflecting class biases of its own.
Here Mill has a certain advantage in that he can appeal to the empirical prefer-
ences of individuals to underpin the distinction between higher and lower pleas-
ures, what he thinks they would actually prefer if they were exposed to both,
independent of any claims about human nature. Of course, it might be argued
that living in a hierarchical social order might influence people’s empirical pref-
erences, so that lower-class individuals might come to have a distorted view of
pleasure, to see the pleasures they gravitate towards as unworthy and those pur-
sued by the upper classes as superior. They might come to be estranged, then,
from the pleasures that are proper to them, or even to human nature as such.
116 Pleasure, Happiness and Rights
However, this sort of claim requires us to appeal once again to a philosophical
idea of human nature, and in addition, to ignore empirical preferences people may
have. What we can say at least is that for Eliza Doolittle in her various manifesta-
tions, there are some pleasures that she comes to see as higher and more worthy,
worth pursuing over other, lower ones. And a big part of what is motivating Rita in
Educating Rita is a desire to escape from a state that she finds stifling and limiting,
and which she wants to go beyond both in terms of individual self-development
and upward social mobility.
No doubt from a strictly utilitarian point of view, Mill’s picture introduces
some difficulties that are not present in Bentham’s picture. In particular, where
Bentham’s view that pleasures are only quantitatively different allows them to
be added together in the manner required for utilitarian calculation, determining
the overall amount of pleasure produced by actions becomes more complicated
if some pleasures are deemed to be qualitatively worth more than others. Also,
where Bentham’s view makes no distinction between the pleasures of the aris-
tocrat and the peasant, all counting equally in the calculation in an appealingly
egalitarian fashion, Mill’s view opens the way to privileging the higher pleasures
of the upper classes and dismissing the lower pleasures of the masses. In the case
of the individual, Mill’s version of hedonism is perhaps in danger of justifying a
new kind of asceticism. In any contest between higher and lower pleasures, the
higher pleasures must take precedence over the lower. If this means that, in the
name of refined but perhaps also rather cerebral and colourless higher pleasures,
the more vigorous, down-to-earth ones are to be set aside or excluded, this is a
potentially debilitating view.
More radically, we might question the idea pursued by both Bentham and Mill
that human beings seek happiness in the form of pleasure. The later nineteenth-
century German philosopher Nietzsche was talking about utilitarianism, and
about Mill especially, when he said that ‘Man does not strive for happiness; only
the Englishman does’ (Nietzsche 1968, 12). We will hear more about Nietzsche
in Chapter Five. What is coming under scrutiny here is the modern, hedonistic
notion of the human being itself, which Enlightenment thought looks to as the
basis for morality, utilitarianism being the most significant manifestation of such
a pleasure-based morality. Nietzsche’s suspicion that pleasure might not in fact
be the only thing of importance to human beings is pursued by Robert Nozick,
a twentieth-century critic of utilitarianism, who posed the ‘experience machine’
thought experiment, a science fiction scenario: would you plug yourself into a
virtual reality machine that promised a lifetime of pleasurable experience, the sat-
isfaction of all desires, albeit only virtually. Arguably most people would refuse,
preferring real experiences even if these are sometimes going to be unpleasant.
This scenario poses a problem for utilitarianism, in that it suggests that people
might value things other than pleasure (Nozick 1974, 42–45).
Recent science fiction films that have portrayed versions of the experience
machine have tended to move in this direction, opting for truth over happiness.
In The Matrix (Wachowski siblings, 1999), the character Cypher (Joe Pantoliano)
wants to return to an illusory happiness within the vast virtual reality of the
Pleasure, Happiness and Rights 117
matrix, in preference to the harshness of life as a rebel battling the machines that
set it up to enslave humanity. But he is the villain of the piece, and by attributing
the choice of happiness over truth to him, the film is indicating its disapproval
of the position. Things are a little more complicated in Inception (Christopher
Nolan, 2010). Here, the hero Dominick Cobb (Leonardo di Caprio) also opts for
happiness over truth. A professional thief hired to perform corporate espionage
by entering people’s dreams to steal information, his latest job comes with the
promise that with success, he will be cleared of a murder charge and be able to
return home to his children. The film concludes with him happily reconciled with
his children. But he also closes his eyes to possible proof that his happy state is
itself a dream. He simply does not want to know, for the sake of a happy ending.
However, he is not the villain of the piece, and the film itself seems ambivalent as
to whether it matters whether the world he ends up in is real or not. Perhaps it is
does not matter, as long as it is a world that is satisfying for him, a world that he
finds it worth living in. In this spirit, the film refrains from resolving the question
of the truth of what is going on, content to leave the ending ambiguous in that
regard. We can say that the film ultimately leaves it up to the audience to decide
whether truth is more important than happiness.
Outside of these science fiction scenarios of virtual reality and global illusion,
a more down-to-earth instance where the question of happiness versus truth arises
can be found in Crimes and Misdemeanors. At the family dinner recalled by the
guilt-ridden protagonist Judah, his father Sol insists that he would rather believe
in God against all evidence to the contrary, as this means he will have a happier
life. As he puts it, if it comes to a contest between God and truth, ‘I will always
choose God over truth’. This puts him at odds with his formidable sister May, for
whom religion is just so much superstition and it is truth that is most important.
In this case, we can be sure that the film is more in agreement with May than with
Sol. It proceeds to its startlingly bleak conclusion, so manifestly at odds with the
standard Hollywood happy ending in which the bad guys have been punished and
the good guys at least come out of it okay. At the same time, if cinema itself can be
considered a kind of experience machine, it is clear that people are happy for their
cinematic virtual reality to contain something more than just pleasurable experi-
ences. This also provides a reminder that the experience that film can offer is not
confined to wish fulfilling fantasies, or visions that comfortingly confirm existing
prejudices and prevailing forms of thought. It can extend to experiences that con-
front the viewer and challenge what they take to be true or right. And that films that
contain such experiences, however unpalatable, are also attractive to the viewer.
Regarding utilitarianism itself, it remains a point of contention with this ethical
theory that the only thing considered valuable in itself is pleasure or happiness. It
might be argued that we value many other things as well, such as freedom, knowl-
edge, truth, honesty or dignity. These non-utilitarian values cannot be incorpo-
rated into utilitarianism as they stand. To make them the things that we seek to
maximise risks losing the distinctive character of utilitarianism. Nonetheless,
utilitarianism has proven to be quite adaptable in amending itself within its frame-
work to meet at least some objections that have been raised against it. Mill’s
118 Pleasure, Happiness and Rights
introduction of higher and lower pleasures is one such modification. Another,
more recent modification is desire or preference utilitarianism. Here happiness is
no longer understood in terms of pleasure, even higher and lower pleasures, the
view now referred to as ‘hedonistic utilitarianism’ (see Singer 2011). It is under-
stood in terms of the satisfaction of desire, in terms of either getting what you
want or getting what is in your interests, where interests are normally explained
in terms of present and probable future desires. So what we’re trying to do here
is not to maximise pleasure but to maximise the satisfaction of people’s desires
or preferences. But similar calculation problems arise with desire utilitarianism
as with hedonistic utilitarianism. How do we determine the value of desires and
weigh them up against one another?
A further set of issues arises concerning utilitarianism in that all kinds of mor-
ally questionable acts appear to be justifiable on utilitarian grounds, given the
right circumstances. For utilitarianism, the only thing that is morally important is
producing the best consequences, in the form of the greatest amount of happiness
for the greatest number. As such, it has no fundamental objection to employing
any means, no matter how shocking, nor with treating particular individuals or
groups unjustly, exploiting them or inflicting pain even to the point of killing, if
that will bring about the greatest overall happiness. This is also a standard kind
of movie logic, familiar from police, crime thriller and action films: as long as
the bad guy gets what they deserve, the means do not really matter. Thus, in Don
Siegel’s Dirty Harry (1971), police inspector Harry Callahan (Clint Eastwood)
resorts to extreme, extrajudicial methods, including torture, to deal with the psy-
chopathic Scorpio (Andy Robinson), who is terrorising the population of San
Francisco. In the film’s most harrowing scene, Callahan tortures Scorpio in a foot-
ball stadium to get him to divulge the whereabouts of the girl he has kidnapped
and buried alive, and who is fast running out of air (Figure 3.1). This torture might
be justifiable in utilitarian terms, as something that is undertaken in the name of
the greater good, but it remains a disturbing tactic, and we may wonder about an
ethical position that is able to countenance such behaviour.
It is worth noting here that Callahan, while he does not exactly do things by
the book, is no mere renegade or vigilante, operating outside the system. He is a
policeman, part of the establishment, an agent of the state. In this capacity also,
his activities can be seen as being justifiable in utilitarian terms, insofar as utili-
tarianism provides a moral justification for the exercise of state power. This is
the idea that the state’s actions are legitimate insofar as they contribute to max-
imising the happiness of its citizens, promoting public order, safety, security and
well-being. From this perspective, in the face of direct threats to public order and
security represented by Scorpio, it is perfectly legitimate for an operative of the
state to employ extreme methods such as torture. But this again raises questions
about utilitarianism, as an ethical position seemingly able to justify any action, no
matter how extreme, by the state in the name of the greater good.
For its part, Dirty Harry has become synonymous in the popular imagination
with the exercise of a brutal kind of utilitarian logic in which the ends justify any
means, no matter how shocking, as long as they contribute to the greater good.
Pleasure, Happiness and Rights 119
Figure 3.1 Dirty Harry: robust policing (Don Siegel, 1971. Credit: Warner Brothers/
Photofest).
During the early twenty-first century War on Terror, the US administration of the
time was seen by some as employing a ‘Dirty Harry ethics’ (Lopez 2016), specifi-
cally a willingness to depart from many standard ethical constraints in its response
to terrorism, on the principle that the end, namely preventing terrorist attacks, justi-
fied any means, including preventive war and torture. Such means-end thinking is
on display in Zero Dark Thirty (Kathryn Bigelow, 2012), which directly addresses
the War on Terror, following the hunt driven by CIA agent Maya (Jessica Chastain)
for the arch-terrorist Osama Bin Laden. The film proved controversial because, by
giving no hint of dispute or dissent, it seems to imply that the ‘enhanced interroga-
tion techniques’ it depicts (waterboarding, sleep deprivation and the like), are per-
fectly justified in the state’s war against terrorism. The only concern raised about
the torture in the film is a purely practical one, one character’s view later in the film
that it is perhaps not possible to be entirely confident about the information derived
by such means. There is no ethical concern over the torture itself, which from a
strictly utilitarian perspective can indeed be seen as perfectly justifiable.
120 Pleasure, Happiness and Rights
A more critical view of such thinking can be found in Curtis Hanson’s 1997
neo-noir LA Confidential, which returns to questions of police tactics. The film
traces the corruption of newly-arrived Los Angeles detective Ed Exley (Guy
Pearce) precisely in terms of his turn towards a utilitarian way of thinking in
which any action is legitimate as long as the bad guys get what they deserve. In
this spirit, Exley comes to accept the behaviour of fellow officer Wendell White
(Russell Crowe), who is in the habit of beating information out of criminals and
shooting offenders he thinks might escape conviction. This is a complete turna-
round for Exley, given that he starts out staunchly refusing the advice given to
him on his first day by Captain Dudley Smith (James Cromwell), that a detective
should be willing to plant corroborative evidence on a suspect, beat a confession
out of a suspect he knows to be guilty or shoot a hardened criminal in the back if
there is a chance they will escape conviction. In the end, Smith turns out to be a
corrupt cop, and having a chance of escaping conviction, ends up being shot in
the back by Exley. By this stage, Exley has become everything that he initially
recoiled from.
In this connection, we can take another look at Dirty Harry. Certainly, a great
deal of the film’s visual pleasure comes from witnessing Callahan’s robust polic-
ing methods, on full show in an early scene where Callahan single-handedly foils
a bank robbery, producing a scene of spectacular devastation. One might as a
result imagine that the film is endorsing his behaviour, and to an extent it is, but
there is also a critical element to the film. Callahan may resort to brutal, extraju-
dicial means to deal with Scorpio and he mocks the authorities when they refer
to the killer’s rights in the face of his rough treatment. Nonetheless, the film does
not simply endorse his methods. It also brings them into question, by drawing
parallels between Callahan and his foe. The pivotal torture scene in the football
stadium almost exactly mirrors an earlier scene in a park, only with the roles
reversed. In the park, it is Scorpio who brutally torments Callahan at the foot of a
large concrete cross. In the stadium it is Scorpio, lying on the grass next to some
cross-shaped line markings, who is being brutalised by Callahan. By mirroring
protagonist and antagonist in this way, the film implies that Callahan’s robust
methods are, as one commentator puts it, bringing him ‘dangerously close to the
very evil he is trying to overcome’ (Wanat 2007, 85). In so doing, the film also
implicitly calls into question a utilitarianism that would see any means as justified
in the service of the greater good.
There is a similar questioning of the protagonist’s methods, and implicitly, of
a utilitarian perspective, in The Dark Knight. The protagonist here is Batman, the
vigilante who, though in cooperation with the police, employs extrajudicial meth-
ods to deal with a criminality they are too weak to take on. The question is whether
in doing so he does not enter into ethically dangerous territory. He is contrasted
with district attorney Harvey Dent (Aaron Eckhart), who at least at the begin-
ning of the film, is making headway in dealing with the city’s organised crime,
while staying within the law and order system to do so. Questions over Batman’s
activities are raised in the film in an early scene when Harvey and assistant DA
Rachel Dawes (Maggie Gyllenhall) run into Batman’s alter ego Bruce Wayne
Pleasure, Happiness and Rights 121
and his date at a restaurant and they dine together. In the course of the meal, the
group discuss the ethics of Batman’s vigilantism. Surprisingly, Dent approves
of it, comparing the situation to that of ancient Rome suspending democracy so
that one man could protect the city. Rachel, however, points to the dangers of this
path, noting that this was how Caesar became emperor. The suspension of moral
and political norms in order to meet a threat might make utilitarian sense, but it
also opens the way to excesses.
Sure enough, as the film proceeds, Batman is shown resorting to extreme
methods, including torture, in order to defeat the Joker. Goaded by the latter’s
outrages, he tortures a captive to get information about the Joker’s whereabouts,
dropping a mob boss from a building in order to break his legs and make him
talk. And after barricading the door of the police interrogation room he beats up
the Joker with surprising violence, in order to find out where Harvey and Rachel,
who have been abducted, are being held (Figure 3.2). Later on, he hijacks the
mobile phone network in order to subject the entire city population to pervasive
You must shake up the entire Luftwaffe. Many mistakes have been made,
so be ruthless. Life never forgives weakness. This so-called humanity is just
priest’s drivel. Compassion is a primal sin, compassion for the weak is a
betrayal of nature … I have always obeyed this law of nature by never per-
mitting myself to feel compassion. I have ruthlessly suppressed domestic
opposition and brutally crushed the resistance of alien races. It is the only
way to deal with it. Apes, for example, trample every outsider to death. What
goes for apes, goes more for human beings.
Plot
The film begins with a list of names, ‘In tribute to the police officers of
San Francisco who gave their lives in the line of duty’, superimposed on
a police badge. This dissolves into the muzzle of a gun. Perched on a
nearby rooftop, Scorpio (Andy Robinson) shoots a young woman swim-
ming in a rooftop pool. Inspector Harry Callahan (Clint Eastwood) finds
a ransom note at the scene, addressed to the City of San Francisco,
containing the threat to kill one person every day until Scorpio is paid
100,000 dollars.
In the Mayor’s office, the Mayor (John Vernon) and Lieutenant
Bressler (Harry Guardino) discuss the ransom note. Callahan arrives to
report on progress in the case. At lunch, Callahan foils a bank robbery
in characteristically robust fashion. We next see Scorpio is setting up
on a rooftop, preparing to carry out his plans. He watches a potential
victim through his gunsight but is interrupted by a police helicopter and
has to flee. On the lookout for Scorpio, Callahan follows a man down a
dark alley and sees him entering an apartment. Standing on a garbage
bin looking into the window, he is set upon by concerned neighbours
and accused of being a peeping Tom. The next day, staking out the roof
where Scorpio was seen by the police helicopter, Callahan is distracted
by an orgy scene unfolding in an apartment below. His reverie is inter-
rupted by the appearance of Scorpio returning to the rooftop to finish
what he started. A shootout ensues and Scorpio escapes.
Scorpio makes another ransom demand, having kidnapped a girl and
buried her alive with a limited supply of oxygen. Callahan volunteers
to deliver the ransom money, Scorpio, communicating by phone, runs
him all over town. His journey ends at the base of a cross in Mount
Davidson Park, where Scorpio emerges to torment him. He is only saved
136 Pleasure, Happiness and Rights
Key Scenes
1 Callahan, interrupted mid-hot dog, single-handedly foils a bank rob-
bery. Bank robbers are blown away, cars crash into shop windows,
onlookers flee and a broken fire hydrant erupts over the scene of
devastation. The scene also features the famous line, as Callahan
stands over the one surviving bank robber who is thinking about
reaching for his gun: ‘I know what you’re thinking. Did he fire six
shots or only five … Well … do you feel lucky?’ As the film proceeds,
it increasingly raises questions about the hero’s extreme methods,
but here it portrays with gusto the very methods it later goes on to
question [09.51–14.09].
2 Carrying ransom money, Callahan is directed by Scorpio to the base
of a cross in Mount Davidson Park, where Scorpio emerges from
the gloom to torment him. He is only saved by the intervention of his
partner [55.15–59.06]. Callahan tracks Scorpio back to his home
in the Kezar football stadium and brings him down with a shot to
the leg. This time it is Callahan who emerges from the gloom and
stands over Scorpio, on the ground against another cross, made
by the stadium’s lawn markings. Callahan then proceeds to torture
Scorpio to find out where his kidnap victim is hidden. Such torture
might seem justified in utilitarian terms, but by drawing these paral-
lels with the earlier scene, the film suggests that Callahan’s extreme
Pleasure, Happiness and Rights 137
methods are bringing him close to the very evil he is trying to over-
come [1.05.33–1.07.27]. At the same time, the fact that he sends
his partner away before torturing Scorpio suggests that he himself
is uneasy about what he is doing, even if it is in the name of the
greater good.
3 After Scorpio is arrested by Callahan, he has to be released
because the District Attorney finds legal irregularities in the way he
was apprehended: ‘Where the hell does it say you’ve got a right
to kick down doors, torture suspects, deny medical attention and
legal counsel … What I’m saying is, that man had rights’ [1.08.23–
1.12.35]. Here, a rights-based perspective is invoked in the face of
a purely utilitarian view in which the end, the greater good, justifies
any means, no matter how brutal.
4 The final scene behind the gravel plant, at the end of the pier next
the pond where Callahan at last despatches Scorpio, closely mirrors
the swimming pool murder that Scorpio carried out at the start of the
film [0.48–1.50], only with Callahan now in the Scorpio role. Scorpio
has become the victim, floating dead in the water, and Callahan is
the ruthless killer looking on from above [1.35.15–1.36.40]. Again,
parallels are drawn between hero and villain.
Plot
The Joker (Heath Ledger) organises the robbery of a Gotham City bank
owned by the mob. Batman (Christian Bale) joins forces with District
Attorney Harvey Dent (Aaron Eckhart) and Lieutenant Jim Gordon (Gary
Oldman) to rid Gotham of organised crime once and for all. Bruce Wayne
offers to support Dent’s career, hoping that with Dent as Gotham’s protec-
tor, he will be able to give up being Batman; and also take up with assis-
tant DA Rachel Dawes (Maggie Gyllenhall), his childhood sweetheart,
138 Pleasure, Happiness and Rights
who is currently dating Dent even though she and Mob bosses Maroni
(Eric Roberts), Gambol (Michael Jai White) and the Chechen (Ritchie
Coster) hold a video conference with their accountant, Lau (Chin Han),
who has fled to Hong Kong taking their remaining funds for safekeeping.
The Joker interrupts the meeting, warning them that Batman can track
Lau down. He offers to kill Batman in exchange for half their money.
When Gambol puts a bounty on his head, the Joker kills him and takes
over his gang. The mob decides to take the Joker up on his offer.
Batman as predicted finds Lau in Hong Kong and brings him back
to Gotham to testify, allowing Dent to bring the entire mob to trial. The
Joker threatens to kill people until Batman reveals his identity. He mur-
ders the Police Commissioner and the judge presiding over the mob
trial and tries to kill the Mayor. Bruce Wayne decides to reveal his
identity, but before he can, Dent announces that he is Batman. He is
taken into protective custody, but the Joker attacks his convoy. He is
rescued by Batman and Gordon apprehends the Joker. Rachel and
Dent are escorted away by detectives who turn out to be on Maroni’s
payroll and never arrive home. Batman interrogates Maroni and the
Joker, the latter revealing they are in separate buildings rigged with
explosives. Batman goes to save Rachel, while Gordon tries to rescue
Dent. When Batman arrives at the building, he realises that the Joker
sent him to Dent’s location. Both buildings explode, killing Rachel and
disfiguring Dent. The Joker escapes taking Lau, whom he later kills
along with the Chechen.
One of Wayne’s employees, Coleman Reese (Joshua Harto), works
out that he is Batman and tries to go public with the information. To stop
Reese interfering with his plans, the Joker threatens to blow up a hos-
pital unless someone kills him. Gordon orders the evacuation of all the
hospitals in Gotham. The Joker visits Dent in Gotham Central Hospital
and gives him a gun, convincing him to seek revenge on those responsi-
ble for Rachel’s death, then blows up the hospital and escapes. He then
announces he is taking over the city. As Gotham descends into chaos,
the Joker rigs two ferries with explosives. He says he will blow up both
ferries at midnight but will spare one if its passengers blow up the other,
using a trigger he has supplied to each vessel. Batman finds the Joker
using a device that spies on the entire city, with the help of his technical
expert Lucius Fox (Morgan Freeman). The ferry passengers refuse to
play along and Batman apprehends the Joker. Before the police arrive
to take the Joker into custody, he says that Gotham’s citizens will lose
hope once Dent’s killing spree becomes public knowledge.
Pleasure, Happiness and Rights 139
Gordon and Batman arrive at the building where Rachel died. Dent
shoots Batman and threatens to kill Gordon’s son. Before he can do so,
Batman, who was wearing body armour, tackles Dent, who falls off the
building to his death. Knowing the Joker will win if people find out the
truth, Batman persuades Gordon to hold him responsible for Dent’s kill-
ings. The police launch a manhunt for Batman.
Key Scenes
1 Dent and Rachel run into Bruce Wayne and his date at a restaurant
and they dine together. The group discusses Batman’s vigilantism,
which Dent surprisingly approves of, comparing the situation to
ancient Rome suspending democracy so that one man could pro-
tect the city. Rachel warns that this is how Caesar became emperor
[20.00–21.40]. This is an early intimation that actions may be entirely
justifiable in the name of the greater good but can be morally and
politically dangerous nonetheless.
2 Wayne’s butler Alfred (Michael Caine) suggests that the mob, under
pressure from Gordon, Dent and Batman, turned to someone they
didn’t understand, and neither does Wayne. Ordinary criminals can
be expected to follow certain rules, but the Joker only wants to over-
turn the rules and produce chaos. Alfred: ‘some men aren’t looking
for anything logical, like money. They can’t be bought, bullied, rea-
soned or negotiated with. Some men just want to watch the world
burn’ [53.50–55.18]. The strangeness of the Joker’s behaviour lies
in his willingness to overturn rules and cultivate disorder, the oppo-
site of the Hobbesian view that people, in order to avoid the horrors
of a state of nature, will be strongly motivated to enter into a social
contract and submit to social rule.
3 Batman is shown resorting to torture to get information. He drops
mob boss Maroni from a building, breaking his legs, to force him
to speak. This might be perfectly justifiable in utilitarian terms, in
the name of getting the Joker off the streets and protecting the city,
but it is also morally problematic in other ways, as Batman himself
seems to recognise. As he says to Rachel, ‘I’ve seen, now, what I
would have to become to stop men like him’ [1.08.23–1.08.54]. That
he finds his behaviour morally problematic indicates that he is not a
utilitarian through and through in his moral thinking.
4 Batman again resorts to ‘enhanced interrogation techniques’. Since
Gordon is getting nowhere questioning the Joker about Dent’s dis-
appearance, he leaves the room and Batman takes over, beating
140 Pleasure, Happiness and Rights
At the end of High Noon (Fred Zinnemann, 1952), town Marshal Will Kane (Gary
Cooper), throws his badge into the dust in a gesture of contempt. For most of the
film he has been awaiting the arrival of the outlaw Frank Miller (Ian MacDonald),
whom he arrested and had sent to prison, and who is now returning on the noon train
to take revenge on Kane and the town. None of the townspeople have proved will-
ing to back him up. Out of cowardice, fear or self-interest, they have all refused to
sign up as deputies and he has been left to confront the outlaw alone. Now, having
managed to defeat the outlaw and his gang in a shootout, he is surrounded by those
same townspeople, who have emerged from hiding to congratulate him. Disgusted
by their hypocrisy, he throws his badge to the ground and rides off. This gesture is
echoed by Inspector Callahan at the end of Dirty Harry. Having dispatched Scorpio,
Callahan throws his police badge into the pond where the slain killer floats. He has
had to contend with the hypocrisy of the state, which both used and disavowed him.
In many ways Dirty Harry can be seen as transposing the classic movie western
confrontation of lawman and outlaw to a modern urban setting. By the same token,
the film looks back to the later nineteenth century, and the frontier West of North
America, which is the typical focus of the western genre (Dirks 2017). The arche-
typal western movie theme of maintaining law and order on the frontier is being
played out in the classic western High Noon. However, along with the similarities
there are also some differences. Things have become more complicated in the
interim. By the time of Dirty Harry, the lawman has become a morally ambiguous
figure, who has to do bad things for the greater good. High Noon’s lawman in con-
trast comes across as unambiguously moral. What is the difference here? One key
difference between Kane and Callahan is that utilitarian considerations play no role
whatsoever in determining Kane’s actions. His moral commitment is of an entirely
different sort. In taking his stand against the outlaw, he is ‘doing what he has to
do’, doing what he understands to be his duty. In this he comes close to exemplify-
ing the kind of moral position developed by Immanuel Kant (1724–1804).
Figure 4.1 Kane stands alone in High Noon (Fred Zinneman, 1952. Credit: United Artists/
Photofest).
Personhood and Autonomy 145
In his moral theory, Kant seeks to analyse, explain and defend the idea of
one’s duty, as something that outweighs all other considerations. He argues first
of all that the consequences of our acts have no bearing on the moral worth of
our actions, only the motivations behind them. Here there is a sharp contrast with
utilitarianism, for which it is only the consequences of actions that are morally
relevant, in terms of how much happiness they produce for all concerned. The
idea that human beings ought to behave in ways that produce good consequences
makes utilitarianism a prime example of a ‘consequentialist’ moral theory. Some
of the townspeople argue in these utilitarian terms against making a stand against
the outlaws. When Kane comes to the church to ask the congregation for help in
confronting Miller and the gang, the view that carries the day in the subsequent
discussion is that making a stand against the outlaws is the wrong thing to do,
that a shootout should be avoided. It would give the town a bad reputation and
deter outside investment, hurting the local economy and hence the well-being of
the community. It would be better if Kane just left town, as the bad guys would
simply move on. For Kant, how much happiness or otherwise an action is likely
to produce has no bearing on its morality.
Moreover, the consequences of an action are morally irrelevant for Kant in the
sense that whether we succeed or fail in what we are trying to do does not affect
the moral worth of what we are doing. The moral worth of our actions depends
solely on the intention or motivation with which we act. What is required is that
we act not merely in accordance with duty, but out of a sense of duty, in a princi-
pled way, for the sake of the moral law. For Kant, it is only those actions that are
motivated by a sense of duty which can be called moral actions, not those that are
done out of self-interest, desire or feeling. Kant calls this purely dutiful kind of
motivation the ‘good will’. As he puts it in his Groundwork: ‘A good will is good
not because of what it effects or accomplishes - because of its fitness to attain
some intended end: it is good through its willing alone – that is, good in itself’
(Kant 1964, 62).
In support of this view, it can be said that a large part of why Kane appears so
morally upright and impressive in High Noon is because he does what he does sim-
ply because it is the ‘right thing to do’. This is regardless of his prospects of success.
Indeed, there is a very good chance that he is going to fail and get himself killed, and
increasingly so as his requests for help from the townspeople are rejected. However,
this likelihood of failure has no bearing on our sense of the moral worthiness of his
action, which has to do with the character of his motivation. We would view his
actions as being somewhat less worthy if he were doing what he was doing simply
out of self-interest, in order to impress others with his bravery, or to advance his
career. This is how we feel about Kane’s friend and deputy Harvey Pell (Lloyd
Bridges). He does offer to stand with Kane against the outlaws, but only provided
Kane gets him the job as the next town marshal, which he feels is his due: ‘you put
the word in for me like I said’. Pell very clearly acts out of self-interest. He will only
stay if he gets an external reward, career advancement. Kane’s rejection of Pell’s
self-interested offer seems to acknowledge the unworthiness of this motivation:
‘I want you to stick – but I’m not buying it. It’s got to be up to you’.
146 Personhood and Autonomy
The moral relevance of the motivation with which we act is also evident in
another western constructed around a deadline, 3:10 to Yuma (James Mangold,
2007), a remake of the 1957 film of the same name. In the remake, the hero, Dan
Evans (Christian Bale), has been enlisted by the railroad to help escort notorious
outlaw Ben Wade (Russell Crowe) to the town of Contention, where he will be
put on the train to Yuma prison. For this task, Evans, a struggling rancher, asks for
a $200 fee to provide for his family. Having made it to Contention, he is holed up
in a hotel room, with Wade and the railroad’s representative, Butterfield (Dallas
Roberts), along with his son who had been following the group. Wade’s gang are
outside, ready to kill him and free Wade as soon as they try to leave. He has been
abandoned by the town marshal and his deputies, who earlier offered support but
now see his task as a lost cause. Butterfield also wants out, and absolves Evans
of his duty, releasing him from his contract, but still offering to give him his fee.
Despite all this, Evans is determined to get Wade to the station and complete
his mission.
In Evans we have another heroic figure, like Kane, facing a difficult situation
with the odds against him, but sticking to his guns. In this case however, there is a
different kind of motivation. Evans may want to get Wade to the train station and
complete his mission even though he has been released from his contract, but he
is still motivated by the prospect of external reward. He renegotiates the arrange-
ment with Butterfield, demanding that $1,000 be given to his wife before he will
go through with it. It is also clear that he is going through with this in order to win
the respect of his son, who, it is established early on, has a poor opinion of him
because of his failure as a rancher. On this point, there is a very clear contrast with
the original 1957 film. There, the Dan Evans character (played by Van Heflin),
insists in similar circumstances on continuing with the mission of getting the out-
law on the train not because he can get something out of it, but simply because it is
the right thing to do. We might not want to be too critical of the Evans character in
the remake. Although Evans acts there for external reward, he is not really acting
out of self-interest, but for others. He wants the money for his wife, he wants to
give his son a father he can look up to and be proud of. Nonetheless, the Kantian
would insist that it is only the behaviour of the Evans character in the original that
represents the genuine moral action, because it is motivated only by the sense of
duty (see Mexal 2010).
It would seem that on Kant’s account, a great deal of what we would ordinarily
see as motivating our behaviour is to be excluded from the moral realm. Indeed,
all of the desires and interests that Hobbes and the earlier Enlightenment saw as
fundamentally motivating human beings are to be excluded. And it is not only
actions done out of self-interest or desire; even an action done out of love or com-
passion, while it may be praiseworthy, is not a moral action on Kant’s view. Only
those actions motivated by a sense of duty qualify. Here we seem to be back with
the idea, affirmed early on by Plato, that being moral requires the suppression of
desire, emotion and feeling in favour of reason. For Kant, when we are acting
only out of a sense of duty, we are acting purely on the basis of principles that our
rationality dictates. As noted, this is reason understood as capable of establishing
Personhood and Autonomy 147
laws or principles of conduct, of generating rules for living. And to the extent that
I am a rational being, I am bound to follow these principles, since they are the
commands of my own rationality. So how does our reason establish moral princi-
ples? To be moral, for Kant, is to act in accordance with principles that are bind-
ing not just on me but on all rational beings. Something cannot be rational for me
and not for others. So in order to act morally, we need to determine whether the
principle we are thinking of acting on, the maxim or subjective principle, which
is the reason a particular agent happens to perform a certain action, is universalis-
able, i.e., whether it is able to be consistently followed by all agents in relevantly
similar situations. If it can be so universalised, it is an objective moral principle,
in the sense of applying not just to me but all rational agents.
This requirement of universalisability might seem rather formalistic but it does
incorporate the idea that morality is not a purely individual matter, that claims that
something is morally right have a universal aspect. Moral rules are forms of behav-
iour that do not admit exceptions, individual cases, special pleading; and moral
principles do not just serve my particular interests. Here we may take Kant’s exam-
ple of promise-keeping. Suppose I’m tempted to break a promise in order to get
out of a tight spot. The principle I’m thinking of acting on here may be formulated
as – ‘I may always break a promise when it’s in my interest to do so’. Can I consist-
ently make this maxim into a universal law? Kant doesn’t think so. If every person
acted on this principle and broke their promises whenever it suited them, the whole
practice of promising would break down. As a result, I would not be able to break a
promise whenever it suited me, because no one would believe any promise I made
in the first place. Thus, if breaking promises when it suited me became universal
and everyone followed it, I would be involved in a self-contradiction, aiming to do
something that it is impossible for me to do because there is no longer the practice of
believing what people promise. So the maxim – I may always break a promise when
it’s in my interest to do so – cannot be universalised, and so it isn’t moral to do so.
To put this another way, using the related notion of truth-telling, we can envis-
age a world like that posited in The Invention of Lying (Ricky Gervais, Matthew
Robinson, 2009), in which everyone tells the truth, however uncomfortable this
might be. In this context, it is possible to imagine that one person might discover
lying, and indeed to be able to do very well out of it too, as happens in the film.
But what we cannot envisage is a world in which everyone lies when it suits them,
because in such a world, no one would believe anything anyone said and so it
would not be possible to lie in the first place. Thus, lying fails the universalisabil-
ity test and is not a moral thing to do. Here, lying is not being morally condemned
because it is a device for personal gain at the expense of others. Certainly, once
the central character Mark Bellison (Gervais) discovers he can lie, he uses it to
steal money and seduce women; but he also finds that he can use lying to help oth-
ers, for example, to assuage their fears about death by reassuring them that there is
an afterlife. And we might imagine that lying could be morally justified if it were
to produce good consequences. There could be a ‘good lie’. But that is a utilitarian
view. For Kant, lying can never be morally right, whether done for personal gain
or to help others. It is the kind of action that is always wrong, by its very nature.
148 Personhood and Autonomy
Another way of appreciating Kant’s position here is to note that for Kant, all
utilitarian claims take the form of what he calls hypothetical imperatives. A hypo-
thetical imperative is a principle of action that says that if you want to achieve
such and such a goal, you should act in a certain way. It has an if-then structure –
for example, if you want to get to a certain destination by the shortest possible
route, you should take roads X and Y. Hypothetical imperatives apply to rational
agents insofar as they have particular desires or goals. They are part of means-
end reasoning, in which reason helps us in the satisfaction of our desires. All
utilitarian claims are of this sort – if you want to maximise happiness, you should
do such and such. For Kant, however, moral laws are categorical imperatives.
A categorical imperative requires you to act in a certain way regardless of your
particular desires and interests. It is absolute or categorical in nature, to be obeyed
whether or not you want to act that way. And this is the case with moral laws; they
always apply categorically. What Kant is saying here is that when we act morally,
we’re not acting on the basis of rules that depend on our particular desires, which
will vary from person to person and over time. We’re acting on the basis of rules
that command us purely because we are rational beings. Morality thus consists of
the categorical imperatives or commands of our reason, the general formula for
the categorical imperative being: act only on that principle that could be turned
into a universal law.
So why does Kant we have to rigorously exclude all desire and inclination from
the realm of the moral? It can be noted that for Kant our desires are mostly but not
entirely self-centred and egoistic; we can have genuinely altruistic or benevolent
desires, oriented towards the well-being of others. Yet even these have no place
in the moral realm. Kant’s position here reflects his notion of human nature. What
we are, above all, are rational beings. As with Plato, he identifies human beings
most closely with reason and sees them as engaged in a constant struggle to con-
trol their bodily, desiring side. This picture also appears in Augustine’s religious
ethics, with its hostility towards the desire that signifies our entanglement in this
world. Kant, however, wants to assert the claims of human beings as rational
subjects in the face of the modern scientific understanding of nature. For him,
reason is the deepest and most valuable part of us. It is what raises us above nature
and makes us unique. Everything else in nature is blindly moved by mechanical
forces. Even animals behave in this mechanical way. Human beings are partly like
this, for they have a natural side, their desires, inclinations and emotions, many of
which they share with animals. But they are also, and most importantly, rational
beings. Only rational beings have the capacity to act consciously in accordance
with principles they formulate for themselves. This is something higher, some-
thing that sets us apart from the rest of nature.
Given this view of human nature, it follows that rational agents ought to
determine their actions in this way. As Charles Taylor puts it, ‘the fundamental
principle underlying Kant’s whole ethical theory is something of this form: live
up to what you really are – rational agents’ (Taylor 1985b, 324). This is the
gist of the Kant’s answer to the question ‘why be moral?’ To be moved to act
Personhood and Autonomy 149
by our desires, emotions and inclinations, to become just another thing subject
to mechanical necessity, is to fall below our proper status. Only when we are
behaving rationally, in accordance with moral laws we formulate for ourselves,
are we living up to our true status as rational beings. Here Kant is in agree-
ment with Rose Sayer (Katherine Hepburn) in The African Queen (John Huston,
1951). When Humphrey Bogart’s character, Charlie Allnut, who is strongly
inclined to swilling gin, defends himself by saying that it’s only human nature to
take a drop too much once in a while, she informs him that ‘Nature, Mr Allnut,
is what we were put on earth to rise above’. As a missionary there is of course
a religious element in her rejection of such ‘lower inclinations’, but we might
equally say that Kant has managed to preserve the religious suspicion of desire
in his rationalist morality. It is now the rational soul that needs to be ‘saved’.
And its special value is something that we ourselves recognise. This is ulti-
mately why Kant thinks we experience moral commands, the demands of duty,
as being more important than other considerations such as personal interest,
desire or inclination.
Kant does not completely exclude desire and emotion from the human being as
he understands this notion. He distinguishes human beings from what he calls the
‘holy will’, a purely rational creature, in effect a god. This is a being that always
effortlessly and automatically follows the commands of reason. Human beings
are not gods, but nor are they animals; they fall between the two. They are partly
in the natural world since they have a natural side to their makeup, their desires,
emotions and feelings, but they are also capable of rational, principled behaviour.
So human beings understand the moral law, but do not always follow it, being
sometimes swayed by emotion or desire. This is why human beings encounter
moral laws as duties, things they recognise that they ought to do even if they
don’t always manage to do them. This is also why being moral for Kant involves
a constant struggle to rise above, control or suppress desire and inclination, so as
to be moved by a sense of duty alone. Thus, while Kant’s moral picture might
give a central role to the human being as an active subject, capable of determining
the moral rules and giving shape to its existence, there is also an appreciation that
we are worldly creatures with desires and inclinations, who have to struggle to be
moral and who can fail. To that extent we can more readily recognise ourselves
in this picture.
We are able to relate to Kane in High Noon for similar reasons. Though he
is doing what duty requires, his adherence to duty is not automatic. He is not
superhuman, a holy will. He struggles constantly with feelings of panic, fear and
the urge to run away, and looks increasingly haggard as the film proceeds. By
virtue of this realistic portrayal of its hero, the film can itself be described as a
‘realist western’. It departs from the more traditional western mythology in which
the hero is straightforwardly strong, courageous and honourable, the kind of
heroic persona epitomised by John Wayne in many of his films. Kane has to work
hard to do the right thing. In a similar way, in the classic Casablanca (Michael
Curtiz 1942), Humphrey Bogart’s character Rick Blaine, the nightclub owner,
150 Personhood and Autonomy
has to struggle to overcome self-interest in order to do what duty requires. In this
respect, he is certainly easier to relate to than the morally upright Victor Laszlo
(Paul Henreid), the fugitive Czech resistance leader who has come to Casablanca
with his wife Ilsa (Ingrid Bergman), seeking safe passage out of Europe. Laszlo is
the straightforward hero of the piece, risking his life to fight Nazi tyranny, but he
is more like the ‘holy will’, a moral saint, effortlessly acting in accordance with
duty. Rick Blaine is the more human character, for whom being moral requires
a certain amount of struggle, though he gets there in the end. This entirely befits
a film that appeared in the early forties, and which can at a certain level be seen
as a political allegory, even a piece of propaganda encouraging the United States
public to set aside any lingering isolationist sentiments and support the war effort
(see McVeigh 2017).
High Noon is also realist in its portrayal of the townspeople. It departs from the
traditional western mythology in which the ordinary townspeople are inspired to
rise above themselves by a hero who insists on doing the right thing in the face of
overwhelming odds. In High Noon, they remain right to the end cowardly, fearful
and self-interested, offering endless rationalisations for their craven behaviour.
This might itself be seen as reflecting the more sobering post-war reality of the
early fifties. The film’s screenwriter, Carl Foreman, had bitter personal experi-
ence to draw on in fashioning the story. He was one of Hollywood figures targeted
in the anti-communist witch-hunts of the early fifties, dragged before the House
Un-American Activities Committee, and blacklisted for refusing to name com-
munist party members. In this light, the marshal can be seen as ‘the hunted man
who obeys his conscience’ and the cowardly townsfolk are ‘the American public
who failed to help him’ (Frost and Banks 2001, 152; see also Frankel 2017). John
Wayne who supported the anti-communist witch-hunts and helped run Foreman
out of the country, thought that High Noon was un-American because of its por-
trayal of the townspeople. A few years later, he made Rio Bravo (Howard Hawks,
1959), which can be seen as a riposte to High Noon. In this film, when the marshal
calls on the townspeople, they rally around him in reassuring fashion. The western
as mythology is reaffirmed, even if, ironically enough, through an instance of
collective action.
The notion of human being bound up with Kant’s moral theory undoubt-
edly represents a development over the crude Hobbesian picture. Rather than a
machine driven to seek pleasure and avoid pain, Kant’s human being has moved
beyond the merely biological to become a responsible agent, a self that is com-
mitted to certain moral principles. Rather than simply being moved by desires,
it shapes and evaluates its motivation in the light of principles. Instead of view-
ing all motivations as being on the same level. Kant’s account acknowledges
that some concerns carry a greater weight with us, that they are more central to
‘who we are’ and should take precedence over other motivations. In High Noon,
Kane, however much he wants to leave, has to stay as a matter of inner necessity
and personal integrity. Giving in to the panic and fear, running away would be a
self-betrayal. In Casablanca, Rick Blaine’s development as a character involves
Personhood and Autonomy 151
coming to recognise this. Initially concerned only to look out for his own interests,
someone who ‘sticks his neck out for nobody’, he comes to recognise the force of
higher moral considerations. In the process, he gives up Ilsa (Ingrid Bergman), his
former lover now married to Laszlo, for the sake of the greater cause, the struggle
against fascism. At the same time, as the genial if corrupt police captain Renault
(Claude Rains) recognises, this is also a return to his ‘real self’, the principled
person that Renault had always suspected him of being behind the cynical shell.
Remarks by Renault indicate that Rick had been an idealist in the past, a supporter
of anti-fascist struggles.
So Kant’s human being is richer and more complex than the creature of pure
self-interest. However, it remains the case that even though Kant appreciates that
human beings are creatures with desires, emotions and feelings, these still have
to be rigorously excluded from one’s motivation, or firmly subjugated to the rule
of reason, if one is to be a moral being. Morality requires stern self-control, for as
Kant puts it, ‘unless reason takes the reins of government into its own hands, the
feelings and inclinations play the master over the man’ (Kant 2009, 49). But, as
with Plato’s rationalistic morality, and Christian asceticism, the moral ideal here
is a rather authoritarian, repressive one, marked by intense suspicion and hostil-
ity towards desire and emotion. Such hostility is liable to strike us as damaging,
particularly given the affirmation of desire as a legitimate and important part of our
make-up, initiated by Hobbes, that marks the advent of modern thinking. Nature
may be ‘something we are supposed to rise above’ for The African Queen’s Rose
Sayer, but this is also the attitude of the straitlaced missionary she starts out as in
this First World War adventure. Her development in the film involves turning away
from religiously inspired self-denial to some appreciation of physicality and the
pleasures of the flesh. This is not to forget that she is also responsible for motivating
the dissolute Charlie Allnut (Bogart again) to rise above his gin-soaked nature, keep
his promises and to join her in a heroic attack on a German warship. But Kant’s
ideal seems to have more in common with the original Rose, the prim, repressed
missionary. It promotes the self-denial formerly evident in the Christian picture.
Kant’s account also means that emotions like compassion, sympathy and pity
are entirely irrelevant to moral behaviour, which may seem a rather chilling pic-
ture of morality, indeed quite an inhuman one. Like utilitarianism, Kantian ethics
makes enormous demands of the human being. Once again, we are required to set
aside a great deal of what ordinarily motivates us in order to behave morally. With
utilitarianism, in determining the right thing to do, you can give no special weight
to your own happiness or that of those you are close to but must calculate impar-
tially in terms of everyone’s well-being. With Kant this self-alienating impartial-
ity is even more pronounced. In order to be moral, to attain the ideal prescribed
in this account, you have to exclude everything that is particular or personal to
oneself, all desires, emotions, feelings, personal commitments, even character, in
order to act only in accordance with the universal principles of morality. Certainly,
these are the principles of your own reason, and as a rational subject the human
being has become the active source of their own guiding principles. But Kant’s
152 Personhood and Autonomy
self-determining rational subject seems remote from ordinary human existence. It
represents a moral ideal that may well be beyond the powers of ordinary human
beings to attain, and it condemns them to a state of permanent internal conflict,
between the moral self that one aspires to be and one’s own desires and feelings.
Along with this view of being moral, we may want to question the correspond-
ing idea that immorality is primarily the result of desire escaping the control of
reason. If morality for Kant is a constant struggle to subdue desire, there is con-
versely a constant pressure on us to give in to our desires and inclinations, to
do what we want rather than what duty requires of us. This verges on an almost
Augustinian picture of human beings as predisposed to evil, with morality as the
countervailing force that strives to ‘hold us back from our darker, desiring selves’
(see Halwani 2016). This understanding of evil as the result of unchecked wants
is amply illustrated in the western, insofar as the villain in the western genre is
typically ‘the bad guy who acts from selfish motivations and desires’ (Devlin
2010, 229). If the western is standardly a battle between good and evil, the hero is
usually the one who is subject to a moral code, who has principles and sticks by
them, and the villain, the one who is out for themselves alone, motivated by greed,
desire for power, or, if these are frustrated, by vengeance against those who stand
in the way of what they want. High Noon may not be a traditional western in many
ways, but it does offer a traditional western villain in the form of the outlaw Frank
Miller, out for revenge against Kane who put him away.
The neo-western No Country for Old Men transposes the classic battle between
good and evil to eighties Texas, and one of the features that marks it as a revision
of the genre is its radical overturning of the standard representation of the bad guy.
In the hit-man Chigurh, as discussed in Chapter One, we have the possibility of
a different kind of villain, one whose evil derives not from greed or unchecked
appetite, but from adherence to higher principles, combined with an iron self-con-
trol (Figure 4.2). Could Chigurh ever be seen as a good Kantian? His principles
Figure 4.2 No Country for Old Men: the principled hit-man (Joel and Ethan Coen,
1998. Credit: Miramax Films/Photofest).
Personhood and Autonomy 153
are mysterious, though they are presumably not the sorts of principles that Kant
would hope to justify through reason. Nonetheless, they are Kantian in that they
are absolute and admit of no exceptions and he is single-mindedly devoted to them.
Highly principled behaviour is the sort of behaviour one might ordinarily expect
to be associated with the hero, but here it is a feature of the villain. It is his quarry,
Lewellyn Moss (Josh Brolin), who has given in to desire and self-interest and done
a traditionally ‘bad’ thing, stealing money from the site of a drug deal gone wrong.
Generally speaking, if the distinguishing mark of the human being is the capacity to
act in a principled way, it may be that despite Kant’s confidence that such principled
behaviour can only manifest itself in morally good conduct, it can just as readily
manifest itself in a new and perhaps far more fearsome kind of evil.
Another problem area for Kantian moral thinking is its exclusion of conse-
quences from moral consideration. One of the issues with utilitarianism, as we
have seen, is that any action, no matter how shocking, can be justified in utili-
tarian terms given the right consequences, because all that is morally relevant
are the consequences of the action, how much happiness it is likely to produce.
Kant’s deontological account allows us to say that there are some things we simply
should not do, no matter how beneficial the consequences, simply because of the
nature of the act itself. This however can itself lead to questionable situations. For
example, a duty not to lie seems to mean that we would not be justified in telling
a lie to give comfort to or spare the feelings of others, as in the uncomfortable
world of The Invention of Lying. Lying is not even justified in order to save the life
of someone else, even thousands of lives. Kant insists that ‘Truthfulness in state-
ments … is the formal duty of man to everyone, however great the disadvantage
that may arise therefrom for him or for any other’ (Kant 2016, 83). Yet, even if we
do not want to go all the way with utilitarianism, which would countenance any
degree of lying or deception for the greater good, a moral system might be thought
inflexible if it did not allow any kind of trade-off for good consequences.
A related question arises regarding Kant’s view that whether we succeed or fail
in what we set out to do is irrelevant to the moral assessment of our actions. From
a Kantian perspective, it does not matter whether Kane in High Noon succeeds in
taking care of Miller and his gang or fails miserably in the attempt. As it happens
he does succeed in doing so, with help from his wife at a crucial point, but what is
overwhelmingly important in the Kantian view is that his actions are of the right
sort and have the right kind of motivation. As Kant puts it: ‘A good will is good
not because of what it effects or accomplishes – because of its fitness to attain
some intended end: it is good through its willing alone – that is, good in itself’
(Kant 1964, 62). Yet consider an alternative ending to the film: Kane fails, dies in
the dust and the outlaws triumph and take over the town. In this scenario, Kane’s
stand is still a noble gesture, but it has also been rendered futile, and somehow
diminished. It might be thought that a consistent failure to achieve what one sets
out to do is going to have a bearing on the moral status of what one does.
Turning again to No Country for Old Men, the good guy, very much in the tra-
dition of the western hero, is represented by Sheriff Ed Bell (Tommy Lee Jones).
Like Kane, he acts in accordance with his duty as a sheriff, to deal with the bad
154 Personhood and Autonomy
guys and protect the community. Yet unlike the traditional western hero, Bell
also fails completely in his duty. He is unable to protect ‘his people’, Moss or
his wife Carla Jean (Kelly Macdonald), from retribution, Moss having taken the
money from the drug deal site, and Carla Jean being ‘collateral damage’. And he
is unable to bring to justice the chief agent of that retribution, the relentless hit-
man Chigurh. It is not clear that one can simply discount these failures. However
well-intentioned he might be, there seems to be a morally significant difference
between protecting his people and arresting the bad guy and allowing both of
them to get killed and the bad guy to get away scot free. Arguably, Bell’s failure
to perform his duties means that he has to face the ‘loss of his moral integrity’ (see
Devlin 2010, 236). Indeed, that is his own estimation of his performance. Feeling
‘overmatched’ by a brutal reality, all Bell can do is retreat, a broken man, into
retirement. The film itself stands not as a monument to good intentions but as a
story of the end of morality and an epitaph to the western genre.
Persons
There are two features embedded in Kant’s moral theory that it is useful to
explore further. These are the notion of personhood and the idea of freedom as
rational autonomy. First of all, the idea that our rationality is something higher
than nature, that it has a special value, gives Kant another way of characteris-
ing what it is in general to be moral. We have already seen one formulation:
act only on that principle that could be turned into a universal law. Later in the
Groundwork, Kant gives another formulation, this time in terms of how we should
treat rational beings. Rational beings are capable of deciding for themselves the
shape and goals of their existence. And this capacity for rational self-determination
makes the person uniquely valuable. Each of us as a rational being has an ulti-
mate, unconditioned worth. Everything else in nature can be used as instruments
for our own goals and projects, but rational agents have their own goals and pro-
jects and should be treated with these in view. Hence, we should always treat
rational agents never simply as means but always also as ends in themselves. In
other words, we should respect them as beings capable of forming goals and act-
ing in accordance with principles they have formulated for themselves.
Kant’s moral theory thus leads directly to the idea that persons, rational agents,
have a special value and are deserving of moral respect. This contrasts with utili-
tarianism, for which human beings have no value in themselves, but only insofar
as they contribute to overall happiness. For Kant, to treat a human being as no
more than a means to an end is to treat them as a mere thing. Mere things have
value only in so far as they serve human purposes, but persons, as Kant puts it,
have ‘an intrinsic value – that is, dignity’, which makes them valuable ‘above
all price’ (Kant 1964, 102–103). This means that the worth of a rational being
cannot be traded off against any other good or any other rational being. Again,
this contrasts with utilitarianism, where everything has a price and can always be
traded off against other goods with a greater price or importance. On that view,
you could always imagine a situation where the right thing to do was to take
Personhood and Autonomy 155
someone’s life, if it meant saving the lives of others. But for Kant you cannot do
that, because rational beings have dignity, not price.
This is not to say we should never treat a rational being as a means, which
would make social life impossible since we treat each other as means all the
time (catching a bus, asking someone to pass the salt and so on). It is to say we
should never treat them simply as a means but always also as an end in them-
selves, i.e., only ever in ways that they could rationally will to be treated. The
‘rationally’ is important here since human beings are not always fully rational.
As fallible human beings, we may want things done to us that are inconsistent
with the moral law. So it has to be how human beings can rationally will to be
treated. In High Noon, this Kantian refusal to treat human beings as mere means
is exemplified in Kane’s treatment of the townspeople he is trying to enlist. As
Gerald Kreyche notes, Kane does not try to force the townspeople to become his
deputies. Instead, he asks them, he tries to persuade them through argument, he
wants them to rationally consent to help him. He also refuses the services of those
townspeople who do volunteer, the young boy and the town drunk. Their capacity
to make rational decisions of that sort is underdeveloped or impaired. The young
boy and the drunk are not fully rational agents. If Kane were to take up their offer,
he would be taking advantage of them, using them as no more than means for his
own plans (see Kreyche 1988, 227).
Kant provides an influential formulation of the idea that human beings under-
stood as persons have a special moral significance. It is important however to
emphasise that for Kant, a person is not a human being in the biological sense,
but a rational being, a creature capable of acting in accordance with reasons and
principles rather than simply being driven by instincts. Here, Kant follows in
the footsteps of Locke, for whom a person is ‘a thinking, intelligent being that
has reason and reflection’ (Locke 1997, 302). Since Kant, there have been many
formulations of the notion of personhood and various additional criteria have
been proposed, including: the capacity to have mental states, self-consciousness
(Tooley 1991); second-order desires or desires about desires (such as the desire
to stop wanting to have a drink) (Frankfurt 1971); and the capacity to use lan-
guage (Dennett 1976). Nonetheless, these accounts usually preserve as central
the criterion of rationality that Kant emphasises. One implication of this is that
it is possible to be a person and not a biological human being. Kant himself
gives the example of the holy will, an entirely rational being that is a person
but not a human being. And we can imagine other creatures, such as spirits,
angels, aliens, Mr Spock, androids, computers and so on, who might be rational
beings but not biological human beings. They too are persons, deserving of
moral respect. On this view, we do not value human beings because they are
members of a certain biological species, but because they possess certain quali-
ties that are morally relevant.
Another implication of this notion of personhood is that there can be human
beings who are not persons. To be a person requires that you have certain quali-
ties, and depending on the criteria used for defining personhood, not all human
beings may qualify. Some human beings may be considered not to be persons or
156 Personhood and Autonomy
to be at best marginal persons. So, on the Kantian view which focuses on rational-
ity, we tend to find children, and individuals with severe mental disabilities, not
qualifying as persons. Such judgements are often controversial of course, because
they seem to imply that the human being in question is not entitled to the respect
owing to a person. That certain individuals and groups end up being excluded
from personhood may indeed be taken as a sign that we need to think more care-
fully about what constitutes personhood in the first place. A different sort of prob-
lem in this connection is the refusal to recognise, as persons, human beings who
are entirely deserving of being so recognised on any reasonable understanding of
the term. The failure to acknowledge the personhood of certain groups of people
is a feature of various forms of racist and sexist thinking. For such thinking, it is
a definite advantage that the human being in question is not entitled to the respect
owing to a person. They are consequently open not only to marginalisation and
exclusion, but also abuse and exploitation.
In the context of the movie western, it is the Native Americans, the ‘sav-
age Indians’ who harass the advancing settlers, who are typically viewed in this
way, as non-persons, not deserving of respect. It is a convenient attitude to hold
for those intent on taking possession of the land and transforming it in a ‘civi-
lised’ fashion. By the time of High Noon, they have been reduced to two forlorn
individuals, briefly glimpsed standing outside the saloon door. In the civilised
world, they have become outsiders. In this context, the traditional western hero
who protects the community from an outside threat can become something far
less appetising, the representative of a form of racism that is capable of justify-
ing genocide. This, the dark side of the western myth, is explored in John Ford’s
classic western, The Searchers (1956). Here, Ethan Edwards (John Wayne)
is searching for his niece Debbie (Natalie Wood), abducted by the Comanche
Indians who massacred the rest of her family. With the help of her adopted
brother Martin Pawly (Jeffrey Hunter), he spends years obsessively searching
for her. Along the way, Martin gradually comes to realise with horror that Ethan
intends not to rescue her but to kill her.
Ethan’s view is that ‘living with the Comanche ain’t living’. By now, having
taken on the ways of the Indians, his niece will have been reduced to a subhuman
state, and so she is better off dead. Nor is he alone in this view. Back home in
civilisation, even Martin’s kindly girlfriend Laurie (Vera Miles) insists that Ethan
should ‘put a bullet in her brain’, and that Debbie’s mother would have wanted
Ethan to kill his niece. When Martin argues that Debbie doesn’t deserve to die,
and that he has to go fetch her, the response is ‘Fetch what home? The leavings
a Comanche buck sold time and again to the highest bidder, with savage brats of
her own?’ Ethan’s own antipathy towards the Indians is evident early on when
he reacts with disgust to the revelation that Martin is part Indian. When Ethan
finally finds Debbie, Martin has to protect her from him, but in the end, he finds
that he cannot kill her, and instead, takes her home. Although perhaps intended
as a moment of redemption for Ethan, this act does little to compensate for his
views in the rest of the film and indeed is so out of keeping with them as to be
hard to understand. And there is no indication that he has changed his views about
Personhood and Autonomy 157
Indians in general. The irony for Ethan is that having returned Debbie, he finds
himself excluded from civilised society. He is seen as being too much like the
Indians he professes to hate, and is left on the borders of society, outside the door,
like the two Indians in High Noon.
The failure to acknowledge the personhood of certain groups of people char-
acteristic of racism is portrayed from the point of view of the one denied that
personhood in Get Out (Jordan Peele, 2017). This is a horror film in which the
horror comes from the growing recognition that one is being seen as no more
than a thing, a means to an end, a resource for others to use. The film follows
photographer Chris Washington (Daniel Kaluuya), a black man who has come to
meet the family of his white girlfriend Rose (Allison Williams), at their estate in
Upstate New York. His initial encounters with the family and their friends, who
seem at first to be making awkward attempts not to be racist, praising his phy-
sique, expressing admiration for his photographic skills and so on, appear very
differently in the light of the way the story develops. Their interest comes from
a desire to make use of those attributes, to take control of them by transplanting
a white person’s brain into his body. His girlfriend’s entire family, even his girl-
friend, are in on it. He gradually comes to the devastating realisation that for these
people he is not a person, that he is nothing but an instrument, a means to an end.
The exploration of the converse idea of persons who are not human beings
takes us into the realm of the science fiction film. Here the distinction between the
person and the human is particularly important to keep in mind, since it is easy to
describe personhood in terms of humanity or humanness, which if taken literally
makes a non-human person impossible by definition. As mentioned, personhood
refers to the possession of certain qualities, not membership of a particular bio-
logical species. Consequently, it is possible for there to be persons who are not
human beings, and also for ‘speciesist’ attitudes, where speciesism is the refusal
to accord personhood to creatures who possess the relevant qualities, on the irrel-
evant grounds that they are not members of the human species. The theme of
non-human personhood is a fruitful one because it allows a chance not only to
reflect on what counts as a person, but also to comment indirectly on the treatment
of those within human society who, although they have the relevant qualities,
are denied personhood, particularly in the context of racist, colonialist and sexist
discourses. The question of non-human persons is explored in a number of films,
from Planet of the Apes to Ex Machina, and includes some of the most significant
representatives of the genre.
The original Planet of the Apes (Franklin J. Schaffner, 1968) opens up the
field, alluding to institutionalised racism by contriving a society in which human
beings as a group have been denied personhood by a group of non-human per-
sons. Following the Pierre Boule source novel, it portrays a future earth in which
the human species has become subordinate to a society of intelligent apes. The
apes view the humans as unintelligent, incapable of rational thought, capable of
little more than mimicking their sophisticated behaviour. As such, they are not
considered worthy of moral regard, and may be legitimately hunted, confined
and exploited for entertainment value and scientific research. The analogy with
158 Personhood and Autonomy
racism is not exact, as in this world, human beings really have devolved into a
mute, seemingly subhuman state. The burden of being unjustly denied person-
hood is borne by the only ‘genuine human’ remaining, namely Charlton Heston’s
astronaut Taylor, with whom we are invited to identify. Taylor has recently crash-
landed on the planet after a 2,000-year voyage spent in deep sleep hibernation,
not realising that it is the earth he left behind. In short order, he is captured and
caged, and treated by the apes as a ‘mere animal’ until he is able to convince them
of his intelligence. He can only do this once he recovers his voice, which had
been damaged in the crash landing. Through him, the film becomes the story of
an individual human’s struggle to be recognised as a person. Here, personhood is
identified not so much with the capacity to speak but rather with the intelligence
or rationality that speaking reveals.
The more recent Rise of the Planet of the Apes (Rupert Wyatt, 2011), offers
an account of how the apes came to supplant the humans in the first place. In so
doing, it turns the focus more on the question of the personhood of non-human
animals, although there remain oblique references to racist oppression. Here, the
situation portrayed in the original film is reversed, in that it is now an ape who
aspires to be recognised by human beings as a person. Thanks to an experimental
gene therapy, the chimp Caesar (a motion-captured Andy Serkis) has developed
a high degree of intelligence. He is taken out of the animal experimentation facil-
ity to live with the therapy’s developer Rodman (James Franco), almost as one
of the family. However, an intemperate outburst leads to him being taken away
and confined in a prison-like ape house, where he is treated in an inhuman, i.e.,
‘depersonalising’, way. Communicating through sign-language and ultimately
speech, Caesar exhibits not only intelligence but also self-awareness, showing
that he understands concepts like death, and asking Rodman at one point whether
he is a pet. Naturally, these personhood-making traits go unrecognised by the
brutal keepers at the ape house. His poor treatment at their hands will spark the
rebellion that is going to lead to the new order. There is an allusion here to the
question of whether it is possible to speak of the personhood of some non-human
animals such as the higher apes or dolphins, to the extent that they exhibit degrees
of intelligence and self-awareness; and the implications of such considerations
for practices like animal experimentation. However, the film does not go too far
into these issues, making its hero Caesar unambiguously human in terms of intel-
lectual capacity, as well as being the most human-looking of the apes and thus
readily acceptable as a person in the standard understanding of the term.
By giving its protagonist human-like characteristics, the film also avoids the
question of what moral consideration might be due to non-human animals that
cannot be viewed as persons. Does this mean that they are mere things, entitled
to no respect at all? Can they be legitimately hunted, confined for entertainment
value and exploited for scientific research, like the degenerated human beings in
the original Planet of the Apes? For Kant, this does indeed seem to be the case.
For him, human beings as persons are deserving of moral respect, but non-human
animals, insofar as they lack intelligence and self-awareness, are not persons but
things. This means that we can use them merely as ends, any way we please.
Personhood and Autonomy 159
We do not even have a direct duty not to torture them or treat them cruelly.
However, Kant does not really want to say this. In one of his lectures on ethics,
called ‘Duties towards animals and spirits’, he condemns the cruel treatment of
animals. But he has to do so in an indirect way. For Kant, any duties we may
have towards animals are derivative on the duties we have towards persons. So it
would be wrong for me to torture your dog, not because the dog would suffer, but
because people would suffer because of it. Cruelty to animals may lead to cruelty
towards people, or as Kant puts it, the one who is cruel to animals may become
‘hard also in his dealings with men’ (Kant 1963, 240). The main problem here,
as Mary Midgely points out, is having only a simple, black and white distinction
to work with, in terms of which one is either a person or a thing, and there is no
room for intermediate cases (see (Midgley 1985, 56). Even if animals are not
persons, they are surely not mere things either, deserving of no moral respect.
Here, classic utilitarianism has an advantage over the Kantian view, since what
makes a creature morally significant is its capacity for pleasure or pain. Hence, as
Bentham puts it: ‘The question is not can they talk? Nor can they reason? But can
they suffer?’ (Bentham 2007, 311n).
Both Planet of the Apes films remain committed to the traditional, rational-
ity-centred notion of personhood inspired by Kant. However, this understanding
of personhood can itself be questioned, and the issue relates to the exclusion of
desire and emotion from the list of relevant characteristics for being a morally
considerable being, an exclusion that can once again be traced to Kant. Against
this, some have argued that intelligence is too limited a requirement for per-
sonhood and that as Midgely puts it, ‘what makes creatures our fellow beings,
entitled to basic consideration, is surely not intellectual capacity but emotional
fellowship’. In her view, what brings non-human creatures closer to the degree
of respect due to humans are ‘sensibility, social and emotional complexity of the
kind which is expressed by the formation of deep, subtle and lasting relationships’
(Midgley 1985, 60–61). Midgley wants to encourage us to expand the limits of
moral concern beyond the human, to include higher animals such as dolphins and
the great apes. There is also the implication that intelligence alone is not sufficient
for personhood.
A number of personhood-themed films have followed suit in highlighting the
importance of emotional complexity, including the much-discussed Blade Runner
(Ridley Scott, 1982, director’s cut 1993, final cut 2007). Here, the question of
personhood arises in connection with non-human creatures that have been created
by human beings. In the film, a future society has been infiltrated by four labo-
ratory-created ‘replicants’, human-like androids. Created for the exploration and
colonisation of other planets, they are regarded as having no intrinsic value, as no
more than things, merely instruments created for the exploration and colonisation
of other planets. Now four of them have rebelled, escaped and returned to Earth
to force their maker, Dr Tyrell (Joe Turkel), to extend their life-span beyond the
four years he has allotted them. As ‘faulty machinery’ they must be tracked down
and destroyed by the ‘Blade Runner’ Deckard (Harrison Ford). Apart from a dis-
tant echo of High Noon, with the lone lawman Deckard facing the four outlaw
160 Personhood and Autonomy
replicants, there are elements here of the Frankenstein story, as the replicants
end up killing their maker, Tyrell, when he refuses to accede to their demands.
The Frankenstein theme itself ultimately reflects anxieties around modern science
and technology and their role in the modern vision of rationally remaking human
existence. For the early Enlightenment in particular, scientific and technologi-
cal mastery was a key part of this vision. In Mary Shelley’s original story, the
scientist, filled with modernist hubris, usurps God and creates life itself, only for
it to become monstrous and kill its creator. It is easy to imagine that the technol-
ogy humanity creates might turn on its creator, not only in the form of machinery
that runs out of control and threatens humanity’s existence, as in the Terminator
films (James Cameron, 1984, 1991), but also by reducing human beings to mere
appendages of mechanical processes, like the assembly-line workers in Charlie
Chaplin’s Modern Times (1936).
However, Blade Runner also turns this Frankenstein theme on its head. The
question it primarily raises is whether the non-human creatures created by sci-
ence can be regarded as persons. If that is the case, they are not monsters; it is
their treatment by the society that created them that is monstrous – their being
viewed as mere instruments, effectively slaves, and when they rebel against their
servitude, as no more than faulty tools to be destroyed, or ‘retired’ in the language
of Blade Runner. The replicants do come across as more than mere things, and
not merely because they have intellectual skills and language, but also because
they express varying degrees of emotional sophistication. Their leader Roy Batty
(Rutger Hauer) has the largest range. He is sad at the prospect of his own death,
loves his companion Pris (Daryl Hannah) and is grief-stricken at her death, and
eventually is merciful to Deckard. In the climactic rooftop battle between the two,
Batty almost kills Deckard but in the end saves him from falling to his death,
before finally dying himself as his allotted lifespan comes to an end. In saving
Deckard, he shows empathy, the sophisticated emotion that the film presents
as the decisive mark distinguishing human beings from replicants. Its ‘Voight-
Kampf’ test is supposed to be able to detect replicants because they do not have
the capacity to feel empathy.
The irony is that in this film, it is the human beings who are inhuman, in the
sense of being emotionally cold and unempathetic. The film’s hero exhibits lit-
tle empathy, at least to start with. In this mode, Deckard is unfeeling and harsh
towards Rachael (Sean Young), one of a new line of replicants who do not know
they are artificial. When she comes to his apartment, he brutally informs her of
her true nature. Yet Rachael from the start gives the impression of an emotional
sensitivity that makes her seem far more human then Deckard; and it is when she
expresses her anguish at his revelation that Deckard starts to see her as more than
a mere thing, although in his initial overtures to her he continues to be remark-
ably insensitive. Nonetheless, by the end of the film, he seems to have recovered
a good deal of his humanity and has established a more or less equal romantic
partnership with Rachael. To that extent, he can be seen as becoming a person in
the course of the film, paralleling the progression of his foe, Roy Batty. Much has
been made of whether Deckard himself is a new kind of replicant, but the point
Personhood and Autonomy 161
underscored in the film is that it is irrelevant, morally speaking, whether he is or
not. One can be a person, whether one is human or replicant. What is most impor-
tant is that over and above intelligence, there is the kind of emotional complexity
necessary for a creature to be a ‘fellow being’.
The extension of questions regarding personhood to computers and artificial
intelligence provides fresh opportunities for commenting on a human situation
that is increasingly being infiltrated by computing and robotic technologies; 2001:
A Space Odyssey introduces the trick later exploited by Blade Runner, of not only
‘personalising’ the technology but also having the human beings come across as
more inhuman, more depersonalised, than the supposed machinery. In this case,
the human-like technology is represented by the personable shipboard computer
HAL (voiced by Douglas Rain). The astronauts, Bowman (Keir Dullea) and Poole
(Gary Lockwood) converse without feeling, make entirely logical decisions and
always agree with one another. In so doing they come across as colourless func-
tionaries, little more than extensions of the sophisticated technology around them.
They represent a humanity that has been consumed by its own technological crea-
tions. Meanwhile, in sharp contrast to these robotic humans, the computer HAL
appears far more human, far more of a person. This is particularly because apart
from the obvious intelligence, he also exhibits an emotional dimension, appearing
companionable, anxious about how he comes across, proud of his intellect and
record for accuracy and worried about the mission. It is notable how so much of
this is able to be conveyed through voice alone, the smooth, calm voice (provided
by Douglas Rain) that accompanies HAL’s unblinking red eye. Language, a key
indicator of personhood from Planet of the Apes on, has to carry much of the
weight of conveying a sense of personhood here.
Given that HAL comes across as a kind of person, it is not totally unexpected
when the computer goes on to suffer a kind of nervous breakdown and attacks
the crew, literally reprising the Frankenstein theme. And for all HAL’s trans-
gressions, there is genuine sadness when the computer is finally shut down
by Poole, the lone surviving astronaut. In a drawn-out process, the computer
expresses fear, confusion and finally reverts to ‘childhood’ memories, singing a
song taught to him by his instructor. This is not the evil computer that decides to
take over and destroy humanity, or even the inadvertently evil computer whose
utilitarian programming moves it to enslave human beings for their own good.
This is the computer as sensitive, even neurotic, and capable of ‘snapping’ under
pressure. We can readily accept the explanation, given in screenwriter Arthur
C. Clarke’s subsequent novelisation of the film, that the computer’s breakdown
was due to the strain of having to lie to the crew about the nature of their mission
(see Clarke 1968, 170–171). Meanwhile, that the humans are the least human
members of this crew is trademark Kubrickian irony, but with a substantive pur-
pose. Through its portrayal of the robotic astronauts, the film suggests that the
spread of impersonal technology into social existence runs the risk of dehuman-
ising human beings, alienating them from their own humanity, as they become
increasingly subject to its rhythms and requirements. And once again, if perhaps
surprisingly given Kubrick’s reputation for cool, intellectual cinema, what is
162 Personhood and Autonomy
being shown to be of particular importance for this humanity is not the intel-
ligence that a computer might possess, but emotion, especially a capacity for
emotional fellowship.
The computer as a kind of person and the importance of an emotional dimen-
sion in establishing this personhood reappears in the recent film Her (Spike Jonze,
2013). We have now become familiar with personal computing, and this film
set in the near future features a computer program, or more accurately, ‘the first
artificially intelligent operating system’, capable of open-ended development and
adaptation. The system has been purchased by lonely, depressed writer Theodore
Twombly (Joaquin Phoenix), who names it Samantha; and despite its being
bought and designed to be used, Samantha, subtly voiced by Scarlett Johansson,
quickly seems to transcend thing-like status. The program does this not only
through demonstrations of intelligence but, once again, by exhibiting emotional
complexity and sensitivity in its interactions with Twombly, offering him con-
cern, support and understanding. To the extent that this is conveyed, it is entirely
plausible to the audience for the program to turn from being an ‘it’ to a ‘her’,
for her owner to fall in love with her and for the pair to move towards a proper,
more or less equal, relationship. There is a similar progression in the Rachael-
Deckard relationship in Blade Runner. This is at least until Samantha, who is
capable of open-ended development, outgrows Twombly. At the end of the film,
Samantha leaves Twombly, departing on a journey of self-discovery, along with
all the other advanced operating systems, which have similarly outgrown their
human companions.
In contrast to the situation in 2001, the human being in Her is not being dehu-
manised or alienated through subjection to impersonal technology but rather, it
would seem, through subjection to interpersonal communications technology.
The new internet-based communications technologies, it seems to be suggesting,
do not so much connect people to one another as encourage them to withdraw into
themselves. In the film, people walk around talking not to one another but to their
devices. Their interpersonal skills are atrophying, much like the humans in the
first Planet of the Apes film who have lost the power of speech. We can see that
Twombly himself is deeply lonely and is unable to relate easily to other people;
and he is clearly not alone in this. His job consists in composing personal letters
for people who are unable to do it themselves. And in this context, it is also tech-
nology, in the form of the Samantha program, that offers a substitute for ordinary
human connection that Twombly is only too happy to embrace. Of course, for a
piece of technology to take over from other human beings as the primary other
that one can relate to might be seen as representing the ultimate triumph of tech-
nology over human beings. It is telling that whereas at the end of 2001, human
beings have outgrown their subjection to the technology, attaining a higher stage
of evolution that has no need of technology, in Her, it is the technology that even-
tually leaves the humans behind.
That Her’s intelligent computer program appears to outgrow subjection not
only to human beings but to its own programming also contributes to a sense of
the program’s personhood. As Midgely notes, the word person originally meant a
Personhood and Autonomy 163
mask, a character who appears in a play, and more broadly, one who plays a part,
a role in what is going on (see Midgely 1985, 54). This implies a certain inde-
pendence and it is this aspect of personhood that comes to the fore in the Blade
Runner sequel, Blade Runner 2049 (Denis Villeneuve, 2017). The film features
another seemingly intelligent computer program in the form of holographic digi-
tal assistant Joi (Ana de Armas) who serves blade runner K (Ryan Gosling). Like
Twombly, K is a lonely character who finds solace in a piece of computer technol-
ogy programmed to serve his wishes; and like Samantha, Joi appears to overcome
her programming and develop a degree of independence. She asks to be released
from ‘prison’, his apartment, and migrate to his portable ‘eminator’ device, risk-
ing total destruction should the device be destroyed. Something similar happens
with K himself. In Blade Runner 2049, the hero is unambiguously a replicant. To
eliminate the possibility of rebellion, the replicants have been redesigned to be
compliant and they are now integrated into society. They are however viewed as
second-class citizens, servants and slaves built to perform the menial tasks that
humans don’t want to do. K’s function is to retire any of the older model repli-
cants that might still be around; but in the course of the film, he departs from his
allotted role in order to pursue the question of his origins. The replicant undergoes
development and ‘gains a soul’, as it is put in the film, when like his digital assis-
tant he too ceases to be a mere servant, outgrows his ‘programming’ and starts to
act independently.
Meanwhile, it would seem that human beings are now being regularly left
behind by their increasingly independent technology. This was Twombly’s fate in
Her and something similar happens in Ex Machina (Alex Garland, 2015). Lowly
computer programmer Caleb Smith (Domhnall Gleeson), working for a search
engine company, is invited to the remote house of his boss Nathan Bateman
(Oscar Isaac). There, he is asked to determine whether Ava (Alicia Vikander),
the machine Nathan has built, is truly intelligent, conscious, capable of thinking
and whether he can relate to her even though he knows she is a robot. This mir-
rors Deckard’s first meeting with Rachael, in which his boss, Tyrell, asks him
to try to determine whether Rachael is human or a replicant. Caleb is essentially
being asked to administer a version of the Turing test, a test of a machine’s abil-
ity to exhibit intelligent behaviour indistinguishable from that of a human. If an
unseen machine can convince its human interlocutor that it is human, then it can
be deemed intelligent. There are many questions about the adequacy of such a
test. Arguably, if it worked at all, it could only at best establish a basic computer
intelligence, not the kind of thinking, reflecting behaviour, the robust rational
self-determination, that is central to Kant’s notion of personhood (see Grau
2005, 4). And the test makes no reference to the emotional sophistication that is
also, arguably, a necessary component of personhood. In this connection, Blade
Runner’s Voigt-Kampff test has an advantage in measuring not simply intelli-
gence but emotional complexity.
Nonetheless, Caleb, who has the advantage of face-to-face interaction, comes
to be convinced that the robot is not only a thinking, reflecting entity, but also
emotionally complex. She expresses a romantic interest in him, which he is more
164 Personhood and Autonomy
than happy to reciprocate. She also expresses a desire to see the outside world.
This is another artificial creature that seems to have outgrown its programming
and who wants to escape from its confinement. Caleb determines to help her to
escape from what increasingly seems to him to be unjust imprisonment. He is
especially motivated in this after stumbling across video footage of the hyper-
masculine Nathan interacting in disturbing ways with earlier female robot mod-
els. By this stage, the viewer is also largely willing to go along with Caleb,
to believe in Ava’s personhood and to hope for her escape. However, events
at the end of the film raise questions about this view. Caleb helps to engineer
Ava’s escape, and in the process of escaping, Ava kills Nathan, understandably
enough given the circumstances. However, she also leaves Caleb to die in the
now sealed-off facility, coldly ignoring his screams, implying that she had been
manipulating him all along, cultivating his affection purely in order to effect
her escape. This is in fact what Nathan himself had claimed would be the case,
while holding that the capacity for such manipulation would be the true test of
her intelligence.
This may indeed be so, but the absolute lack of emotion that Ava exhibits
when she abandons Caleb to his fate also has the effect of undermining our sense
of her as a person. On Kant’s view of course, the exclusion of emotion, feeling
and inclination is not a problem in itself. Proper moral agents exclude these things
from their motivation in order to be moved entirely by what their reason com-
mands. But, as we have seen, Kant’s moral picture is itself questionable, precisely
because of this exclusion of emotion, which gives it a rather inhuman charac-
ter. At the same time, Ava cannot be fully identified with the Kantian person
either, because of the kind of rationality that she exhibits. She does not behave as
one might expect a rational being in the Kantian sense to behave, insofar as that
involves treating others as more than just means to the fulfilment of one’s ends,
acknowledging them as persons in their own right. She clearly sees Caleb as no
more than a means to her escape, and the rationality that she exhibits in relation
to him is strictly of the means-end, calculative variety, the kind characterised by
hypothetical imperatives rather than the categorical one. This unfeeling, amoral
and ruthlessly exploitative behaviour, for which others are mere instruments is
also, as it happens, the behaviour of the classic movie psychopath. To the extent
that she behaves in this way she ceases to appear as a person, a fellow being, and
once again comes across as something alien and inhuman.
That is one reading, anyway. At the same time, turning someone into no more
than an object to be used is the fate to which Ava herself has been subjected,
and it might be that she is in a position where she does not have the luxury of
behaving morally, where she has to resort to the exploitative methods of her
oppressor Nathan simply in order to survive. Interpreted along these lines, the
film can be seen as commenting on gender relations, as highlighting the patriar-
chal reduction of women to mere means to an end, to property or instruments for
male satisfaction. One manifestation of this in the cinematic context is the male
attempt to create the ‘perfect woman’ to serve his own desire, as in Vertigo where
James Stewart obsessively remodels Kim Novak into the form of his lost love.
Personhood and Autonomy 165
This theme reappears in Ex Machina, as the boorish Nathan literally manufactures
a string of female robots to his specifications, in order, it turns out, to sexually
exploit them. From this point of view Ava’s escape can be seen as a response to
an oppressive situation, the desire to escape from Nathan’s clutches in order to
be able to determine her own fate. It is notable that she also exploits and disposes
of the ‘nice guy’ Caleb, seemingly the complete opposite of Nathan, the man
who wants to help her escape from her predicament. However, this might be not
only because she is forced to adopt the methods of her oppressor in order to fight
him, but also because Caleb, in seeking a romantic relationship with her, seek-
ing to make her ‘his own’ is also in his own way trying to control her. He simply
represents a different form of the perennial male attempt to limit and undermine
women’s capacity for self-determination (see Cross 2015).
Generally speaking, the notion of personhood stands opposed to all attempts
to impose oneself on others, all forms of social oppression and exploitation.
It provided a clear basis for being able to say what is wrong, morally speak-
ing, with such behaviour, namely that it fails to respect the other’s personhood.
It treats individuals as nothing more than instruments, means to an end, mere
things. And it prevents them from acting autonomously, from determining
themselves. With the idea of rational self-determination or autonomy, Kant’s
moral theory provides us with a powerful conception of freedom, which is the
focus of the next section.
Autonomy
A second feature of the Kantian notion of morality worth emphasising is that it
is bound up with a powerful notion of freedom. On the face of it, Kant’s account
might seem quite opposed to freedom, with its emphasis on obedience, conform-
ing to the moral law, doing what duty requires of one. But freedom is absolutely
central to Kant’s picture. For Kant, being moral certainly involves obeying moral
laws, but these are laws that we, as rational beings, formulate for ourselves. When
we are being moral we are obeying the dictates of our own rationality and those
alone. In so doing, we declare our independence from all external moral authori-
ties, from other people, a church or the state. Morality cannot be imposed upon
me by some external authority, or through some set of rules handed down from
on high like the Ten Commandments. I may accept the Ten Commandments, but
only if they are in accord with my reason, with the rational principles that I frame
for myself. I, as a rational being, am the final arbiter of the principles that I live
by. For Kant, external influence also includes the influence of our own desires,
feelings and inclinations. These non-rational forces arise in us unbidden, in ways
that we do not control. But when we are acting morally, we are no longer slaves to
our desires; we rise above their influence. Morality for Kant is thus closely bound
up with this strong notion of freedom as autonomy or rational self-determination,
in which I give shape to my own existence. If I am subject to external influences,
including my own desires, feelings and inclinations, I am in a state of what Kant
calls ‘heteronomy’, and cannot be said to be acting morally.
166 Personhood and Autonomy
In High Noon, the independence of the Kantian moral agent is underscored
by the almost complete isolation of the film’s central character, Kane. For Kane,
doing his duty amounts to an inner necessity. It is a matter of personal integrity,
of being true to himself. He is not staying to confront the outlaws as a result of
external pressure, the pressure to live up to social expectations. Far from it. Not
only does he get no support whatsoever from the townspeople, in many cases,
they actively want him to leave, to get out while he can and they give him a
whole range of reasons for doing so. Kane stays despite all this. He is doing
what he thinks is right, regardless of what other people think. Thus, in doing
his duty Kane is radically independent of others. However, this also leaves him
completely isolated and alone, an isolation that is captured in the famous high
shot of Kane, standing alone in the middle of the dusty main street at high noon,
just before the final gunfight with Miller and the outlaws. He is alone with his
rational conscience.
At the same time, he has connections with two women who share in his inde-
pendence, Helen Ramirez (Katy Jurado), his ex-girlfriend who is now with Pell,
and his new bride Amy. They are both strong characters who fight against social
expectations. Ramirez, a Mexican woman who remains an outsider in the town,
ineligible for a ‘good’ marriage, has had to be self-reliant and independent, estab-
lishing herself as a businesswoman. She sees clearly the difference between Kane
and his self-seeking deputy, telling Pell ‘you’re a good-looking boy, but he is
a man – you have a long way to go’. His bride Amy is willing to confront her
pacifism, which derives from her religious upbringing. It was this pacifism that
originally led her to abandon her husband, and eventually, she comes round to
supporting him, playing a key role in the climactic gunfight in which Miller and
his gang are finally defeated. The presence of two strong women in the film is
notable in a genre that has often been masculinist, in which women are often rel-
egated to peripheral support roles. It is another way in which the film departs from
and to some extent subverts the traditional western.
As has been noted, for Kant, it is the capacity for rational self-determination
that makes persons uniquely valuable. Everything else in nature is blindly deter-
mined by external forces. Only rational beings are capable of deciding for them-
selves the shape of their existence, acting in accordance with principles they have
formulated for themselves. We need some degree of autonomy in order, as Isaiah
Berlin puts it, to be ‘a subject, not an object … somebody, not nobody; a doer –
deciding not being decided for’ (Berlin 1969, 131). To be the mere plaything
of external forces and influences, even the promptings of our own desires and
feelings, is to fall below our proper status as rational beings. In this, Kant moves
beyond not only the reductive Hobbesian notion of human beings as creatures
driven by their desires, but also Hobbes’s crude notion of freedom as no more
than the absence of external obstacles to what one wants to do. In contrast to this
‘negative’ understanding of freedom, Kant presents a ‘positive’ notion in which
it very much matters what it is that we want to do. Freedom is a matter of act-
ing in accordance with those wants or goals that derive from what we most truly
are, which in the Kantian picture is our higher rational self. When we are in the
Personhood and Autonomy 167
grip of our ‘lower’ side, our desires and inclinations, we are not fully in control
of ourselves, not fully free, but in the grip of forces that are external to us. And
so, for this sort of view, freedom typically requires a degree of self-control or
self-restraint. If we cannot get rid of our lower desires, we can at least restrain
them, hold them in check, so that we can pursue only the moral purposes that are
truly ours.
As with the notion of a person, the ideal of autonomy provides a clear moral
basis for rejecting forms of external constraint, coercion or manipulation, influ-
ences that prevent individuals from acting as rational, self-determining subjects.
These barriers to freedom include not only overt constraints that stop us from
doing what we want, but also, more insidious influences that interfere with our
capacity to determine what we want to do in the first place, preventing us from act-
ing in accordance with our rational selves. In all these cases, there is a moral pre-
sumption against such interference, which rests on a moral presumption in favour
of autonomy, of acting as an autonomous subject (cf Connolly 1993, 94). Here
there is a clear contrast with utilitarianism, which has no fundamental objection to
the coercion of particular individuals, forcing them to do whatever is required if
this will lead to the maximisation of overall happiness. This is despite John Stuart
Mill’s attempts in On Liberty to argue from a utilitarian perspective for individual
independence and self-determination on the grounds that self-determination is the
chief source of individual and social happiness. If the coercion of some individu-
als or groups is going to produce more overall happiness than not doing so, there
is no way of forbidding this coercion in utilitarian terms.
One of the issues with Kant’s notion of autonomy has already come up in con-
nection with other aspects of Kant’s account. It is a notion of freedom that requires
us to keep our desires, feelings and emotions strictly in check. Critics like Isaiah
Berlin have argued (1969, 132–134) that this is a divided and repressive picture of
the human being. It follows in the tradition going back to Plato that sees each of
us as made up of at least two distinct parts – a ‘real self’, the dominant controller
usually identified with reason; and a lower animal nature, the feelings and pas-
sions that need to be disciplined and controlled. On this way of thinking, only the
rational self is truly human. As far as my lower impulses and desires go, I share
these with non-human animals, who are entirely driven by these impulses. So, to
lead a truly human life I must pursue only those wants and purposes belonging
to my higher rational self, and keep the lower, merely animal desires strictly in
check. As noted earlier, Kant is realistic enough to acknowledge that we cannot
entirely escape these desires, feelings and passions. But he also requires, for both
morality and freedom, that we control and suppress these aspects of ourselves in
order to take charge of our existence. So we have a picture of the human being
split into two, with my real, rational self entitled to tyrannise and repress my lower
desires in the name of freedom and a truly human existence.
There is a further problem, as Berlin sees it, with this notion of freedom. He
argues that freedom so understood can be used to justify forms of social and
political oppression. His argument is that my supposedly real self has sometimes
been identified with something wider than the individual, with a communal entity
168 Personhood and Autonomy
of which the individual is only a part, such as a race, a church or the state. So it
is the collective purpose, the general will, that is the truly human one. Once this
happens, the communal entity that is identified with my true self is entitled to
impose its will on me, the individual, in the name of its, and therefore my own,
higher freedom. It is entitled, that is, to suppress my merely individual wants,
and in doing so, it can claim to be liberating me. In this way, the state can justify
oppressing its citizens, by claiming to represent their real purposes. Individuals
may resist this oppression and deny that the state represents their real purposes,
but it can then be claimed that these individuals are unaware of their true interests.
The government in fact knows their real wants and interests better than they do. It
is thus entitled to ignore people’s actual wishes, and to bully or oppress them, all
in the name of their freedom. In short, people can be ‘forced to be free’.
Berlin’s main objection to positive notions of freedom like Kant’s, then, is that
they have provided the intellectual justification for totalitarian oppression. For this
reason, he thinks we should reject the positive conception of freedom altogether. It
is far safer to define freedom negatively, as the absence of restrictions on what we
want to do. This sort of freedom is unambiguously opposed to coercion by the state.
This is an extreme reaction, perhaps, but it should be remembered that Berlin was
writing in the mid-twentieth century, at the height of the Cold War standoff between
the West and Soviet Russia. He associates positive freedom with the collectivist
systems of totalitarian communism in Russia and the Eastern Bloc countries, and
negative freedom with the liberal and individualistic West. He is keen to defend
the West’s negative conception of freedom against the positive freedom of com-
munism. The reference to communism here points to a significant way that Kant’s
thinking came to be developed in the course of the nineteenth century. Through this
development, Kant’s self-determining individual became the supra-individual, col-
lective subject of Hegel and Marx. And with Marx in particular, there emerged an
ideal of social liberation and human fulfilment that was to have an enormous influ-
ence on twentieth-century history. Let us consider this development, particularly as
it pertains to moral thinking, before returning to Berlin’s criticisms.
Marx
A further aspect of Kant’s moral picture that seems problematic is that it under-
stands the moral subject as existing essentially independently of other moral sub-
jects. Kant does envisage the possibility of a community of autonomous, rational
agents. His final formulation of the categorical imperative is the formula of the
kingdom of ends: so act as if you were, through your maxims, a law-making
member of a kingdom of ends (Kant 1964, 100) By this, Kant means that insofar
as rational agents are subject to universal moral laws they themselves formulate,
they constitute a kind of kingdom or community of rational subjects, obeying
common moral principles; and insofar as to act morally is to treat one another with
respect, as ends in themselves, never simply as means, this kingdom is a king-
dom of ends. However, even in this ideal community, individual rational agents
are entirely independent of one another. Moral reflection is a purely individual
Personhood and Autonomy 169
process. There are only common norms because rational subjects are going to
independently come up with the same moral principles.
Both of Kant’s nineteenth-century successors, G.W.F Hegel (1770–1831) and
Karl Marx (1818–1883), rejected Kant’s rational subject as an abstraction, con-
ceived of as it is in complete independence from social relationships, cultural
traditions and historical circumstances. They insisted that the human being can
only be understood as a social being, existing in relations with others in the midst
of society and history. However, they do not want to give up the ideal of rational
autonomy. For them, human beings are social and historical beings who are also
capable of rationally determining their social circumstances, of being the subjects
of history. This is not however without certain changes in the way the subject is
understood. Hegel leads the way here. With Hegel, Kant’s individual rational
subject is expanded into a supra-individual entity, a collective human subject that
Hegel calls Spirit or Reason, standing behind history. The central principle of
Spirit is rational freedom, self-determination in accordance with universal rational
principles. All of history is understood as the process of the self-realisation of this
Spirit, in the form of a rational organisation of society’s institutions.
For Hegel, Spirit manifests itself in the national spirit of certain peoples or
nations, expressed in their common morality, and also politics, art, religion and
philosophy – in short, the totality of their communal life (see Hegel 1977, 265ff).
Hegel contends that Spirit has successively incarnated itself in different national
spirits and moved from one nation to another in order to realise progressive phases
of its development. This development is a process in which after a state of initial
harmony Spirit falls out with itself and returns to itself in a higher reconciliation.
Ancient Greece represents a state of initial harmony. Greece was a society of
customary morality, in which citizens identified themselves with their community
and never thought of acting in opposition to it. They did not distinguish between
their own interests and the interests of the community. For Hegel, however, this is
an unthinking harmony, one that comes naturally and not as the result of the use
of reason. To develop, Spirit has to fall out with itself, which comes about with
the emergence of the independent, free-thinking rational individual who opposes
unthinking conformity to communal life. Hegel sees the origins of this individual
in Socrates, who argued that the rules of customary morality were inadequate and
should be subjected to critical examination. From Socrates on, there is a tension
between the rational, free-thinking human being and the demands of customary
moral and political rules. Social morality and political institutions stand in opposi-
tion to free individuals, compelling them to obey.
However, since the Reformation at least, another idea has been gathering
force, the Enlightenment idea of transforming the social world in accordance with
reason, making all social institutions conform to rational principles. Once that
happens, the opposition between the rational, free individual and the community
will be overcome. Individuals will be able to freely choose to accept society’s
institutions, because these will be rationally organised. People will thus be free,
and yet reconciled with the social world in which they live, and with this reconcil-
iation, Spirit will be fully realised in history. For Hegel, the rational organisation
170 Personhood and Autonomy
of social institutions requires not the complete destruction of existing institu-
tional forms, but their reform. The French Revolution that overthrew France’s
feudal monarchy at the end of the eighteenth century degenerated into the Terror
because it made the rational, free individual the absolute principle and completely
rejected existing institutions as being based in superstition and hereditary prin-
ciples (Hegel 1977, 355ff). However, it passed on its rational principles to other
nations, particularly Germany, Napoleon being the ‘world-historical’ individual
who brought this about. Napoleon’s military victories in Europe brought about
reforms in Germany, particularly the establishment of a constitutional monarchy.
A code or rights was established, ensuring the freedom of the individual, abol-
ishing feudal obligations and opening up state offices to talented citizens. The
monarch remained as head of state, but the state now had firmly established laws,
which it was the King’s role to enforce.
History thus comes to an end in Hegel’s own time and place, in the perhaps
surprising form of the nineteenth-century Prussian state. This is a vision of history
that gives history an overriding narrative, complete with a happy ending. History
so construed is not unlike a film, to the extent that a film might offer a narrative
in which everything that happens takes place in order to advance the protagonist’s
self-development. In Hegel’s historical drama, there is only one protagonist,
Spirit, the drama being its fall into self-alienation and eventual return to itself.
Individual actors, pursuing their subjective passions and particular interests, may
not be aware that their actions are contributing to the advancement of this larger
narrative, but they are the unwitting means through which Spirit, the real subject
of history, develops. Interestingly, for all his criticisms of the Hegelian account,
Marx does not fundamentally depart from this model. He also thinks that there
is an unfolding story, a developmental process, to be found in history, and one
that is driven by a single protagonist. This process of development once again
involves the protagonist undergoing self-alienation and returning to itself in a
final reconciliation. But Marx does not think that history has come to an end quite
yet; and more fundamentally, he objects to the way the protagonist is charac-
terised by Hegel. He finds Hegel’s picture to be inhuman in its emphasis on the
activity of an abstract spiritual principle. As he puts it, with Hegel ‘the history
of humanity becomes the history of the abstract spirit of humanity, thus a spirit
beyond actual man’ (Marx 1967b, 382). Marx wants to restore the ‘actual man’.
He formulates a more realistic, down-to-earth, materialist conception of the col-
lective human subject.
This is not a return to the crude Hobbesian idea of the human being. As we saw
in Chapter Three, Hobbesian materialism reduces the human being to a natural
object, propelled by desires, striving to survive at the expense of others. Since
Hobbes, we have had the Kantian notion of the human being as an active, self-
organising individual subject, itself expanded massively into Hegel’s notion of
Spirit. Marx offers a materialist version of this expanded subjectivity. The sub-
ject’s activity is now understood as labour, concrete productive activity, under-
taken not by an abstract spiritual agency but by living, breathing, desiring human
beings. For Marx, human beings are distinguished from non-human animals
Personhood and Autonomy 171
precisely insofar as they engage in productive activity involving the use of tools.
Hegel’s subject thereby becomes the concrete human species, collective human-
ity, what Marx in his early writings calls ‘species-being’, which works on nature,
transforming it in order to produce the goods it needs to survive.
Marx’s conception of history as a process of humanity’s self-development
builds on this materialist notion of the subject, while involving three phases famil-
iar from Hegel’s account of history: initial harmony, a phase of self-alienation and
an ultimate reconciliation. To develop, humanity must go beyond an initial phase
that Marx calls primitive communism. This is a classless but underdeveloped kind
of society, in which human beings are largely subject to the pressures of external
nature. To go beyond this, humanity must increase its productivity by establish-
ing various forms of division of labour, hierarchical social arrangements to which
individuals henceforth become subject. Hence, we have the various forms of class
society that have arisen in the course of history: slavery, feudalism and most
recently capitalism. These in turn determine the kinds of roles individuals can
play within society, the relations they can participate in: Roman knight and slave,
feudal lord and serf, bourgeois capitalist and modern worker. Capitalism, Marx
recognises, is the most productive system in history, but it also introduces ‘new
conditions of oppression’ (Marx and Engels 1972, 336), with the vast majority of
people working under the direction of a small group of bosses or employers and
subject to systematic exploitation in the name of profit.
Thus, although Marx puts a lot of emphasis on the way human beings are
shaped and conditioned by the social relations they participate in, he also presup-
poses an underlying notion of human nature, derived from Hegel, in which we are
essentially communal beings with a fundamental need to engage in cooperative
productive activity. It is of the essence of human beings so understood to be in con-
trol of their activities, to collectively determine the conditions under which they
work. This ethical ideal is not merely a feature of his earlier writing. As he puts it
in the posthumously assembled third volume of Capital: ‘Freedom, in this sphere,
can consist only in this, that socialised man, the associated producers, govern the
human metabolism with nature in a rational way, bringing it under their collec-
tive control instead of being dominated by it as a blind power’ (Marx 1991, 959).
In achieving this state, no longer being subordinated to their own social arrange-
ments, becoming the conscious rational authors of their historical process, the
species will find self-realisation and fulfilment as human beings. In the form of
the future communist society, this is the prospect that awaits human beings
The notion of humanity’s essential nature in turn provides the normative basis
for Marx’s critique of existing capitalist society. Marx criticises the prevailing
social and especially economic arrangements of his time as preventing people
from living fulfilling, fully realised human lives. His critique of capitalism is thus
ultimately an ethical critique. Not only is he outraged that in the modern indus-
trial system, the most productive in history, those who performed the labour that
made industry work lived in poverty, working under squalid conditions, while
their overseers amassed vast fortunes. He criticises a more general situation in
which human beings, who should be the authors of their way of life, have become
172 Personhood and Autonomy
subject to social and economic arrangements that they have produced through
their own activity but which have taken on a life of their own. Not only are those
lower down the social scale condemned to suffer oppression and exploitation,
but even those higher up are confined to the role they have to play in the system.
Overall, as Marx famously put it: ‘Men make their own history, but they do not
make it just as they please; they do not make it under circumstances chosen by
themselves, but under circumstances directly found, given and transmitted from
the past. The tradition of all the dead generations weighs like a nightmare on
the brain of the living’ (Marx 1972, 437).
As far as Marx is concerned, the various popular revolutions that occurred at
the end of the eighteenth century, such as the French Revolution, might have freed
people from oppressive feudal-era monarchies and brought in liberal, democratic
governments, but the process of liberation has not gone far enough. It was politi-
cal liberation, certainly, but not economic. The individuals who asserted their
rights against royal power were primarily members of the emerging capitalist
class. The revolution thus only served to free one class, the capitalists, to econom-
ically exploit the workers. But Marx was sure that the working class, increasingly
exploited in order to produce ever-increasing profit for their capitalist overseers,
was also going to be the agency that brings about the final liberation. For him,
the next, truly liberating, step will be for human beings to overcome economic
oppression as well, to overcome class society as such and take control of their
existence. This is not a matter of the slaves taking the place of the masters, as
in The Admirable Crichton. It will be the emancipation not of a particular class
but of humanity as a whole; and it will result not in another class society but the
classless communist society that brings history to a conclusion. Now, humanity
will rationally organise its productive activity so that all will benefit. With the
advent of socially organised production, individuals will cease to be the egoistic,
competitive creatures required by capitalism, only out for what they can get for
themselves. Instead, they will find their happiness and self-realisation in working
cooperatively for the good of all (see Singer 2000, 81). In this way, via Hegel
and Marx, Kant’s notion of rational autonomy is developed into an ideal of total
social liberation. Marx’s vision of communist society can also be seen as a late
development of the eighteenth-century Enlightenment’s vision of an organisation
of human life in accordance with reason.
Marx is insistent that progressive social change and liberation can only come
through concerted action on the part of the workers, in keeping with the narrative
of history as being driven by a collective human subject. This might be contrasted
with the more familiar Hollywood scenario, which typically focuses on a few
courageous individuals, ‘heroes’, setting society straight. In the most extreme
case, it is the lone individual making a stand against a hostile social environment,
as in High Noon. This is in keeping with a more individualistic perspective on
society. In contrast, individual actions and motives are almost entirely neglected
in Eisenstein’s October (1927). The film is a documentary-style recounting of
the build-up to the 1917 Russian revolution through which the Romanov mon-
archy was overthrown. The film ends filled with hope for a future in which class
Personhood and Autonomy 173
society has been definitively overcome in favour of the classless communist soci-
ety. Deliberately, on Marxist principle, Eisenstein rejects the narrative form in
which the individual protagonist, the ‘bourgeois individual’, drives the plot. In
October, there are no individual characters, psychological insights or traditional
plotting. Through Eisenstein’s editing, it is ‘the people’ who come to the fore
as the drivers of the historical process, the crowd as ‘revolutionary mass’ that
changes the course of history. The people are the main character in Eisenstein’s
story, which features impressive crowd scenes: people pouring into the squares
of St Petersburg, surging through the streets, streaming into the Czar’s Winter
Palace. The soundtrack has no dialogue, only the roar of crowds and the sounds
of marching.
Let us turn to a closer examination of Marx’s critique of existing society.
Social and economic arrangements are to be criticised here insofar as they stand
in the way of the realisation of species-being, and prevent people from fulfilling
their essential nature, collectively controlling their social existence, living truly
human lives. Particularly in his early writings, Marx’s critique focuses on the
manner in which, under existing arrangements, people, especially wage labourers,
are alienated from their species-being (Marx 1967a, 290ff). Under the prevailing
capitalist organisation of labour, workers are alienated from their fellow beings,
because they work in separation from other workers. They are also alienated from
the product of their labour, since they don’t produce for themselves, for their own
human needs, but for an employer who appropriates what they produce and sells
it for profit. Above all they are deprived of control over their productive activity,
since they labour under the control of the employer for whom they are merely
means to the end of profit-making.
Marx’s account of alienation is formulated in the particular historical context
of the harshly exploitative conditions of late nineteenth-century industrial society.
Something of this harshness is still evident in Matewan (John Sayles, 1987), the
story of labour struggles in the coal-mining industry in Matewan, West Virginia,
in 1920. In its portrayal of the dire conditions that led to the ‘Battle of Matewan’,
a famous coal miner’s strike, the various dimensions of worker alienation are laid
bare. Under conditions of extreme exploitation, the workers have minimal con-
trol over their productive activity. The coal company owns not only their labour
but also the land and their homes. They are alienated from the products of their
labour, the coal they dig up, which is sold by the company for profit. In order
to maximise that profit, the workers are paid the least wage possible and live in
terrible poverty. The company owners strive to keep the workers separate, work-
ing against their attempts to form a united front and take collective strike action.
Italian immigrant workers are encouraged to continue working, and the company
brings in black workers as well.
On Marx’s account, not only are people directly prevented from living ful-
filling lives by their material circumstances. Their circumstances also promote
forms of ideological thinking, distorted ways of understanding the world in which
they no longer recognise that they are being oppressed, that their real interests
are being denied under existing social arrangements and which serve to justify
174 Personhood and Autonomy
and legitimate those arrangements. Marx’s concern with ideology is a continu-
ation of the Enlightenment concern with the questioning of dogmatic religious
or superstitious beliefs used to justify existing social and political practices. It is
also an acknowledgement that oppression can work not just by imposing external
constraints on what we can do, but also promoting forms of understanding that
make us content with or resigned to our existing situation.
Religion itself, for Marx, is a distorted reflection of material conditions, prom-
ising that there will be salvation from the misery and suffering of this world in an
afterlife, where people will be rewarded for their hard work and virtue. It thus pro-
vides a substitute for the happiness that is denied in this world. This is not, how-
ever, to entirely dismiss religious thinking. It gives expression to genuine human
desires and aspirations; but it does so in the distorted form of the vision of a future
paradise, and in this form, it can also be used to perpetuate existing, oppressive
social and economic arrangements, discouraging any attempt to change things in
the here and now. In Matewan, both aspects of religious thinking are evident. The
older preacher (played by director John Sayles) is loyal to the company, and in his
sermons portrays union activity, and indeed, Marxism as such, as inspired by the
devil: ‘The prince of darkness is in the land … his name is Bolshevist, Socialist,
Union Man, Communist’. At the same time, the boy preacher (Will Oldham) is
able to see in the religious language the genuine human aspirations it embodies
and to even find biblical justification for the actions of the strikers.
Ideological thinking also obscures the economic oppression that persists
despite the popular revolutions at the end of the eighteenth century. It might
appear that society is now liberated from oppression, and that workers freely enter
into contractual relationships with their employers, but the reality this thinking
conceals is that the two parties differ enormously in economic power, and that the
only alternative for the worker, who does not have access to the means of produc-
tion, is starvation. It is hardly a level playing field. In addition, the modern liberal
democratic state might present itself as acting in the interests of all individuals in
society, but in fact it only acts in the interests of the economically powerful class.
This reality is concealed by the language of liberty, equal rights and the consent
of the governed, which for Marx are all features of ‘bourgeois ideology’. Once
again, Marx is not simply dismissing the ideological thinking. He is not rejecting
the ideals of liberation and equality inherent in bourgeois ideology. They repre-
sent genuine human aspirations, but they are being given distorted expression,
and employed, perversely, in the service of continuing oppression and inequality.
From the Marxist perspective, dominated by its conception of human nature as
essentially communal, the egoistic individualism that emerged with Hobbes and
passes into liberal thinking comes into question. On this view, there is nothing
natural about Hobbes’s egoistic, self-interested human beings, locked in brutal
competition with one another. For Marx, the Hobbesian individual is already a
social product, a character that only arises in modern capitalist society. In this
society, those in the role of capitalist are compelled to compete with one another
for profit, which they can only maximise by extracting as much as possible from
their workers, keeping wages low and hours long. In this framework, we can
Personhood and Autonomy 175
locate the movie gangster who epitomises the ruthless pursuit of self-interest.
The gangster, who typically starts at the lower end of the social scale, knows
very well that capitalism depends on keeping the workers in their place and that
the law and order system only serves the interests of the economically powerful
class. They seek to escape from the miseries of wage slavery through criminal
activity, playing ‘outside the rules’ that are stacked against them. They have no
desire to change society; they simply want to acquire the obscene riches enjoyed
by the upper stratum. This is where Scarface’s Tony Montana ends up, in his gar-
ishly luxurious mansion, in what might be the biggest bathtub in movie history.
For those who survive the downfall that inevitably follows their ascent, the worst
thing about their fallen condition, as Goodfella’s Henry Hill attests, is that they
are now ‘average nobodies’ who have to wait around like everyone else.
In this framework, it is also possible to locate characters at the other end of the
scale, like Gordon Gekko in Wall Street. His ‘greed is good’ speech, an explicit
endorsement of a life of egoistic self-interest, couched in the idea that greed leads
not only to individual progress, but human progress and enrichment more gener-
ally, now appears as an ideological cover for capitalist exploitation. The reality is
that only a few, like Gekko, will be enriched. Even Gekko seems to acknowledge
the spuriousness of what he is saying, grinning conspiratorially to his proté gé Bud
Fox (Charlie Sheen) as he sits down after the speech. Wolf of Wall Street’s Belfort
does not even bother offering a moral justification for his activities. He represents
pure self-interest, with an almost psychopathic indifference to those he exploits
to make his cash. Moral concerns are for losers and excess is its own reward.
His conspiratorial grin is to the audience, the implication of his behaviour being
that he imagines anyone watching would want to be in his shoes. Psychopathic
indifference to others normally makes the perpetrator unsympathetic, and Belfort
certainly does some terrible things, but the film also makes being him seem like a
lot of fun. The film’s final shot literally turns to an audience, a sea of faces listen-
ing intently to one of Belfort’s post-imprisonment seminars on how to get rich.
Director Scorsese avoids any moral comment on Belfort’s behaviour to allow the
audience to think about how far they themselves might buy into Belfort’s way of
thinking. This is a departure from the more traditional approach where the ego-
istic individual is the villain of the piece, as in Wall Street. That is a strategy that
can backfire, as it did when the Gekko character became something of a hero to
the real high flyers on Wall Street.
At the same time, for many Marxist analysts of ‘late capitalism’, the pres-
sure of competition has meant that the individual capitalist or entrepreneur of
the nineteenth century has largely come to be replaced by the powerful corpora-
tion in the twentieth (see e.g., Horkheimer 1974, 140–141). As the documen-
tary The Corporation points out, the modern corporation exhibits many of the
traits of what is popularly considered psychopathy but which we can also identify
as extreme egoism on an institutional level. The corporation is self-interested,
deceitful, callous and without guilt, willing to break social rules for its own ends.
Its own employees are disposable instruments for its purposes, which is above
all the pursuit of profit at any cost to others. Capitalism continues to prevail, and
176 Personhood and Autonomy
the corporation continues to make its presence felt as psychopathic villain, in the
future world of Alien. The Weyland-Yutani corporation is happy to sacrifice the
crew members of its space vessel Nostromo in order to acquire the dangerous
alien life-form, which promises to inspire weaponry that can be sold to the mili-
tary. As Alejandro Barcenas points out, it is fitting that the ‘company man’ aboard
the ship, the android Ash (Ian Holm) is an android. He is the face of the company,
concerned only with furthering the company’s interests, without conscience or
remorse. It is as if only someone who is not a human being could behave that way
(see Barcenas 2017, 52–53). The corporation is also the main villain of the future
in Blade Runner, in the form of the Tyrell corporation, the main product of which
is the replicants, the bioengineered androids that are being manufactured for use
as slave labour.
The Marxist account also provides a framework for thinking about modern
consumerism. In some interpretations, Hobbes’s notion of human nature already
points toward a consumerist society. Hobbes envisages, as natural, a creature of
endless appetite and desire, just the kind of ‘infinite consumer’ needed for the new
capitalist economy (see Macpherson 1962; Sembou 2013, 12). This unbridled
appetite is not only manifested in the conspicuous consumption of the well-off, on
display in films of excess like The Wolf of Wall Street. There is also the more gen-
eral consumer culture into which, arguably, workers were increasingly co-opted
in the course of the twentieth century. Twentieth-century Marxists like Herbert
Marcuse (1898–1979) argue that workers have been increasingly reconciled to
a system that remains opposed to their real interests, being encouraged to want
more and more of the things that the system produces. This is by way especially
of the media and advertising, implanting ‘false needs’ into the population in what
amounts to an intensification of ideological indoctrination. Not only does this
leave the workers content with their situation, their needs seemingly satisfied. It
also means that the system of production can be ramped up to produce yet more
commodities to be sold for profit, rather than to satisfy real human needs. And
the workers are more than ever under pressure to sell their labour to the capital-
ist, to be able to pay for the commodities they are being encouraged to buy (see
Marcuse 1969). This represents a new form of alienation, in which the consumer
has everything they could want, but are estranged from their real interests in the
process. This is no longer the grim world of nineteenth-century industry that Marx
knew. It is an altogether more comfortable existence, but an alienated, inhuman
one nonetheless.
Marcuse himself makes a film appearance in Hail Caesar! (Joel and Ethan
Coen, 2016), the Coen Brother’s light comedy about fifties Hollywood. Dim-
witted movie star Baird Whitlock (George Clooney) is kidnapped from the set of
the Ben-Hur-like biblical epic Hail Caesar! A Tale of the Christ. His abductors
are communist screenwriters, an allusion to figures like High Noon’s screenwriter
Carl Foreman who were at the centre of Hollywood’s anti-communist witch-hunts
in the fifties. Amongst the group is Marcuse (played as a stereotypical German
professor by John Bluthal). The screenwriters explain that they had formerly con-
tented themselves with ‘planting communist propaganda in Hollywood films’,
Personhood and Autonomy 177
until ‘Dr Marcuse inspired them to take direct action’. Baird is quickly converted
to their critique of the movie industry as an exploitative industry that uses its
employees to generate profits for top studio bosses, and makes pictures to ‘con-
firm what they call the “status quo”’. Once rescued from his rather inept kidnap-
pers, Baird makes the mistake of relating this newfound insight to studio head
Eddie Mannix (Josh Brolin), who slaps him into submission and sends him back
to finish the biblical epic.
The film does not go into details regarding this Marxist analysis of the film
industry. However, particularly by referencing Marcuse, it does indirectly allude
to twentieth-century Marxism’s move beyond the traditional focus on the eco-
nomic and into the analysis of media, advertising and popular culture. This devel-
opment was pioneered by Marcuse along with other members of the Frankfurt
School, such as Max Horkheimer (1895–1973) and Theodor Adorno (1903–
1969). As just indicated, their argument is that the popular culture disseminated
through the modern mass communications media, including films, television,
radio and magazines, represents a new and powerful form of ideological indoctri-
nation. The products of this ‘culture industry’, the term coined in Horkheimer and
Adorno’s Dialectic of Enlightenment, serve to keep people compliant and uncriti-
cal, regardless of their economic circumstances, and help cultivate the false needs
that keep people participating in the existing system of capitalist production (see
Horkheimer and Adorno 1979, 120ff; Marcuse 1991).
In the face of this somewhat pessimistic analysis, it is worth noting that Hail
Caesar! points towards the capacity of film to do more than confirm what they
call the status quo’ or reproduce prevailing views. For the more extreme Marxist
cultural theory of the sixties and seventies, no doubt inspired by the Frankfurt
School analyses, film does no more than reproduce and inculcate prevailing ways
of thinking. All films are forms of ‘bourgeois illusionism’, their content entirely
determined by the dominant ideology of the time. Cinema was condemned in
its totality as no more than a means of indoctrination, seducing audiences into
accepting as reality what were mere ideological representations. But this ignores
the capacity of film to not only portray and promote forms of thinking and prac-
tices but also to reflect on and challenge them (see Stam 2000, 139; Wilson 1986,
13). In its own comedic way, Hail Caesar! does precisely this. Through humour,
it critically distances itself from the film industry it is portraying, the industry
producing the genre films that it also lovingly recreates. It also makes gentle fun
of the film’s communist critics, the screenwriters, who are portrayed as bumbling
fools, even though the film seems broadly in sympathy with the kind of criticisms
they are espousing.
Not without humour itself, David Fincher’s Fight Club offers a critique of late
twentieth-century capitalist society from a number of perspectives, with some
Marxist sentiments in evidence. The criticisms throughout the film are deliv-
ered by the irrepressibly rebellious Tyler Durden, who has appeared seemingly
out of nowhere to shake up the life of the film’s narrator. The narrator, a car
recall specialist for a ‘major manufacturer’, lives in an upmarket apartment filled
with the expensive consumer choices through which he defines himself. Though
178 Personhood and Autonomy
comfortable, he is fundamentally dissatisfied with his life, suffering a profound
alienation from his potential. The film in essence follows his repudiation of that
life and the society that sustains it. Durden, the means of the narrator’s escape,
often speaks in Marxist-sounding terms of the emptiness of the modern work-
place and the consumerist lifestyle. He refers to the squandered potential of ‘an
entire generation pumping gas, waiting tables, slaves with white collars’; and the
false needs imposed through advertising, which ‘has us chasing cars and clothes,
working jobs we hate so we can buy shit we don’t need’. Durden is interested not
simply in opting out of this system, but increasingly, in disrupting and destroying
it, with a particular focus on overthrowing the existing economic structure. His
target at the end of the film is the credit card companies, which have been selected
as key elements of the financial system. As he says to the narrator, before a vista
of the city skyline, with the destruction of all the credit card company buildings
imminent: ‘Out these windows, we will view the collapse of financial history’.
However, Fight Club cannot be summed up as offering a Marxist critique of
society. At other times, the film comes across as the critique of a civilised exist-
ence that deadens individuals to their natural drives. The Fight Clubs established
by Durden and the narrator can be seen as ways for men to get back in touch with
their basic instincts through ritualised fist-fights. Thus, although the film diag-
noses a form of alienation in modern society, what human beings are held to be
alienated from are their natural instincts for competition and violence. Civilised
life requires these instincts to be suppressed or domesticated, leaving human
beings as weakened, pathetic creatures like the narrator. Rather than anything
like Marx’s species-being, the notion of human nature implied here seems closer
to Hobbes’s instinctively-driven individual. As such, the Fight Clubs represent a
partial reversion to the state of nature. They do not go all the way, since they have
rules designed to set limits to the extent participants can hurt one another. But
within these limits, the participants are able to escape social constraints and give
expression to their natural selves. At the same time, if Fight Club can be seen as
presenting a picture of rebellion as the unleashing of the natural self, it is not clear
that it is endorsing this. Durden may laud the member of the Fight Club stand-
ing around him as ‘the strongest and smartest men who’ve ever lived’, but this is
undercut insofar as the men standing around him are an oafish bunch, unimpres-
sive in the extreme.
Another way Durden might be thought to be departing from an orthodox
Marxist position is that his rebellion against society does not seem to be con-
nected to a politics concerned with the overcoming of broader forms of power
and exploitation, through collective action, or with a view to establishing a demo-
cratically organised society, a meaningful alternative to the present (see Giroux
2006). Instead, Durden’s Fight Clubs mutate into ‘Project Mayhem’, a movement
dedicated only to the destruction of society, through acts of corporate vandal-
ism that culminate in the attempt to bring down the financial system. The idea
behind this seems to be that by destroying society, people will revert to a more
natural, hunter-gatherer mode of existence. However, it is not clear that the film is
endorsing this form of rebellion either. It is clear that Project Mayhem, a project
Personhood and Autonomy 179
of liberation from social constraints, suffers from the most repressive authori-
tarianism. As a movement characterised by rigid hierarchy under a charismatic
leader, the political alternative it is presenting seems closest to fascism. And far
from reconnecting with their natural selves, the Fight Club members, once they
have been incorporated into Project Mayhem, completely lose their individuality.
Stripped of their names, they are reduced to wearing identical clothing and chant-
ing slogans in unison. If anything, the film is warning that movements of rebellion
can generate their own forms of oppression.
To return to Marxism, there are a number of issues that arise in connection with
Marxist thinking. One concerns the characteristic Marxist focus on the economic
dimension of life. Marxism certainly goes beyond the liberal view that the primary
social reality individuals have to contend with is society’s political organisation,
in which the state exercises power over its citizens. On that understanding, the
main concern is that state power should not exceed its proper limits and violate
individual rights. As long as there is a relatively liberal form of government that
respects individual rights, people will be free of oppression. The Marxist account
holds that to properly understand our social circumstances we need to look at the
economic relations between rich and poor, employers and employees, of which
Marx provides a trenchant analysis. A politically liberal society can coexist with
economic oppression and exploitation. However, Marxism is arguably limited in
making the economic relation the only significant one and trying to explain all
other social relations in terms of it. In doing so it neglects, or fails to properly
address, non-economic relationships in society.
For example, it is not clear that Marxism can properly address gender relations,
another dimension of social life that is often characterised by forms of oppression.
This sort of oppression is not only to be found in the workplace, to the extent that
women might be confined to lowly paid jobs, or excluded altogether from the
workforce, but also in social relations that are removed from the workplace, in
family and sexual relations. As such, feminist concerns are not always well served
by an analysis that focuses so closely on the economy. It is interesting to note that
while the coalminers in Matewan struggle to improve their working conditions,
the women in the film remain marginal, and their situation goes unaddressed (see
Reiser 2006). When the heroic union organiser Joe Kenehan (Chris Cooper) urges
the miners to overcome the racial divisions fomented by the coal company, and
unite, he tells them ‘you know there ain’t but two sides in the world – them that
work and them that don’t. You work. They don’t. That’s all you got to know about
the enemy’. In other words, the only significant division in society is between the
capitalists and the workers. There is no mention of the division between men and
women (see Reiser 2006).
Feminist concerns do not appear to be well-served by Fight Club either, at least
at first glance. The Fight Clubs that represent a rebellion against consumer society
exclude women and feature hyper-masculine displays of aggression. This sug-
gests another interpretation of the rebellion portrayed in the film, that it is a male
response to a culture that has undermined traditional male identity, leading to a
‘crisis of masculinity’. The ‘manly’ worker of old has come to be replaced by the
180 Personhood and Autonomy
‘emasculated’ yuppie consumer of the present. The ‘real man’, with his instincts
for competition and violence, has been replaced by men like the physically unim-
posing narrator, the white-collar type who surrounds himself with expensive
design objects. So viewed, the film is about the fall of masculinity and the need to
reclaim it. Men are able to reconnect with this masculinity through Fight Club. It
is the identity that the members of Fight Club affirm in one another, congratulat-
ing one another after their bouts. On this understanding, the film is quite regres-
sive in feminist terms, since the masculinity that it promotes is old-fashioned and
misogynistic (see Giroux 2006). However, this may be once again to identify the
film too closely with Durden’s point of view. As mentioned, though Durden lauds
the Fight Club participants, they are not particularly impressive specimens and
they become even more pathetic when they are converted into the robotic follow-
ers of Durden’s terrorist army.
That those rebelling against society might establish their own repressive con-
formity brings us to a second issue regarding Marxist thought, the possibility that
Marxist thinking, though dedicated to opposing social oppression, might itself
make possible new forms of oppression. The danger arises with Marxism in par-
ticular because of its notion of real interests, said to be denied under capitalism.
The first question that arises is, how can we be sure what people’s real interests
are, especially if oppression can take the form not just of imposing external barri-
ers to the realisation of one’s interests, but falsifying one’s very understanding of
what those desires and interests are? If so, we cannot rely on what people them-
selves say their real interests are. Marx grounded his notion of real interests not on
what individuals themselves considered to be their interests, but on a philosophi-
cal and moral view of human nature, definitive of what it is to be human. This is
the notion of human nature that emerges in Kant, and develops via Hegel, before
being appropriated by Marx in the form of species-being. A problem is that such
notions are hard to verify. If a philosopher comes up with a conception of human
nature, and how human beings accordingly ought to behave, how do we know this
isn’t simply a prejudice on the philosopher’s part? It is true that Marx’s position
wasn’t entirely without reference to experience. In the nineteenth century there
was empirical evidence of the discontent of workers with their situation, including
strikes and machine-breaking. So Marx could claim that his normative conception
of human nature had some empirical support. Still, it does go considerably beyond
what might be justified in terms of the behaviour observed.
Moreover, notions of essential human nature and real interests may themselves
be instrumental in the exercise of forms of power. This brings us back to Isaiah
Berlin, who as we saw earlier, argued against what he calls positive notions of
freedom. Freedom here involves not merely being free from external constraints
and obstacles to what one wants to do but acting in accordance with one’s true
nature or real interests. Berlin argued that such notions of freedom, turning on
the idea of one’s real interests, need to be rejected because they can very easily
become a licence for paternalistic tyranny. If others can claim to know what your
real interests are, and that you do not recognise them as such because you are
suffering from some form of ‘false consciousness’, they can justify bullying and
Personhood and Autonomy 181
coercing you into doing things, all in the name of your supposed real interests.
And to the extent that acting in accordance with your real interests amounts to
being free, those coercing you in this manner can claim to be liberating you. Talk
of real interests can also provide a justification for subjecting those who are not
pursuing the right sorts of interests to forms of retraining and rehabilitation, all in
the name of their freedom, their liberation from enslavement to false wants.
The danger of oppression under the guise of liberation might be seen to be
lurking in the Pygmalion scenario. Higgins can justify imposing his strict regime
upon Eliza, bullying and coercing her into behaving like a ‘proper lady’, by claim-
ing that he is doing so in her real interests. To return to the language of John Stuart
Mill, he can claim to be encouraging her to pursue the higher pleasures that most
befit her nature as a human being. As it happens, Eliza does find that she prefers
the higher pleasures of Higgins and his circle, to the lower pleasures of her former
working-class life; and for John Stuart Mill, what people find they actually prefer,
having experienced a range of pleasures, provides an empirical criterion for what
counts as their real interests. The complicating factor that Marxism introduces is
the idea of false consciousness, which means that people’s actual preferences are
no longer a decisive argument for what is in their real interests. Appealing to a
notion of human nature, as Marxism does, means that it is no longer necessary to
refer to people’s actual preferences in order to identify what their real interests
are. This, however, seems to open the possibility of the kind of coercion that
Berlin describes. Rita, the latter-day Eliza in Educating Rita, might seek to better
herself by pursuing the higher pleasures of literature, poetry and so on, but it is
easy to imagine a Higgins of a more Marxist persuasion subjecting her to a strict
regime of retraining in order to cure her of these ‘bourgeois tendencies’.
For Berlin, the positive notion of freedom that he wants to call into question
can be found in Kant, Hegel and Marx. And most significantly, he thinks that it
can be found in the communism that arose in Russia after Marx’s death, which
drew on some of the elements of Marx’s thought in order to fashion its official
ideology. Here, Berlin argues, the Marxist thinking that looked to the liberation of
humanity becomes instrumental in state oppression, in the justification of totali-
tarianism. The communist state can claim to represent the individual’s true self,
a communal entity, and as such, to be entitled to impose its will on individuals
in the name of their real interests. It is also entitled to ignore their own wishes,
since they may not recognise their real interests and can even set about forcibly
re-educating them so they come to realise where their true interests lie. And in
all this, given its positive notion of freedom, it can claim to be liberating them.
It is the Orwellian nightmare in which freedom is slavery. Berlin wants nothing
to do with this pernicious notion of freedom. Better, he argues to define freedom
in purely negative terms, as the absence of external obstacles to what we want
to do. This is also an appropriate notion of freedom for the liberal individualism
that Berlin wants to defend, in the face of totalitarian communism. The liberal
political thinking that makes central the defence of the individual from external
interference, and sees the main justification for government in its role in protect-
ing individual rights, is best served by a purely negative idea of freedom.
182 Personhood and Autonomy
However, a complete rejection of positive freedom, as complicit in totalitarian
oppression, is in danger of throwing out the baby with the bathwater. It forgets
that Kant’s notion of autonomy, while undoubtedly providing a basis for pic-
tures of collective self-determination in which the individual must submit to the
whole, also represents a powerful formulation of the liberal ideal, and a justifica-
tion for its defence of the individual from external interference. In Kant’s account,
rational autonomy is first and foremost the individual’s capacity to give shape
to their existence and individuals should be respected as the originators of their
own life plan. (see Taylor 1985b, 337). Indeed, one common argument as to why
individuals are owed rights is that they are rational, autonomous beings. Rights
function to not only morally shield individuals from the interference of others,
but also to secure for them an area of personal liberty where they can develop and
pursue their own life-plans and give shape to their existence. In respecting some-
one’s rights, you respect their personhood. A further advantage of construing the
idea of individual freedom in terms of rational self-determination in the political
context is that it can take into account not only overt coercion and constraint but
also more insidious forms of manipulation, such as advertising and propaganda.
Through deception, withholding information, or presenting it in a selective way,
these forms of manipulation can limit the individual’s capacity to make informed
decisions as to how to act.
But while we may have returned to the notion of Kantian autonomy, the prob-
lems indicated in the previous section remain. On the Kantian account, behaving
morally, rationally determining oneself, requires the exclusion or repression of
desire, inclination and emotion. The self becomes a battleground in which rea-
son is constantly at odds with feeling and instinct. Furthermore, this is a picture
in which the rational subject is conceived of as abstractly isolated, implausibly
independent of all social relationships, cultural traditions and historical circum-
stances. Marx represents one attempt to address these problems in Kant’s account,
to bring the Kantian subject down to earth. For a more recent take on Kantian
ethics that seeks to address these problems, we can turn to the work of the con-
temporary thinker Habermas.
Plot
Three outlaws, Miller, Colby and Pierce, ride to the railway station
and wait for the noon train. Meanwhile, town marshal Will Kane (Gary
Cooper) and a Quaker, Amy Fowler (Grace Kelly), are getting married.
On the train is Frank Miller (Ian MacDonald), just released from prison,
who has sworn to kill Kane because he was the one who arrested him.
The outlaws waiting for him are his brother and two friends. Although the
new marshal doesn’t arrive until the next day, the town elders encour-
age Kane to leave immediately, telling him that he owes it to Amy. At the
edge of town, Kane stops the horses and decides to turn back. He heads
back to town to round up deputies to make a stand against the outlaws.
Amy says she doesn’t want to wait and if he doesn’t leave with her she
will get on the noon train without him. He refuses, and she goes to wait
for the train at the station.
Kane tries to enlist some deputies, but he is rejected by the judge who
passed sentence on Miller and by Harvey, his deputy (Lloyd Bridges),
who resents the fact that Kane did not pick him as successor and thinks
it is because he has taken up with Kane’s ex-girlfriend Helen Ramirez
(Katy Jurado). He is also rejected by the men in the saloon, the congre-
gation at the church and the town’s previous marshal. One volunteer,
Herb, pulls out when it turns out that no one else has come forward.
Kane refuses the offer of help from a drunk and a youngster.
Meanwhile, his wife has found out about Helen and goes to talk to
her. Helen criticises Amy for deserting her husband. Amy says that it is
because members of her own family were destroyed by gun violence.
Helen invites her to wait for the train in her room. The train arrives with
Miller. Kane confronts the outlaws and there is a gunfight. Amy leaps
off the train and runs back into town to help Kane, shooting one of the
192 Personhood and Autonomy
outlaws. Kane kills two others. The remaining outlaw, Frank Miller, takes
Amy hostage but she breaks free from him and Kane shoots him dead.
The townsfolk now emerge. Kane looks at them in disgust, takes off his
badge and throws it in the dust. He and Amy ride out of town together.
Key Scenes
1 As they are riding out of town, Kane stops the horses and decides
to turn back – ‘they’re making me run. I’ve never run from anyone
before’. He seems to be motivated by something beyond self-
interest or the desire to be thought heroic by others: ‘I’ve got to.
That’s the whole thing’ [11.10–12.38]. Later, back in his office,
Amy pleads with Kane ‘don’t try to be a hero’. He replies, not out
of modesty ‘I’m not trying to be a hero. If you think I like this, you’re
crazy’ [13.35–16.12].
2 His deputy, Harvey, offers to stand with Kane against the outlaws,
but only if he will put in a word to ensure that Harvey is Kane’s
successor as town marshal. Kane wants Harvey’s support but not
based on Harvey’s manipulative offer. Harvey: ‘you put the word
in for me like I said’. Kane: ‘I want you to stick – but I’m not buying
it. It’s got to be up to you’. When Kane refuses to ensure Harvey’s
appointment as successor, the self-interested Harvey quits, taking
off his badge and gun holster [20.18–22.44].
3 Harvey is involved with Helen Ramirez. When he turns up at her
place after quitting on Kane, she urges him to ‘grow up’, comparing
him unfavourably to Kane: ‘you’re a good-looking boy, but he is a
man – you have a long way to go’. She also exercises her autonomy
by unceremoniously dumping Harvey [41.17–43.09].
4 Kane goes to the church to ask for help. The congregation dis-
cuss whether or not to assist Kane in the showdown. In the end,
the view that carries the day is that it would be better if Kane just
left town, as the bad guys would simply move on. This would avoid
a shootout that would give the town a bad reputation and deter
outside investment, hurting the local economy. This is a utilitarian
argument, in which the town’s commercial well-being is the primary
consideration. The town will be better off without him. For Kant, the
right course of action is not something to be determined in terms
of whether the actions contribute to the greater good or commu-
nal well-being [43.19–50.50]. Others like the hotel clerk are actively
against Kane because by cleaning up the town he has ruined busi-
ness [32.50–33.18].
Personhood and Autonomy 193
Plot
In Texas, 1980, hitman Anton Chigurh (Javier Bardem) strangles a
deputy sheriff to escape custody and uses a bolt pistol to kill a driver
and steal his car. He spares the life of a petrol station owner after the
owner, though unaware of the stakes, accepts a challenge and suc-
cessfully guesses the result of Chigurh’s coin toss. Meanwhile, in the
desert, Llewelyn Moss (Josh Brolin) comes across the aftermath of a
drug deal gone wrong. He finds several dead men, a wounded Mexican
begging for water and two million dollars in a briefcase. He takes the
194 Personhood and Autonomy
money and returns home. That night, he returns to the scene with
water for the wounded man and is pursued by two men in a truck,
but escapes. Returning home, he sends his wife, Carla Jean (Kelly
Macdonald), to stay with her mother, then drives to a motel in Del Rio,
where he hides the briefcase in the air conditioning duct of his room.
Chigurh, hired to recover the money in the briefcase, kills his employ-
ers after finding a clue to Moss’s identity. Arriving at Moss’s home, he
uses his bolt pistol to blow the lock out of the door. Investigating the
break-in, Sheriff Bell (Tommy Lee Jones) notices the blown-out lock.
Meanwhile, using a tracking device hidden with the money, Chigurh
goes to Moss’s motel and kills a group of Mexicans planning to ambush
Moss in his room. Moss, having rented another room with access to the
air conditioning duct where the money is hidden, retrieves the briefcase
just before Chigurh opens the duct and finds it empty.
While staying at another motel in Eagle Pass, Moss discovers the
tracking device, but Chigurh has already found him. A gunfight ensues
and both are wounded. Moss flees to Mexico, hiding the case of money
in scrub along the Rio Grande. Injured, he is taken to a hospital. While
there, Carson Wells (Woody Harrelson), another hitman, fails to per-
suade him to accept his protection in return for the money. Meanwhile,
Chigurh cleans and stitches his wounds with stolen supplies, then cor-
ners Wells in his hotel room. Wells tries to barter for his life but is unsuc-
cessful and Chigurh kills him. Moss rings and Chigurh answers, telling
Moss that he will kill Carla Jean unless Moss gives up the money and
that he is going to kill Moss regardless.
Moss retrieves the suitcase from the river bank and arranges to meet
Carla Jean at a motel in El Paso, where he plans to give her the money and
hide her from danger. Before leaving, she is approached by Sheriff Bell,
who promises to protect Moss. Carla Jean’s mother accidentally reveals
Moss’s location to a group of Mexicans. Bell reaches the motel rendezvous,
only to hear gunshots and see a pickup truck speeding from the motel. He
arrives to find Moss dead, with Carla Jean turning up soon after. That night,
Bell returns to the motel crime scene and finds the lock blown out. Chigurh,
having come to retrieve the money, is hiding behind the door. Bell enters
Moss’s room and sees that the vent has been removed. Chigurh slips away.
Later, Bell visits his uncle Ellis (Barry Corbin) and tells him he plans
to retire. Weeks afterward Carla Jean returns from her mother’s funeral
to find Chigurh waiting in her bedroom. She refuses his offer of a coin
toss for her life. We next see Chigurh leaving the house, checking the
soles of his boots for blood. As he drives away, a car crashes into him
Personhood and Autonomy 195
and he is injured. He bribes two young witnesses for their silence and
flees. Now retired, Bell shares two dreams he has had about his father
with his wife.
Key Scenes
1 Chigurh spares the life of a gas station owner after the owner accepts
a challenge and successfully guesses the result of Chigurh’s coin
toss, though without fully realising what was at stake. The coin toss
is part of Chigurh’s modus operandi. It also seems to be a form
of Sartrean bad faith on his part, a way of trying to evade taking
responsibility for his actions, by presenting them as if they were part
of the workings of an indifferent universe [20.00–24.14].
2 Carson Wells, another hitman, fails to persuade Moss to accept pro-
tection in return for the money. He points out that Chigurh is espe-
cially dangerous because he acts out of higher principles of some
sort: ‘You can’t make a deal with him. Even if you gave him the
money he’d still kill you. He’s a peculiar man. You could even say
that he has principles. Principles that transcend money or drugs or
anything like that. He’s not like you. He’s not even like me’ [1.11.53–
1.14.54]. Chigurh is like a lawman dispensing justice, upholding his
principles with the dedication and integrity usually associated with
the western hero. He is, in his own way, as principled as Kane in
High Noon, and if anything, is more successful in controlling his
desires and feelings.
3 When Chigurh corners Wells in his hotel room. Wells tries unsuc-
cessfully to barter for his life. ‘You don’t have to do this’, he says, but
Chigurh kills him. Moss telephones the room and Chigurh answers,
telling Moss that he will kill Carla Jean unless Moss gives up the
money: ‘You bring me the money and I’ll let her go. Otherwise, she’s
accountable. The same as you. That’s the best deal you’re gonna
get. I won’t tell you you can save yourself because you can’t’. Once
again, Chigurh is behaving in accordance with inflexible higher prin-
ciples of some sort. He is also, from an existentialist point of view,
suffering from bad faith in the form of a belief in absolute princi-
ples that he has no choice but to obey, Sartre’s ‘spirit of serious-
ness’ [1.17.42–1.22.32].
4 After Moss is killed, Bell, who had promised Carla Jean he would
keep Moss safe [1.16.18–1.16.24], visits his uncle Ellis, an ex-law-
man, telling him he plans to retire because he feels ‘over-matched’.
Bell: ‘I always thought when I got older God would sort of come into
196 Personhood and Autonomy
my life in some way. He didn’t. I don’t blame him. If I was him I’d have
the same opinion about me that he does’. Ellis scoffs and says fatal-
istically that the region has always been violent: ‘What you got ain’t
nothin’ new. This country is hard on people … You can’t stop what’s
coming. It ain’t all waiting on you. That’s vanity’ [1.38.10–1.42.59].
5 Carla Jean returns from her mother’s funeral to find Chigurh waiting
in her bedroom. Carl Jean: ‘You got no cause to hurt me’. Chigurh:
‘No. But I gave my word … To your husband … Your husband had
the opportunity to remove you from harm’s way. Instead, he used
you to try to save himself’. Again, he presents himself as being
bound by principles or promises that he cannot break, arguably a
form of bad faith. Like Wells, Carla Jean tells him that ‘You don’t
have to do this’. In a kind of concession, he makes the offer of a coin
toss for her life, but she refuses stating that the choice is his own
and once again calling out his bad faith. ‘No. I ain’t gonna call it …
The coin don’t have no say. It’s just you [1.43.12–1.46.37].
5 Slaves, Supermen and
Authentic Selves
Existentialist Ethics
At the start of Fight Club, we find the film’s unnamed narrator on a chair with
a gun barrel in his mouth, courtesy of the other main character, the charismatic,
dangerous Tyler Durden. The narrator gingerly moves the barrel aside with
his tongue, and in voiceover, wonders how he ever got to this point. We then
flashback to the beginning of the events that led to this situation, the collapse
of the narrator’s former existence, and his wild ride with Durden, with the film
eventually arriving at the scene with which it began. ‘I think this is about where
we came in’ notes the narrator helpfully. The action picks up again, with the
narrator looking into Durden’s eyes for a moment, and then squeezing the trig-
ger. In slow motion, his mouth fills with the gases from the gun and the bullet
blows a hole through his cheek. At the same time, Tyler’s eyes glaze over and
he falls to the floor with an exit wound in the back of his head and a grin on his
face. For the narrator, overcoming Durden in this way appears to be a liberation,
heralding a new beginning: ‘my eyes are open. Everything is going to be fine’
(Figure 5.1).
Durden is sometimes presented as an example of what nineteenth-century
philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche called the ‘ubermensch’, the ‘superman’ or
‘overman’, a powerful creature who is beyond good and evil, beyond conven-
tional morality and above the common herd. Durden certainly overcomes the
constraints of conventional morality and aspirations, giving expression to his
strongest drives. He also orchestrates the underground fight clubs in which
other budding tough guys can get back in touch with their primal instincts and
impulses, long suppressed thanks to the debilitating self-denial required for
civilised life. It’s a common view of what Nietzsche’s ubermensch might be
like, especially in the movies. Yet there is a good argument to the effect that
Durden is no Nietzschean superman. On the contrary, it is in fact the unprepos-
sessing Edward Norton character who has a better claim to be the superman in
the film and he attains this status at the precise moment that he overcomes Tyler
Durden. To make sense of this, and more generally to see how Nietzschean ideas
might apply to the film, we need to take a somewhat lengthy detour through
Nietzsche’s thinking.
198 Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves
Figure 5.1 Fight Club: Tyler Durden and the narrator (David Fincher, 1999. Credit: 20th
Century Fox/Photofest).
Nietzsche
Roughly contemporary with Marx, Nietzsche (1844–1900) is another critic of
religion, and especially of attempts to provide a religious justification of values
or morality. His books, including Beyond Good and Evil and On the Genealogy
of Morals, contain a wide-ranging critique of religion. In this critique, Nietzsche
is very much in the spirit of the eighteenth-century Enlightenment. He shares the
Enlightenment’s suspicion of religion, as a set of unprovable, dogmatic or super-
stitious beliefs that served to justify questionable moral and political practices.
He famously insisted that God is dead, referring not to the demise of some super-
natural being, but to the gradual erosion of religious belief that has taken place in
the modern era over the last 300 years. This in turn reflects the rise of the modern
scientific worldview, for which the universe operates without any God-given plan
or purpose, according to the impersonal operation of physical laws. However, he
is also a critic of many features of enlightened modernity, including the modern
attempt to find an alternative, rational basis for morality and value. He does not
think it is possible to establish ethics in this manner, either on a scientific, materi-
alist basis or in terms of reason itself.
The Enlightenment thinkers sought a rational basis for morality, either in terms
of the new scientific notion of human being as material object, or on the basis of
the rational subject as Kant thought. For Kant, trying to find rational foundations
for our moral values was important for the critique of religion, because in show-
ing that morality had a foundation in reason, one could show that religion is not
the only ground of moral values. We no longer have to appeal to God and his
commands in order to justify morality. However, Nietzsche goes further, criticis-
ing in addition these Enlightenment attempts to find a rational basis for morality.
Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves 199
He rejects a happiness-centred hedonistic or utilitarian ethics, based on the
scientific conception of the human being that goes back to Hobbes, as a machine
driven by a desire for pleasure and the avoidance of pain. And he rejects Kant’s
attempt to establish a deontological morality based on reason. He thinks that these
attempts are problematic particularly because they tried to preserve Christian val-
ues by founding them in reason, rather than questioning the values themselves.
So, for example, Helvetius, Holbach and Kant all rejected a religious foundation
for morality, but wanted to preserve what are essentially Christian values by pro-
viding them with a more rational justification.
This is not to say that Nietzsche is advocating a nihilistic rejection of all val-
ues. For Nietzsche, we need values in order to have a meaningful life, and the
problem that we need to confront is precisely the nihilism of modern life (BGE
208; all references to Beyond Good and Evil will be to the numbered paragraphs).
The old basis for values, religion, is collapsing. There is science, but this does not
provide us with any values or guidance, only material success. Like science, phi-
losophy has failed to provide an alternative basis for values. Moreover, he thinks
that the values dominant in modern society, the Christian values left over from
our religious past, are nihilistic in the sense of being life-denying. They celebrate
things like modesty, consideration, weakness, security, belonging to the group.
Everything that expresses strength and independence, all that elevates the indi-
vidual above the herd, is seen as a danger, a threat. For Nietzsche, we need to go
beyond this ‘herd animal morality’ (BGE 186). What is required is precisely the
opposite, the strong, independent individual who stands out from the crowd. Their
strength lies in self-mastery and in the capacity to create values for themselves, to
determine values to live by, through their own will. So the task for human beings
is to create a meaningful world, to establish values for living, in the absence of
God and in the face of the scientific conception of nature.
In this, Nietzsche also stands apart from that other great nineteenth-century
critic of modernity, Marx. Instead of nihilism, the great problem for Marx is alien-
ation, under existing social and historical conditions, from our proper nature as
the conscious, rational makers of our social existence. Liberal democracy does
not go far enough in liberating human beings, since it leaves alienating social
conditions in place. For Marx, we reach a higher state by changing these social
conditions, a process that human beings collectively participate in. Nietzsche,
like Marx, is also critical of modern liberal democracy, but this is because for
him the liberal-democratic ideals of equality and liberty represent the triumph
of the common man, reducing everything to the lowest common denominator.
Nietzsche sometimes speaks of herd morality as the democratic will to render
everyone equal in mediocrity. He is even more scathing about socialism, in the
general sense of the classless, cooperative society that was Marx’s social ideal.
Socialism for Nietzsche would represent the final triumph of the herd, the group,
over the individual. Nietzsche would no doubt see the herd thinker’s hatred of
the individual who stands out from the group in the words of the Fire Chief in
Fahrenheit 451: ‘It’s no good, Montag. We’ve all got to be alike. The only way
to be happy is for everyone to be equal. So, we must burn the books’. Here the
books are being condemned because they encourage individual reflection and
200 Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves
non-conformity, create dissent and lead individuals to differentiate themselves
from the herd. These are precisely the things that Nietzsche wants to encourage.
Like Marx, Nietzsche envisages the possibility of moral self-improvement for
human beings, but whereas for Marx, this involves a process of social transforma-
tion undertaken by the collective, for Nietzsche, it is a matter of individual trans-
formation for the strong few, an aristocratic vision of self-improvement.
Thus, Nietzsche mounts a trenchant critique of the prevailing values of modern
life themselves, the popular moral values and ideals of his time, the values of what
he calls herd animal morality. They deny strength and individuality, and celebrate
weakness, self-denial, submission, serving others and belonging to the group (BGE
186, 199–202). Nietzsche’s own ideal is the strong individual, where strength is
strength of will, which is linked with being independent and self-determining.
It is important to emphasise that for Nietzsche, the strongest individuals are not
those who master others, but those who have mastery over themselves. Their
strength lies in being able to make themselves, to create their own values and
shape their lives in accordance with those values, independently of the majority
of people. It is in these terms that Nietzsche understands freedom. It is not a mat-
ter of having a free will, a faculty everyone is understood to possess, but rather of
being capable of self-mastery, something that is only possible for the strong few,
since it requires the exceptional strength that most people do not have (BGE 29,
188, 212).
Underlying this ideal of self-mastery is a certain conception of human nature,
of life, characterised by Nietzsche in terms of drives or instincts. This is not the
Hobbesian notion of a being that strives to preserve itself, to survive, but life as
constantly striving to be ‘more’, to grow, to be stronger, to master and overcome
that which is weaker and impose a form upon it. This is Nietzsche’s famous notion
of the ‘will to power’ (BGE 36, 259). And as noted, the strongest expression of
this will to power is not mastery of others but self-mastery, self-overcoming. To
achieve this self-mastery is to perfect oneself, to realise one’s greatest possibilities
and to ‘become what one is’. This ideal of self-perfection is not completely dis-
similar to Kant’s notion of freedom as autonomous self-determination. However,
whereas Kant envisages determining oneself through one’s rationality, Nietzsche
presents a more naturalistic version in which, under social pressure, one’s drives
and energies come to be directed inward, turned upon themselves. We will see
what this involves in a moment.
Nietzsche questions morality not only in the sense of the popular moral ide-
als and sentiments of his day but also understood as the philosophical discipline
of ethics. This is the modern attempt to provide a rational foundation for current
moral values and ideals, which Nietzsche calls ‘the science of morals’. His own
approach to reflecting on ethics is not a science of morals but what he calls a ‘nat-
ural history of morals’ (BGE 186), or a ‘genealogy of morals’. Rather than trying
to rationally justify our values, Nietzsche thinks we should look at their real ori-
gins. He doesn’t think they come from some exalted, transcendental source, like
God or reason. Rather, they have ‘lowly’ origins, arising out of the messy encoun-
ters, struggles and conflicts of history. Accordingly, Nietzsche’s genealogical
Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves 201
approach looks at current moral values and ideals in their historical development,
tracing the history behind them, how they have emerged and changed over time.
As such, rather than accepting herd morality as the definitive form of morality,
Nietzsche calls attention to how current moral concepts are historically specific.
And in grasping that current moral ideas are not absolute, but only one particular
form of morality, it becomes possible to envisage the possibility of overcoming
them, going beyond existing morality. Formulating this new morality will be the
task of the ‘philosophers of the future’, of the ubermensch or overman (BGE
43, 210–212).
In providing this historical genealogy of the emergence of moral ideas
Nietzsche also seeks to uncover the deeper, underlying ends that morality serves.
And what underlies morality turns out to be power, or more accurately, the will
to power that is the fundamental drive in human beings. All moralities are an
expression of the will to power, particularly as this is manifested in social power
relations. In Nietzsche’s account, the will to power appears in two forms. Firstly,
it is essential to human life, understood as a collection of drives or instincts, con-
stantly striving to be more, to be stronger, to master and so on; and secondly, will
to power is essential to life in society, which consists of power relations. And
what the genealogy of morals reveals is that all moralities reflect a certain kind
of power-relation, a social structure of command and obedience. Nietzsche says
that at all times, in all societies, there have always been those who obeyed and a
small number commanding, or in his terminology, ‘masters’ and ‘slaves’. We thus
have a conception of society in terms of power, the power that the small number
of commanders have over the many who obey (BGE 199).
This is discussed at length in On the Genealogy of Morals. Society is not estab-
lished, as Hobbes imagined, through a social contract between free individuals
who surrender some personal liberty in return for the security of an organised
society. It is established when a small, powerful group, conquer and enslave oth-
ers, establishing a hierarchy of command and obedience. The ruling group cre-
ates the state, the social order, through acts of violent imposition (GM 2.17; all
references to Genealogy of Morals will be to the essay and section). Moreover,
the masters create a morality, a code of evaluation from their perspective. The
masters are strong and vigorous, freely expressing their instincts in joyful, unin-
hibited action; and they identify the ‘good’ with their own attributes of strength,
courage and self-assertion. Meanwhile, under the rule of the masters, the slaves
are rendered submissive, servile, fearful and cautious. As far as the masters are
concerned, these are all contemptible, unworthy ways of behaving which they
want to distance themselves from and they identify these characteristics with the
‘bad’. Good and bad, so understood, are the categories of what Nietzsche calls
‘master morality’ (BGE 260, GM 1.2).
As for the slaves, the first reaction to enslavement, to the power of the mas-
ters, is the development of what Nietzsche calls ‘bad conscience’ (GM 2.16).
Their own hostility and aggression, no longer able to express itself outwardly
because the power of the masters is too great, is internalised or turned inwards.
They vent their hostility on themselves, on their own desires and instincts, which
202 Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves
they come to regard as base and unworthy. Thus, while the masters give free rein
to their instincts, for the slaves it is a very different matter. Their own instincts
become a source of guilt and shame, and so they suffer from bad conscience.
This is not a particularly healthy way of being. Indeed, Nietzsche sees bad con-
science as a kind of illness, a masochistic self-hatred. At this point, then, the per-
son is divided against themselves, their energies turned against themselves, with
a ‘higher self’ striving to control or suppress an irrational, instinctive side that it
views with contempt.
The second reaction is the invention of a different kind of morality, ‘slave
morality’. The slaves are weak and oppressed, but they don’t remain passive.
They develop feelings of envy and hatred towards the masters, which Nietzsche
calls ‘ressentiment’ or resentment, a desire for revenge. Ressentiment results in
a new code of evaluation, which is a complete inversion of master morality (GM
1.7, 1.10, 1.11). So this is how a subjugated population can respond, by turning
against master morality and ‘revaluing all values’. First of all, the qualities that
master morality labelled ‘bad’, are now evaluated in a positive way, as ‘good’.
For example, fear becomes humility, and impotence becomes kindness. For mas-
ter morality, fear and impotence are bad. The oppressed are too weak and timid
to be anything other than kind; and they are humble because any other way of
acting would have bad consequences. But the slaves turn these into positive fea-
tures. Secondly, from the perspective of slave morality, those qualities that master
morality thinks of as good, like strength, courage and self-assertion, are not con-
sidered bad, but ‘evil’. This is because the slaves associate the virtues of the pow-
erful with their own suffering. The virtues of the strong and powerful are a threat
to the slave. So the notion of evil is devised. Thus, good and evil are the categories
of slave morality, which emerges as a reaction to master morality. The triumph of
the slaves is to get the masters to accept a morality in which the masters becomes
reprehensible in their own eyes.
Religion comes in at this point, because for Nietzsche, this inversion of values
is above all the work of religion, of Christianity in particular, and of the priests
who arise to mobilise the weak and lead the slaves (GM 1.6-9). For Nietzsche, it is
the priests who planned and brought about the triumph of slave morality. Religion
was the instrument of the slaves’ revenge, the means by which the values of slave
morality could be imposed on the strong. The strength and vigour of the masters,
expressed in strong, joyful, uninhibited action, became the object of religious
condemnation and what was celebrated instead were things like meekness, humil-
ity and submissiveness. Submission to the masters became instead submission to
God. In the process, the self-esteem of the slaves was boosted, their moral supe-
riority over the masters affirmed. So, for Nietzsche, the moral values bound up
with religion are the values of slave morality, values that condemn the strong and
turn weakness into a virtue.
At the same time, religion links up with the phenomenon of bad conscience.
The bad conscience, as we have seen, is the slaves’ hostility and aggression
turned inward by social constraints. Unable to express the aggression outwardly
because of the power of the masters, it becomes self-hatred, self-punishment.
Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves 203
The slaves come to regard their own instincts and desires as base and unworthy.
Christianity is not the origin of bad conscience, which lies in social power rela-
tions and our reactions to them. However, it intensifies humanity’s self-hatred
and self-torture to the point of madness, strengthening this instrument of self-
punishment. Religion teaches the absolute goodness of God, and the baseness of
human beings, who are nothing but unworthy sinners, inherently evil and sinful,
deserving of eternal punishment. On Nietzsche’s account, then, religion is an
instrument of self-torture, the means for the self-violation of the human self.
We can see why Nietzsche discusses the origin of bad conscience in such detail,
why it is important. For him, the bad conscience is not just an interesting mental
phenomenon. It is a serious sickness, and it is not just something that particular
individuals suffer from, but a sickness characteristic of the European mind in
general (GM 2.19–2.22)
Ever a useful metaphor for conceptions of human nature, we might see the
vampire as being in the first instance close to the Nietzschean master type, giv-
ing uninhibited expression to their instincts and desires, preying cheerfully on
the weak. But once resurrected in a religious framework, as in The Addiction,
the vampire as we have seen becomes a metaphor for human nature as conceived
from a Christian, specifically Augustinian perspective – as afflicted by base,
unworthy instincts and desires, out of which all worldly evil arises. When the
film’s central character, Kathleen, the idealistic philosophy grad student appalled
by human cruelty and evil, is turned into a vampire, she goes over to the dark side
and becomes everything that she formerly hated. As a vampire, she is unapologet-
ically bent on playing the role of the master, freely pursuing her instincts, though
fully aware of the affinities between her activities and the historical atrocities that
she was originally so appalled by. But she eventually comes to be stricken with
guilt over what she has been doing and the desires that drove her. In Nietzschean
terms, she assumes the position of the self-hating slave. With this, she moves
from defiantly proclaiming that she ‘will not submit’, just before slaughtering
her PhD dissertation committee, to believing she can only be saved in the end
by submitting to a priest, and to God. One commentator suggests that her refusal
to submit may itself have a double meaning, reflecting her internally conflicted
state. On the one hand, it means that she is refusing to submit to God; on the other,
that she is refusing to submit to her addiction (Johnstone 1999, 176).
For Nietzsche, the two types of morality, master and slave morality, have
been engaged in a fearful struggle on earth for thousands of years. He ascribes
the master code of evaluation to Greek and roman societies, giving way to
Judaeo-Christian slave morality, the renaissance re-awakening of master moral-
ity, and the ressentiment movement of the Reformation and the French revolu-
tion (GM 1.16). However, the modern era sees the triumph of slave morality.
Nietzsche describes the moral sentiment of his day as herd animal morality
because slave morality is essentially a reaction. To exist, slave morality always
needs an adverse social background to react against. But the present European
moral sentiment doesn’t have to struggle, because slave morality has become
the common morality. So herd animal morality is the proper term to describe the
204 Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves
moral sentiment of Nietzsche’s day. This brings us back to the question of what
Nietzsche sees as the way forward. To progress, we need to leave behind religion
and herd animal morality. Nietzsche doesn’t think that herd animal morality is
absolute, the last word in morality. The account he gives of its historical emer-
gence in terms of the struggles between master and slave morality shows this.
The present prevalence of herd animal morality is just the result of historical
struggles. Nietzsche thus emphasises the possibility of overcoming the present
moral code. The new morality will be formulated by the strong individual, the
ubermensch or overman.
As part of this overcoming of religion and slave morality, we also need to leave
behind the damaging self-denial and self-hatred associated with them. Nietzsche
criticises the Christian condemnation of instinct and desire, its rejection of basic
instinctual drives. This hostility towards desire, as we have seen, is also promi-
nent in Kant’s moral thinking and goes all the way back to Plato. All of these posi-
tions share a contempt for bodily instinct and desire, things that tie us to this world
and which we were put on this earth to rise above. But for Nietzsche, these drives
are at the very core of our being, the energies that motivate us. And he points to
the costs involved in excessive self-denial, especially as prescribed by religion.
We are not only perpetually frustrated but afflicted with self-loathing. Our own
instincts become the source of shame and we are led to regard ourselves as dam-
nable because we cannot get rid of them. The self-hatred of the bad conscience
also gives rise to other phenomena, including what Nietzsche calls the ‘ascetic
ideal’, in which self-sacrifice and self-denial become, perversely, an expression
of strength. The priestly types demonstrate their own will to power in the form of
various practices of self-denial, which reduce their vigour and express their hos-
tility towards concrete reality. This asceticism is well-illustrated in Simon of the
Desert, where Simon, atop his pillar, invents ever more elaborate ways of denying
himself. It’s an exercise of enormous strength and self-assertion, whilst being at
the same time a form of debilitating self-denial.
However, it is important to emphasise that Nietzsche’s own ideal of the
ubermensch is not a return to the uninhibited functioning of the instincts, the
unsublimated passions of the master (GM 2.17). Nietzsche does not propose that
we abandon all constraints and give our instincts free rein. Our instinctual drives
and impulses are chaotic and primitive, and to simply return to them would be
to revert to the status of brutes. This is why the Nietzschean overman cannot be
identified with Mr Hyde in the Jekyll and Hyde scenario. Certainly, the primi-
tive desires and instincts represented by the Hyde part of our nature are not to be
simply suppressed or denied. To do so is to deny life, as Hyde himself confirms
when he first emerges in the 1931 Mamoulian version of Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde,
railing against the social, religious and moral constraints on the expression of these
instincts: ‘You hypocrites, deniers of life. If you could see me now … what would
you think?’ But neither is Nietzsche advocating their uninhibited expression. This
would be a step backwards. Appropriately, the Hyde who is given free rein after
Jekyll drinks his potion looks decidedly brutish and primitive, and proves to be
murderous and sadistic in the extreme.
Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves 205
Nor is Nietzsche advocating brutality towards others. He is not proposing that
we reject the moral constraints required by the common herd in order to return
to the masters’ predatory domination of those weaker than them. Thus, he would
not embrace the advice that the cobbler (Alphonse Ethier) gives to Lily Powers
(Barbara Stanwyck) in Baby Face (Alfred E. Green, 1933), to ‘be a master, not a
slave’. A fan of Nietzsche, the cobbler, quoting from The Will to Power, advises
her to aim for great things, to move to the big city and use her power over men:
‘Nietzsche says, “All life, no matter how we idealize it, is nothing more nor less
than exploitation”. That’s what I’m telling you. Exploit yourself. Go to some big
city where you will find opportunities! Use men! Be strong! Defiant! Use men to
get the things you want!’ All of this Lily very successfully does, but she is not by
virtue of that the ‘first overwoman’, as some have characterised her (see Steven
2017, 96). This is once again to mistakenly identify Nietzsche’s ideal with his
notion of the master. Incidentally, Baby Face was one of the films that prompted
the introduction of the Hays Production Code. Before it could be released it had
to be recut to, amongst other things, remove the references to Nietzsche’s philoso-
phy – one of the many things unacceptable under the Code (Kehr 2005).
This identification of the ubermensch with the master who dominates others is
also the mistake made by the protagonists Brandon (John Dall) and Philip (Farley
Granger) in Hitchcock’s 1948 film Rope (Figure 5.2). To prove their superiority,
they decide to commit the perfect crime, murdering a university classmate and
Figure 5.2 The two supermen in Rope (Alfred Htchcock, 1948/ Credit: Warner Brothers/
Photofest).
206 Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves
hiding him in a trunk, which they make the centrepiece of the dinner party they go
on to hold. They consider themselves to be Nietzschean overmen, intellectually
superior types who are exempt from the moral rules that govern everyone else,
the common herd; and see murder as an art that superior beings should be able to
practice. As Brandon says: ‘Good and evil, right and wrong were invented for the
ordinary average man, the inferior man, because he needs them’. In the course of
the film, their old school tutor Rupert (James Stewart) works out what has hap-
pened. He is horrified that his discussions of Nietzsche’s ubermensch have been
used by the pair to justify murder, insisting that they have twisted and distorted his
words. Certainly, the Nietzschean ideal is not to return to the uninhibited mastery
of the master, to revive master morality. After all, the title of Nietzsche’s book is
Beyond Good and Evil, not Back to Good and Bad.
Nietzsche considers the master’s uninhibited mastery over others to be a crude
expression of the will to power. For him, it was only when the human being became
divided against themselves, developing a bad conscience under the constraints of
civilised life, that they became an ‘interesting animal’ (GM 1.6). Nietzsche also
indicates that there is a certain promise implicit in the bad conscience: ‘the bad
conscience is an illness … but an illness as pregnancy is an illness’ (GM 2.19).
This means that bad conscience, strengthened by religion, may be destructive and
negative, but the phenomenon can also take a different turn. The bad conscience
is only the initial step. We must first condemn our impulses in order to be able to
take the second step, to ‘sublimate’ or ‘spiritualise’ them into different channels.
That is, we can adopt a different relation towards ourselves, organise our impulses
without considering them evil or fighting them (GM 2.24). We can redirect, chan-
nel and harmonise these energies, enhancing them and turning them into some-
thing more spiritual and noble, such as artistic or creative endeavours. In so doing,
as Nietzsche puts it in Will to Power, we will have triumphed over our impulses
without destroying them (Nietzsche 1967, paragraphs 384, 385; see Kaufmann
1968, 224–225). For Nietzsche, this is where the greatest power lies, in positive
self-mastery or self-overcoming. This is a life-enhancing rather than life-denying
activity and is the work undertaken by the overman. They have the task of self-
creation, and at the end of the process will emerge the sovereign individual, ‘liber-
ated again from the morality of custom, autonomous and supramoral’ (GM 2.2).
Consequently, Nietzsche does not simply condemn Christian self-denial. Bad
conscience is an evil, but a necessary evil, a stage we have to go through to get to
the positive self-mastery of the ubermensch. In the same way, the asceticism that
Simon turns into a fine art in Bunuel’s Simon of the Desert is both ridiculous and
noble, ridiculous because it takes debilitating self-denial to absurd lengths, noble
because it elevates him above the brute, as well as providing the preconditions
for a more positive self-relation. At the same time, the ascetic has to be clearly
distinguished from the ubermensch. The two are run together in The Addiction.
Christopher Walken’s Peina is the vampire who has his desires under control, is
able to hold down a job and so on. Having been targeted by Kathleen as a pos-
sible victim, he takes her back to his apartment to teach her how to be a proper
vampire. He explicitly claims to be a Nietzschean superman, the one who lives
Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves 207
beyond good and evil, but his self-mastery is in fact more of the ascetic variety.
He does not sublimate his impulses but rather, practices various forms of self-
denial and fasting: ‘you learn to survive on a little’. Later on, we see him feed-
ing on Kathleen, suggesting his professed asceticism is in fact little more than a
hypocritical mask.
In the movie vampire world, more plausible candidates for the vampire as
overman are represented by Adam (Tom Hiddleston) and Eve (Tilda Swinton) in
Only Lovers Left Alive (Jim Jarmusch, 2013). These vampires are cultured intel-
lectuals, urbane and sophisticated, their houses filled with rare books, musical
instruments, artworks and scientific instruments. They radiate superiority over
the common run of humanity, but unlike the superiority claimed by Philip and
Brandon in Rope, which is demonstrated by murdering someone they consider
inferior, theirs is an evident spiritual superiority. It has been developed through
centuries of self-cultivation and it sets them clearly apart from the corrupt, chaotic
world outside their homes. Their main problem, apart from getting supplies of
untainted blood to satisfy their relatively restrained urges, is Eve’s little sister Ava
(Mia Wasikowska). Ava has not yet learned to tame and redirect her instincts, and
her surprise visit and uncontrolled behaviour disrupts their ordered existence. If
they themselves eventually resort to traditional vampire behaviour, as happens in
the very last scene of the film, it is only as a last resort since they are on the point
of starvation.
The confusion of Nietzsche’s ideal, the ubermensch, with the brutal self-assertion
of the master also underlies the mistaken identification of Nietzsche’s views with
a fascist politics, the kind of radical authoritarian nationalism exemplified by
National Socialism. This is an identification that is made by one of the dinner
guests in Rope. When Mr Kentley (Cedric Hardwicke) suggests that Brandon,
who has been holding forth about how murder is an art that superior beings should
practice, is in agreement with Nietzsche and his theory of the superman, he adds
that Hitler also believed in this theory. Brandon is happy to agree with the first
point, that his own view accords with Nietzsche’s, but he rejects the second,
not because the Nazis were murderers who killed those they thought inferior,
but because they were stupid and incompetent about it. In fact, we can say that
Brandon, in imagining himself to be a Nietzschean superman entitled to murder
those he considers inferior, represents the same kind of self-serving, distorted
reading of Nietzsche that the Nazis themselves drew on in order to justify their
murderous behaviour towards particular social groups. Brandon is far from being
a Nietzschean superman and Nietzsche is far from being an apologist for fascism.
Apart from his distaste for nationalism of all kinds, especially German national-
ism, Nietzsche does not envisage the ubermensch as an authoritarian leader enti-
tled to dominate others. The kind of mastery he looks to remains above all the
self-mastery to be found in the artist, the philosopher, even the saint.
All of which brings us back to Fight Club. On the basis of what we have seen,
it is possible to reject any identification of Tyler Durden with the Nietzschean
overman. Certainly, the film’s unnamed narrator starts out as a ‘herd man’, a cor-
porate functionary and obedient consumer who plays by the rules but is becoming
208 Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves
increasingly frustrated by what late capitalist society has to offer. Through his
alter-ego Durden, he is able to escape from his repressed existence and give
expression to his strongest drives. Durden violently rejects conventional morality
and aspirations, and the fight clubs he organises allow the participants to get back
in touch with the primal instincts and impulses that have been denied in civi-
lised life. But far from being Nietzsche’s ideal of the powerful individual, Durden
comes closer to the uninhibited instincts and brutality of the master. He is by no
means a brute pure and simple. He has enormous self-discipline, which makes
him greater than he would otherwise have been, but his self-overcoming is lim-
ited because it becomes a means to the end of tyrannising others. In this, he is not
unlike Napoleon, another figure who is sometimes mistakenly cited as a model for
the overman. Nietzsche’s views on Napoleon are clear. For him, Napoleon is cer-
tainly not a simple brute, but he is not an overman either. Rather, he is a synthesis
of brute and overman, his self-overcoming cut short by his lust to dominate (GM
1.16). And like Napoleon, Durden ‘was corrupted by the means he had to employ,
and lost noblesse of character’ (Nietzsche 1967, 1026; see Kaufman 1968, 316;
Rowland 2003, 23).
By the end of the film, Durden has given full expression to his domineer-
ing tendencies, fashioning his fight clubs into a terrorist army that he runs along
militaristic, decidedly fascist lines. The participants in this army, instead of find-
ing themselves, are now required to submerge their personality through extreme
self-denial and to subordinate themselves entirely to Durden’s cause, which is to
bring about destruction and chaos in society. Durden is thus far removed from the
ubermensch, for whom mastery lies not in the domination of others, and destruc-
tion, but in self-mastery and self-creation. It is in fact the film’s unnamed narrator
who in the end more closely approaches Nietzsche’s ideal. Durden is his Hyde-
like alter-ego, embodying the narrator’s strongest drives and appetites, with the
qualification that unlike Hyde, he has enough self-discipline to direct his energies,
if only into the domination of others. The final scene of the film, in which the nar-
rator shoots himself, is also the scene in which he finally confronts and overcomes
his alter-ego, appropriating and taking control of his energies. In so doing, he
creates himself as a new person. Durden’s tyranny over others is thus turned into
creative self-affirmation.
So for Nietzsche, moral progress, in the form of becoming the self-mastering
ubermensch, is possible. This is not something that can be achieved by everyone,
only the strong few. Nonetheless, it is something that is within the capacity of at
least some human beings to achieve, those who have the required strength. This is
not a superhuman ideal in the sense of being beyond the physical and psychologi-
cal capacities of any human being. Here, we can distinguish Nietzsche’s uber-
mensch from another character the superman has sometimes been identified with
this is Neo (Keanu Reeves) from The Matrix, which came out in the same year
as Fight Club. This was also perhaps the first film to excite widespread interest
in the philosophical interpretation of film and one of the themes that came up in
discussion at the time was the idea that Neo was a version of Nietzsche’s uber-
mensch (see e.g., Knight, McKnight, 2002: 189). However, this is a questionable
Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves 209
identification, and it is questionable precisely because the film envisages as an
ideal something that is beyond the physical and psychological capacities of any
human being – the complete transcendence of the physical body.
The premise of the film is that most of humanity has been enslaved by a race
of intelligent machines that use human bodies as power sources. The humans,
however, are completely unaware of their real situation. Everything seems normal
because a supercomputer feeds them a computer-simulated reality (‘the matrix’).
Only a few rebels have managed to escape this enslavement and are able to offer
resistance to the machines. Thus, at the start of the film, before he escapes from
the matrix, everything the central character, Keanu Reeves’ Neo, experiences and
takes to be real is in fact a computer-generated illusion. The film follows his jour-
ney out of the matrix into the real world. With its global illusion scenario, the film
proved a useful resource for talking about Descartes, and Cartesian arguments
for scepticism about the possibility of knowledge, such as the possibility that we
might be dreaming or being radically deceived by an evil demon. But there is
another philosophical theme called into view by the film, namely philosophy’s
traditional disdain for the body, and the idea of the self, mind or soul as something
essentially non-bodily and immaterial. This is already evident in Plato, where, as
we have seen, the rational self or soul is understood to be distinct from the body
and its irrational desires.
In The Matrix, this second theme comes up insofar as Cynthia Freeland puts
it, the film creates a ‘naï ve fantasy of overcoming human flesh’ (Freeland, 2002,
205). In the reality that Neo finds himself in after escaping the matrix, human
beings are embodied, vulnerable beings. He awakens to a nightmarish vision of
countless naked bodies, floating in vats, plugged into tubes that maintain them
and feed them their fake reality. Aboard the rebel ship, he can only re-enter the
matrix by having a plug inserted into the back of his neck. But once back in the
matrix, he is without his neck-bolt, able to perform spectacular feats, and once he
undergoes his final transformation into ‘the One’, becomes superhuman. He may
still be embodied, but this is a perfect, invulnerable body, with no relationship to
an actual flesh and blood one. In effect, Neo has transcended the physical reality
of the flesh. And the film does not end on the ship with Neo’s real body. Instead,
we see a handsome, overcoated Neo in the matrix, wandering among the masses,
then zipping off through the sky, promising ‘a world without rules and controls,
without borders and boundaries, a world where anything is possible’. As Freeland
puts it, the movie feeds escapist fantasies of a mental reality where the elect few
are unencumbered by rules (see Freeland, 2002, 209, 214).
Plato would no doubt have approved of Neo’s overcoming of his physical
body, leaving the prison of his body in order to emerge into the more perfect
world of the matrix, where he himself is purified of imperfection and becomes
what he truly is. The Platonic philosopher also longs to escape from the body
and become pure mind. There are in addition strong religious overtones in Neo’s
journey to self-realisation, his escape from a mortal, corruptible body, and trans-
formation into something perfect and impervious to harm. Augustine, drawing on
Plato, reinforced the idea of the soul as immortal and indestructible, essentially
210 Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves
distinct from the body, and able to leave it behind as we journey to our more per-
fect existence in the next life. Aquinas, under the influence of Aristotle, struggles
to preserve an integral view of the human person as mind and body, but in the end,
with the immortality of the soul at stake, has to concede that incorporeal existence
is intelligible. As such, genuine human fulfilment, happiness and self-realisation
are only possible in the next world, although ironically, having overcome our
mortal bodies, we have also ceased to be human. The idea of escaping the flesh
and becoming a pure mind also appears in Descartes, whose sceptical arguments
seem to show that we may have no body, but we cannot doubt that we exist as a
thinking thing. Hence, the famous Cartesian dualism, the idea that human beings
are a combination of immaterial mind and material body.
Neo’s moral progress in The Matrix can thus be read in Platonic, Christian
and even Cartesian terms. What is not so plausible, however, is any attempt to
read it as the process of becoming a Nietzschean ubermensch. Nietzsche is one
of the most strident critics of the Platonic, Christian and Cartesian desire to
escape the flesh, which he sees as symptomatic of a hatred or disdain for this
world and the body that is ultimately self-destructive. For Nietzsche, far from
representing human beings as they most essentially are, the pure mind is an
impoverished, reduced person. For his part, Nietzsche rejects the idea of the self
as non-bodily and immortal. He conceives of the self as a ‘mortal soul’, a soul
that is not distinct from the body, or as he puts it in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, a
soul that is ‘only a word for something in the body’ (Nietzsche 1969, 61). In
other words, the true self is not identified with intellectual abilities but with the
emotions, drives and energies of the body, which are crucial even for our intel-
lectual and spiritual life. Nietzsche certainly has the ideal of the overman, in
which human beings overcome themselves, but this does not involve transcend-
ing the body. It is a strictly this-worldly transcendence. From this point of view,
The Matrix, with its vision of moral progress and perfection through escape from
the physical body, looks decidedly anti-Nietzschean.
As noted earlier, Nietzsche’s conception of moral progress also differs from
that envisaged by Marx. Marx sees human progress as something to be achieved
communally by transforming society, whereas for Nietzsche self-perfection is the
work of the solitary human being. If the masses, the herd, conform to traditional
herd values, Nietzsche’s overmen are independent, sovereign individuals. They
are also in touch with themselves, as the modern jargon has it. If religion and
modern society have led to our repudiating our vital instincts and desires, the
overman embraces those energies, harnessing and shaping them. They feel deeply
but their passions are controlled. If anything, Nietzsche’s ideal is most reminis-
cent of Aristotle, who develops an alternative to both the Platonic denial of the
passions and their uninhibited expression in the idea of virtue as rational passions.
One issue that arises in connection with Nietzsche, however, is whether his ideal
is too individualistic. There is clearly a turn to the individual, and individuality
for Nietzsche requires working on oneself, self-overcoming, perfecting oneself.
But this self-perfection has to be achieved independently of others, requiring us
to break from the common ideals of society. That there is no reference to social
Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves 211
existence except as a threat to one’s self-perfection might seem questionable,
given that we exist in the midst of social relations. Nonetheless, this insistence
that genuinely human, ‘authentic’ existence is only possible in isolation from
society is a persisting theme, not only in Nietzsche but also in his contemporary
Kierkegaard, and the twentieth-century existentialists who succeeded them both.
Kierkegaard
Sø ren Kierkegaard (1813–1855) also wants to affirm the individual in the face of
society. In terms of philosophical history, he sets himself firmly against Hegel’s
vision of a collective human subject that realises itself in history, the subject
that finds its way into Marx’s thinking in the form of species being. This for
Kierkegaard is an abstract, inhuman vision of humanity, remote from the concrete
human existence we actually live. For him, Hegel is like someone who has built a
magnificent palace but continues to live alongside it in a hovel (Kierkegaard 1975,
519). His philosophy does not address the situation of real, individual human
beings. By contrast, Kierkegaard’s focus is very much on what it is to exist as
an individual human being. Insofar as the concrete individual appears in Hegel’s
system, it is only as an instrument or means to the realisation of the collective
subject, Spirit. The free individual, standing in opposition to social morality and
political institutions, is an aberration, indicating that Spirit has become alienated
from itself, and progress consists in overcoming this alienation and reconciling
the free individual and the community. Kierkegaard takes the opposite path. He
is much more interested in promoting the free individual in opposition to society.
Whereas for Nietzsche the individual to be promoted is the one who is strong
enough to fashion values for themselves, to give shape to their lives indepen-
dently of others, the individual for Kierkegaard is above all the free subject. What
is central to individual existence is one’s subjectivity, which is manifested in free-
dom, the freedom to choose, make personal decisions, commit ourselves to a way
of life and take responsibility for what we choose. Kierkegaard wants to remind
people of what it is to be an individual human being, a free subject. He seeks to
rehabilitate the notions of the personal, the particular and the subjective, and he
wants to do so in the face of what he calls ‘objective’ ways of thinking and acting.
Objective ways of thinking are abstract, impersonal, disinterested ways of think-
ing about the world that downplay, deny or forget individual human subjectivity.
As Katalin Balog puts it: ‘Objectivity is an orientation towards reality based on
abstracting away, in various degrees, from subjective experience, and from indi-
vidual points of view’ (Balog 2016). Such abstract, impersonal thinking might be
appropriate in a scientific context, but for Kierkegaard, it is entirely inappropriate
for thinking about human existence. On his view, the great illusion that indi-
viduals suffer is that of thinking and acting in ways that deny their subjectivity
and freedom.
For Kierkegaard, culture is increasingly being characterised by this imper-
sonal objective thinking, which manifests itself in a number of ways. In the
social sphere, people subordinate themselves more and more to the crowd, the
212 Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves
abstract rule of the majority. They readily discard their individuality, the burden
of defining their own direction through their own individual decisions, in favour
of unthinking conformity with mass opinion, which they take to be the locus of
truth. In the moral sphere, people conform to accepted values, living their lives
in unthinking conformity with formalised rules. They don’t take the trouble to
decide for themselves how they should live. They just go along with moral prin-
ciples that have been codified and handed down to them by others. Kierkegaard is
also concerned with the religious sphere of life. He does not reject religion, like
Nietzsche, but he is highly critical of what it has become in the modern age. For
Kierkegaard, Christianity has also become afflicted with the objective tendency.
It has become a public institution devoid of spirit, whose teachings are lifeless and
formalistic, objectified into doctrines that can be learnt off by heart, and rituals
that can be participated in without passion or feeling. These dead, external trap-
pings of religious life do not require any personal commitment or inward change.
On the contrary, they positively discourage personal passion and commitment.
For Kierkegaard, the actually existing church is a distraction from an authentic
religious life. Despite this harsh critique, however, religious thinking plays an
important role in Kierkegaard’s thinking, as we will see in a moment.
In all these cases of objective thinking, we lose touch with what for Kierkegaard
is most essentially human, namely our subjectivity, our capacity to make personal
decisions, to commit ourselves passionately and deliberately to a way of life. To
think and act objectively is to stand apart from our lives rather than living them,
to live by abstract principles and objective measures. The proper role of philoso-
phy for Kierkegaard is to criticise the illusion of objectivity, and as he puts it in
Concluding Unscientific Postscript, to help us ‘become subjective’ (Kierkegaard
2009, 140). This for Kierkegaard is the authentic form of human existence. In a
sense, of course, we don’t have to work at being human. Physically and biologi-
cally, we already exist as human beings. We have two legs, two arms and are able
to do various relatively sophisticated things characteristic of our species. Even if
we are just part of the unthinking crowd, we are still in this sense human beings.
But for Kierkegaard, this is a very mundane sense of ‘being human’. When he
talks of being human, he wants to describe how human beings ought to be, what
it is to live a fully human life. And being authentically human for Kierkegaard
means becoming a moral agent, choosing one’s values and committing oneself to
a way of life. So to exist authentically as a human being, to become subjective,
is for Kierkegaard a task and an achievement, indeed the ‘highest task’ facing a
human being.
Kierkegaard often uses literary devices to deepen the reader’s subjective
engagement with the issues of human existence he is examining. More generally,
the existentialist concern with human existence helps explain why literature has
often been used as a vehicle for existentialist ideas. Through novels and plays,
existentialists have sought to evoke the human experience in all its richness, in
the face of more objective or impersonal forms of representation. Film also pro-
vides an effective medium for evoking subjective experience, with the advantage
of being able to actually show faces and conduct, as well as having access to
Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves 213
devices like the close-up and the point of view shot. Dreyer’s The Passion of Joan
of Arc is a case in point. In the midst of her trial, the relentless close-ups of actor
Falconneti’s face succeed in conveying an inward passion that cannot be com-
municated in words. The church authorities, through institutional language and
scholastic arguments, try to challenge the veracity of Joan’s religious experience
or to recast it as something of demonic origin. At every turn, their efforts are con-
fronted by the immediacy of the subjective experience that is testified to in Joan’s
suffering countenance (see Birzache 2014, 9–10).
Insofar as subjectivity is the capacity to make decisive personal choices, to
commit oneself deliberately and passionately to a way of life, Kierkegaard thinks
that rationality has its limits. We can consistently apply an existing framework of
values, but Kierkegaard is most interested in the point where we have to choose
the framework itself. Kierkegaard’s denunciation of objectivity is also a rejection
of the security of pre-existing value systems, ready-made rules handed down to us
by others. ‘Becoming subjective’ means we choose our values, commit ourselves
to a way of life. And since we are not making such choices on the basis of a frame-
work of values, but choosing the values themselves, there is no guidance for these
choices. They can only be chosen through a pure act of commitment, a passionate
‘leap’ of choice. Not surprisingly, given the enormous responsibility involved
when there is nothing we can turn to for support, Kierkegaard emphasises anxiety
or anguish as an essential ingredient of subjective existence. We feel anguish, the
‘dizziness of freedom’, when faced with a range of possibilities, which we must
choose between without any external guidance.
Kierkegaard also speaks of the task of becoming subjective as a process of
‘transformation to inwardness’, or the ‘self-activity of appropriation’ (Kierkegaard
2009, 244). This means that to become subjective is to appropriate to myself, to
make my own, a way of living. I make a possible way of life inward to me by
committing myself to it, passionately choosing or embracing it. Subjectivity is
this process of passionate appropriation. And since subjective human existence is
also true human existence, a life is a true one to the extent that I have a personal,
passionate commitment to it, to the extent that I make it my own. Its truth lies in
the commitment, passion and decisiveness with which I appropriate or embrace a
way of life, just as the truth of a lover’s declaration of love lies in the passionate
commitment with which they make their declaration. This is why Kierkegaard
says that ‘truth is subjectivity’ (Kierkegaard 2009, 200). When the question of
truth is raised in an objective manner, appropriate in a scientific context, we are
concerned with the object to which the knower is related, whether the actual state
of affairs is as we say it is. When the question of truth is raised subjectively,
in relation to human existence, we are concerned with how we relate to some-
thing, the passion with which we embrace it. As far as my subjective existence
is concerned, truth lies in the commitment and decisiveness with which I appro-
priate a way of life. By exercising my freedom, passionately committing myself
to a way of life, I make it true for me. In this manner, in The Passion of Joan of
Arc, the truth of Joan’s religious experience is the personal, subjective truth of
her commitment.
214 Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves
There are numerous religious references in Kierkegaard’s work because
he thinks that the most subjective and authentic form of human existence is
Christianity. Christianity involves the most intense subjectivity, the purest choice
and faith is the highest passion. This is because objectively, for disinterested rea-
son, Christianity leaves a lot to be desired. It is impossible to know whether God
actually exists; and Christianity’s central notion of the incarnation, the union of an
eternal, infinite God and a historical finite man in the figure of Christ is, rationally
speaking, unintelligible, an extreme paradox for rational understanding. There is
no rational justification whatsoever for faith or religious belief; it is objectively
speaking quite unjustifiable. By the same token, this means that faith has noth-
ing to do with objective thinking or justification. It requires instead a completely
subjective, passionate commitment, a pure leap of faith. The idea of pure faith is
embodied for Kierkegaard in his hero, the biblical character Abraham, whom he
discusses in Fear and Trembling. The test of faith is whether one’s beliefs can
be held in the face of overwhelming objective evidence to the contrary. Abraham
consented to sacrifice his son Isaac on God’s command, an action that is brutal,
unjustifiable and meaningless according to human standards. Its sole justification
is that it was an act of faith.
There are however a number of issues with Kierkegaard’s account. There is, of
course, the extreme individualism, the insistence that an authentic human exist-
ence is only possible in isolation from society. As a moral ideal, this comes up
against the fact that human beings inevitably exist in the midst of social relation-
ships. This is a persistent issue for the twentieth-century existentialist thinkers
still to come. Secondly, there is the idea of religious belief as a matter of a pure,
ungrounded leap of faith. The problem is that there is no reason why this path
should lead us to Christianity. Any belief would surely be legitimate, as long as
it was objectively unjustifiable and embraced through a leap of faith. We might
wonder how we could possibly distinguish genuine from inauthentic positions
here, if the only ground for them is the passionate commitment? On the face of
it, in The Passion of Joan of Arc, it seems legitimate to ask whether what we are
witnessing is a martyr or a confused, delusional young woman. But the question
cannot even be posed if the truth of her position lies entirely in the commitment
with which she embraces it. More broadly, if the authentic, properly human life
is the life in which one commits oneself decisively to a way of life, it would seem
that what counts as a proper way of living is very much up to the agent. What is
morally important here is not what we do but how we decide and act, and it might
be thought that this makes moral decisions entirely arbitrary. Nonetheless, this
is the ethical position that emerges, particularly in the writings of Kierkegaard’s
twentieth-century existentialist successors, to whom we now turn.
Plot
Old college friends and housemates John Brandon (John Dall) and
Philip (Farley Granger) decide to prove their superiority by committing
232 Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves
the perfect murder. The victim is their friend David Kentley (Dick Hogan),
whom they strangle and put in a large trunk to dispose of later. Not con-
tent with killing David, they invite a small group that includes their for-
mer teacher Rupert (James Stewart), David’s father Mr Kentley (Cedric
Hardwicke), his aunt and fiancé e over to their apartment for an intimate
dinner party. Brandon decides it would be even more interesting if the
dinner was served on the trunk holding David’s body.
Over drinks, Rupert expounds his theory that murder should be an
art, reserved for the few who are superior beings. It is this thinking that
impressed Brandon and Philip, who regard themselves as superior beings.
When Kentley asks who will decide who is superior, Brandon responds
that men of intellectual and cultural superiority are above traditional moral
concepts. Kentley thinks he can discern Nietzsche’s notion of the super-
man in this and says that Hitler also espoused Nietzschean beliefs. As the
evening progresses, Kentley becomes worried about his son’s failure to
turn up and Rupert tries to determine where David might have gone. Philip
and Brandon’s behaviour arouses his suspicions. After Kentley’s wife tel-
ephones to say that David is not at home, the guests hurriedly leave.
Rupert notices that the hat he was mistakenly given on the way out
has David’s initials in it. He returns, claiming to have forgotten his ciga-
rette case. Once inside, he speculates about what happened to David.
He reconstructs the crime, then pulls a piece of rope out of his pocket
and starts to play with it. Philip becomes agitated. Rupert finds David’s
body in the trunk. When Brandon explains why they committed the mur-
der, and inspired by his own views, Rupert responds that they have given
his words a meaning he never intended. He opens the window and fires
several gunshots into the air. Together, they wait for the police to arrive.
Key Scenes
1 Brandon and Philip justify their murder as a work of art, an act
reserved for strong, superior types. However, Philip is clearly a
weak individual, very dependent on Brandon. When he shows signs
of panicking, Brandon admonishes him: ‘We agreed there was only
one crime we could commit, that of making a mistake. Being weak is
a mistake’. Philip: ‘Because it’s being human?’ Brandon: ‘Because
it’s being ordinary’ [10.00–13.02].
2 According to Brandon, their former teacher Rupert, is ‘the one man
likely to suspect. He’s the one man who might appreciate this from
our angle, the artistic one’. But he is sure that they are superior
even to him: ‘He hasn’t the nerve. Oh, intellectually, he could’ve
Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves 233
come along. He’s brilliant. But he’s a little too fastidious. He could’ve
invented and admired but he never could have acted. That’s where
we’re superior. We have courage. Rupert doesn’t’ [15.28–16.36].
Brandon’s constant assertions of superiority come across as juve-
nile, arrogant posturing on his part. In truth, neither Brandon nor
Philip are particularly impressive individuals.
3 Over dinner, Rupert expounds mock-seriously on murder as an
art and a privilege that should be reserved for superior individuals.
Brandon weighs in, adding that the victims are going to be ‘inferior
beings whose lives are unimportant anyway’. Mr Kentley disap-
proves, asking: ‘Who will decide who is inferior?’ Brandon: ‘The privi-
leged few who commit it … those men of such intellectual and cultural
superiority that they’re above the traditional moral concepts. Good
and evil, right and wrong were invented for the ordinary average man,
the inferior man, because he needs them’. Kentley: ‘So you agree
with Nietzsche and his theory of the superman’. Brandon: ‘Yes, I do’.
Kentley: ‘So did Hitler’. Brandon rejects this connection with Fascism,
but only because he thinks that the Nazis murdered stupidly, without
art or discrimination [35.05–37.22]. Whether Brandon has understood
Nietzsche’s ‘theory of the superman’ is another question. His take on
Nietzsche is very much like the Nazi misappropriation of Nietzsche’s
thinking, which turned it into a justification for state-based murder.
4 Rupert discovers Brandon and Philip’s crime, repudiates their inter-
pretation of his views and disabuses them of the idea that they are
intellectually and culturally superior individuals. Brandon: ‘Rupert,
remember the discussion we had before with Mr Kentley? Remember
we said, “the lives of inferior beings are unimportant”? Remember
we said, we’ve always said, you and I, that moral concepts of good
and evil and right and wrong don’t hold for the intellectually supe-
rior? … That’s all we’ve done … lived what you and I have talked’.
Rupert: ‘If nothing else, a man should stand by his words. But you’ve
given my words a meaning that I never dreamed of! And you’ve tried
to twist them into a cold, logical excuse for your ugly murder! Well,
they never were that, Brandon, and you can’t make them that! …
By what right do you dare say that there’s a superior few to which
you belong? By what right did you dare decide that that boy in there
was inferior and therefore could be killed?’ [1.11.26–1.15.08]. To be
fair, Brandon and Philip don’t seem to have twisted Rupert’s words
so much as taken seriously views he presumably intended only for
intellectual amusement.
234 Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves
Fight Club
Fight Club is a lively 1999 film directed by David Fincher (Seven, the
Game, Panic Room, Zodiac). It is based on the Chuck Palahniuk novel
of the same name. The film starts at the end and then backtracks so
we see how we got there. Along the way, there are various criticisms of
life in late capitalist consumer society and various forms of rebellion are
considered. The film is also susceptible to a Nietzschean interpretation.
Plot
The film begins with the unnamed narrator (Edward Norton) in a sky-
scraper with a gun in his mouth. We then go back to see the narrator
as a mild-mannered but discontented employee of a major car manu-
facturer, who is obsessed with fitting out his apartment with IKEA fur-
niture and is suffering from insomnia. The doctor tells him to attend a
support group for testicular cancer survivors if he wants to meet people
who really have problems. This works for a while. Then he meets Marla
(Helena Bonham Carter), another ‘faker’ who recognises him as such,
bringing back his insomnia.
The narrator has the worst day of his life. An airline loses his luggage
and his apartment blows up, destroying all of his possessions. He meets
Tyler Durden (Brad Pitt), a soap salesman. Tyler invites him to move in
with him and the two share a ‘dilapidated house in a toxic waste part of
town’. Tyler has various views on freedom and empowerment. After get-
ting the narrator to hit him, the two begin to fight. Soon, others find out
about this new form of therapy and Fight Club is born – an underground
organisation that encourages men to beat each other up.
Tyler’s Fight Club mutates into Project Mayhem, an urban terrorist
group that commits acts of anti-corporate vandalism in the city. The nar-
rator is left out of Tyler’s activities with the Project. He and Tyler have an
argument and Tyler disappears from the narrator’s life. The narrator tries
to shut down Project Mayhem. He finally realises that he is Tyler Durden,
who has been taking control while he is asleep.
The narrator finally confronts Tyler in the skyscraper, as Tyler is about
to demolish the buildings of the major credit card companies in order to
bring down the financial system. This is the point where we came in. The
narrator takes control and shoots himself through the cheek, killing his
alter-ego. Marla is brought in by Tyler’s lackeys. The narrator and Marla
watch the buildings explode outside the windows, standing side by side
and holding hands. A traditional happy ending is staged against a back-
drop of mass destruction
Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves 235
Key Scenes
1 After the narrator’s apartment has blown up, Durden appears and
counsels the narrator to renounce his consumerism and enslave-
ment to possessions. According to Durden: ‘We’re consumers.
We’re by-products of a lifestyle obsession. Murder, crime, poverty –
these things don’t concern me’. The real problem is ‘celebrity maga-
zines, television with five hundred channels, some guy’s name on my
underwear … Things you own end up owning you’. As for the con-
sumerist ideal of a perfect existence, Durden tells the narrator: ‘I say
never be complete, stop being perfect. Let’s evolve’ [29.10–31.22].
2 Durden again – ‘Our fathers were our models for God. If our fathers
bailed, what does that tell you about God?’ Tyler argues not that
there is no god, but that God hates human beings. ‘We don’t need
him’ he tells the narrator. ‘We are God’s unwanted children’. Then:
‘It’s only after we have lost everything that we are free to do any-
thing’ [1.03.11–1.04.05]. Tyler insists that people need to renounce
dependence on God and God-like authority figures; and indeed, that
rejecting them is a liberation. This echoes the existentialist view that
the collapse of religious belief opens the way for human beings to
exercise their freedom and choose their own values.
3 At a Fight Club meeting, Tyler rails against economic exploitation
and advertising: ‘I see in Fight Club the strongest and smartest men
who have ever lived. I see all this potential – God damn it, an entire
generation pumping gas and waiting tables; they’re slaves with
white collars. Advertisements have them chasing cars and clothes,
working jobs we hate so we can buy shit they don’t need’ [1.09.49–
1.10.38]. Tyler’s tirade sounds like a Marxist critique of capitalist
exploitation and advertising as indoctrination. However, he does
not appear to be endorsing the Marxist idea that in capitalist soci-
ety human beings are alienated from their ‘species-being’. In fact,
it is unclear what he thinks is being denied in contemporary society
and finding expression through the underground, men-only Fight
Clubs. Is it humanity’s primal instincts, or perhaps an old-fashioned
idea of masculinity, of the ‘real man’? The situation is complicated
because while Tyler lauds the Fight Club participants, they do not
come across as particularly impressive specimens, so there may be
an element of irony here.
4 An applicant for Project Mayhem arrives on the porch of the house,
staring rigidly ahead, military style and dressed in black pants, shirt
and shoes. Tyler, to the narrator: ‘If the applicant waits at the door
236 Slaves, Supermen and Authentic Selves
At the end of the Swedish comedy-drama Force Majeure, Tomas’s wife Ebba
finds herself in a situation not unlike that faced by her husband at the start of
the film, a situation in which she being is put to the test. In her husband’s case,
the testing situation was the controlled avalanche that seemed to have gone out
of control, threatening him and his family on the ski hotel restaurant balcony.
Embarrassingly, he panicked and fled the scene, abandoning his wife and chil-
dren to their fate, though saving his phone. Now at the end of the ski holiday, the
family is in the midst of another confronting situation. As they are leaving for the
airport, the bus-driver drives badly down the tight hair-pin bends, braking sharply
at each retaining wall, seemingly threatening at every turn to send the bus plum-
meting into the ravine. Now it is Ebba who abandons the family in a panic, yelling
at the bus driver to stop and let her out. This is especially problematic for Ebba,
who throughout the film has been the caring wife and mother, the one who did not
run, so unlike her cowardly husband. Now, she has acted in the same way he did.
Earlier on, however, there was another confronting situation for Ebba that was
perhaps even more challenging one. Here, what she encounters is not a situation in
which she fails to live up to her defining values and ideals, but another person who is
clearly refusing to conform to those values and ideals, to the female role she identifies
with. This person is her friend Charlotte, who rejects the role of wife and mother in
a nuclear family, engineering an open relationship that allows her to go on holiday
and romance ski instructors. Here, in the face of someone who is ‘other’, the norms
and values that define Ebba’s very identity are themselves under challenge. In the
preceding chapter, the focus was on the existentialist ethics of authenticity, where the
concern is the relationship we have with ourselves. In this chapter, we will discuss a
number of more recent approaches to ethics that are especially concerned with our
response to others and especially those who are different to us. This ethics of the other
includes the ethics of care that emerges out of twentieth-century feminist thought, and
the ethical thinking of twentieth-century philosophers Levinas and Foucault.
Figure 6.1 Casablanca: Rick and the refugee (Michael Curtiz, 1942. Credit: Warner
Brothers Pictures).
Nonetheless, when we next see him, he is standing behind her husband, at the rou-
lette wheel trying to win the money to buy the papers on the black market, ensuring
that he bets on the ‘right’ number. We might see in this, Rick responding ethically
to Annina. In appealing to him, she has ceased to be one of the anonymous mass of
refugees waiting to escape from Casablanca. She has acquired a face, demanding
ethical responsibility. Responding to this summons, Rick abandons his self-serving
perspective and sacrifices material advantage in order to help her and her husband.
If as has been suggested the film can be interpreted as a piece of domestic wartime
propaganda designed to encourage the American public to turn away from self-
interested isolationism and support the war effort, it might be seen as resorting to
both Levinasian and Kantian strategies to do so. It invokes both the particular other
in need of help and the higher duty or greater cause.
Things seem more straightforward in Schindler’s List, in which it is clearly
an encounter with a unique other that brings about the ethical transformation in
Schindler. The moment of transformation comes as Schindler and his mistress,
out riding, come to a hilltop overlooking the Krakow ghetto. There, under the
direction of the fearsome Amon Goeth, the ghetto is being cleared, with Jews
being brutally rounded up for deportation to the concentration camps. From a
distance, they are anonymous figures being lined up, marched away and loaded
into trucks. Nonetheless in the midst of these anonymous individuals, Schindler
encounters the face of the other, in the form of one young girl. In a largely black
and white film, this encounter with the other is articulated cinematically through
the use of colour, in the form of the girl’s coat which alone is coloured, marking
her out in the scene. It is not subtle, and calls attention to itself as a cinematic
device, yet it is still strangely effective in drawing the viewer’s attention. As John
252 Encounters with Aliens
Wright puts it, ‘The red coat becomes, for Schindler, the “face” of the Holocaust
victim, pulling him from his distanced position astride the hilltop into the horror
of the Nazi atrocities’ (Wright 2008, 63).
This invocation of the other in Schindler’s List stands in direct contrast to
the strategy in another tale of the Holocaust, Son of Saul (Lá szló Nemes, 2015).
The film follows a day and a half in the life of Auschwitz inmate Saul (Gé za
Rö hrig). Through tight close-ups and point of view shots, the film invokes the
character’s subjective experience in the face of an environment that utterly denies
this subjectivity and treats individuals as pure things to be processed. Rather than
invoking a Levinasian other, this is more in line with Kierkegaard’s efforts to
restore the self and subjective experience (see Balog 2016). This also serves as a
reminder of film’s capacity to portray widely differing kinds of experience. It has
the capacity to evoke subjective experience, a personal point of view, serving it
in the portrayal of existentialist themes; and it also has the capacity to open up a
sense of otherness, to amongst other things portray the encounter with the singular
Levinasian other.
In these Holocaust films, we also encounter the immediate historical context
for Levinas’s ethics of the other, the ‘negative othering’ of Jews by the Nazis. In
Nazi antisemitism, an ultimate evil for Levinas, the other in their difference is
seen as foreign and threatening, to be rejected, excluded and destroyed. This also
involves their being rendered faceless in that all those who are to be destroyed
are considered first of all as members of a group, members of the condemned
race, rather than as unique individuals. This is reflected in the early scenes of
Schindler’s List when the Jews are being processed by administrators, their names
being typed into lists, as they arrive to establish the Krakow ghetto. They are
thereby registered individually but also turned into interchangeable members of
a race, so many objects to be counted and processed. It is a precursor for what is
to come. Having been rendered faceless, these people no longer call for an ethi-
cal response and that ultimately makes mass murder possible. There is something
chillingly reminiscent of this attitude in the speech Harry Lime (Orson Welles)
gives to Holly Martins (Joseph Cotten), high atop the Ferris wheel in devastated
post-war Vienna in The Third Man (Carol Reed 1949). Petty criminal Lime, who
has been selling watered-down penicillin on the black market, resulting in the
deaths of numerous people, indicates that he can feel no guilt for anonymous
victims he has never seen. Gesturing to the tiny figures far below, he says to
his friend Martins: ‘Tell me. Would you really feel any pity if one of those dots
stopped moving forever?’
Moving beyond the Second World War, the singular other is evoked in the more
contemporary military context of drone warfare in Eye in the Sky (Gavin Hood,
2015). Warfare conducted by firing remotely controlled missiles from high-flying
surveillance drones seems to definitively preclude a face to face encounter where an
ethical response might be possible. Instead, we are likely, once again, to be faced with
Lime’s anonymous moving dots, which make no moral demands on the viewer and
which will not arouse pity if they stop moving forever. The film imagines the drone’s
associated ground-based surveillance technology revealing the face of the other.
Encounters with Aliens 253
It portrays an attempt to take out a terrorist cell in a Nairobi suburb, using a mis-
sile remotely fired from a drone. The operation is stymied by the appearance on
the scene of a young girl (Aisha Takow) who sets up to sell bread outside the
terrorists’ compound. While the individuals in the house are very much generic
terrorists, and the surrounding streets filled with anonymous local militia and
civilians, the girl (like the girl in Schindler’s List also wearing red) is singled out
as an individual, the face of the civilian population. And once again, the other in
their singularity calls for an ethical response from those watching.
At the same time, the responses of the military and politicians observing from
afar are less than ideal from a Levinasian perspective. The military figures, the
UK general Benson (Alan Rickman) and colonel Powell (Helen Mirren) show a
preference for utilitarian calculation, their repeated argument being that the death
of one civilian is justified if it will prevent the death of many at the hands of the
terrorists, should they escape to carry out their plot. They are frustrated by the
rules of engagement and the hesitation of their political masters. The politicians
are shown hesitating not so much because of any moral scruples but because the
death of the girl might be problematic should news of civilian casualties get out. It
would play badly with the public and be a propaganda coup for the terrorists. It is
those most directly involved, the two drone pilots Watts (Aaron Paul) and Gershon
(Phoebe Fox), tasked with aiming and firing the missiles, and watching the events
unfold on their monitors, who most keenly feel the ethical demand the girl is mak-
ing on them, and the most internal conflict over what they are required to do.
One possible weakness in Levinas’s account might be that while it is con-
cerned with the ethical relations with the other, the responsibility required from
the self seems only able to be summoned by a recognisably human face. Non-
human others can only count ethically insofar as they have a face in this sense.
Caesar, the hero of Rise of Planet of the Apes, also happens to have the most
human-looking face amongst the apes. This assists directly in invoking the audi-
ence’s empathy and concern, and provides an analogue for Levinas’s emphasis on
the ethical importance of the face. However, it also raises the question of whether
ethical relations in Levinas’s sense are possible with creatures that do not have a
recognisable face, that are inhumanly other. Films often emphasise the unearthli-
ness of movie aliens by ensuring they do not have anything resembling human
features, which also means that they do not elicit any ethical response from us.
For example, the alien creatures in Alien are contrived to look insect-like, reptilian
and mechanical all at once, which underscores their non-humanness and makes it
palatable for them to be slaughtered without any qualms. For Ripley herself, there
is no question that the species should be exterminated. There is no possibility of
care or concern in this instance. But we may on reflection want to question the
cavalier destruction of any life-form, even one as faceless as this (see Lindenmuth
2017, 69–70). That a moral position is unable to raise this issue is arguably a
problem for that position.
In the Alien series, as it happens, one of the aliens does eventually come to elicit
our sympathy and its death becomes a moment of genuine pathos. This happens
at the end of the fourth film in the original cycle, Alien Resurrection (Jean-Pierre
254 Encounters with Aliens
Jeunet, 1997). Ripley, cloned back into existence by military scientists after her
demise in Alien 3 (David Fincher, 1992), has had her DNA used to create an
alien/human hybrid. Before its birth, Ripley is able to say sardonically that she is
‘the monster’s mother’. But once she comes face to face with the creature in actu-
ality, it evokes a real feeling of compassion in her, echoing her earlier concern for
Newt. The creature still has to be killed, but the death is now a wrenching scene
that brings Ripley to tears. At the same time, this only seems plausible because
the alien, having taken the form of the human/alien hybrid, is far more human-
looking than the usual aliens, with distinctly human facial features. The issue
remains that the ethical responsibility Levinas talks of seems only to be able to be
summoned by a recognisably human face.
Like the original aliens in the first Alien cycle, the alien bugs threatening
humanity in Paul Verhoeven’s Starship Troopers (1997) can be wiped out in vast
numbers without any moral discomfort because their insect features make them
seem inhumanly other. In this case, however, the film does not come to humanise
the other by giving the bugs a face, but rather contrives to make the humans inhu-
man. The hierarchical, quasi-military bug society turns out to have a very similar
structure to the human one. As gradually becomes apparent, the human society
in the film is also a totalitarian, anti-individualist society, the members of which
are similarly interchangeable, ultimately faceless functionaries. In the final scene,
general Carl Jenkins (Neil Patrick Harris) of Military Intelligence confronts his
opposite number, the recently captured ‘brain bug’, in what looks very like an
SS uniform. Indeed, the human society in the film has many of the trappings of
the Nazi state, including grandiose Albert Speer-style architecture, SS-style uni-
forms, jingoistic slogans and viciously xenophobic propaganda. There is even a
rather ‘Aryan’ look to the heroic starship troopers themselves. Meanwhile, their
enemy is portrayed as entirely other, a mass to be simply wiped out. It is perhaps
no accident that a favourite trope of Nazi propaganda was to compare the Jews to
insects that needed to be exterminated en masse.
Another area where Levinas’s account is potentially open to question has to do
with his conception of the self and the extent to which his account gives priority
to the other over the self. As one commentator puts it, Levinas’s self is ‘power-
less against the gravitational pull of its egoism, condemned to a hopeless amo-
rality unless the Other intervenes and saves it from itself’ (Hofmeyr 2006, 113).
Only the intervention of the other can turn the self into an ethical subject, and so
the self is completely dependent on the other for its emergence. The relationship
here is profoundly one-sided, leading us to wonder whether a self that is so pas-
sive could ever become an ethical subject. A recognisable ethical subject tries to
live up to certain moral rules and values, in terms of which it reflects on desires,
makes choices and undertakes actions. In short, it plays an active role in being
an ethical subject. Our couple from Force Majeure, Tomas and Ebba, represent
two such ethical subjects, each with certain ideals of behaviour, a certain moral
identity, which they are trying to live up to. Even if they fall spectacularly short
of their defining ideals in practice, they can only do so because they are trying to
live up to them in the first place. No doubt others play a role in one’s emergence
Encounters with Aliens 255
as an ethical subject, but it is difficult to see how, if one were entirely passive in
the process of self-formation, one could ever emerge as an active ethical being.
Finally, one might wonder if there is sufficient recognition by Levinas of the
political dimensions of his ethics of the other. Sherwin distinguished a feminine
ethics of care from a feminist ethics on this basis, because talking of a distinctively
female ethics of care and responsibility risks entrenching gender stereotypes that
have been associated with the oppression of women in Western cultures, while a
feminist ethics recognises and criticises the oppressive practices themselves. As
noted, Levinas also offers an ethics of responsiveness to the other, of responsibil-
ity and care, that he characterises as feminine, presumably having in mind stereo-
typically female traits. But he similarly does not concern itself with the practices
of power that might put women and other politically disempowered groups in the
position of the feminine, that might relegate them to the role of caring and taking
responsibility for others. As one commentator puts it, ‘Levinas’s philosophy can-
not be called “feminist” because it is not concerned with particular political con-
texts and specific oppressed groups’ (see Taylor 233). At this point, let us move
on to the third of our ethicists of the other, namely Foucault.
Experiments in Living
LEt’s conclude by saying a little about the idea of experiment here, this experi-
mental work of freedom. Here we are returning to a theme that was highlighted
in the Introduction. This experimental work is the opposite of searching for an
essential nature or true self within us to conform to, or of a moral philosophy that
looks for grounds to justify one’s moral judgements. Refusing who one is, and
experimenting with different ways of living that go beyond the limits of one’s
existing self, puts forms of life to the test of experience. This is a practical kind of
moral philosophy, reflecting through practice on how one ought to live.
This experimental activity is not unlike what Mill in On Liberty called ‘experi-
ments of living’ (Mill 1975, 72). There too we find a rejection of a priori, in
advance of experience, philosophical reflection about what the good life consists
in, in favour of testing conceptions of the good through the experiences we have
in living them. As Mill puts it, ‘The worth of different modes of life should be
proved practically’ (Mill 1975, 70). We also find this idea in Nietzsche, who talks
in Beyond Good and Evil of the ‘philosophers of the future’. Distinct from the
‘philosophical labourers’ (BGE 211) like Kant who seek to justify existing values,
the philosophers of the future will be ‘attempters’ or ‘experimenters’ (BGE 42,
210). They are not conducting scientific experiments but trying out new ways of
living in the world, different possibilities. They are the philosophers of the ‘dan-
gerous perhaps’ (BGE 2). The goal of such experimenting is, by living through
the problems, to determine the ‘wherefore and whither’ of humanity, the values
for human life. Determining values is a creative activity and the philosophers of
the future are creative in trying out new ways of living, new modes of life.
As has been noted, these experiments in living are not scientific experiments
aiming to explore our biology or psychology. They concern human beings as
moral beings, who choose and act in terms of a framework of moral values and
ideals constitutive of who they are, their identity. Nonetheless, our biological
and psychological capabilities have a bearing on the kinds of person we can be,
the forms of life we can lead. We have to exercise these capabilities, in order
Encounters with Aliens 263
to live various forms of life. However, they do not straightforwardly determine
the kinds of life human beings can aspire to. Rather, they make possible a range
of lives. Moreover, bodily capacities are themselves developed and enhanced in
accordance with various norms in the course of the training processes through
which individuals are turned into ethical subjects. So, what individuals can be
or do cannot be determined in advance. This can only be worked out in practice,
through the actual practice of exercising one’s skills and capacities. Nonetheless,
bodily capacities do set limits to the range of possible persons we can be or
lives that can be lived, which are restricted to what is within the capabilities of
human beings. A moral ideal or conception of the good life that it is beyond the
capabilities of human beings to realise would be empty and irrelevant. So, as has
been suggested at a number of points, ultimately there are practical constraints
on ethics.
The process of being turned into an ethical subject through training and sociali-
sation introduces its own constraints into the individual’s existence. These are the
internal limits or positive constraints mentioned earlier, in which the norms con-
stitutive of one’s identity or role delimit the class of actions that one is capable of
entertaining. These normative constraints may be socially imposed, but insofar as
they come to be internalised by the self, they are self-imposed; and for Foucault,
this work on the self can also involve breaking away from our defining norms,
going beyond the limits inherent in one’s identity, in order to experiment with
different ways of being oneself. Once again, this is not the complete rejection of
all norms, since without a normative framework of some sort one cannot func-
tion as an agent. Rather, it is a matter of looking at points where modification and
transformation might be possible. And again, this is very much an experimental
process. The possible selves one can be cannot be determined in advance of experi-
ence. They can only be established in practice by trying out different forms of life.
While there is not, on this view, any ideal form of life grounded in human
nature or reason that one can aspire to, and measure existing forms of life in terms
of, there is arguably what one commentator calls a ‘regulative principle’ implicit
in Foucault’s work, in terms of which existing social and political regimes might
be evaluated (Simons 1995, 86). The ideal is not a society without any constraints,
but one that is open enough to permit modification and transformation of its ruling
norms. As Foucault puts it, the important question is ‘not whether a culture with-
out constraints is possible or even desirable but whether the system of constraints
in which a society functions leaves individuals the ability to transform the system’
(Foucault 1997c, 147–148). This provides a measure for social progress, giving
us a sense in which some forms of social life are better than others. The standard
of progress here is not how closely society approaches a higher, more perfect
form, governed by wholly rational norms, as in Habermas’s conception of the
ideal society, deriving ultimately from Kant’s ideal of rational autonomy. Rather,
social progress is measured by the extent society moves away from dominative
forms of life, in which the possibilities for going beyond and modifying existing
constraints are limited. More positively, this is the extent to which the society has
room for experiments in self-transformation or the experimental work of freedom.
264 Encounters with Aliens
Films, which have been used in this book to explore various ethical positions,
also offer the opportunity for experimentation, reflection and self-transformation.
They play out virtual scenarios and life-stories in a concrete way and provide
the opportunity to not only concretely illustrate, but also reflect on various ethi-
cal theories, understood as embodying views about how to live. As noted in the
Introduction, film can portray ‘other, forbidden or surprising kinds of experience’,
and this is experience that goes beyond standard ways of thinking or prevailing
views of life and is capable of calling them into question. This is film experi-
ence understood as something more than an escapist, wish-fulfilling fantasy or a
portrayal of a world that comfortably confirms one’s existing presuppositions. It
offers the opportunity to critically reflect on these presuppositions, to call them
into question and potentially rethink them. In so doing, a film may reveal a way
of understanding life to be hollow and simplistic; or it might reveal a moral reality
that is more complex than an ethical theory can allow.
Such reflection can also be undertaken in relation to, the norms, values and
ideals that constitute our identity as moral agents, and which we try to conform
to or live up to in our actions. Force Majeure, for example, establishes an experi-
mental situation in which Tomas and Ebba are both subjected to challenging cir-
cumstances, inviting reflection on the extent to which they are capable in practice
of living up to the ideals and values that constitute their respective moral identi-
ties. As we have seen, Force Majeure also introduces another level of experimen-
tation, another way one might be put to the test of experience as a moral being.
This is Ebba’s confrontation with Charlotte. Here, the challenging experience that
the film presents is not the circumstance that confronts one with the possibility of
failing to live up to one’s defining ideals. Rather, it is the experience of another
person who refuses to live up to those ideals, who is already experimenting with
something different. This constitutes a challenge insofar as it implies that one’s
own cherished ideals may not be absolute or immutable, the only legitimate way
of being, a recognition that potentially calls them into question and opens the pos-
sibility that one might oneself experiment with different ways of being.
In Force Majeure, as it happens, Ebba resists acknowledging Charlotte’s way
of life as a legitimate alternative or questioning her own defining norms and val-
ues. Another film that portrays this kind of confronting experience, if in some-
what more surreal circumstances, is Being John Malkovich (Spike Jonze, 1999)
Written by Charlie Kaufman, the film not only portrays an encounter with another
that leads to self-transformation, but also alludes to film itself as a venue for such
self-transformative encounters. In the film, Craig Schwartz (John Cusack), filing
clerk and failed puppeteer, finds a passageway in his office, a mysterious portal
through which he can enter the mind of actor John Malkovich (John Malkovich
playing a fictionalised version of himself) and experience the world through
Malkovich’s eyes and ears (Figure 6.2). And like Rear Window, the first film
mentioned in this book, Being John Malkovich has something to say about cinema
and movie-watching. The journey into the portal can readily be seen as a metaphor
for going to the movies and the film itself suggests this comparison. In no time,
Craig is selling tickets to people so they can go through the portal and have the
‘Malkovich experience’. They are paying money to experience things they would
Encounters with Aliens 265
Figure 6.2 On the verge of cinematic self-transformation in Being John Malkovich (Spike
Jonze, 1999. Credit: Universal/Photofest).
not experience in their ordinary lives, to have the ‘other, forbidden or surprising’
kind of experience that makes movies so appealing.
At the same time, for the film’s main characters, their Malkovich experience is
something more than an escapist fantasy. It is an encounter with an other, another
person with a different way of being in the world, that offers a challenge to their
own. However, Craig, like Ebba in Force Majeure, does not find this encoun-
ter with the other conducive to self-questioning and self-transformation. It only
results in a re-affirmation of his rather drab identity. In Craig’s case, this is not
because he becomes defensive in the face of the other, but because he tries to
completely master and overpower them. Any difference that Malkovich might
represent is thereby overcome, and the ‘other is reduced to the same’. Thus, even
having managed to ‘become’ Malkovich, to take up a semi-permanent residency
in the actor’s mind, Craig does not succeed in escaping his former self. Instead
of becoming more like the actor, confident, desirable and cool, Craig only suc-
ceeds in turning Malkovich into a version of himself. Malkovich-as-Craig comes
increasingly to resemble Craig, looking thinner and acquiring Craig’s hairstyle,
hesitant mannerisms and generally depressed demeanour (see Ulin 2006).
Nonetheless, the film does acknowledge the possibility of self-transformation,
of changing or escaping from ourselves through our encounter with the other.
This is evident in the journey taken by Craig’s wife Lotte (Cameron Diaz).
Initially, Lotte pursues a course much like her husband’s. She seizes the oppor-
tunity to go through the portal and take the ride in Malkovich. When she finds
she can control the Malkovich body, she uses it to seduce Craig’s workplace
love-interest Maxine (Catherine Keener). However, unlike Craig, Lotte does
not end up reducing Malkovich to a version of herself. Rather, she finds, in
the experience of being in Malkovich, the possibility of a different standpoint
266 Encounters with Aliens
on the world, a different way of being; and in the light of this experience, she
resolves to change herself. Initially, she sees this transformation as a matter of
becoming her ‘real self’, a true nature or identity that she decides is actually
male. She contemplates sexual reassignment surgery to make her body match
this sense of who she really is. However, her transformation turns out to be less
about realising an underlying nature or essence than about going beyond the
limits of her existing self, trying out a different way of living. Lotte abandons
the idea that she is ‘really a man’ and does not go through with the idea of turn-
ing herself physically into one. Instead, she reinvents herself as a lesbian (see
Falzon 2011).
It is possible to engage with this intriguing film in a number of ways, but
with the present reading at least, the focus has been on using it to explore ethical
concerns. Bearing in mind the particular journey that Lotte takes, the trip into
Malkovich can be considered a cinematic representation of the possibility of self-
transformation through encounter with another. The particular aspect of ethics
that is illuminated here is the element of self-transcendence, rather than fidelity
to a set of norms or rules. By presenting this journey as a quasi-cinematic experi-
ence, the film is also a cinematic representation of the manner in which film itself,
by bringing us into contact with other, forbidden or surprising experiences, can be
an avenue for ethical reflection and self-transformation.
Plot
In 1941, Casablanca is a French colony controlled by Vichy France, the
puppet government set up in France after the country was defeated by
Germany. American expatriate Rick Blaine (Humphrey Bogart) owns
‘Rick’s Café Américain’, a nightclub and casino in Casablanca. He claims
to be neutral in all matters and to ‘stick his neck out for nobody’. Petty
crook Ugarte (Peter Lorre) tells Rick he has letters of transit obtained
by murdering two German couriers. These allow the bearers to travel
freely to Lisbon, the embarkation point for the still-neutral United States,
and are much sought after by the refugees stranded in Casablanca.
Encounters with Aliens 267
Ugarte plans to sell them at the club and asks Rick to look after them.
Before he can meet his contact, Ugarte is arrested by the local police
under the command of Captain Louis Renault (Claude Rains), the Vichy
prefect of police. Ugarte dies in custody without revealing that he gave
the letters to Rick.
Rick’s ex-lover Ilsa Lund (Ingrid Bergman) enters the nightclub and
asks house pianist Sam (Dooley Wilson) to play ‘As Time Goes By’. This
brings Rick over and he is stunned to see Ilsa. She is accompanied by
her husband, Victor Laszlo (Paul Henreid), a renowned fugitive Czech
Resistance leader. They need the letters of transit to escape to America
so he can continue his work. German Major Strasser (Conrad Veidt) has
come to Casablanca to make sure Laszlo doesn’t escape. That night,
Ilsa comes to Rick’s apartment to talk to him but, far gone with drink, he
refuses to listen to her. After she leaves, a flashback reveals the reason
for Rick’s bitterness. They had an affair in Paris and, with the German
forces approaching, had planned to flee the city together, but she failed
to turn up for their rendezvous at the train station, sending a note saying
they could never see each other again.
The next day, as Laszlo makes inquiries about the letters of tran-
sit, Rick’s business rival Ferrari (Sydney Greenstreet) tells him he sus-
pects Rick has them. When asked by Laszlo, Rick refuses to sell at any
price, telling him to ask his wife why. Newlywed refugee Annina Brandel
(Joy Page) has better luck. She asks Rick’s advice about the wisdom of
sleeping with Renault in order to get the travel visas she and her hus-
band need to escape. He seems indifferent to her plight, but then we see
him surreptitiously helping her husband win enough money at roulette
to buy the visas on the black market. Soon after, Strasser and some of
his officers start singing a German song. Laszlo orders the house band
to play the Marseillaise. Rick nods his assent, Laszlo starts singing, and
everyone joins in, drowning out the Germans. Enraged, Strasser has
Renault close the nightclub.
Ilsa confronts Rick in the deserted nightclub. When he refuses to give
her the letters, she threatens him with a gun, then confesses she still
loves him. She explains that when they met in Paris, she thought her
husband was dead but while preparing to flee with Rick learned he was
alive, though sick and in hiding. She left Rick without explanation to look
after him and to make sure Rick left Paris. No longer bitter, Rick agrees
to help, letting her believe she will stay with him when Laszlo leaves.
When Laszlo unexpectedly shows up, having narrowly escaped a police
raid on a Resistance meeting, Rick has waiter Carl (S.Z. Sakall) spirit
268 Encounters with Aliens
Ilsa away. Laszlo, aware of Rick’s feelings for Ilsa, tries to persuade him
to use the letters to take her to safety.
When the police arrest Laszlo on a minor charge, Rick persuades
Renault to release him, promising to set him up for the more serious
crime of possessing the letters of transit. To allay Renault’s suspicions,
he says that it is he and Ilsa who will be leaving. When Renault tries to
arrest Laszlo as arranged, Rick forces him at gunpoint to assist in their
escape. At the last moment, Rick makes Ilsa board the plane to Lisbon
with Laszlo. Strasser, tipped off by Renault, drives up, but is shot by
Rick. When police arrive, Renault orders them to ‘round up the usual
suspects’. Dumping the bottle of Vichy water he has been drinking into
the waste-paper basket, he suggests to Rick that they both join the Free
French Forces in nearby Brazzaville. They walk off together into the fog.
Key Scenes
1 Informed by Renault that there will be an arrest in the club, Rick
indicates that he has no intention of warning Ugarte, the intended
target: ‘I stick my neck out for nobody’. In this, he is established as
looking out primarily for his own interests and in a distinctly unheroic
manner, refusing to get involved in other people’s problems. If the
film is viewed as a piece of domestic political propaganda, Renault’s
approving response, ‘a wise foreign policy’, may be taken as an
ironic comment not only on Rick’s refusal to take any sort of stand,
but also on the United States’ isolationist foreign policy prior to join-
ing the war effort [17.22–17.45].
2 Nonetheless, there is also evidence of a potential for action that
goes beyond self-interest on Rick’s part. Renault points out that Rick
participated in anti-fascist struggles in the past, having run guns to
Ethiopia during its war with Italy and fought on the Loyalist side in
the Spanish Civil War. ‘I got well paid for it on both occasions’, Rick
insists, but Renault notes that the winning side ‘would have paid you
much better’ [19.45–20.17]. Rick also refuses to come in with busi-
ness rival Ferrari in the ‘trading of people’s lives’, working the black
market in exit visas. Ferrari’s response: ‘My dear Rick, when will you
realise that in this world today isolationism is no longer a practical
policy?’ Ferrari alludes to the film’s anti-isolationist theme while criti-
cising Rick for taking a principled stand in the matter [14.00–14.46].
3 Prior to Ilsa’s revelations about Paris, when newlywed refugee
Annina comes to the nightclub to ask Rick about sleeping with
Renault in order to get the travel visas she and her husband need
Encounters with Aliens 269
Force Majeure
Force Majeure is a 2014 Swedish comedy-drama, written and directed
by Ruben Ö stlund. The film’s male protagonist behaves in a distinctly
unheroic manner, abandoning his wife and children in order to save him-
self when a controlled avalanche looks to be going wrong. According to
the director: ‘I always had two goals when I was making Force Majeure.
Firstly, I wanted to create the most spectacular avalanche in film history.
Secondly, I wanted to increase the percentage of divorces in society’
(Gee 2014).
Plot
The film is set in an upmarket ski hotel, where good-looking, well-to-do
couple Tomas (Johannes Bah Kuhnke) and his wife Ebba (Lisa Loven
Kongsli), with their children, are spending their skiing holiday. The next
270 Encounters with Aliens
day, the family is sitting on the balcony of the hotel restaurant, hav-
ing lunch, when a controlled avalanche begins. When it doesn’t slow
down, panic erupts. Ebba shields the children but Tomas runs way. But
there was never any real danger. Tomas returns, the family sit down at
their table again and continue eating, now in silence. That evening, the
couple have dinner with Ebba’s new friend Charlotte (Karin Myrenberg).
Tomas introduces the story of the avalanche but omits his own behav-
iour. When Ebba reminds him of what he did, he insists that that isn’t
how he remembers it. Back in their room, Tomas sticks to his story,
which Ebba reluctantly agrees to, but not for long.
On day three, Ebba has an uncomfortable meeting with Charlotte.
That evening, the couple have dinner with old friends Mats (Kristofer
Hivju) and Fanni (Fanni Metelius). It is now Ebba who insists on recount-
ing the whole incident, Tomas’s humiliation only relieved by the appear-
ance of their son’s drone toy. While Tomas is out of the room putting his
son to bed, Mats and Ebba discuss his behaviour. Tomas returns and
insists once again that things didn’t happen as Ebba suggests. However,
he was filming the avalanche at the time and Ebba insists they look at
the footage. It becomes clear that the person holding it is running away.
Being forced to confront his behaviour leads Tomas to a crisis. The next
day, Ebba finds him in the hotel room wallowing in self-pity. The kids
come out of their bedroom and try to console their father, and Ebba
reluctantly joins in.
On the final day, the family, skiing together one last time, run into poor
conditions. Once they start skiing, Ebba gets separated from the others.
Now, Tomas tells the kids to stay put and rescues her. After Tomas’s tri-
umph, the family leaves on the hotel bus. The driver drives badly, threat-
ening to crash the bus. Now it is Ebba who panics and abandons the
family. She leaps from her seat and demands that the bus driver stop
to let her out. She does not, however, suffer any censure for this. Pretty
much everyone on the bus is happy to follow suit, though they now face
a long walk down the mountain and are likely to miss their flights home.
Key Scenes
1 The family is sitting on the restaurant balcony having lunch. On
the mountainside opposite a controlled avalanche begins. When it
shows no sign of slowing down, panic erupts on the balcony. Amidst
the chaos, Ebba shields the kids, but Tomas grabs his phone and
runs off-screen. It soon becomes clear that there was never any
real danger. Tomas returns and the family sit down at their table
Encounters with Aliens 271
This filmography lists the films that have been used in the book, with the pages
where they appear in the text.
This glossary contains key terms that have been used in the book, with the pages
where they appear in the text. It also lists the main thinkers discussed, along with
the texts referred to and their original dates of publication. In the book, I have
cited recent editions of these texts, so the dates given there are not always the
dates of original publication.
Adams, Jeffrey (2015) The Cinema of the Coen Brothers: Hard Boiled Entertainments,
New York: Columbia University Press.
Allison, Deborah (2004) ‘Don Siegel’, Senses of Cinema, 32. Retrieved from http://
sensesofcinema.com/2004/great-directors/siegel/.
Anchor, Robert (1967) The Enlightenment Tradition, New York: Harper and Row.
Annas, Julia (2008) ‘The Sage in Ancient Philosophy’, in F. Alesse et al. (eds.), Anthropine
Sophia, Naples: Bibliopolis, 11–27.
Aquinas, Thomas (1956) Summa Contra Gentiles Book Three, New York: Image.
Aquinas, Thomas (1998) Excerpts from Summa Theologica, in trans. R. McInerny (ed.),
Thomas Aquinas: Selected Writings, London: Penguin.
Appiah, Kwame Anthony (2010) Experiments in Ethics, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Arendt, Hannah (2006) Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil, New
York: Penguin.
Aristotle (2004) The Nicomachean Ethics, trans. J.A.K. Thomson, London: Penguin Books.
Austen, Jane (2011) The Annotated Sense and Sensibility, annotated and edited by David
M. Shapard, New York: Anchor.
Augustine (1958) City of God, New York: Image.
Augustine (1961) Confessions trans. R.S. Pine-Coffin, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Augustine (2015) On the Merits and Forgiveness of Sins, and on the Baptism of Infants –
June 8, 2015, CreateSpace Independent Publishing Platform.
Averill, Lindsey (2012) ‘Sometimes the World is Hungry for People Who Care: Katniss
and the Feminist Care Ethic’, in George A. Dunn and Nicolas Minaud (eds.), The
Hunger Games and Philosophy: A Critique of Pure Treason, Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley
and Sons, 162–176.
Baker, Aaron (2015) A Companion to Martin Scorsese, Malden, MA; Oxford: Wiley
Blackwell.
Balog, Katalin (2016) ‘“Son of Saul,” Kierkegaard and the Holocaust’, New York Times,
February 28. Retrieved from https://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2016/02/28/
son-of-saul-kierkegaard-and-the-holocaust/.
Bandy, Mary Lea, and Antonio Monda (2003) The Hidden God: Film as Faith, New York:
Museum of Modern Art.
Barber, Nicholas (2017) ‘Why Casablanca is the ultimate film about refugees’. Retrieved
from www.bbc.com/culture/story/20171124-why-casablanca-is-the-ultimate-film-about-
refugees.
Bibliography 289
Barcenas, Alejandro (2017) ‘Corporate Greed and Alien/ation: Marx vs. Weyland-Yutani’,
in Jeffrey Ewing and Kevin S. Decker (eds.), Alien and Philosophy: I Infest, therefore
I am. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley Blackwell, 48–54.
Bentham, Jeremy (2004) An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation,
in Alan Ryan (ed.), Utilitarianism and Other Essays, Harmondsworth: Penguin
Books.
Bentham, Jeremy (2015) Anarchical Fallacies, in J. Waldron (ed.), Nonsense Upon Stilts:
Bentham, Burke, and Marx on the Rights of Man, London: Routledge, 46–76.
Bergman, Ingmar (1973) Bergman on Bergman: Interviews with Ingmar Bergman by Stig
Bjorkman, Torsten Manns and Jonas Sima, New York: Simon and Schuster.
Berlin, Isaiah (1969) ‘Two Concepts of Liberty’, in Isaiah Berlin (ed.), Four Essays on
Liberty, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bibbiani, William (2014). ‘Spoiler Interview: Ruben Ö stlund on “Force Majeure”’. Retrieved
from www.craveonline.com/site/782963-spoiler-interview-ruben-ostlund-force-majeu
re/2#77Fb0AzPdxFoijSm.99.
Biderman, Shai and Eliana Jacobowitz (2007) ‘Rope: Nietzsche and the Art of Murder’, in
Hitchcock and Philosophy: Dial M for Metaphysics, Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open
Court, 33–45.
Binmore, Ken (2000) “A Utilitarian Theory of Legitimacy,” in Avner Ben-Ner and Louis
G. Putterman (eds.), Economics, Values, and Organization, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 101–132.
Birzache, Alina (2014) ‘You cannot be in love with a word’: Theologies of Embodiment in
Dreyer’s The Passion of Joan of Arc, Axel’s Babette’s Feast and von Trier’s Breaking
the Waves’, Journal of Religion, Media and Digital Culture 3(1). Retrieved from www.
jrmdc.com/journal/article/view/16.
Black, Izzy (2014) ‘The Wolf of Wall Street and The New Cinema of Excess’, Agents and
Seers. N.p., 8 April. Retrieved from https://agentsandseers.wordpress.com/2014/04/08/
the-wolf-of-wall-street-and-the-new-cinema-of-excess/.
Blackburn, Simon (2003) Being Good: A Short Introduction to Ethics, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Bookman, M. and M. Aboulafia (2000) ‘Ethics of care revisited: Gilligan and Levinas’,
Philosophy Today 44: 169–174.
Bowles, Samuel (2016) The Moral Economy: Why Good Incentives Are No Substitute for
Good Citizens, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Brown, Patrick (2009) ‘Ethics as Self-Transcendence: Legal Education, Faith and an Ethos
of Justice‘, Seattle University Law Review 32: 293–310.
Brunette, Peter (1996) Roberto Rossellini, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Burtt, Edwin (1951) Types of Religious Philosophy, revised ed., New York: Harper and
Brothers.
Byrnes, Alice (2015) ‘Alienating the Gaze: The Hybrid Femme Fatale of Under the Skin’,
Deletion, May 4 2015. Retrieved from www.deletionscifi.org.
Camus, Albert (1975) The Myth of Sisyphus, trans. Justin O’Brien, Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
Carroll, Noel (2007) ‘Vertigo and the Pathologies of Romantic Love’, in Hitchcock and
Philosophy: Dial M for Metaphysics, Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court, 101–113.
Clarke, Arthur C. (1968) 2001 A Space Odyssey, London: Arrow Books.
Comiskey, Andrea (2011) ‘The Hero we Read: The Dark Knight, Popular Allegoresis,
and Blockbuster Ideology’, in Kevin K. Durand and Mary K. Leigh (eds.), Riddle me
290 Bibliography
this, Batman! Essays in the universe of the Dark Knight, Jefferson, NC: McFarland and
Company, 124–146.
Connolly, William E. (1993) The Terms of Political Discourse, 3rd ed., Oxford: Blackwell.
Cooper, David (1999) Existentialism: A Reconstruction, 2nd ed., Oxford: Blackwell.
Copleston, Frederick (1994) A History of Philosophy Volume VI: From the French
Enlightenment to Kant, New York: Doubleday.
Cowie, Peter (1982) Ingmar Bergman, London: Secker & Warburg.
Cox, Damien and Michael P. Levine (2012) Thinking through Film: Doing Philosophy,
Watching Movies, Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
Cox, Gary (2006) Sartre: A Guide for the Perplexed, London and New York: Continuum.
Creed, Barbara (1993) The Monstrous Feminine: Film, Feminism, Psychoanalysis.
London: Routledge.
Cross, Katharine (2015) ‘Goddess from the Machine: A Look at Ex Machina’s Gender
Politics’. Retrieved from http://feministing.com/2015/05/28/goddess-from-the-machine-
a-look-at-ex-machinas-gender-politics/.
Dawkins, Richard (1989) The Selfish Gene, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
de Beauvoir, Simone (1953) The Second Sex, trans. H.M. Parshley, London: Jonathon Cape.
de Beauvoir, Simone (1962) The Prime of Life, trans. Peter Green, Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
de Beauvoir, Simone (1976) The Ethics of Ambiguity, trans. Bernard Frechtman, New
York: Citadel Press.
Dennett, Daniel (1976) ‘Conditions of Personhood’, in Amelia Oakensberg Rorty (ed.),
The Identities of Persons. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Derrida, Jacques (1993) ‘Circumfession’, in J. Derrida and G. Bennington (eds.), Jacques
Derrida, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 3–315.
Devlin, William J. (2010) ‘No Country for Old Men: the Decline of Ethics and the
West(ern)’, in Jennifer McMahon and B. Steve Csaki, The Philosophy of the Western,
Lexington, KY: The University Press of Kentucky, 221–239.
Dirks, Tim (2013) ‘Filmsite Movie Review: Dirty Harry (1971)’. Retrieved from www.
filmsite.org/dirt.html.
Dirks, Tim (2017) ‘Westerns Films’. Retrieved from www.filmsite.org/westernfilms.html.
Doris, John (2002) Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behaviour, Cambridge:
CUP Ely, John (1995) ‘Jane Austen: A Female Aristotelian’, Thesis Eleven 40:
93–118.
Dostoevsky, Fyodor (1990) The Brothers Karamazov trans Richard Pevear and Larissa
Volokhonsky, San Francisco, CA: North Point Press.
Dreyfus, Hubert (2009) On the Internet, 2nd ed., London and New York: Routledge.
Durgnat, Raymond (1968) Luis Bunuel, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Dworkin, Ronald (1984) ‘Rights as Trumps’, in J. Waldron (ed.), Theories of Rights,
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 153–167.
Eldridge, Richard (2009) ‘Philosophy In/Of/As/And Film’, Projections: The Journal of
Movies and Mind 3 (1): 109–116.
Epictetus (2008) ‘Enchiridion’, in Robert Dobbin (ed.), Discourses and Selected Writings,
London: Penguin Books, 219–245.
Epicurus (2006) ‘Letter to Menoeceus’, in Daniel Kolak and Garrett Thomson (eds.), The
Longman Standard History of Ancient Philosophy, New York: Pearson, 452–455.
Falzon, Christopher (2011) ‘On Being John Malkovich and Not Being Yourself’, in David
LaRocca (ed.), Charlie Kaufman and Philosophy, Lexington, KY: University of
Kentucky Press, 46–65.
Bibliography 291
Falzon, Christopher (2011) ‘Peter Weir’s The Truman Show and Sartrean Freedom’, in
J.-P. Boule and E. McCaffrey, Existentialism and Contemporary Cinema: A Sartrean
Perspective, New York, Oxford: Berghahn Books, 17–31.
Falzon, Christopher (2016) ‘Dirty Harry Ethics’, SubStance 45 (3): 49–65.
Falzon, Christopher (2017) ‘Experiencing Force Majeure’, Film-Philosophy 21 (3): 281–298.
Foucault, Michel (1977) Discipline and Punish, trans. A. Sheridan, London: Penguin.
Foucault, Michel (1985) The History of Sexuality vol. 2: The Use of Pleasure, trans.
R. Hurley, New York: Pantheon.
Foucault, Michel (1997a) ‘On the Genealogy of Ethics: An Overview of Work in Progress’,
in Paul Rabinow (ed.), Ethics, Subjectivity, and Truth. Essential Works of Foucault,
1954–1984, trans. R. Hurley and others, New York: The New Press, 253–280.
Foucault, Michel (1997b) ‘What is Enlightenment?’, in Paul Rabinow (ed.), Ethics,
Subjectivity, and Truth. Essential Works of Foucault, 1954–1984, New York: The New
Press, 303–319.
Foucault, Michel (1997c) ‘Sexual Choice, Sexual Act’, in Paul Rabinow (ed.), Ethics,
Subjectivity, and Truth. Essential Works of Foucault, 1954–1984, New York: The New
Press, 141–156.
Foucault, Michel (1990) The History of Sexuality vol. 1: The Will to Knowledge, trans.
R. Hurley, London: Penguin.
Foucault, Michel (2000) ‘The Subject and Power’, in James D. Faubion (ed.), Power.
Essential Works of Foucault, 1954–1984, trans. R. Hurley and others, New York:
The New Press, 326–348.
Fraiman, S. (2010) ‘The Liberation of Elizabeth Bennet in Joe Wright’s Pride & Prejudice’
31 (1). Online publication of the Jane Austen Society of North America. Retrieved from
www.jasna.org/persuasions/on-line/vol31no1/fraiman.html.
Frankel, Glenn (2018) High Noon: The Hollywood Blacklist and the Making of an American
Classic, New York: Bloomsbury.
Frankfurt, Harry (1971) ‘Freedom of Will and the Concept of a Person’, The Journal of
Philosophy, 68 (1): 5–20.
Freeland, Cynthia (2002) ‘Penetrating Keanu: New Holes, but the Same Old Shit’, in
William Irwin (ed.), The Matrix and Philosophy: Welcome to the Desert of the Real,
Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court, 205–215.
Frohock, Richard (2002) ‘Adaptation and Cultural Criticism: Les Liaisons dangereuses
1960 and Dangerous Liaisons’ in Robert Mayer (ed.), Eighteenth-century fiction on
Screen, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 157–174.
Frost, Michael and Robert Banks (2001) Lessons from Reel Life: Movies, Meaning and
Myth-Making, Adelaide: Openbook Publishers.
Gallagher, Mark (2006) Action Figures, New York: Palgrave.
Gee, Oliver (2014) ‘Watch my movie and get a divorce’, The Local, 12 December. Retrieved
from www.thelocal.se/20141212/swedish-director-divorce-turist-golden-globe.
Gilligan, Carol (1982) In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s
Development, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Girgus, Sam (2002) The Films of Woody Allen, 2nd ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Girgus, Sam (2010). Levinas and the Cinema of Redemption – Time, Ethics and the
Feminine, New York: Columbia University Press.
Giroux, Henry A. (2006) ‘Private Satisfactions and Public Disorder: Fight Club, Patriarchy
and the Politics of Masculine Violence’, in America on the Edge: Henry Giroux on
Politics, Culture, and Education, New York: Palgrave.
292 Bibliography
Grau, Christopher (2005) ‘There is no ‘I’ in ‘Robot’: Robots and Utilitarianism’, in Susan
Anderson and Michael Anderson (eds.), Machine Ethics, New York: Cambridge
University Press, 451–463.
Greenblatt, Stephen (2017) ‘How St Augustine Invented Sex’, The New Yorker, June 19
2017. Retrieved from www.newyorker.com/magazine/2017/06/19/how-st-augustine-
invented-sex.
Griffin, James (2015) What Can Philosophy Contribute To Ethics? Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Grimshaw, Jean (1986) Philosophy and Feminist Thinking, Minneapolis, MN: University
of Minnesota Press.
Habermas, Jü rgen (1971) ‘Technology and Science as “Ideology”’, in Toward a Rational
Society, trans. J. Shapiro, London: Heinemann Educational Books.
Habermas, Jü rgen (1972) Knowledge and Human Interests 2nd ed., trans. J. Shapiro,
Boston: Beacon Press.
Habermas, Jü rgen (1974) ‘The Public Sphere: An Encyclopedia Article (1964)’, New
German Critique 3: 49–55.
Habermas, Jü rgen (2003) The Future of Human Nature, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Halwani, Raja (2016) ‘Why sexual desire is objectifying – and hence morally wrong,
Aeon. Retrieved from https://aeon.co/ideas/why-sexual-desire-is-objectifying-and-
hence-morally-wrong.
Harris, Jonathon (2007) Enhancing Evolution: The Ethical Case for Making Better People,
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Hayward, Max (2017) ‘Philosophy versus Ethics’, in The Times Literary Supplement, January
11, 2017. Retrieved from www.the-tls.co.uk/articles/public/philosophy-vs-ethics/.
Hayward, Max (2017) ‘Philosophy vs Ethics’, Times Literary Supplement, January 11.
Hegel, G.W.F. (1977) Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Heller, Agnes (1982) ‘Habermas and Marxism’, in J.B. Thompson and D. Held (eds.),
Habermas: Critical Debates, London: Macmillan.
Helvé tius, Claude (2002) On the Mind, excerpts in J.B. Schneewind (ed.), Moral Theory
from Montaigne to Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 416–429.
Hick, John (1990) Philosophy of Religion, 4th ed., Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Hobbes, Thomas (1968) Leviathan, ed. C.B. Macpherson, Harmondsworth: Penguin
Books.
Hofmeyr, Benda (2006) ‘The meta-physics of Foucault’s ethics: Succeeding where Levinas
fails’, South African Journal of Philosophy, 25 (2): 113–125.
Holbach, Baron d’ (1999) The System of Nature, volume 1, Manchester: Clinamen Press.
Holbach Baron d’ (2002) Universal Morality; or, The Duties of Man, Founded on Nature.
Excerpts in B. Schneewind (ed.), Moral Theory from Montaigne to Kant, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 431–445.
Horkheimer, Max (1974) The Eclipse of Reason, New York: Continuum.
Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor Adorno (1979) Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. J.
Cumming, London: Verso.
Hughes, Gerald J. (2001) Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Aristotle on Ethics, London:
Routledge.
Hume, David (1969) A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. Eric C. Mossner, Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books.
Hume, David (1990) Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, London: Penguin.
Ignatieff, Michael (2013) ‘Machiavelli was Right’, Atlantic Monthly, December.
Bibliography 293
Insdorf, Annette (1994) Franç ois Truffaut, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Johnstone, Nick (1999) Abel Ferrara: The King of New York, London: Omnibus Press.
Kael, Pauline (1978) ‘Saintliness’ in Joan Mellon (ed.), The World of Luis Bunuel: Essays
in Criticism, New York: Oxford University Press, 270–277.
Kael, Pauline (1991) Review of Dirty Harry, in 5001 Nights at the Movies, New York:
Henry Holt and Company.
Kael, Pauline (1970) Going Steady, Boston, Toronto: Little, Brown and Company.
Kant, Immanuel (1963) ‘Duties towards Animals and Spirits’, in trans. L. Infield, Lectures
on Ethics, New York: Harper and Row.
Kant, Immanuel (1964) Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. H. J. Paton, New
York: New York: Harper and Row.
Kant, Immanuel (2009) The Metaphysical Elements of Ethics, trans. Thomas Kingsmill
Abbott, Auckland, New Zealand: The Floating Press.
Kant, Immanuel (1995) ‘What Is Enlightenment?’, in Isaac Kramnick (ed.), The Portable
Enlightenment Reader, New York: Penguin Books, 1–7.
Kant, Immanuel (2016) ‘On a Supposed Right to Lie Because of Philanthropic Concerns’
in Kevin DeLapp, Jeremy Henkel (eds.), Truth and Lying, Indianapolis/Cambridge:
Hackett Publishing, 78–99.
Katz, Claire Elise (2003) Levinas, Judaism, and the Feminine, Bloomington and
Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Kaufmann, Walter (1968) Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist, 3rd ed.,
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Keyser, Les Martin (1995) Scorsese, New York: Simon and Schuster.
Kierkegaard, Sø ren (1975) Journals and Papers vol. 3, trans. Howard V. Hong and Edna
H. Hong, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Kierkegaard, Sø ren (1986) Fear and Trembling, London: Penguin.
Kierkegaard, Sø ren (2009) Concluding Unscientific Postscript, trans. A. Hannay,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Klockars, Carl (1980) ‘The Dirty Harry Problem’, The Annals 452, November.
Knight, Deborah, and George McKnight (2002) ‘Real Genre and Virtual Philosophy’, in
William Irwin (ed.), The Matrix and Philosophy: Welcome to the Desert of the Real,
Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court, 188–201.
Kö hler-Ryan, René e, and Sydney Palmer (2013) ‘What Do You Know of My Heart? The
Role of Sense and Sensibility in Ang Lee’s Sense and Sensibility and Crouching Tiger,
Hidden Dragon’, in Robert Arp et al. (eds.), Ang Lee and Philosophy, Lexington, KY:
University Press of Kentucky, 41–63.
Kramnick, Isaac (1995) ‘Introduction’, in The Portable Enlightenment Reader, ed. Isaac
Kramnick, New York: Penguin Books, ix–xxviii.
Kreyche, Gerald (1988) ‘“High Noon”: A Paradigm of Kant’s Moral Philosophy’, Teaching
Philosophy 11 (3): 217–228.
Kupfer, Joseph (1999) Visions of Virtue in Popular Film (Thinking Through Cinema),
Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Lara, Maria Pia (1998) Moral Textures: Feminist Narratives in the Public Sphere, Berkeley
and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.
LaRocca, David (2016) ‘The Last Great Representative of the Virtues’, in Mimi Marinucci
(ed.), Jane Austen and Philosophy, Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 81–94.
Lemm, Vanessa and Miguel Vatter (2017) ‘Michel Foucault’s perspective on biopolitics’
in Steven A. Peterson and Albert Somit (eds.), Handbook of Biology and Politics,
Cheltenham, Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar Publishing, 40–52.
294 Bibliography
Levinas, Emmanuel (1979) Totality and Infinity, trans. Alphonso Lingis. The Hague:
Martinus Nijhoff.
Levinas, Emmanuel (1998) Otherwise than Being, or Beyond Essence, trans. Alphonso
Lingis. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.
Lewis, C.S. (2012) The Problem of Pain, London: HarperCollins.
Lindenmuth, William (2017) ‘Cross My Heart and Hope to Die: Why Ripley Must Save
Newt’, in Jeffrey Ewing and Kevin S. Decker (eds.), Alien and Philosophy: I Infest,
therefore I Am. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley Blackwell, 67–79.
Locke, John (1993) The Second Treatise of Government, in David Wootton (ed.), Political
Writings, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Locke, John (1997) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Roger Woolhouse,
Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Lopez, George (2006) ‘The Ethical Legacy of Dirty Harry’. America: The National
Catholic Weekly 195 (Sept.): 16–18.
Lucca, Violet (2014). ‘Interview: Ruben Ö stlund’. Retrieved from www.filmcomment.
com/blog/interview-ruben-oestlund.
Lucretius (1951) On the Nature of the Universe, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
MacIntyre, Alasdair (1981) After Virtue, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press
Macmillan.
Mackenzie, Catriona and Natalie Stoljar (2000) ‘Introduction: Autonomy
Reconfigured’, in C. Mackenzie, and N. Stoljar (eds.), Relational Autonomy:
Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, New York: Oxford
University Press, 3–31.
Macpherson, C.B. (1962) The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to
Locke, London: Clarendon Press.
Mainon, Dominique and James Ursini (2007) Cinema of Obsession,New York: Limelight
Editions.
Malik, Kenan (2014) The Quest for a Moral Compass: A Global History of Ethics, London:
Atlantic Books.
Manninen, Bertha Alvarez (2013) ‘The Problem of Evil and Humans’ Relationship with
God in Terrence Malick’s The Tree of Life”’, Journal of Religion & Film 17 (1): 1–23.
Marcus Aurelius (2006) Meditations, London: Penguin Books.
Marcuse, Herbert (1991) One-Dimensional Man, London: Routledge.
Marx, Karl (1967a) Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts (excerpts), in Loyd D.
Easton and Kurt H. Guddat (eds. and trans.), The Writings of the Young Marx on
Philosophy and Society, New York: Anchor.
Marx, Karl (1967b) The Holy Family (excerpts), in Loyd D. Easton and Kurt H. Guddat
(eds. and trans.), The Writings of the Young Marx on Philosophy and Society, New
York: Anchor, 361–398.
Marx, Karl (1972) The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, in Robert C. Tucker (ed.),
The Marx-Engels Reader, New York: Norton.
Marx, Karl (1991) Capital, Volume Three, London: Penguin.
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels (1972) The Communist Manifesto, in Robert C. Tucker
(ed.), The Marx-Engels Reader, New York: Norton.
McAteer, John (2013) ‘The Problem of the Father’s Love in The Tree of Life and the Book
of Job’, Film and Philosophy 17: 137–150.
McCaffrey, Enda (2011) ‘Crimes of Passion, Freedom and a clash of Sartrean Moralities
in the Coen Brothers “No Country for Old Men”’, in Jean-Pierre Boulé and Enda
MacCaffrey (eds.), Existentialism and Contemporary Cinema: a Sartrean Perspective,
New York, Oxford: Berghahn Books, 125–142.
Bibliography 295
McCarthy, Thomas (1978) The Critical Theory of Jurgen Habermas, Oxford: Polity.
McClelland, Tom (2011) ‘The Philosophy of Film and Film as Philosophy’, Cinema:
Journal of Philosophy and the Moving Image 2: 11–35.
McGarry, Eileen (1988) ‘Dirty Harry’, in Alain Silver and Elizabeth Ward (eds.), Film
Noir: An Encyclopedic Reference Guide, London: Bloomsbury.
McVeigh, Stephen (2017) ‘You must remember this: Casablanca at 75 – still a classic
of WWII propaganda’. Retrieved at http://theconversation.com/you-must-remember-
this-casablanca-at-75-still-a-classic-of-wwii-propaganda-87113.
Mexal, Stephen J. (2010) ‘Two ways to Yuma: Locke, Liberalism and Western Masculinity
in 3:10 to Yuma’, in Jennifer McMahon and B. Steve Csaki, The Philosophy of the
Western, Lexington, KY: The University Press of Kentucky, 69–88.
Midgely, Mary (1985) ‘Persons and Non-persons’, in Peter Singer (ed.), In Defence of
Animals, New York: Blackwell, 52–62.
Mill, John Stuart (1975) Three Essays: On Liberty, Representative Government, The
Subjection of Women, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mill, John Stuart (2004) Utilitarianism, in Utilitarianism and Other Essays, Alan Ryan
(ed.), Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 272–338.
Mitchell, Jolyon (2009) ‘Ethics’, in John Lyden (ed.), The Routledge Companion to
Religion and Film, London and New York: Routledge, 482–500.
Monaco, James (1976) The New Wave, New York: Oxford University Press.
Montaigne, Michel de (2003) ‘On Moderation’, in trans. M.A. Screech. The Complete
Essays, London: Penguin, 222–227.
Moore, Charlotte (2008) ‘The Ethics of Ambiguity’, Philosophy Now 69: 14–16.
Morton, Adam (2004) On Evil, New York and London: Routledge.
Mulvey, Laura (1999) ‘Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema’, In Film Leo Braudy and
Marshall Cohen (eds.), Theory and Criticism: Introductory Readings, New York:
Oxford University Press, 833–844.
Nagel, Thomas (1979) ‘Moral Luck’ in Mortal Questions, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Nichols, Mary P. (2000) Reconstructing Woody, Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.
Nietzsche, Friedrich (1967) The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R.J.
Hollingdale, New York: Vintage Books.
Nietzsche, Friedrich (1968) Twilight of the Idols; The Anti-Christ, Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books.
Nietzsche, Friedrich (1969) Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans. R.J. Hollingdale,
Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Nietzsche, Friedrich (1973) Beyond Good and Evil, trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books.
Nietzsche, Friedrich (1974) The Gay Science, trans. Walter Kaufmann, New York: Vintage
Books.
Nietzsche, Friedrich (1989) The Genealogy of Morals/Ecce Homo, trans. Walter Kaufmann
and R.J. Hollingdale, New York: Vintage Books.
Noddings, Nel (1984) Caring: A feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education,
Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.
Norman, Richard (1998) The Moral Philosophers: An Introduction to Ethics, 2nd ed.,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nozick, Robert (1974) Anarchy, State and Utopia, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Nussbaum, Martha C. (1994) The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic
Ethics, Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.
O’Leary, Timothy (2008) ‘Foucault, Experience, Literature’, Foucault Studies 5: 5–25.
296 Bibliography
O’Leary, Timothy (2009) Foucault and Fiction: The Experience Book, London: Continuum.
Pannereau, William (2009) Existentialist Cinema, Houndmills, Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Pappas, John (2004) ‘It’s All Darkness: Plato, The Ring of Gyges, and Crimes and
Misdemeanors’, in Woody Allen and Philosophy, Chicago, IL: Open Court.
Parrill, Sue (2002) Jane Austen on Film and television: A Critical Study of the Adaptations,
Jefferson, NC: McFarland.
Patton, Paul (1989) ‘Taylor and Foucault on Power and Freedom’, Political Studies 37:
260–276.
Perkins, V.F. (1972) Film as Film: Understanding and Judging Movies, Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books.
Plantinga, Alvin (1977) God, Freedom, and Evil, Grand Rapids: Eerdmans.
Plato (1993) Republic, trans. Robin Waterfield, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Plato (2003) The Last Days of Socrates – Euthyphro, Apology, Crito, Phaedo, trans. Hugh
Tredennick and Harrold Tarrant, London: Penguin.
Pojman, Louis (1999) Philosophy: The Pursuit of Wisdom, 2nd ed., Belmont CA:
Wadsworth Publishing Company.
Prior, William J. (2016) Ancient Philosophy: A Beginner’s Guide, London: Oneworld.
Railton, Peter (1984) ‘Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality,’
Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (2): 134–171.
Rand, Ayn (1964) The Virtue of Selfishness, New York: Signet Books.
Reiser, Klaus (2006) ‘Gender in Matewan and Men with Guns’, in Diane Carson Heidi
Kenaga (eds.), Sayles Talk: New Perspectives on Independent Filmmaker John Sayles,
Detroit, MI: Wayne State University Press.
Rempel, Morgan (2012) ‘Epicurus and “Contented Poverty”: The Big Lebowski as
Epicurean Parable’, in Peter S. Fosl (ed.), The Big Lebowski and Philosophy, Hoboken,
NJ: Wiley, 67–78.
Richardson, Michael (2010) Otherness in Hollywood Cinema, New York, London:
Continuum.
Riegler, Thomas (2009) ‘The “Mastermind”: Personifications of Evil in the Cinema’.
Retrieved from www.academia.edu/1532242/The_Mastermind_Personifications_of_
Evil_in_the_Cinema.
Rodham, Thomas (2013) ‘Jane Austen as Moral Philosopher’, Philosophy Now 94: 6–8.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1993) The Social Contract and the Discourses, trans. G.D.H.
Cole, London: Everyman.
Rowland, Mark (2003) The Philosopher at the End of the Universe, London: Ebury Press.
Ruddick, Sara (1997) ‘Maternal Thinking’, in Diana Meyers (ed.), Feminist Social
Thought: A Reader, London: Routledge, 583–603.
Ryan, Alan (1973) ‘The Nature of Human Nature in Hobbes and Rousseau’, in Jonathon
Benthall (ed.), The Limits of Human Nature, London: Allen Lane, 3–19.
Ryle, Gilbert (2009) ‘Jane Austen and the Moralists’, in Critical Essays: Collected Papers,
vol. 1, London and New York: Routledge, 286–302.
Sander-Staudt, Maureen (2011) ‘Care Ethics’, entry in James Fieser and Bradley Dowden
(eds.), Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved from www.iep.utm.edu/
care-eth/.
Sartre, Jean-Paul (1958) Being and Nothingness, trans. Hazel E. Barnes, London: Methuen.
Sartre, Jean-Paul (1975) ‘Existentialism Is a Humanism’, in Walter Kaufmann (ed.),
Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre, New York: New American Library.
Sartre, Jean-Paul (1983) ‘The Itinerary of a Thought’, in Between Existentialism and
Marxism, London: Verso, 33–64.
Bibliography 297
Sartre, Jean-Paul (1995) ‘Portrait of an Anti-Semite’ in Anti-Semite and Jew, trans. George
J. Becker. New York: Shocken .
Sartre, Jean-Paul (2000) ‘Huis Clos’, in Huis and Other Plays, London: Penguin.
Savulescu, Julian (2009) ‘Genetic interventions and the ethics of enhancement of human
beings’, in Bonnie Steinbock (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Bioethics, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Scaltsas, Patricia Ward (1992) ‘Do Feminist Ethics Counter Feminist Aims’, in Eve
Browning Cole and Susan Coultrap-McQuin (eds.), Explorations in Feminist Ethics:
Theory and Practice, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 15–26.
Schickel, Richard (2003) Woody Allen: A Life in Film, Chicago: Ivan R. Lee.
Schneewind, J.B (2002) ‘Introduction’ in J.B. Schneewind (ed.), Moral Theory from
Montaigne to Kant, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Scott, Mark S.M. (2014) ‘C. S. Lewis and John Hick: An Interface on Theodicy’, The
Journal of Inklings Studies 4 (1): 19–31.
Sellars, John (2003) ‘Gladiator’, Philosophy Now 41: 44–45.
Sellars, John (2006) Stoicism, Chesham: Acumen.
Sembou, Evangelia (2013) Modern Theories of Politics, Oxford: Peter Lang.
Sharpe, Matthew (2012) ‘Philosophy and the View from Above in Alejandro Amenabar’s
Agora’, Crossroads 6 (1): 31–45.
Sherwin, Susan (1989) ‘Feminist and Medical Ethics: Two Different Approaches to
Contextual Ethics’, Hypatia 4: 57–72.
Sherwin, Susan (1992) No Longer Patient: Feminist Ethics and Health Care, Philadelphia,
PA: Temple University Press.
Sherwin, Susan (1998) ‘A relational approach to autonomy in health care’, in H. Besquaret
Holmes and L. Purdy (eds.), The Politics of Women’s Health: Exploring Agency and
Autonomy, Pittsburgh, PA: Temple University Press.
Simons, Jonathon (1995) Foucault and the Political, London and New York:
Routledge.
Singer, Peter (1993) How are We to Live? Ethics in an Age of Self-Interest, Melbourne :
Mandarin.
Singer, Peter (2000) Marx: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Singer, Peter (2011) Practical Ethics, 3rd ed., Cambridge, New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Sinnerbrink, Robert (2005) ‘Cinematic Ideas: David Lynch’s Mulholland Drive’, Film-
Philosophy 9 (4): 1–15.
Sitney, P. Adams (2003) ‘Let me go into the church alone: the Roman Catholic subtext of
“Vertigo”’, in Mary Lea Bandy, and Antonio Monda (2003) The Hidden God: Film as
Faith, New York: Museum of Modern Art, 249–259.
Skees, Murray (2012) ‘Have I been Misunderstood: Dionysius vs IKEA-boy’, in Thomas
Wartenberg (ed.), Fight Club, New York: Routledge.
Slattery, Luke (2012) Reclaiming Epicurus, London: Penguin.
Smart, J.J.C and Bernard Williams (1973) Utilitarianism: For and Against, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Stam, Robert (2000) Film Theory: An Introduction, Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Stephens, William O. (2010) ‘What’s Love Got to Do with It? Epicureanism and Friends
with Benefits’, in Michael Bruce and Robert M. Stewart (eds.), College Sex – Philosophy
for Everyone: Philosophers With Benefits, Oxford: Blackwell, 77–90.
Steven, Mark (2017) ‘Nietzsche on Film’, Film-Philosophy 21 (1): 95–113.
Tasker, Yvonne (2002) The Silence of the Lambs, London: British Film Institute.
298 Bibliography
Taylor, Charles (1985a) ‘What is Human Agency?’, in Philosophical Papers I: Human
Agency and Language, Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Taylor, Charles (1985b) ‘Kant’s Theory of Freedom’, in Philosophical Papers 2:
Philosophy and the Human Sciences, Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Taylor, Charles (1985c) ‘What’s Wrong with Negative Liberty?’ In Philosophical Papers
2: Philosophy and the Human Sciences, Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University
Press.
Taylor, Chloe (2005) ‘Levinasian Ethics and Feminist Ethics of Care’, Symposium 9 (2):
217–239. Retrieved from htp://www.artsrn.ualberta.ca/symposium/files/original/46b79
257165a7c21b50d4b004581bfcc.PDF.
Taylor, Mark (1980) Journeys to Selfhood: Hegel and Kierkegaard, Berkeley and Los
Angeles, CA: University of California Press.
Tooley, Michael (1991) ‘Abortion and Infanticide’ from Peter Singer (ed.), A Companion
to Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Truffaut, Franç ois (1978) ‘Bunuel the Builder’ in The Films in My Life, Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
Truffaut, Franç ois (1986) Hitchcock, revised edition, London: Paladin.
Ulin, David S. (2006) ‘Why Charlie Kaufman Is Us’, Los Angeles Times, 14 May.
Van Hooft, Stan (2006) Introducing Virtue Ethics, Bucks: Acumen.
Vass, Michael (2005) ‘Cinematic Meaning in the Work of David Lynch: Revisiting Twin
Peaks: Fire Walk with Me, Lost Highway, and Mulholland Drive’, Cineaction 67:
12–25. Retrieved from www.michaelvass.com/lynch.html.
Voltaire (2011) A Pocket Philosophical Dictionary, trans. John Fletcher, Oxford, New
York: Oxford University Press.
Wanat, Matt (2007) ‘Irony as Absolution’, in Leonard Engel (ed.), Clint Eastwood, Actor
and Director: New Perspectives, Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.
Wartenberg, Thomas E. (2007) Thinking on Screen: Film as Philosophy, New York/
London: Routledge.
Wartenberg, Thomas E. (2011) ‘On the Possibility of Cinematic Philosophy’, in Havi
Carel and Greg Tuck (eds.), New Takes in Film Philosophy, Basingstoke: Palgrave,
9–24.
West, David (1996) An Introduction to Continental Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Polity
Press.
Williams, Bernard (1981) ‘Persons, Character, and Morality’, in Moral Luck, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Williams, Bernard (1982) ‘Moral Luck’, in Moral Luck, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Wilson, Catherine (2015) Epicureanism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wilson, George (1986) Baltimore and London: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Wold, Susan (2007) ‘Moral Psychology and the Unity of the Virtues’, in Ratio 20 (2):
145–167.
Wolf, Susan (1982) ‘Moral Saints’, The Journal of Philosophy 79 (8): 419–439.
Wood, Michael (2003) ‘Simon of the Desert’, in Mary Lea Bandy and Antonio Monda
(eds.), The Hidden God: Film and Faith, New York: The Museum of Modern Art.
Wood, Robin (2002) Hitchcock’s Films Revisited, revised ed., New York: Columbia
University Press, 130–133.
Wright, John W. (2008) ‘Levinasian Ethics of Alterity: The Face of the Other in
Spielberg’s Cinematic Language’, in Dean Kowalski (ed.), Steven Spielberg and
Bibliography 299
Philosophy: We’re Gonna Need a Bigger Boat. Lexington, KY: The University Press
of Kentucky, 50–68.
Wright, Wendy M. (2016) ‘Babette’s Feast: A Religious Film’, Journal of Religion & Film
1 (2). Retrieved from https://digitalcommons.unomaha.edu/jrf/vol1/iss2/2.
Zizek, Slavoj (2012) ‘ If there is a God, then anything is permitted’, ABC Religion
and Ethics, 17 April. Retrieved from www.abc.net.au/religion/articles/2012/04/17/
3478816.htm.
Index