Continuity Properties of Preference Relations
Continuity Properties of Preference Relations
www.elsevier.com/locate/entcs
Marian Baroni1
Department of Mathematics and Statistics
University of Canterbury
Christchurch, New Zealand
Douglas Bridges2
Department of Mathematics and Statistics
University of Canterbury
Christchurch, New Zealand
Abstract
Various types of continuity for preference relations on a metric space are examined constructively. In
particular, necessary and sufficient conditions are given for an order-dense, strongly extensional preference
relation on a complete metric space to be continuous. It is also shown, in the spirit of constructive reverse
mathematics, that the continuity of sequentially continuous, order-dense preference relations on complete,
separable metric spaces is connected to Ishihara’s principle BD-N, and therefore is not provable within
Bishop-style constructive mathematics alone.
realised that the existence of a utility function representing a given preference re-
lation required justification; furthermore, one could not automatically assume that
the utility function, if it existed, was continuous. This led to the study of necessary
and sufficient conditions for the existence of continuous utility functions, a topic
which has been explored in depth since the appearance of the pioneering work of
Debreu in the 1950s [11,12].
Early in the constructive analysis of preference relations it became clear that
straightforward constructivisation of the classical proofs of the existence and con-
tinuity of utility functions was not possible. In fact, Debreu’s famous theorem on
this subject is false in recursive constructive mathematics [6]. Since the smoothest
constructive path to an existence theorem for utility functions uses a very strong
continuity condition on the preference relation [4], it would be interesting (maybe
useful?) to have an existence theorem under weaker continuity conditions on prefer-
ences. To that end, it makes sense to examine the constructive connections between
various types of continuity of preferences, analogous to ones for continuity of func-
tions. We begin such an examination in this paper.
Let X be a set that is inhabited in the sense that we can construct an element
of it. A binary relation on X is called a preference relation if it satisfies these
two axioms:
P1 ∀x,y∈X (x y ⇒ ¬ (y x)) ;
P2 ∀x,y∈X (x y ⇒ ∀z∈X (x z ∨ z y)) .
The corresponding preference-indifference relation is then defined by
∀x,y∈X (x y ⇔ ¬ (y x)) .
[a, →) = {x ∈ X : x a} ,
(a, →) = {x ∈ X : x a} ,
(←, a] = {x ∈ X : a x} ,
(←, a) = {x ∈ X : a x} .
M. Baroni, D. Bridges / Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science 202 (2008) 19–25 21
In this paper we are particularly interested in the case where (X, ρ) is a metric
space. The standard inequality on X is then defined by
x a ⇒ ∃N ∀nN (xn a)
and
a x ⇒ ∃N ∀nN (a xn ) ;
nearly continuous at a if for each S ⊂ X and each x in the closure S of S,
x a ⇒ ∃s∈S (s a)
and
a x ⇒ ∃s∈S (a s) ;
nondiscontinuous at a if both the sets (←, a] and [a, →) are closed in X.
We say that is, for example, sequentially continuous on X if it is sequentially
continuous at each point of X. It is straightforward to show that if is represented
by a pointwise, sequential, or nearly continuous 3 utility function, then itself has
the corresponding continuity property on X.
Our aim is to investigate, within the framework of Bishop-style constructive
mathematics (BISH), 4 connections between these notions of continuity.
Proposition 1.1 For preference relations on a metric space, pointwise continuity
at a point implies sequential continuity, which implies near continuity, which implies
nondiscontinuity.
for all sufficiently large n. The case a x is similarly handled. Thus is nearly
continuous at a.
To prove that near continuity implies nondiscontinuity, suppose that is nearly
continuous at a, and consider a sequence (xn )n1 in X that converges to x and
satisfies xn a for all n. Assume that a x. Clearly, x belongs to the closure of
[a, →). Since is nearly continuous at a, it follows that a s for some s ∈ [a, →), a
contradiction. Consequently, ¬(a x) and therefore x a—that is, x ∈ [a, →). We
prove similarly that the lower contour set at a is closed; so the preference relation
is nondiscontinuous at a. 2
Proof. Omitted. 2
Our next task is to produce necessary and sufficient conditions for the sequential
continuity of a certain type of preference relation on a complete metric space (Propo-
sition 1.5 below). We require the following two lemmas, which are reminiscent of
Ishihara’s tricks [13,9].
λn = 0 ⇒ ∀kn (xk b) ,
λn = 1 − λn−1 ⇒ a xn .
Lemma 1.4 Under the hypotheses of Lemma 1.3, either xn b for all sufficiently
large n, or else a xn for infinitely many n.
Proof. The proof uses inductive application of Lemma 1.3 and is omitted. 2
M. Baroni, D. Bridges / Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science 202 (2008) 19–25 23
Theorem 2.1 If BD-N holds, then every sequentially continuous, order-dense pref-
erence relation on a separable metric space is pointwise continuous.
Proof. Omitted. 2
(←, 1) = {x ∈ X : u(x) = 0}
The preference relation used in the proof of Theorem 2.2 is not order dense.
We do not know whether BD-N is a consequence of the proposition “Every sequen-
tially continuous, order-dense preference relation on a complete, separable metric
space is uniformly continuous”.
M. Baroni, D. Bridges / Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science 202 (2008) 19–25 25
Acknowledgement
The authors thank the Department of Mathematics & Statistics at the University
of Canterbury for supporting Marian Baroni as a doctoral student while this paper
was begun. They also thank the referee for pointing out several errors in the original
version, and for pointing out a major simplification in the proof of Theorem 2.1.
References
[1] Aczel, P., and M. Rathjen, “Notes on Constructive Set Theory”, Report No. 40, Institut Mittag–Leffler,
Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences, 2001.
[2] Baroni, M.A., “The Constructive Theory of Riesz Spaces and Applications in Mathematical Economics”,
Ph.D. Thesis, University of Canterbury, Christchurch, New Zealand, 2004.
[3] Bishop, E.A., and D.S. Bridges, “Constructive Analysis”, Grundlehren der Math. Wiss. 279 (1985),
Springer-Verlag, Heidelberg.
[4] Bridges, D.S., The constructive theory of preference relations on a locally compact space, Proc.
Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie can Wetenschappen, Ser. A, 92 2 (1989), 141–165.
[5] Bridges, D.S., Constructive methods in mathematical economics, Mathematical Utility Theory, J. Econ.
(Zeitschrift für Nationalökonomie), Suppl. 8 (1999), 1–21.
[6] Bridges, D.S., and F. Richman, A recursive counterexample to Debreu’s theorem on the existence of a
utility function, Math. Soc. Sciences 21 (1991), 179–182.
[7] Bridges, D.S., and L.S. Vı̂ţă, Apartness spaces as a framework for constructive topology, Ann. Pure
and Applied Logic 119 (2003), 61–83.
[8] Bridges, D.S., and L.S. Vı̂ţă, “Techniques of Constructive Analysis”, Universitext, Springer-New-York,
2006.
[9] Bridges, D.S., D. van Dalen and H. Ishihara, Ishihara’s proof technique in constructive analysis, Proc.
Koninklijke Nederlandse Akad. Wetenschappen (Indag. Math.) N.S., 14 2 (2003), 163–168.
[10] Bridges,D.S., H. Ishihara, P.M. Schuster and L.S.Vı̂ţă, Strong continuity implies uniform sequential
continuity, Arch. Math. Logic 44 (2006), 887–895.
[11] Debreu, G., Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function, Decision Processes (R.
Thrall, C. Coombs, and R. Davies, eds), John Wiley, New York, 1954.
[12] Debreu, G., “Theory of Value”, John Wiley, New York, 1959.
[13] Ishihara, H., Continuity and discontinuity in constructive mathematics, J. Symbolic Logic 56 4 (1991),
1349–1354.
[14] Ishihara, H., Continuity properties in constructive mathematics, J. Symbolic Logic 57 2 (1992), 557–
565.
[15] Ishihara, H., Sequential continuity in constructive mathematics, Combinatorics, Computability and
Logic (C.S. Calude, M.J. Dinneen and S. Sburlan, eds), Springer-Verlag, London, 2001, 5–12.
[16] Ishihara, H., and S. Yoshida, A constructive look at the completeness of D(R), J. Symb. Logic 67
(2002), 1511–1519.
[17] Lietz, P., “From Constructive Mathematics to Computable Analysis via the Realizability
Interpretation”, Ph.D. Thesis, Technische Universität, Darmstadt, Germany, 2004.