Statistics with Commonsense Using Statistics with Commonsense Kault instant download
Statistics with Commonsense Using Statistics with Commonsense Kault instant download
https://ebookname.com/product/statistics-with-commonsense-using-
statistics-with-commonsense-kault/
https://ebookname.com/product/commonsense-methods-for-children-
with-special-educational-needs-6th-edition-peter-westwood/
https://ebookname.com/product/probability-and-statistics-with-r-
arnholt/
https://ebookname.com/product/commonsense-methods-for-children-
with-special-educations-needs-international-relations-and-
security-in-the-digital-age-5th-edition-peter-westwood/
https://ebookname.com/product/care-planning-in-mental-health-
promoting-recovery-2nd-edition-edition-hall/
The Jewish Bible A JPS Guide JPS Guides Jewish
Publication Society
https://ebookname.com/product/the-jewish-bible-a-jps-guide-jps-
guides-jewish-publication-society/
https://ebookname.com/product/the-prehispanic-ethnobotany-of-
paquime-and-its-neighbors-paul-e-minnis-author-michael-e-whalen-
author/
https://ebookname.com/product/rediscovering-interlanguage-1st-
edition-larry-selinker/
https://ebookname.com/product/manipal-manual-of-surgery-4th-
edition-shenoy-rajgopal/
https://ebookname.com/product/alternative-medicine-in-america-
from-quackery-to-commonplace-1st-edition-mary-ruggie/
The myths of security what the computer security
industry doesn t want you to know 1st Edition John
Viega
https://ebookname.com/product/the-myths-of-security-what-the-
computer-security-industry-doesn-t-want-you-to-know-1st-edition-
john-viega/
STATISTICS WITH
COMMON SENSE
David Kault
Greenwood Press
Westport, Connecticut • London
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Kault, David.
Statistics with common sense / David Kault.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-313-32209-0 (alk. paper)
1. Statistics. I. Title.
QA276.12.K38 2003
519.5—dc21 2002075322
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data is available.
Copyright © 2003 by David Kault
All rights reserved. No portion of this book may be
reproduced, by any process or technique, without the
express written consent of the publisher.
Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 2002075322
ISBN: 0-313-32209-0
First published in 2003
Greenwood Press, 88 Post Road West, Westport, CT 06881
An imprint of Greenwood Publishing Group, Inc.
www.greenwood.com
Printed in the United States of America
Preface vii
Acknowledgments ix
Glossaries xi
Statistical Computer Program xiii
1 Statistics: The Science of Dealing with Variability and Uncertainty 1
2 Descriptive Statistics 9
3 Basic Probability and Fisher's Exact Test 33
4 Discrete Random Variables and Some Statistical Tests Based on Them 63
5 Continuous Random Variables and Some Statistical Tests
Based on Them 97
6 General Issues in Hypothesis Testing 141
7 Causality: Interventions and Observational Studies 167
8 Categorical Measurements on Two or More Groups 175
9 Statistics on More Than Two Groups 197
10 Miscellaneous Topics 227
Appendix: Table of the Standard Normal Distribution 239
Answers 241
Annotated Bibliography 253
Index 255
This page intentionally left blank
Preface
the answers from the formula or the computer and understanding how to com-
bine these answers with common sense.
This book is primarily aimed at people who learned statistics at some stage,
never properly understood it, and now need to use it wisely in everyday pro-
fessional life. However, the book should be equally suitable as an introductory
text for students learning statistics for the first time. There is a large number of
introductory statistics texts. This text stands out in three ways:
The last point requires an immediate qualification to prevent the large num-
ber of people with mathematics phobia from shutting the book for good at this
point. No mathematical background beyond grade 10 is assumed, and the
mathematics often consists of simply explaining one logical idea. Because
formulas that can't be fully understood by someone with grade 10 mathemat-
ics are omitted, there is less mathematics than in most statistics texts.
The aim is to show the limited connection between wise decision making
and statistics as it is conventionally practiced, and to show how this situation
can be rectified by combining statistics with common sense.
Acknowledgments
I thank my former statistics teacher, John Hunter, for his teaching, his inspira-
tion, and his suggestions for this book. I also thank my son Sam for his proof-
reading. I am grateful for the support given to me by James Cook University
of North Queensland in writing this book and the accompanying statistical
computer program.
This page intentionally left blank
Glossaries
MATHEMATICAL SYMBOLS
< less than
^ less than or equal to
> greater than
^ greater than or equal to
7^ does not equal
~ approximately equals
~ is
U or (meaning one or the other or both)
H and
| given
n\ n factorial, meaning nx(n-\)x(n-2)x...x3x2x 1; for example,
4!=4x3x2xl=24
"Ck Number of ways that from n objects k objects can be chosen (from n
Choose k)
for example,
Many people frequently come across questionable decisions made on the ba-
sis of statistical evidence. This book will help them to make their own in-
formed judgment about evidence based on statistical analyses. Only some
people will need to undertake statistical analyses themselves. On the other
hand, it is just a small step from understanding statistical evidence to being
able to undertake statistical analyses in many situations. It is a small step be-
cause in most cases the actual calculations are performed by a computer. The
only additional skill to be learned in order for readers to perform statistical
analyses for themselves is to learn which button on the computer to press.
Doing helps learning, so this book includes questions, some of which are in-
tended to be answered with the assistance of a statistical computer program.
There are many statistical computer programs or "packages" available. Al-
most all would be capable of the calculations covered in this book. However,
none are ideal. Many are unnecessarily complex for use in straightforward
situations. The complexity, profusion of options, and graphical output may
serve to confuse and distract users interested only in straightforward situa-
tions. Many contain errors in that they use easy-to-program, approximate
methods when exact methods are more appropriate. Some contain other er-
rors. Few programs are available free of charge, even though most of the intel-
lectual effort underpining such programs is ultimately a product of publicly
funded universities in which academics have worked for the public good.
In response to these issues, I have written a statistical program to accom-
pany this book. I have called the program "pds" for Public Domain Statistics.
It is designed to run on the Windows operating system (version 95 or later),
and occupies about 1 Mb. It is available for distribution free of charge with the
proviso that it is not to be used against the interests of humanity and the envi-
XIV Statistical Computer Program
Statistics can be defined as the science of dealing with variability and uncer-
tainty. Almost all measurements made by scientists and people in many other
fields are uncertain in some way. In particular, most measurement devices
have limited accuracy, so there is uncertainty about the exact value. Some-
times what is being measured varies from individual to individual and from
time to time, making it impossible to measure the true average exactly. For
example, it is impossible to know exactly the true average blood pressure of
the average healthy person.
Often we have to make a decision against a background of variability. We
might be interested in a new blood pressure treatment. Should we believe that
the new treatment works better than the standard treatment? The figures we
collect after trying out the new treatment and comparing it with the standard
treatment may slightly favor the new treatment. However, there is so much
variability in blood pressure from person to person and from day to day that it
will often be difficult to know whether it would be more reasonable to put
slight changes in the average down to the effects of variability rather than to
believe that the new treatment was superior to existing treatments.
field treated with Bloggs's fertilizer the wheat grew better than on the side
treated with Jones's fertilizer and conclude that Bloggs makes better fertilizer
than Jones. Maybe on Bloggs's side of the field the soil was better to start with.
More measurements were needed and these measurements had to be analyzed
"scientifically." There was a need for a scientific approach to making decisions
that took account of the variable nature of many types of measurements.
One important ingredient in the scientific approach seemed to be objectiv-
ity: Scientists were seen as using calculated reason based on hard facts. Mak-
ing decisions based on guesswork and intuition did not seem to be part of the
scientific method. There was therefore pressure to invent an objective method
of drawing conclusions from uncertain or variable information. A method was
wanted that did not depend on intuition. As a result, a method of objective
decision making on the basis of variable data was developed early in the twen-
tieth century and is widely used today. This method is properly called frequentist
statistics. Other mathematically based methods of making decisions in the
face of uncertainty were also developed and come under the heading statistics,
but since these other methods are not objective and are often more difficult,
they are not as well known. Frequentist statistics is so popular and so widely
used that most people don't even realize that it is just one of a number of
different varieties of statistics. For most people, frequentist statistics is "statis-
tics." This book, too, will usually just use the word "statistics" in place of the
mouthful "frequentist statistics."
STATISTICAL IMPERIALISM
Nevertheless, statistics has become the approach that the modern world takes
to analyzing figures. Anybody who has to deal with making decisions on the
basis of figures who simply looks at the figures rather than "get stats done on
them," whether they be a researcher or an administrator, would be regarded as
Dealing with Variability and Uncertainty 3
inadequate in their job and unable to cope with the intelligent, modern ap-
proach. Statistics has conquered the world of decision making. There is an
almost religious belief that the modern world knows how to approach all prob-
lems and that "stats" is part of this approach. Nobody seems to notice that
statisticians don't share this unthinking faith in statistics. Statisticians see some
value in frequentist statistics, but many believe that it is not reasonable to try
to deal with measurements involving uncertainty or variability in an entirely
objective way. To base all analyses on figures alone means to abandon com-
mon sense, and often common sense can bring more wisdom to a subject than
a blind analysis of figures. As a result of ignoring common sense, a consider-
able part of the world's scientific output is wasted effort. Analysis of experi-
ments without the benefit of common sense can lead to misleading and
sometimes dangerous conclusions. The use of common sense shows that many
experiments should not have been performed in the first place.
mon sense here would lead to far better decision making than blind applica-
tion of frequentist statistics.
are?" Expressed another way, we want to ask, "Are the differences real or are
they just due to coincidence?" Instead of answering that question we get a
reply to the question, "If we were to put the differences down to sheer coinci-
dence, what sort of coincidence would we be dealing with?"
The situation here can be compared with the situation of a biologist study-
ing mammals on an island. The biologist may already know that there are cats
on the island, but she may be interested in whether there are different mam-
mals as well. Say the biologist came across some yellow fur. The biologist
will want to ask, "This animal has yellow fur. Does this mean that there are
different mammals here and not just cats?" In the analogy with the questions
asked and the answers given by statistics, the biologist would receive an an-
swer to the secondary question, "Do cats often have yellow fur?"
Let us say that in the case of the exam results of the student pianists we got
the reply from the computer, "Chance alone could often lead to a difference of
2 percent or more between the average of the two groups." From this, if we
were just looking at the figures and ignoring any background knowledge or
common sense, we could say, "The figures themselves give no convincing
evidence of any benefit from the half hour extra tuition." However, it is tradi-
tional in frequentist statistics to leave out the important qualifiers "the figures
themselves" and "convincing" from this sentence and instead state, "There is
no evidence of any benefit from the half hour extra tuition." Even worse, this
misleading form of words is sometimes further distorted to become "statisti-
cal tests have proven that extra tuition is of no benefit." However, as discussed,
even if chance could easily account for the difference in the marks, it does not
accord with common sense to say that we have proven that we should blame
chance for the difference in the marks of the two groups of students.
Now let's say we got the opposite message from the computer: "Chance
alone would hardly ever lead to such a big difference between the two groups." It
is then traditional in frequentist statistics to make the decision that there is a real
difference in the progress of the two groups of student pianists. What is meant by
"hardly ever"? The actual result given by the computer is a probability. Tradition-
ally, "hardly ever" is taken to mean less often than one in twenty times. The
synonyms "/? value less than 0.05," "statistically significant at the 0.05 level,"
"significant at the 0.05 level," or "statistically significant" are often used. If
this happened in the case of the student pianists, we would be happy to agree
with the conclusions reached by someone following the tradition of frequentist
6 Statistics with Common Sense
statistics. In other words, both common sense and frequentist statistics would
tell us that we should believe that the extra tuition is of some benefit.
We have seen in the case of the student pianists an example where stats
could tell us we shouldn't believe something makes a difference when com-
mon sense tells us that it does. There are cases where "stats" tells us that we
should believe that something makes a difference, but common sense tells us
that it doesn't. In such cases we make the judgment that chance, even a rather
tiny chance, is a more reasonable explanation for the differences than the ex-
planation that there is a real underlying difference. For example, let's say a
friend claimed to be a clairvoyant. You tested her powers by seeing if she
could guess some number between 1 and 100 that you had written on a piece
of paper. If she happened to get the correct number and you were an unthink-
ing frequentist statistician, you would now believe that your friend is a clair-
voyant. Why? Because chance alone would hardly ever allow her to get the
correct number. Here, the chance involved would be 1 chance in 100, or/? = 0.01.
Since this is less than a one-in-twenty chance, it is the sort of chance that hardly
ever occurs, and so following the strict traditions of frequentist statistics we would
say that there is statistically significant evidence that your friend is a clairvoyant.
However, most people are at least a bit skeptical about clairvoyants, or at least
won't readily believe that their friends are clairvoyants, and so most people
would not be convinced by one correct guess out of 100 numbers. For these
people, following the traditions of frequentist statistics would lead to a con-
clusion that they felt was not supported by the evidence. Some skeptics might
want to see your friend correctly choose a nine-digit number—chance alone
would allow a correct guess only once in a billion times—before they might
start to believe that genuine powers of clairvoyance is a better explanation
than chance. For such skeptics in this situation, the p value that is just tiny
enough to make them change their minds would be one in a billion or/? =
'A ooo ooo ooo- Here it would be inappropriate for skeptics to use the traditional
value p - 0.05 as the benchmark for the sort of chance that is unreasonably
small. Instead, such skeptics should use/? = 0.000000001 as the benchmark.
Restating, when we see a difference between two groups we might want to
ask, "Could the difference just be due to coincidence?" Statistics does not
answer this question, but instead answers the related question, "If we were to
put the differences down to coincidence, what sort of coincidence would we
be talking about?" The answer to this second question is the p value. If the p
value is unreasonably small, smaller than some arbitrary benchmark (the co-
incidence is highly unlikely), it is more reasonable to believe the difference is
"for real." There is a tradition of using a fixed value of 0.05 as the benchmark
for what is unreasonably small. However, if this tradition is blindly accepted
and the benchmark is not adopted to suit circumstances and common sense,
"stats" can lead to unreasonable, even bizarre, decisions.
This section on the logic used in statistics requires some thought. The logic
is a bit twisted and difficult. However, the ideas just explained are the main
ideas underlying introductory statistics. If you understand these ideas, you
Dealing with Variability and Uncertainty 1
containing such information are headed "Optional" and set between rules. In
some places, these optional sections contain additional examples.
Answers to the questions at the ends of the chapters are given at the end of
the book, beginning on page 241.
SUMMARY
• Statistics is a way of making a decision about whether differences are "for real" or
just a result of chance.
• The form of statistics in common use attempts to be entirely objective and so just
looks at the figures available and entirely ignores any common sense knowledge of
the area.
• As a result, statistics cannot directly answer the question, "Is there a real differ-
ence?" Instead, it answers an indirectly related question: "If we were to blame
coincidence for the difference, what sort of coincidence would we be talking about?"
The answer to this question is called the/? value. If the/? value is smaller than some
benchmark, the coincidence is regarded as unreasonably long and we conclude that
there is a real difference.
• Traditionally, the benchmark p value is taken to be 0.05.
• Blind adherence to this traditional benchmark can lead to unreasonable decisions
that defy common sense.
Put simply, the/? value tells us how easy it is for chance alone to explain differ-
ences. It does not tell us how likely it is for chance to be the true explanation.
QUESTIONS
1. Think of another situation, like the music students and the extra tuition example,
where you would believe that the benefits were "for real" regardless of results
from a statistical analysis telling you that the favorable results could be easily
explained by chance.
2. The roulette wheel in a casino can stop in thirty-eight different positions. The
casino is known to operate the roulette wheel fairly. You notice that the roulette
wheel hasn't stopped on "36" even once in the last 500 goes, so you place a bet on
"36." What is the chance that you will lose your money?
3. Imagine your neighbor claimed to be a clairvoyant and asked you to verify her
powers by getting you to write down a number between 1 and n (where n stands
for a number like 10, 20, 100, or 500) that she then correctly guessed. How big
would n have to be in order to convince you (assuming you can rule out cheating
or magic tricks)?
4. Consider the same scenario as in question 3, but this time you are going to get the
self-declared clairvoyant to perform the number guessing twice in a row and you
will believe in her powers only if she is correct both times. Again, how big would
n have to be in order to convince you (assuming you can rule out cheating or
magic tricks)?
CHAPTER 2
Descriptive Statistics
TYPES OF DATA
Measurements (the words "data" or "information" can be used interchange-
ably here) can be of three basic types: continuous, discrete, and categorical.
Ordinal is a further type which is here described as a subtype of categorical
data.
Continuous Data
In the case of continuous data the thing that is being measured can vary
continuously. An example is the measurement of height. In practice, height
measurements are often rounded to the nearest centimeter or millimeter, but it
is possible for somebody to be, for example, anywhere between 172.3 cm and
172.4 cm in height. If we could use an infinite number of decimal places in
measuring height, there would be an infinite number of heights distributed
continuously between 172.3 and 172.4. Other examples of continuous mea-
surement are weight, temperature, and ozone concentration. In the case of
each of these measurements, the size of the step between one measurement
and the next biggest measurement can be arbitrarily small, so there need be no
Descriptive Statistics 11
cutoff in size between one measurement and the next. Since the size of the
different measurements are not necessarily cut off from each other by any
fixed amount, we regard the measurements as continuous data.
Discrete Data
In the case of discrete data, the measurement has to fall on separated (or
discrete) values. Discrete measurements almost always arise from counting.
An example is the number of accidents the clients of an insurance company
have in one year. For any client the measurement can be 0 or 1 or 2 or 3 and so
on. These numbers are discrete in that they are separated by whole units from
each other. It would make no sense to have the number 1.3 as the number of
accidents a client had. A second example of a discrete measurement is the
number of children in a family, since children also come in whole numbers:
Having 1 child or 2 children in a family makes sense, but no family contains
1.3 children.
ordering in the same way as we think of the numbers 1, 2, and 3, with 2 being
exactly halfway between 1 and 3. A third example could be the classification
of the age of animals as juvenile, immature, adult, or senescent.
Most writers regard ordinal data as a separate type from categorical data, so
the common classification of data types are continuous, discrete, ordinal, and
categorical. How data are classified also depends on our viewpoint. If we look
at plants in a field one by one and decide which species each one belongs to,
we are dealing with categorical data. If we look at the total number of plants
of a particular species in the field, we can regard that number as one item of
discrete data.
As well as classifying data as continuous, discrete, ordinal, or categorical,
data can also be classified according to how many measurements are made on
each individual. Where one measurement is made on each individual, the data
are called univariate. If two measurements are made on each individual, the
data are bivariate. Where more measurements are made on each individual,
the data are multivariate. If we were just interested in height and measured the
height of a number of people, we would have univariate data. If we were
interested in describing the connection between height and weight and mea-
sured these two quantities on each of a number of individuals, we would have
bivariate data. If we were interested in the connection between students' exam
results and their home situation we might measure not only each student's
exam results but also his or her parents' income, parents' educational achieve-
ments, number of siblings, number of hours of TV watched each night, and so
on. This would be multivariate data.
Sources
A.—PRIMARY:
I.—JEWISH:
1.—Old Testament.
2.—Josephus, Antiquities, i., bk. 15, ch. 10, sec. 4-5;
bk. 18, ch. 1, sec. 5; ii., bk. 2, ch. 8, sec. 2-11.
3.—Philo, Contemplative Life. Bohn, Eccl. Lib., 1855,
iv., 1-21.
II.—Greek:
1.—New Testament.
2.—New Testament Apocrypha.
3.—Eusebius, Church Hist., ii., ch. 17. Nic. and Post-
Nic. Fathers, i. Several other eds.
4.—Socrates, Church Hist., i., 13; iv., 23 ff. Ib., ii. Other
eds.
5.—Sozomen, Church Hist., i., 12-14; iii., 14; vi., 28-34.
Ib., ii.
6.—Theodoret, Church Hist., ch. 33. Ib., iii. Bohn Lib.
7.—Evagrius, Life of St. Anthony. Bohn Lib., 1851.
8.—Palladius, Historia Lausiaca. Ed. by Butler, Texts
and Studies. Camb., 1898.
9.—Concerning the Ascetic Life. Not in Eng.
III.—LATIN:
1.—Sulpicius Severus, Dialogues, i.-iii. Nic. and Post-
Nic. Fathers, 2d ser., xi., pt. 11.
2.—Athanasius, Life of Anthony. Ib., iv., 195-221.
3.—Ambrose, Concerning Virgins. Ib., x., 360. Letters,
No. 63. Ib., 457.
4.—Augustine, The Work of Monks. Fathers of the Holy
Catholic Church, xxii., 470-516.
5.—Cassian, Institutes. Nic. and Post-Nic. Fathers, 2d
ser., xi. Cœnobia, Ib. Conferences, Ib.
6.—Jerome, Life of St. Paul the First Hermit. Ib., vi.,
299-318; Letters, No. 22, 130. Ib.
7.—Gregory the Great, Letters. Ib., xii.; Life and
Miracles of St. Benedict. Ed. by Luck, Lond.,
1880.
8.—Rufinus, History of Monks. Not in Eng.
9.—Cassiodorus, Dissertation on Monasticism. Not in
Eng. Letters. Ed. by Hodgkin, Oxf., 1886.
IV.—COLLECTIONS:
The monks sent to England by Pope Gregory the Great soon came to
see that the Celtic Church differed from theirs in many respects.
Augustine himself, having concluded an alliance between Ethelbert
and the Roman See, held several conferences with the Christian
Celts in order to accomplish the most difficult task of their
subjugation to Roman authority. These differences were largely
ritualistic and disciplinary. The Celtic Christians celebrated Easter
according to the calculation of Sulpicius Severus, while the Romans
had another mode of computing the proper day.[237:1] The Celts
appealed to St. John, the Romans to St. Peter.[237:2] The Celtic
Church might be called a monastic Church, since the abbot ruled
over the bishop.[237:3] The Celts shaved the front of the head from
ear to ear as a tonsure, while the Romans shaved the top of the
head leaving a "crown of thorns."[237:4] The Celts permitted their
priests to marry, the Romans forbade it. The Celts used a different
mode of baptism from that of the Romans, namely, single instead of
trine immersion. The calendar for all movable festivals was not the
same. The Celts held their own councils and enacted their own laws,
independent of Rome. The Celts used a Latin Bible unlike the
Vulgate, and kept Saturday as a day of rest, with special religious
services on Sunday.[237:5] Notwithstanding these variances, which
do not seem to be at all on the fundamentals, there were many
doctrinal and constitutional resemblances. Both churches were
orthodox; both used a Latin ritual[238:1]; both had developed an
episcopal organisation; both believed in monasticism; and both were
actively engaged in missionary work. Nevertheless the British
Christians looked with much disfavour upon the Augustine mission to
convert their pagan conquerors and oppressors.
King Ethelbert in 602 arranged a conference of British and Roman
bishops on the Severn in Essex.[238:2] At that gathering Augustine
with unreasonable rigour and haughtiness demanded conformity;
the Britains refused to surrender their independence. To settle the
matter Augustine proposed that an appeal be made to a miracle.
Accordingly a blind Anglo-Saxon was brought in. The Celtic clergy
prayed over him in vain. Whereupon Augustine knelt and prayed,
and immediately the blind man was restored to sight,[238:3] but the
Celts refused to accept that act as final without the consent of a
larger representation in the synod. The next year, therefore, a
second council was held at which the persistent Augustine once
more demanded conformity to Roman practices and the recognition
of papal supremacy, and also requested missionary co-operation, but
the Britains, displeased with Augustine's narrow dogmatism and
apprehensive of the loss of their freedom, refused to submit. "As you
will not have peace with brethren," said the stern Roman monk, "you
shall have war from foes; and as you will not preach unto the
English the way of life, you shall suffer at their hands the vengeance
of death."[239:1] When, ten years later, a wholesale Saxon massacre
of British Christians occurred, in which possibly a thousand priests
and monks were slaughtered and many churches and monasteries
destroyed, further conferences were at an end for fifty years.
It was not until 664 that the famous Council of Whitby was called by
King Oswy of Northumbria in which Bishop Colman and Bishop Cedd,
renowned Celtic divines, defended the British Church; while Bishop
Agilbert, and Wilfred, the greatest English ecclesiastic of his time,
championed Rome. In the discussion about the correct day for
Easter, it was asserted by Wilfred that St. Peter held "the keys to the
kingdom of Heaven." The king then asked Colman and the monks
with him whether that was true, and they were forced to confess
that it was. Consequently, feeling that it was safer to be on the side
of Peter, the "doorkeeper," the king decided in favour of the Church
of Rome.[239:2] This was a very significant victory for the See of St.
Peter, because papal supremacy was now recognised in the British
Isles, and likewise for the future of England, because it opened up a
channel through which Roman Christian civilisation flowed into the
British Isles to influence to a greater or less degree every institution
in that country and, later, through the great empire which England
was to build up to carry those cultural influences around the world.
The work of cementing the Latin and Celtic churches in England into
one was completed by Theodorus, the Archbishop of Canterbury (d.
690), and the Venerable Bede (d. 735). Ecclesiastical unity hastened
political unity in England[240:1] and developed a common civic life
among the divided peoples of the British Isles.[240:2]
Christianity had early spread from Britain to Ireland. The labours of
St. Patrick[240:3] (d. 493) and the work of St. Bridget, the "Mary of
Ireland" (d. 525), have become classics. The Anglo-Saxon invasion
drove many Christians to Ireland in the fifth and sixth centuries, so
that by the seventh century Ireland had become the "Island of
Saints" and the whole island was Christianised. Many famous
monasteries were planted, and an intense missionary zeal had sent
to Scotland, North Britain,[240:4] France, Germany, Switzerland, and
northern Italy many representatives of the Celtic Church.
In 629, Pope Honorius exhorted the Irish Church to conform to the
Roman Easter day. A Celtic deputation was then sent to Rome and,
upon returning home, reported in favour of the Latin system, which
was adopted first in southern Ireland in 632, then in northern
Ireland in 640, and by 704 was generally observed. The Norman
Conquest, in 1066, made the union of Ireland with Rome as well as
with England more complete; but it was left to Henry II., who
conquered Ireland in 1171, to give finality to the dependence of
Ireland on Rome religiously and on England politically.
Christianity was planted in Scotland during the Roman period.[241:1]
An Irish colony, converted by St. Patrick, settled there in the fifth
century. The labours of St. Ninian (sixth cent.), the work of St.
Kentigern (d. 603), and the activity of St. Columba (d. 597)
completed the conversion of the country. St. Columba was a famous
Irish missionary, who went to Scotland in 563, there converted the
king of the Picts and founded many churches. He made his
headquarters on the small island of Iona on which was planted a
monastery famous as a school for missionaries, as the centre of
educational activity, and as the Rome of the Celtic Church.[241:2] For
centuries the Celtic Church maintained its independence in Scotland,
but gradually gave way to the better organised and more aggressive
Roman Church, though the Culdees were not absorbed until 1332.
[241:3]
Sources
Welcome to our website – the ideal destination for book lovers and
knowledge seekers. With a mission to inspire endlessly, we offer a
vast collection of books, ranging from classic literary works to
specialized publications, self-development books, and children's
literature. Each book is a new journey of discovery, expanding
knowledge and enriching the soul of the reade
Our website is not just a platform for buying books, but a bridge
connecting readers to the timeless values of culture and wisdom. With
an elegant, user-friendly interface and an intelligent search system,
we are committed to providing a quick and convenient shopping
experience. Additionally, our special promotions and home delivery
services ensure that you save time and fully enjoy the joy of reading.
ebookname.com