Multivoicedness and univocality in classroom discourse - an example from theory of matter (Mortimer, 1998)
Multivoicedness and univocality in classroom discourse - an example from theory of matter (Mortimer, 1998)
To cite this article: Eduardo Fleury Mortimer (1998) Multivoicedness and univocality in
classroom discourse: an example from theory of matter, International Journal of Science
Education, 20:1, 67-82, DOI: 10.1080/0950069980200105
Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information
(the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor
& Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties
whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose
of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the
opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor
& Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be
independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis
shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs,
expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising
directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of
the Content.
This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes.
Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-
licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly
forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://
www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions
INT. J. sci. EDUC., 1998, VOL. 20, NO. 1, 67-82
The analyses of talk amongst students in three episodes, video recorded from a teaching sequence on the
particle model for Brazilian students (age 14-15) is presented. The analysis has two dimensions: the
discoursive dimension is an attempt to understand how meanings are constructed in the classroom as a
result of discoursive interactions; the conceptual dimension comprises the description of the patterns of
evolution of ideas of matter based on the notion of a conceptual profile of matter, in which conceptual
and historical features of the atom concept are profiled with pupils' and adolescents' ideas on atomism.
From the students talk we can hear the interaction among different 'voices', representing different zones
of a conceptual profile of matter. In this interaction, the students resort to both 'authoritative' and
'internally persuasive' discourses. The analysis emphasizes the role of these two types of discourse and
of epistemological and ontological obstacles in the construction of scientific meanings in the classroom.
Introduction
The investigation of classroom talk, mainly in the area of social psychology and
linguistics, has generated results which have implications for science education.
Some authors, drawing on Vygostky (1978), consider that discourse is at the heart
of the study of teaching and learning, as language is, at the same time, both a
psychological and a communicative tool (Mercer 1996). According to these authors
we use language not only to communicate and to share meaning but also to make
sense of our experience, to constitute our thoughts.
Empirical studies of classroom talk have shown the implicit rules working on
classroom talk, the particular features of this kind of discourse (as, for example, the
I - R - F sequence), and how teachers use the discourse to guide and to evaluate the
learning process (e.g. Edwards and Mercer 1987, Newman et al. 1989, Lemke
1990, Mercer 1995). These studies have indicated that the analysis of classroom
talk should take into account the content of the discourse and how the context of
schooling frames the content and shape of this discourse.
Several authors have attempted to study the discourse of science and of science
classrooms (Lemke 1990, Sutton 1992, Halliday and Martin 1993, Scott 1996,
1997, Ogborn et al. 1996, Mortimer 1997). Scientific language, according to
Halliday (1993), has its own grammar, in which the functions of verbs and
nouns are different from those of everyday language. The processes of science,
which would require an entire phrase to be expressed in everyday language, are
nominalized in scientific language. T h e verbs function as a causal link between
these nouns/processes in a phrase. Through this grammatical metaphor (Halliday
1993) processes are put into a relationship in the construction of a scientific argu-
0950-0693/98 $12 · 00 © 1998 Taylor & Francis Ltd.
68 E. F. MORTIMER
ment. The language of science is, therefore, a way of talking about the world that is
different from everyday language, even in its grammar. Studies of science class-
rooms demonstrate that they are populated by abstract entities (electrons, mol-
ecules and so on) whose meanings are constructed as much as through talk as
through experiments or practical activities. Scott (1996, 1997), for instance, refers
to a 'teaching narrative', a sequence of talk, and activities mediated by talk, that
enact the transformation of knowledge in the intermental plane of the classroom.
These studies also suggest 'that the way in which the teacher "talks around" the
evidence or activity is at least as important as the evidence or activity itself (Scott
1997:127).
The study presented here aims at relating the discoursive analysis of science
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
intensive research on students' alternative ideas, that has identified the same sort
of conceptions related to the same scientific concept in different parts of world.
In this article, the categories of the conceptual profile of matter (Mortimer
1995) will be used to analyse the content of the students' discourse. The first zone
of a conceptual profile of matter is called 'sensible', which means appealing to the
senses, and it is characterized by the absence of any discontinuous notion of mat-
ter. A student who only has this notion of matter represents it as continuous,
without any reference to particles. Its main obstacle is the negation of the possi-
bility of the existence of empty space between the particles. Related to this concept
of matter there is a notion of the physical states of matter being closely linked with
external appearances and physical features of materials, which states, for example,
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
that a solid is hard and a liquid is soft (Stavy and Stachel 1985, Stavy 1988, 1990).
The second zone of the profile is called 'substantialist atomism'. The notion of
substantialism leads to the conclusion that, despite using particles in their repre-
sentations, the students think of such particles as grains of matter than can dilate,
contract, change state, and so forth. Students, thus, make an analogy between the
behaviour of the particles that they draw and that of the substance. They are not
referring to the atom as a scientific concept, but to grains of matter that show
macroscopic properties. This analogy between the macroscopic and the micro-
scopic worlds is the main epistemological obstacle to further progress for students
whose concepts can be classified in this region. Moreover, the fact that they use
particles in their representations of matter is no guarantee that they believe in the
existence of the vacuum between them. This is particularly important in the sense
that someone in this zone has not necessarily overcome the obstacle of the previous
zone.
The kind of ideas that characterize these two first zones of the profile of
matter, i.e. matter as continuous and 'substantialist atomism', are described in
almost all articles about students' ideas related to the concept of matter (e.g.
Piaget and Inhelder 1941, Doran 1972, Novick and Nussbaum 1978, 1981,
Nussbaum 1985, Griffiths and Preston 1992, Garnett and Hackling 1995).
Although it is not possible to relate all the students' ideas about matter to these
two zones, the notion of a conceptual profile of matter provides a theoretical back-
ground that can highlight the main characteristics of such ideas and its main
obstacles to the construction of scientific ideas about matter in the classroom. In
the previous descriptions there was no reference, for example, to the idea that a
molecule is 'macro' in size (Griffiths and Preston 1992). However, if students
think about atoms and molecules as grains of matter that show macroscopic beha-
viour such as dilating, melting and so forth, they should think of these grains as
'macro' in size as well.
The third zone of the profile of matter corresponds to a classic notion of the
atom as the basic unit of matter, which is conserved during chemical transforma-
tions. The atom is a material particle and its behaviour is governed by mechanical
laws, like any other body. Substances are made up of molecules that result from
the combination of atoms. Atoms of the same type have the same atomic number.
This article does not deal with the atom as a system of electrical particles nor
with the quantum mechanical zones of the profile of matter. Nevertheless, it is
important to realize that classical atomism still has some 'substantialist' character-
istics as a legacy of its mechanistic origins. Despite the epistemological difference
between classical atomism and the other two areas of the profile, all these concep-
70 E. F. MORTIMER
tions consider the atom as a kind of material thing, a basic block from which
substances are built. In this sense, all these 'atoms' belong to the same ontological
category. The main difference is that, in a classical view, we cannot attribute all
material behaviour to atoms, just because some forms of behaviour (such as melt-
ing, boiling, dilating) are a consequence of the motion of atoms, molecules or ions
in a vacuum and of the interaction between them, which can vary as the energy of
the system is modified. Consequently, an individual atom does not show properties
like boiling or melting points; these are interpreted as resulting from aggregating
the behaviour of a great number of them in macroscopic amounts. Nevertheless, a
classical atom shows some other material properties like mass, volume, radius, etc.;
it is a material thing, that belongs to the ontological category of substance. Matter
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
The analysis of the social and linguistic features of the classroom has incor-
porated some aspects of research on classroom talk. Studies of the development of
understanding in the classroom have generated several works in recent years and
some of them have a direct relationship with the sociocultural approach and the
semiotic analysis of Vygotsky.
Drawing on the work of Vygotsky, Bakhtin and Lotman, Wertsch (1991)
offers an insightful way to look at the generation of meaning in social settings
that can be used to analyse the construction of shared knowledge in the classroom
and that complements the approach based on conceptual profile outlined here. If
we look at the classroom as a space where at least two different languages - the
scientific and the everyday - are put in contact to generate new meaning, then
dialogicality and multivoicedness offer fundamental categories to analyse this
process. According to Voloshinov, any true understanding is dialogic in nature:
To understand another person's utterance means to orient oneself with respect to it, to
find the proper place for it in the corresponding context. For each word of the
utterance that we are in process of understanding, we, as it were, lay down a set of
our own answering words. The greater their number and weight, the deeper and more
substantial our understanding will be (Voloshinov 1973:102, cited by Wertsch
1991:54)
In this way, an utterance involves not only the voice producing it, but also the
voices to which it is addressed. This is a consequence of the multivoicedness that
characterizes the process of understanding.
Bakhtin's (1981) notion of voice refers to more than an auditory signal. It
involves the much more general phenomenon of the speaking subject's perspective
which is related to his/her world view. Related to the issues of dialogicality and
multivoicedness, Lotman's account of the functional dualism of texts in a cultural
system is very useful for analysing classroom talk. According to Lotman, the two
basic functions that texts fulfil are 'to convey meanings adequately, and to generate
new meanings' (Lotman 198: 34, cited by Wertsch 191:73). The first function -
called by Wertsch the univocal function of text — 'is fulfilled best when the codes of
the speaker and the listener most completely coincide and, consequently, when the
text has the maximum degree of univocality' (Lotman 1988:34). The second
function of a text — called by Wertsch the dialogic function — is to generate new
meanings.
In this respect a text ceases to be a passive link in conveying some constant informa-
tion between input (sender) and output (receiver). Whereas in the first case a differ-
ence between the message at the input and that at the output of an information circuit
72 E. F. MORTIMER
can occur only as a result of a defect in the communication channel... in the second
case such a difference is the very essence of a text's function as a 'thinking device'.
What from the first standpoint is a defect, from the second is a norm, and vice versa
(Lotman 1988: 36-37, cited by Wertsch 1991:74).
Bakhtin's distinction between 'authoritative' and 'internally persuasive' dis-
course is clearly related to the univocal and dialogic functions of text. According to
Bakhtin (1981), in an authoritative discourse the utterances and their meanings are
presupposed to be fixed, not modifiable as they come into contact with new voices.
It is not a free appropriation and assimilation of the world itself that authoritative
discourse seeks to elicit from us; rather, it demands our unconditonal allegiance.
(Bakhtin 1981:343)
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
In contrast, the internally persuasive discourse seeks for the 'counter words', it is
'half-ours and half-someone else's', allowing dialogic interanimation.
The semantic structure of an internally persuasive discourse is not finite, it is open; in
each of the new contexts that dialogize it, this discourse is able to reveal ever new ways
to mean. (Bakhtin 1981: 346; emphasis in original).
According to Wertsch, for any text there is a tension between its univocal and
dialogic functions. Any discourse has authoritative and internally persuasive char-
acteristics. We can look to classroom talk searching for the context where one or
another feature predominates. T h e construction of a new meaning within a pre-
dominantly 'internally persuasive' discourse can be followed by recapitulations
where the 'authoritative' prevails. T h e use — or not — of the appropriate discourse
for each context can help us to explain the matching and mismatching between
teacher and student undertandings.
'">•
w
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
(b)
- So'/.cfc>
(c)
Figure 1. Examples of students' representations for matter undergoing
change (a) discontinuous representations, (b) mixed representations,
(c) sensible representations.
not relate something imagined to the phenomenon but, instead, simply makes a
drawing of the situation [figure l(c)], cannot be considered as having the same
understanding of the word model as the first student.
Episodes 1 and 2 are based on classroom discourse that took place at the
beginning of the teaching sequence, during the discussion of the first two phenom-
ena (compression of air in a plugged syringe; expansion of air heated in a test tube
with a balloon over its neck). Two types of obstacles, belonging to the first two
zones of the conceptual profile of matter, were addressed in these episodes: the
negation of the empty space between particles and substantialism. Episode 3
belongs to the end of the teaching sequence and the analysis attempts to show
how the students use features of a classical view of matter — the third zone of the
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
to the space between particles as something to be addressed, the students might not
take this as a problem. When Raq referred to the space between particles, at the
end of utterance 5, it was not her 'voice' that was speaking, but the teacher's, which
began to frame the student's negotiation of meaning. Raq would prefer to use a
continuous model because in this model 'there won't be space and there won't be
any doubt' (utterance 7). Although her view of matter was not accepted, her
question had to be addressed by her classmates.
The presence of the teacher's voice in the students' dialogue is an example of
the dialogicality that characterizes the generation of new meanings. In this text,
each utterance involves not only the voice producing it, but also the voices to
which it is addressed (Voloshinov 1973). The model that emerges at the end of
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
the episode (utterance 12) also reflects its predominately internally persuasive
nature. According to Bakhtin, 'the semantic structure of an internally persuasive
discourse is not finite, it is open; in each of the new contexts that dialogize it, this
discourse is able to reveal ever new ways to mean' (Bakhtin 1981: 346; emphasis
original). To counter Raq's objection ('But, between the particles, is there a
vacuum?') Car had to re-build her argument. Understanding the difficulty of
the idea of 'nothing' between the particles, she filled the empty space with particles
of things other than air ('we have other particles... nitrogen, pollution, dust, all
sorts of things').
4. Raq: That is model three (she is referring to the number of the model that
they have on the sheet distributed by the teacher).
5. Car: What do you think, Gla?
6. Gla: Nothing... I don't know.
7. Car: Hey! We have to answer h e r e . . . We observed that the balloon filled up,
didn't we? But we have no answer: explain...
8. Raq: We have to explain: Air, when heated, expands.
9. Car: Expands. The air particles expand when heated because there is empty
space between the particles.
10. Edw: It is the air that expands.
11. Car: It isn't the air that expands, it is the particles that expand.
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
12. Car: Ah, now we have to draw h e r e . . . the model that we've chosen... (They
draw.)
13. Car: Here, see: we have to write the characteristics. What is the character-
istics of the first (tube)?
14. Edw: Normal.
15. Car: Normal. T h e particles have their normal size... now, in the second
(tube), they've got bigger, expanded, filling a bigger volume, haven't they?
16. Edw: Yes.
Episode 2 shows that Raq and Car had, at the outset of the episode, a consensus
about attributing the macroscopic property of expanding to the particles
(utterances 1 and 2). As Gla and Edw did not challenge their views, the text
became predominantly authoritative in nature. In contrast to Episode 1, where
'counter-words' had an important role in building a common understanding,
Episode 2 shows no space for voices other than the substantialist one. Car's
emphatic statement in utterance 11 in answering Edw's objection (utterance 10)
shows that she was not trying to negotiate her view any more, but only to find the
best way to express it, which was achieved in utterance 15.
Another characteristic of this episode is that the teacher's voice was not repre-
sented as in Episode 1. The students were not addressing a teacher's question nor did
they take any of his arguments against substantialism into account. The idea of empty
space between particles seems not to be a problem any more, and Car referred to it
in utterance 9 as an 'explanation' for the idea that particles could expand themselves.
2. Ale: We only have to take into account... as a gas has more motion, it has
more energy. N o w . . . , the problem is how to explain gas.
3. Edw: It is this . . .
4. Raq: In the gaseous state the particles have more energy and their motion is
greater . . . wait a minute . . .
5. Ale: Please, you are driving us crazy . . .
6. Raq: Yes ... I am crazy too.
7. Car: If we were talking about solids, how much energy is associated with the
motion of these particles... Because it is solid and they vibrate, I
m e a n . . . t h e n . . . If we chose the liquid it means that they move them-
selves in groups, but if we chose the gaseous they move with more
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
freedom.
8. Raq: But it has to be logical.
9. Ale: Yes, you can't say it is because it is, it is because it i s . . .
10. Car: But it is because it is . . .
11. Gla: The gaseous..., when a gas is heated, its volume increases and its
motion increases as well.
12. Edw: But you can't say that a gas has motion only when it is heated.
13. Car: Good god! It is related to the particles . . .
14. Raq: Why is its motion greater than that of solids and liquids? Because the
particles move individually.
15. Edw: Because they can be considered as individual particles.
16. Car: Then!...
17. Raq: Then they can move faster.
18. Edw: Yes! Move faster.
19. Raq: Then we have to explain it this way. Then we can say that because they
move themselves . . . , no, they move themselves because of what? What
is this?
20. Edw: Because they are individual, the particles are individual... it is t h a t . . .
21. Ale: The problem is the quantity of...
22. Edw: Wait a minute . . .
[They stop and become thoughtful.]
23. Ale: I'd say that they are independent and move more quickly, then . . .
24. Raq: Yes, it is necessary to say that they move more quickly because . . .
25. Ale: How is energy related to motion? How is the amount of energy related
to motion? The greater the energy, the faster the motion. And that is all.
We notice here that the students did not have a full understanding of the question -
how is energy related with the particles' motion - when they began to deal with it.
At the outset Ale seemed to have understood the question, as he tried to relate
motion to energy in the gaseous state (utterance 2), but he was not convinced that
his statement could be the answer. The dialogue that follows shows how the
students try to construct this understanding by building an argument around
the notions of energy, motion and arrangement. In doing so they review several
characteristics of an atomistic model for solids, liquids and gases: which kind of
motion predominates in each state (utterance 7); how heat can affect the volume
and the particles' motion in a gas (utterance 11); that the particles have an intrinsic
motion, as 'y°u can't say that a gas has motion only when it is heated' (utterance
78 E. F. MORTIMER
12); that the particles in a gas are far apart and therefore 'they can be considered as
individual particles' (utterances 15 and 20); and that being individual they move
more quickly (utterances 17, 18 and 23).
Some of these statements are not completely true. For example, the particles of
a gas do not necessarily move faster than the particles of a liquid, as kinetic energy -
and consequently motion - depends on the temperature and not on the particles'
condition of being individual or not. Nevertheless, the students in this episode are
framing a question with much more appropriate variables — motion, energy and
arrangement - than they framed the questions in Episodes 1 and 2. The teacher's
voice is present throughout the episode, but in a way that is different from Episode
1, where it was only referred to. In Episode 3 the teacher's voice becomes the
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
Conclusions
The analysis presented in this article articulates two dimensions of the science
classroom - the discoursive and the conceptual. In describing the evolution of
students' ideas in terms of a conceptual profile of matter, the obstacles to the
construction of a scientific idea and the difficulties students face when trying to
explain some phenomena with their own ideas could be highlighted. However, if
MULTIVOICEDNESS AND UNIVOCALITY IN THE CLASSROOM 79
the analysis had had only this conceptual dimension, we could not say anything
about the way the new ideas emerged in the classroom talk.
The analyses of the episodes demonstrated that the students resorted to three
different zones of a conceptual profile of matter in different parts of a teaching
sequence, and showed the different kinds of discourse they used in building their
arguments. We might expect not to find an authoritative discourse when analysing
the students' talk. Nevertheless, the analysis of these episodes indicates that dis-
course in the classroom can be authoritative or internally persuasive independently
of being enunciated by the students or by the teacher. Both types of discourse were
present in the students' dialogues. An alternation between these two types of
discourse seems to be an important feature of the classroom talk. The phenomenon
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
Acknowledgements
This work was supported by grants from CNPq and CAPES (PADCT-SPEC).
References
BACHELARD, G. (1968) The Philosophy of No (New York: T h e Orion Press) (trans. La
philosophie du non (1940) by G. C. Waterston).
BACHELARD, G. (1975) Les intuitions atomistiques (essai de classification) (Paris: J. Vrin).
BAKHTIN, M. M. (1981) The Dialogic Imagination (edited by Michael Holqust, trans. Caryl
Emerson and Michael Holquist) (Austin: University of Texas Press).
BILLIG, M. (1996) Arguing and Thinking: A Rhetorical Approach to Social Psychology
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
BOHR, N. (1935) Can quantum-mechanical descriptions of physical reality be considered
complete? Physical Review, 48, 696-702.
DORAN, R. (1972) Misconceptions of selected science concepts held by elementary school
children. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 9, 127-137.
DRIVER, R. (1985) Beyond appearance: the conservation of matter under physical and
chemical transformations. In R. Driver, E. Guesne and A. Tiberghien (eds),
Children's Ideas in Science (Milton Keynes: Open University Press).
EDWARDS, D. and MERCER, N. (1987) Common Knowledge: The Development of
Understanding in Classrooms (London: Routledge).
EDWARDS, A. D. and WESTGATE, D. P. G. (1987) Investigating Classroom Talk (London:
Falmer).
EINSTEIN, A., PODOLSKY, B. and ROSEN, N. (1935) Can quantum-mechanical descriptions of
physical reality be considered complete? Physical Review, 47, 777-780.
GARNETT, P. J. and HACKLING, M. W. (1995) Students' alternative conceptions in chemistry:
a review of research and implications for teaching and learning. Studies in Science
Education, 25, 69-95.
GREGORY, J. G. (1931) A Short History of Atomism (London: A. and C. Black).
GRIFFITHS, A. K. and PRESTON, K. R. (1992) Grade 12 students' misconceptions relating to
fundamental characteristics of atoms and molecules. Journal of Research in Science
Teaching, 29, 611-628.
HALLIDAY, M. A. K. (1993) Some grammatical problems in scientific English. In M. A. K.
Halliday and J. R. Martin, Writing Science: Literacy and Discoursive Power
(Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press).
HALLIDAY, M. A. K. and MARTIN, J. R. (1993) Writing Science: Literacy and Discoursive
Power (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press).
KNIGHT, D. M. (ed.) (1968) Classical Scientific Papers: Chemistry (London: Mills & Boon).
KUHN, D. (1992) Thinking as argument. Harvard Educational Review, 62, 155-178.
LEMKE, J. L. (1990) Talking Science: Language, Learning and Values (Norwood: Ablex).
MULTIVOICEDNESS AND UNIVOCALITY IN THE CLASSROOM 81
LOTMAN, Y. M. (1988) The semiotics of culture and the context of a text. Soviet Psychology,
26, 32-51.
MARTON, F. (1981) Phenomenography: describing conceptions of the world around us.
Instructional Science, 10, 177-200.
MERCER, N. (1995) The Guided Construction of Knowledge: Talk Amongst Teachers and
Learners (Clevedon: Multilingual Matters).
MERCER, N. (1996) Las perspectivas socioculturales y el estudio del discurso en aula. In
C. Coll and D. Edwards (eds), Enseñanza, aprendizaje y discurso en el aula:
Aproximaciones al estudio del discurso educacional (Madrid: Infancia Y Aprendizaje).
MORTIMER, E. F. (1995) Conceptual change or conceptual profile change? Science and
Education, 4, 267-285.
MORTIMER, E. F. (1997) Múltiplos olhares sobre um episódio de ensino: 'Por que o gelo
flutua na água?'. In Anais do Encontro sobre Teoria e Pesquisa em Ensino de Ciências:
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
Appendix
(1) Classifying materials as solids, liquids and gases and identifying the criteria used in
the classification.
(2) Choosing, from the models presented in the pre-test and selected by the teacher,
the best model to explain:
2.1. Compression of air in a plugged syringe
2.2. Dilation of air submitted to heating in a test tube with a balloon over its neck
2.3. Vacuum in a flask connected to a large syringe
2.4. Gas odour scattering in the kitchen as it escapes from its container
Downloaded by [The University of Texas at El Paso] at 01:42 18 August 2014
For each of these four phenomena three steps were planned (after the second
phenomenon, step 1 was omitted as it seemed to be redundant):
(a) Identification of the features of the model drawn by the students (class as a
whole)
(b) Discussion in groups to choose the best model (groups of students)
(c) Discussion with the whole class to choose the best model
(3) Summarizing the characteristics of a model for gases:
3.1. How the model explains compression, dilation, vacuum and diffusion:
(a) Group discussion
(b) Class discussion
3.2. Generalizing the model to explain temperature and pressure of gases
(teaching exposition and class discussion).
(4) Generalizing the atomistic model to liquids and gases by choosing, from the mod-
els presented in the pre-test and selected by the teacher, the best one to explain:
4.1. Dilatation, by means of heating with the hand, the alcohol (or mercury)
column of a thermometer
4.2. Melting and vaporization of naphthalene heated in a test tube
For each of these two phenomena two steps were planned:
(a) Discussion in groups to choose the best model (groups of students)
(b) Discussion with the whole class to choose the best model
(5) Summarizing the atomistic model for solids, liquids and gases (group discussion
followed by class discussion).
(6) Generalizing the atomistic model to new situations:
6.1. Spontaneous dissolving of potassium manganate(VII) in water
6.2. Dissolving of sugar and salt in water
For each of these two phenomena two steps were planned:
(a) Discussion in groups to explain the phenomenon based on the atomistic
model
(b) Discussion with the whole class to choose the best explanation
(7) Different conceptions of solids, liquids and gases:
7.1. Analysing the criteria to classify solids, liquids and gases revealed in the first
activities, in the light of the new atomistic concept of solid, liquid and gas.
How does the new concept explain the properties of solids, liquids and gases
identified in the first activity?
7.2. Materials that 'resist' classification as solid, liquid or gas: glass, cloud, fog,
etc. The conception of colloidal solution.
For each of these two themes two steps were planned:
(a) Discussion in group to answer several questions related to the theme
(b) Discussion with the whole class to choose the best answer to each question