471611
471611
DIRECTIONAL SVC
Now, let’s consider examples of Directional SVCs such as (1) and (2) below.
always transitive, and the second verb is a motional intransitive verb, followed by a
directional verb, either lai (come) or qu (go). Even though lai and qu can be a full
33
Li (2001) named the constituent Vi + lai/qu as CDC (Le comple ment directionnel complexe du
verbe; complex directional complement).
106
(complex directional complement).
(3) a. ta qu/lai le
He go/come PERF
‘He went/came.’
modern Mandarin Chinese normally surface in a different word order, i.e. as verb
contrast of (4a) and (4b). A result VP separate from the cause (VP1) by an object NP,
such as (1), is comparatively rare, and the form seems to limit to conditions when the
result VP is a CDC.
He kill-die person-PERF
107
‘He killed someone dead.’
In addition, example (2) shows that VP2 can be simply a direction of the first
action (V1), not a result. Hence, VP2 can be a result like (1), or a pure direction like
(2). Since VP2 is directional in nature, we classify both sentences (1) and (2) into
Directional SVCs.
Finally, these examples cannot be interpreted in other way, such as CCs, since
there is no subject sharing between the two verbs. Nor can VP2 in this construction
controlled by the matrix subject. Contrary to all the previously mentioned Chinese
SVCs, this type involves only object sharing, where the object of V1 is semantically
In the ancient China, there was a period of time when resultative constructions
appeared in the form of RSVCs, where there was an object NP mediating between the
108
two verbs. Mei (1981) demonstrated that, in Tang dynasty, the result phrase can
appear either after the object NP, as (5), or before it, as (6).
Vt + O + result
(5)a. 吹 歡 [情人] 羅裳 開
b. 當 打 汝 口 破
dang da ru kou po
Vt + result + O
(6)a. 折 斷 綠 楊 枝。
109
(李白《宣城送劉副使入秦》Libai, shuanchen song liu fushi ru qin,1810)
b. 今日 壓 倒 元白 矣。
In modern Chinese, the constituent V + CDC can surface in the following word
orders (Li, 2001). Take na chu lai 'take out’ for example:
A. V+O+ Vi+lai/qu
B. V+ Vi+O+lai/qu
C. V+ Vi+lai/qu +O
110
(9) Na chu lai [yizhi bi]
D. BA+O+V+ Vi+lai/qu
Examples (7)-(10) show that the relative positions of the object NP and the
V+CDC are quite free. The object NP can be between the verbs (7-8), after the
behaviors of (9) and (10) indicate that the object NP is actually the object of the whole
complex predicate (V+CDC), instead of just that of the first verb. Now, let’s
compare sentences when the CDC is a result phrase. Take tuei xia qu ‘push down’
for example.
A. V+O+Vi+lai/qu
111
Push he fall go
B. *V+Vi+O+ lai/qu
Push fall he go
C. V+ Vi+lai/qu +O
Push fall go he
112
D. BA+O+V+ Vi+lai/qu
BA he push fall go
smaller non-separable constituent, and so that the possible word orders are more
limited. This is manifested by the ungrammaticality of word order B (12), where the
and (14), again, show that the object NP is the object of the whole constituent V+CDC.
predicate.
113
7.2 The Syntactic Structures
Following our previous discussion, there are three possibilities of the structure
The first possibility assumes VP2 as the head. Hence, V1 would be a modifier
to VP2. In this case, modality, negation and question-formation will be all on the
The second possibility assumes that V1 is the head of the complex predicate.
Theoretically, this is on a par with Huang’s (2006) claim that Chinese has gone
Now, let’s examine the sentence behaviors. The following examples show that
negation, modals and manner adverbs can be placed in front of V1 and scopes over
VP2. On the contrary, VP2 cannot be negated, nor can a modal be placed
immediately before it. If there is a manner adverb specifically modifying VP2, the
34
The argument is based primarily on the derivation of [V sha ‘kill’] NP to [V shi ‘die] NP in Chinese.
114
sentence will be ok with a resultative VP2, but unacceptable with a directional VP2.
b. ta huei na bi chu-lai.
b. ta bu na bi chu-lai.
115
‘He take out the pen quickly.’
b.*ta na bi bu chu-lai.
Examples (15)-(17) show that VP2 falls into the scope of modality and negation
of V1, and hence V2 cannot be the structural head. Examples (18)-(20), especially
independent clause. Thus, the first possibility, right-headed analysis, is out. Finally,
116
the contrast of (20a)-(20b) seems to indicate that a result phrase can be a VP
independent from V1, while a pure directional phrase cannot be separate from the first
verb.
right track. A secondary predicate, like (21), reveals different behaviors with a CDC
on negation (22) and modal (23) placement. Crucially, the secondary predicate hen
congming can not raise to the right of jiao-guo and form a legitimate constituent with
it.
117
He possible teach-EXP one student very smart
‘It is possible that he once taught a student who was very smart.’
Now, we will assume on the second possibility that Directional SVCs are
complex predicates, and V1 is the structural head. V1 must raise to the light v
constituent, can optionally pied-pipe with V1. Moreover, the object yigeren is the
object of the whole complex predicate, instead of just that of tuei, as evidenced by
tuei xia-qu yigeren. This has an extra benefit of avoiding Huang’s PSC. Besides,
as we have mentioned, the result VP can not be further split into smaller units and
consequently neither of the two elements can be raised out from the constituent. In
118
(24)
vP
DP v’
v VP
CAUSE
DP V’
yigeren
V VP
tuei V
xia-qu
On the other hand, when VP2 is a directional VP, the correlation of the two
elements within the VP is rather loose. This VP is a real VP, and can be further
broken into smaller units, such as chu and lai. Hence, after na raises to the light verb,
either chu or chu-lai can optionally raise along with it to the higher position. The
movement of lai alone is ungrammatical, since it reverses the original word order
chu-lai.
119
(25)
vP
DP v’
v VP
CAUSE
DP V’
yizhi bi
V VP
na
chu-lai
Now, we have claimed on the left-headed structure for Directional SVCs, and
dispensed the possibility of the right-headed structure. Yet there is still one
structure proposed by Baker and Stewart. Adopting their analysis, the sentence
structure of a Directional SVC would be like (26). Actually, (26) is roughly the
120
(26)
vP…
v VP
DP V’
yigeren V V
tuei xia-qu
Is there a best choice between (24) and (26)? I believe there is. And the
answer should be (24). A double-headed structure like (26) has long been criticized
head. Moreover, -criterion regulates that an argument should be assigned one and
only one theta role. Clearly, in (26), yigeren inevitably receives two theta roles from
the two heads. On the contrary, our postulation in (24) raises no such problems, for
a maximal projection, VP, intervenes between the two verbs tuei and xia-qu. There
is still one benefit of our analysis. On the VP analysis, that chu or chu-lai in (25) can
121
optionally pied-pipe with V1 is directly accounted for, while it would be a problem
for (26) to explain why chu can raise out of the head verb chu-lai.
structure can explain the sentence behaviors. However, since left-headed analysis
7.3. Summary
resultative VP2 and the other with a pure directional VP2. Even though the two
types are different semantically, they are highly similar in the combination of verb
types (both are Vi +lai/qu) and on the event structure—both denote a single event
with the previous Vt. Syntactically, they are analyzed either a left-headed complex
122