L03 Detailed Notes
L03 Detailed Notes
(1) Define a scientific explanation and discuss the two basic ways in which a theory differs from a
hypothesis.
(2) Explain the difference between two events being correlated and being related as cause and
effect.
(3) Discuss the basic features of the following types of scientific explanations: (a) cause and effect,
(b) causal mechanism, (c) underlying processes, (d) laws, (e) function.
(4) Explain Occam’s Razor, illustrating its use with an example.
(5) Discuss what is a scientific model, the different types and their purpose, and explain the
difference between a model and a theory illustrating your explanation with an example.
1
Lecture 3 HSI1000
explanation because it’s untestable. Therefore, there is no way for us to know for sure whether the
explanation is correct or not.
The bottom line is that a scientific explanation for something must be subject to falsification. If there’s
no way of demonstrating that the explanation is false through experimentation, or “reality checks”,
then the explanation is not scientific.
2
Lecture 3 HSI1000
Science contains many such theories – theories that have been repeatedly put to the test and provide
breadth and depth in their explanatory power. Theories like the theory of evolution, the big-bang
theory, atomic theory, statistical mechanics, the kinetic theory of gases, the theories of special and
general relativity, quantum mechanics. The list goes on and on.
The theories I just mentioned all represent “well-established theories”. They are “well-established”
because they have been tested numerous times in many ways and continue to pass all the tests, but
not all theories are like this.
Obsolete or Superseded Theories
Often these well-established theories have superseded previous, older theories. Theories that were
thought to be correct at the time, but eventually came undone because of new evidence that proved
them wrong – like the Aristotelian world view we discussed during the first lecture. These superseded
theories, now known to be wrong, are still, to this day, called theories. Here’s just one example.
I mentioned germ theory as
currently being the reining theory for
the cause of many diseases. But for
the longest time, the reigning theory
for the cause of disease was demonic
theory. Devils and demons were
thought to be the cause of disease.
This theory gave way to punitive
theory, which explained disease as
punishment by the gods for evils
committed.
3
Lecture 3 HSI1000
3.1.3 In Conclusion
Of course, well-established theories also have to undergo revision when new evidence is uncovered
because science is self-correcting. This is how we end up eventually homing in on the right
explanation for things.
As you can see, the term ‘theory’ is a little more complicated than the term ‘hypothesis’. The term
‘theory’ can apply to well-established and currently accepted explanations, but it can also apply to
contested explanations or even obsolete and wrong explanations. As such it’s always important when
learning or hearing about a theory to clarify the stage of the scientific theory it is at.
Next, we’ll learn about a very common type of explanation used to account for observed phenomena:
causation and its relationship to correlation.
For those interested, here’s a well written article from the New York Times discussing W. Jason
Morgan who developed the Theory of Plate Tectonics. It uses “theory” and “hypothesis” correctly
and very easy to read.
4
Lecture 3 HSI1000
5
Lecture 3 HSI1000
gun picket with 100 soldiers is safe because you know the one guy that happened to make it through
the hail of bullets.
Another example is children drinking fluoridated water have fewer problems with tooth decay
compared to those that don’t. There is a causal link between fluoride and tooth decay. However, it
isn’t true that children who drink fluoridated water will be completely free from tooth decay.
3.2.1.5 Causal explanations can be negative
The previous example brings us to our fifth complication. Sometimes causal explanations can be
negative. For example, fluoridation of water helps prevent tooth decay, or wearing a mask helps
prevent COVID transmission.
3.2.1.5 Causal explanations can involve a series of linked causes and effects
Lastly, causal explanations can involve a series of linked events, like A causing B which in turn causes
C. Terms like proximate and remote are sometimes used to describe the relationship between these
causes. A is a proximate cause of B. Likewise, B is a proximate cause of C. A can be termed as a remote
cause of C. As an example, I’ve embedded a YouTube video illustrating how a butterfly causes a boat
to crash through a roof with this video. After watching the video, you should be able to state the
proximate causes and effects as well as give some examples of a remote cause and effect.
6
Lecture 3 HSI1000
Antioxidant Activity vs Phenolic Content in Local Fruits You will also have to consider the strength of
a correlation. Figure 4 is an example of a
strong positive correlation. See how the data
Ferric Reducing Antioxidant Power
7
Lecture 3 HSI1000
8
Lecture 3 HSI1000
9
Lecture 3 HSI1000
Prof Bettens: So, there you go, that's how CO2 emissions causes the Earth to warm up even more. I
suppose if there was even more CO2 in the atmosphere there would be even more heating up of the
atmosphere and even more heating of the Earth in turn.
Prof Lee: Indeed, yes.
Prof Bettens: OK, thanks.
Figure 8. Highly simplified causal mechanism of how CO2 emissions causes global warming
Providing a causal mechanism clearly enhances our understanding of the phenomenon and may even
provide us with a means of reducing the effect if it is bad, enhancing it if it is good, or protecting it if
the effect is important and must be maintained, etc.
Just knowing a remote cause and its effect is only the first step in any scientific inquiry. Working out
a causal mechanism provides a much clearer picture of what’s going on. But this type of explanation
can still leave us wondering why and how any particular proximate cause results in an effect.
10
Lecture 3 HSI1000
3.3.3 Laws
Some phenomena are explained through scientific laws. These are just generalized descriptions of
regularities that have been found to occur in nature. For example, what happens if the volume of a
container of gas is reduced while its temperature remains constant? The pressure increases. Why?
Robert Boyle (Figure 15), in 1662, showed,
through experiments on air, that the pressure of
a gas varied in inverse proportion to its volume,
provided the temperature remained fixed
(Figure 14). This is known as Boyle’s law. So, as
we reduce the volume, the pressure increases in
inverse proportion. The explanatory power of
laws like these comes from their ability to reveal
how particular events are instances of generally Figure 14. Robert Boyle's original
data from Wikipedia: Krishnavedala
Figure 15. Robert Boyle from understood regularities in nature.
Wikipedia.
This law, like others, tends to be thought of as universal, so we expect Boyle’s law to hold for all
gases, although we know now that gases under extreme conditions can deviate significantly from this
law. As another example, we mentioned Newton’s laws of motion and law of gravity in the first
lecture – again these are expected to hold universally.
11
Lecture 3 HSI1000
These types of laws will be familiar to students of science. In the humanities, there are other types
of laws that exist which are statistical in nature. For example, the law of supply and demand is quite
fundamental to economics, or the law of reciprocity in psychology. There are many such laws, and
again they are rooted in how particular events are instances of regularities that are observed to occur.
So you can see what I mean by a law being “statistical in nature”, let’s consider the law of reciprocity
which says (in simple terms); when someone does something nice for you, you will have a deep-
rooted psychological urge to do something nice in return. In fact, you may even reciprocate with a
gesture far more generous than the original good deed. This type of law is statistical in nature,
meaning that you don’t expect it to be obeyed in every case, but there is a tendency for it to occur
more often than not. Such laws can also be used to explain human behavior, just like Boyle’s law can
be used to explain the behavior of gases.
3.3.4 Function
The final strategy scientists use to explain a phenomenon is function, that is, to explain something
based on the purpose it fulfils. Why am I wearing this black shirt? Because it covers my torso as
required by social norms. The black also gives a good contrast to the background in the lecture video
and doesn’t make me look so, err, large shall we say. I explained my wearing of a black shirt based
on the function it performs.
Why do we have a heart? Because it is the organ needed to pump blood around the body. Why does
a particular trait dominate in a certain species? Because that trait confers a definite evolutionary
advantage to members of the species with that trait. These are examples of function being used to
explain why something is.
It is also used to explain human behavior, like why someone might
be eating rice porridge (Figure 16) for lunch. Maybe the person is
not feeling well. Or one country went to war with another because
the first lacked a necessary resource the second had but refused to
trade. Functional explanations are often used, not just in the
physical, biological and medical sciences, but in the humanities and
social sciences as well.
12
Lecture 3 HSI1000
off. The huge number of collisions occurring with the walls each second produces a constant
outwards force on the walls— this is pressure. By reducing the volume of the container, you increase
the frequency of the collisions with the walls, thus increasing the outwards force on the walls, that
is, the pressure goes up.
This explanation for Boyle’s law is a call to the underlying process of this behavior of molecules and
atoms. It’s a very crude description of the kinetic theory of gases – a theory that explains the behavior
of all gases and their corresponding laws and can even be used to help understand the behavior of
liquids.
We can see a definite interdependence between the different ways of explaining phenomena. The
type of strategy adopted will depend on the questions we ask and the level of detail needed in the
explanation. In science the questions seem never ending, but each time we explain something we
achieve a deeper and fuller understanding of nature and the universe around us.
We’ll finish up this section on the types of scientific explanations, all of which are testable, and
consider in the next section how we might go about choosing competing explanations for the same
phenomenon.
13
Lecture 3 HSI1000
14
Lecture 3 HSI1000
For example, you come home late one evening, dump your Ez-link card on the table then crash on
your bed. The next morning you wake to find your Ez-link card isn’t on the table where you’re pretty
sure you left it. Where could it be? Is it on the floor? Maybe you didn’t leave it on the table, and put
it someplace else? Maybe another family member took it? Maybe someone crept into your flat while
everyone was sleeping and stole just your Ez-link card? Perhaps it simply disappeared?
Occam’s razor would say first check under the table – it’s the simplest and least puzzling explanation,
but if it’s not there, then you have a mystery, and we’re forced to consider the more complex
explanations. Depending on how certain you were about leaving it on the table, you could either just
ask your family members if they took it or start looking for it in plausible locations. Someone creeping
into your house to steal just your card seems pretty unlikely (why steal only the card?) and there’s
no evidence of a break in. The card disappearing into thin air is just not possible. Applying the BDTK
here helps us by using the last tool "Does the claimant use flawed reasoning?" Matter can neither be
created nor destroyed. Objects simply do not disappear.
I’ll finish up this section with an example of a conversation borrowed from Carl Sagan. It helps
illustrate the use of Occam’s razor and highlights the idea of an explanation being testable, which I
discussed in the first video of this lecture. I’ll be asking Prof Lee again, the next lecturer in the course,
to help me out.
16
Lecture 3 HSI1000
study the real system they are meant to represent. There are
many such examples, like architectural models of buildings can
help with visualization of internal relationships within the
structure or external relationships of the structure to the
environment. Figure 21 is a picture of a scale model of
Singapore’s Marina Bay area from 2006 exhibited at the URA
Gallery Museum. Figure 21. Physical model of the Marina Bay
area taken from Wikimedia: No machine-readable author
To assist in better understanding reality, the physical model provided. Calvin Teo assumed (based on copyright claims)., CC BY-SA 3.0
<http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/>, via Wikimedia
can be augmented with instruments to make measurements Commons
of what’s happening in and around the model. Such measurements can assist in optimization and the
design of equipment or processes. For example, the instruments may measure the external flow of
air or water around model buildings, vehicles, people, or hydraulic structures. The physical models
can be placed inside a wind tunnel (Figure 22), like the one on campus, or water tunnel (Figure 23)
or a wave tank (Figure 24) for the testing and making of measurements. Internal flows can also be
17
Lecture 3 HSI1000
studied using physical models with instruments. For example, in the design of ductwork systems,
pollution control equipment, food processing machines, and mixing vessels.
Figure 22. Wind tunnel from Wikimedia: Figure 23. Water tunnel from Figure 24. Wave tank from Wikimedia:
NASA Ames Research Center, Public domain, via Wikimedia Wikimedia: U.S. Navy, Public domain, via Wikimedia Jplourde umaine, CC BY-SA 4.0
Commons <https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/4.0>, via
Commons
Wikimedia Commons
18
Lecture 3 HSI1000
things on the map between FOS and the MRT, just the relevant
features needed for someone to find their way there. It conveys
the necessary concepts and ideas to navigate in the real world.
Diagrams and figures representing ideas and concepts in science
can be thought of as conceptual models. A diagram used to help
explain and even analyze Archimedes’ Principle (Figure 28) is an
Figure 28. Archimedes principle from Wikimedia:
example of a conceptual model. It doesn’t necessarily directly
MikeRun, CC BY-SA 4.0 <https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-
sa/4.0>, via Wikimedia Commons
represent what might be happening in a lab – some
extraneous details are left out. But it does contain all the
important information needed to understand what’s going on.
A diagram of a block sitting on an inclined plane, with all the forces indicated (Figure 29), is a
conceptual model of a real block (Figure 30) sitting on a slope. Again, there’s some things missing
from the diagram, and the objects and surfaces might not even be the same as the diagram. Yet, it
contains what’s needed to describe what is happening, even if the block is not moving.
19
Lecture 3 HSI1000
Conceptual models of reality might appear quite similar to real world objects, but they could also be
diagrams illustrating processes, even one as abstract as a circuit diagram. All conceptual models
depict ideas and concepts within science and can be used to explain phenomena and make
predictions in the real world, just as physical and mathematical/computer models can.
20
Lecture 3 HSI1000
but the correlation may not be perfect in the real-world, so our line, which is a math formula, only
represents a trend.
Many laws in science can be expressed using mathematical formula. These formulae can then be
used to derive even more expressions via the rules of mathematics. Taken together the equations
represent how nature behaves, from the motion of large objects, to the tiniest atom and even sub-
atomic particles, to how fluids flow around objects, or current passes through circuits, or heat is
exchanged between parts of machinery or the ocean and atmosphere, or how waves propagate
through space and time, or diffract around objects, and even how fast chemical reactions are
occurring in a flame or even the biochemistry taking place in organisms. There are just far too many
applications of mathematics to represent or list here.
Nevertheless, when a scientist wants to model something, say the climate, he or she will need to
consider all the necessary laws relevant to the phenomenon in question. This can involve a lot of data
and equations, including chemical reactions. Each of the equations can all be interrelated, making
these models inherently quite complex. When all these equations and data are taken together, they
then constitute a mathematical model. To solve such a complicated model the equations will often
need to be programmed up on a computer for them to “number crunch” the data with the equations
and produce meaningful output.
A write up on the difference between predictions and projects and “The Truth about Scientific
Models” was given in Scientific American recently. Here’s the link if you’re interested:
https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/the-truth-about-scientific-models/
By now you probably can appreciate that each of these model types, physical, conceptual and
math/computer models can be interrelated. For example, the physical model with instruments
attached could have the data read from the instruments and fed into a computer model. It would
then evaluate the performance of the object being modeled and predict how it could behave in the
real world.
A conceptual model could help to establish what equations should be used in a computer model
meant to mimic the real-world thing the conceptual model represented. You’ll get a better idea of
this in the second workshop.
21
Lecture 3 HSI1000
Of course, we should never lose sight of the fact that models, being cut-down and simplified
representations of reality, can actually leave too much of the real-world out and end up producing
the wrong results. However, because science is self-correcting, once such an error is discovered, the
ignored effect can then be included in the model to make an improved version.
22