Changing Conceptions of Psychological Life 1st Edition pdf docx
Changing Conceptions of Psychological Life 1st Edition pdf docx
Visit the link below to download the full version of this book:
https://medipdf.com/product/changing-conceptions-of-psychological-life-1st-editi
on/
REED, E. S., TURIEL, E., & BROWN, T. (Eds.) • Values and Knowledge
Edited By
Cynthia Lightfoot
Penn State University
Chris Lalonde
University of Victoria
Michael Chandler
University of British Columbia
Preface vii
v
vi CONTENTS
It’s in all the papers. Ninety-six years, fifty-some films, and one true love to
her credit, Katharine Hepburn died yesterday. She was, in the words of one
admirer, “an inestimable self;” someone who “reminded us again and again
that self is a gift not to be doubted or squandered or pawned for less that it’s
worth.”1
If the eulogy reveals anything about Hepburn, it speaks volumes about
our folk beliefs of having and valuing and being true to our selves, and the
consequence of it all for directing our lives. Selves, it would seem, should be
taken seriously, particularly by anyone who holds to the prospect that they
are beacons of knowledge and action.
This book stands as commentary on that sentiment. It is a product of the
30th Annual Meeting of the Jean Piaget Society, which convened in
Montréal, Canada, in June of 2000. The contributing authors constitute the
original cast invited to Montréal to speak on the theme of how individuals
come to construe psychological lives—their own and others. Their con-
cerns, more specifically are how our sense of ourselves—who we are and
how we think—emerges developmentally, culturally, and historically, and
the implications such constructions have for personal, social, and political
change. Together, the authors compose an international and interdisci-
plinary group of scholars already well regarded for their work on topics as
diverse as adolescence, language, aging, romance, and morality. Their par-
ticular accomplishment for this special project was to pin their expertise to
the cotter assumption that each of us understands ourselves as moral and
epistemic agents, as authors and narrators of our own lives, and as choosers
and construers of our own experience.
We have organized the book around four major themes that we will out-
line in a moment. There are, however, recurrent issues and sentiments
spanning the sections that create their own level of discourse about selves
vii
viii PREFACE
and minds, and how they have been and ought to be studied. Throughout
the book, for example, the reader is invited to reflect on the inadequacies of
traditionally narrow cognitive approaches to conceptions of psychological
life. By turns the authors take issue with views that settle myopically on that
particular version of self and mind first fashioned and celebrated during
the Enlightenment. Our authors argue that the shopworn account of men-
tal life as objective, reflective, stable, detached, and coherent turns up an in-
dividual so devoid of desire, motive, commitment, and feeling—so anemic
of personality—that it can hardly rise from the sofa, much less engage in
those forms of action that we commonly take as instrumental to the pursuit
of knowledge and collective life.
As their criticisms converge to undermine classical cognitive ap-
proaches, so too do their endorsed alternatives together present something
of a map for how to continue. The reader will find in these pages a call to
feed conceptions of mental life on the lush and shifting fields of attach-
ments and felt experience, epiphany and power, drama and genre, and the
possibility engendered by sheer coincidence. Explorations of a more con-
nected mind and a more convivial self are promised to bring to light possi-
ble solutions to the long-whiskered and doggedly difficult problems of
relating thought and action, unity and diversity, agency and duty.
The first section, Self as Known and as Experienced, includes work that is
principally concerned with elevating the position of our experience of
ourselves in constructing who we are. Agusto Blasi, for example, derides
more traditional approaches for casting mental life in strictly representa-
tional terms. Such approaches, he argues, result in a reductive, “hyphen-
ated self” that is no more than the sum of its constituent parts of
self-perceptions, self-images, self-concepts, and self-evaluations. There is
no place here for an active agent to manage and care for and lay claim to
the various perceptions, images, concepts, and evaluations to which it is
tagged; no place for the felt unity of agents and their own actions. He pro-
poses that the basic self, that is, the self that is foundational to construc-
tions of who we are, is experienced in the course of intentional action.
Intentional action, he suggests, defines a context of “being present to one-
self.” Such presence requires consciousness of our selves as agents; it con-
veys to us our own subject-hood.
Donald Polkinghorne pursues a similar course in his revisionist narrative
approach to personal identity. Although generally sympathetic to narrative
theory’s emphasis on how conceptions of self are affected by the language
and stories in which they are articulated, he argues, like Blasi, that any ac-
count that fails to address the role of identity as experienced is itself a story
only half-told. Polkinghorne and Blasi part ways, however, on the nature of
that experience and the details of its generative power. Drawing from the
theories of Ricoeur, Gadamer, and Merleau-Ponty, Polkinghorne maps out
PREFACE ix
am I?” But because we live in a storied world, the question is more appropri-
ately phrased in poetically nuanced terms: “in what story or stories am I tak-
ing part?” Although the personal pronoun figures into any answer—I am a
performing arts enthusiast; I am a servant of the Lord—Sarbin argues that
our conceptions of self, the meanings of who we are, ride ultimately on the
predicates our pronouns carry in their own wake.
Rom Harré’s chapter focuses likewise on the identity shaping power of
language, discourse and, particularly, personal pronouns. Following
Wittgenstein, he argues that selves are jointly constructed in virtue of don-
ning public masks appropriate to the local milieu. It is on this account that
pronoun systems are of special importance to personal identity: they serve
to locate self-singularities in space and time.
And, finally, a provocative chapter by Amélie Rorty who disavows as mis-
guided any notion of working out versions of persons as integrated, unified,
singular, or coherent. Attenuated across fields of dramatic action, contra-
diction, and revolution, selves, like calla lilies, are suitable to any occasion.
We are each a pocketful of “identity markers,” character-forming patterns
of cognitive and motivational proclivities produced as our situations de-
mand. That these identity markers are often dug out along with odd bits of
laundry lint, matchbooks, or last week’s grocery list just goes to the point of
our immapable futures, and our readiness to make fire.
All told, the reader will find in these pages programmatic efforts vari-
ously attuned to selves and minds as dynamic and structured, present and
represented, felt and known, nonlanguaged and storied, embodied and
theorized. There is paradox aplenty here. And for that we must be grateful.
—Cynthia Lightfoot
—Chris Lalonde
—Michael Chandler
ENDNOTE
1
Verlyn Klinkenborg, NYT; July 1, 2003.
Part I
SELF AS KNOWN
AND AS EXPERIENCED
Chapter 1
Augusto Blasi
University of Massachusetts Boston
The use of the term self, in its nonhyphenated form, has increased exponen-
tially in recent psychological writings. However, referent and meaning are
still imprecise and ambiguous. There seem to be two main referents. Some-
times “self” is used either as synonymous with oneself, the concrete person,
or as equivalent with personality, as defined by temperamental and behav-
ioral traits, or perhaps by salient psychological characteristics. The most
frequent referent of the term, by far, is the subject-as-known, or the product
of self-cognition. I argue here that both these uses of the term are somewhat
inappropriate; I then attempt to define a domain of psychological function-
ing, to which the nonhyphenated “self” should be properly and unambigu-
ously applied. It is not my intention to write about language and to
construct an argument about semantics. In a discipline where agreement is
rarely found, and only on the basis of empirical evidence, a discussion about
the proper use of words is not likely to convince many people. My main in-
tention is positive and substantive, namely, to point to, and clarify a set of
psychological processes, to which the label, self, clearly belongs, and from
which the self as object of cognition should be carefully distinguished. This
domain of functioning, although essential to the understanding of specifi-
cally human characteristics, has been, at least from a theoretical perspec-
3