many hands problem
many hands problem
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The Michigan Law Review Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to Michigan Law Review
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
MORAL RESPONSIBILITY IN THE
AGE OF BUREAUCRACY
David Luban, *
Alan Strudler, **
and David Wasserman***
* Professor of Law, University of Maryland; Research Scholar, Institute for Philosophy and
Public Policy. B.A. 1970, University of Chicago; M.A. 1973, M.Phil. 1973, Ph.D. 1974, Yale. -
Ed.
** Research Scholar, Institute for Philosophy and Public Policy. B.A. 1975, Johnston Col-
lege; Ph.D. (Philosophy) 1982, J.D. 1985, University of Arizona. - Ed.
*** Research Scholar, Institute for Philosophy and Public Policy. B.A. 1975, Yale; J.D.
1978, University of Michigan; M.A. (Psychology) 1984, University of North Carolina. - Ed.
We have presented versions of this paper at the University of Baltimore and The Australian
National University, and have benefited greatly from the helpful comments we received. We are
particularly grateful to John Braithwaite, Teresa Chandler, and Jorge Garcia.
1. FRANZ KAFKA, THE TRIAL 133-34 (E.M. Butler rev. definitive ed., Willa Muir & Edwin
Muir trans., Seeker and Warburg 1956) (1925).
2348
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2349
Kafka leaves us with the distinct impression that Joseph K.'s crime is
precisely his inability to discover what crime he has been accused of.
K. never has a formal trial, yet the novel is called The Trial: evi-
dently, K.'s fruitless effort to learn what he is accused of is his trial.
His execution is therefore just, because Joseph K. lives in a state of
culpable ignorance. In the remarkable parable that his confessor re-
lates to Joseph K. in the ninth chapter, a man comes to the court of
justice but is denied admittance. He waits patiently by the gate for
years, and at the moment of his death learns from the doorkeeper that
the gate will now be closed forever, for it was never intended for any-
one other than the dying petitioner.2 The law is real, and sovereign in
human affairs, but forever withheld from us. That is the extremity of
our condition.3
Kafka found the perfect literary image for his legal and theological
theme in The Trial, and that is the image of bureaucracy. In The
Trial, the emblem of the protagonist's inability to learn the law is his
confrontation with a bureaucracy that frustrates and evades his every
effort to get to the bottom of things, to obtain clarification. Assume a
hierarchical world, a great chain of being; then take away the pinnacle
of the hierarchy, leaving only the lower orders who cannot take ulti-
mate responsibility for anything they do. That is the theological situa-
tion that Kafka ponders, but it is also the secular situation of the
bureaucracy. The everyday experience of the bureaucratic runaround
- tedious, preposterous, yet with potentially fatal consequences
gives the word Kafkaesque its common meaning. The epigraph at the
beginning of this paper encapsulates the Kafkaesque world of bureau-
2. Id. at 238-47.
3. In the grisly story "In the Penal Colony," condemned prisoners are executed on a torture
device that slowly inscribes the law they have violated on their bodies with needles. As the
message takes shape over many hours of suffering, recognition and understanding gradually grow
in the prisoners, until finally they attain a kind of spiritual redemption that comes of knowing
why they are suffering and dying. The officer in charge of the apparatus fervently believes that
this form of punishment alone satisfies the requirements of justice. Faced with the imminent
abolition of this form of execution on humanitarian grounds, the despairing officer climbs into
the apparatus himself, programming it to carve "Be Just" on his body. But the machine disinte-
grates; instead of writing "Be Just," the needles merely punch the officer to pieces, and the dead
officer's face "was as it had been in life; no sign was visible of the promised redemption; what the
others had found in the machine the officer had not found." FRANZ KAFKA, In the Penal Col-
ony, in SELECTED SHORT STORIES OF FRANZ KAFKA 126 (Willa Muir & Edwin Muir trans.,
1952).
Like The Trial, the story may be read as a comment on natural law - law that is so much a
part of the human condition that it must be harrowed into our bodies when we transgress it.
This is, evidently, an outward emblem of the fact that the law already dwells in our nature
and, perhaps, that it dwells in our nature cruelly. In Kafka's parable, it is the officer, the one
remaining believer in this law, who alone is denied the redemption it promises - redemption
that is meant to come through ultimate knowledge of natural law engraved in one's own body.
The officer represents the predicament of the natural lawyer who understands that natural law
binds us but, for whatever reason, cannot discover what it asks of him.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2350 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
4. At this point, however, natural law theorists diverge. Philip Soper, for example, contends
that a good faith belief on the part of the rulers that they are legislating for the common good
suffices to establish a moral obligation on the part of the ruled to obey the law. PHILIP SOPER, A
THEORY OF LAW 79 (1984). John Finnis, by contrast, believes that positive law's inconsistency
with the common good undermines the moral obligation to obey, regardless of what the legislator
may believe. JOHN FINNIS, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS 351-60 (1980). Thus, the
notion of "the rulers' undertaking to legislate for the common good" may be understood subjec-
tively (Soper) or objectively (Finnis). Elsewhere, one of us has criticized Soper's argument.
David Luban, Conscientious Lawyers for Conscientious Lawbreakers, 52 U. PITT. L. REV. 793,
806-09 (1991).
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2351
responsible for acts that positive law did not forbid at the time they
were committed - so-called "crimes against peace" and "crimes
against humanity."5 Anticipating the defendants' protest that they
were merely following official orders that carried the force of positive
law, Article 8 of the Nuremberg Charter specifically provided that
"[t]he fact that the defendant acted pursuant to an order of his govern-
ment or of a superior shall not free him from responsibility."6
That Article 8 represents a flat-out rejection of what might be
called the positivist excuse for atrocious official acts - the excuse that
the acts were licensed by positive law - is intuitively clear. As Stan-
ley Paulson has shown, the defense at Nuremberg relied extensively
upon the positivist excuse, which the Tribunal had little difficulty re-
jecting.7 The natural law argument that unjust laws lose their obliga-
tory character provides a straightforward philosophical justification
for Article 8. Similarly, appeals to natural law clearly form the most
obvious justification for criminalizing "murder, extermination, en-
slavement, deportation, and other inhumane acts ... whether or not in
violation of domestic law of the country where perpetrated."8 Such
crimes against humanity are radically inconsistent with the common
good, and any domestic legal system that permits them must violate
natural law. In addition, Article 7 of the Charter eliminated the act-
of-state defense on the part of those in command positions,9 thereby
recognizing that those who legislate bear moral responsibilities just as
surely as do those who follow orders.
Indeed, the view that the Nazi era exposes the moral deficiency of
positivism compared with natural law is a commonplace. As early as
the mid-1940s, Gustav Radbruch, an eminent pre-War German posi-
tivist, repudiated positivism and embraced natural law, arguing in sev-
eral influential essays that positivism had disarmed German jurists in
the face of Nazism. 0 Thus, international revulsion at the official crim-
5. For an argument that the criminalization of crimes against peace and crimes against hu-
manity represented a legal novelty, see David Luban, The Legacies of Nuremberg, 54 Soc. RES.
779, 797-801 (1987).
6. 1 INTERNATIONAL MILITARY TRIBUNAL, TRIAL OF THE MAJOR WAR CRIMINALS
BEFORE THE INTERNATIONAL MILITARY TRIBUNAL 12 (1947).
7. Stanley L. Paulson, Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg, 4 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 132
(1975).
8. CHARTER OF THE INTERNATIONAL MILITARY TRIBUNAL art. 6(c) (defining crimes
against humanity).
9. See CHARTER OF THE INTERNATIONAL MILITARY TRIBUNAL art. 7.
10. See GUSTAV RADBRUCH, Five Minutes of Legal Philosophy, in PHILOSOPHY OF LAW
109, 109-10 (Joel Feinberg & Hyman Gross eds., Stanley L. Paulson trans., 3d ed. 1980) (1950)
(translating GUSTAV RADBRUCH, FunfMinuten Rechtsphilosophie, in RECHTSPHILOSOPHIE 335,
335-37); GUSTAV RADBRUCH, Gesetzliches Unrecht und Ubergesetzliches Recht [Legal Injustice
and Supralegal Justice], in RECHTSPHILOSOPHIE, supra, at 347. Radbruch's arguments proved
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2352 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
influential in English-language jurisprudence, largely through the prominent place they occupied
in the well-known Hart-Fuller debate. See H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law
and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593, 615-21 (1958); Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law
- A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630, 646-47 (1958). More recently, however,
Ingo Miiller has criticized Radbruch's view, arguing that the worst perversions of justice in the
Third Reich occurred because the Nazi judges were not good enough positivists - they were too
willing to pervert the law for political reasons. See INGO MULLER, HITLER'S JUSTICE (Deborah
L. Schneider trans., 1991). This critique, of course, does not affect the argument that Nuremberg
law represents a repudiation of positivism, nor does it render the positivist excuse acceptable.
11. For an argument that the Nuremberg Charter did not go far enough in this direction
because it safeguarded the principle of national sovereignty, the linchpin of positivism, see
Luban, supra note 5, at 780-90.
12. Regrettably, the acquittal of Oliver North suggests that the excuse lives on in American
criminal law.
13. Rhetorical references to the Nazis as gangsters, criminals, or the like often obscure this
important point. See Luban, supra note 5, at 817-20.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2353
cials of their former regimes, many of whom will surely enter the epis-
temological excuse. Czech novelist Milan Kundera poses the problem
directly in The Unbearable Lightness of Being:
Let us concede that a Czech public prosecutor in the early fifties who
called for the death of an innocent man was deceived by the Russian
secret police and the government of his own country. But now that we
all know the accusations to have been absurd and the executed to have
been innocent, how can that selfsame public prosecutor defend his purity
of heart by beating himself on the chest and proclaiming, My conscience
is clear! I didn't know!14
One might respond with an equally rhetorical question: how can
the prosecutor be blamed if he truly did not know? Kundera's rage
clearly stems from the ready availability of the epistemological excuse
within the secretive Communist bureaucracies, but the fact that an
excuse is a bit too handy does not in itself undercut its viability. Thus,
the problem of bureaucratic irresponsibility faces post-Communist so-
cieties much as it faced post-Nazi Germany.
Bureaucratic evasion of responsibility, however, is not a pathology
confined to police states. A recent article in The Washington Post de-
scribes the loss of six million dollars of the savings of Washington area
Hispanics when the unregulated Latin Investment Corporation failed.
When depositors blamed lax regulation, a D.C. politician responded
that no one in government was to blame. "Frankly, I think the re-
sponsibility belonged to several agencies, including federal agencies
.... Thus, effectively, the responsibility belonged to no one."15 The
bureaucratic evasion of responsibility is as American as your failing
neighborhood bank.
Nor is bureaucratic irresponsibility a pathology limited to govern-
ments. All of us live our lives in the sway of many nongovernmental
bureaucracies - HMOs, business corporations, large employers, and
the like - that function as "private governments" (and often as re-
markably autocratic ones).16 Particularly now, when the erstwhile so-
cialist nations of central and eastern Europe have committed
themselves to programs of privatization and capitalism, and their mas-
sive bureaucracies prepare to shift allegiance from the state to private
owners, the danger of bureaucratic evasion inherent in private govern-
ments as well as public should be clear. The problem of individual
14. MILAN KUNDERA, THE UNBEARABLE LIGHTNESS OF BEING 177 (Michael H. Heim
trans., 1984).
15. Charlene Drew Jarvis, D.C. Council Member, quoted in Carlos Sanchez, A Year Later,
Depositors Still Waiting, Hoping, WASH. POST, Dec. 1, 1991, at B3.
16. See Stuart Macaulay, Private Government, in LAW AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 445
(Leon Lipson & Stanton Wheeler eds., 1986).
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2354 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2355
Kundera recognizes, the problem in the world we live in is not that the
epistemological excuse fails, but that it may succeed all too well.
Thus, the moral relationship between those who rule and those who
are ruled dissolves, and natural law threatens to recede into the realm
of useless abstraction. If bureaucracy indeed installs the epistemologi-
cal excuse as a standing option in our moral lives, then bureaucratic
institutions make a mockery of natural law ideals.
In this article, we shall examine the sources of the epistemological
excuse and the moral resources available for restricting its application.
Our topic, then, is the often-noticed but poorly understood fragmenta-
tion of knowledge and responsibility in large organizations, including
government, business corporations, and professional groups. We wish
to investigate the compartmentalization, mutual buckpassing, and
deniability that too often leads organizations to commit wrongs for
which no individual in the organization seems genuinely responsible.
Bureaucratic organizations parcel out morally significant knowl-
edge among various individuals along the same lines as organizational
tasks. The division of labor is equally a division of knowledge. Super-
visors may not know of wrongful actions by subordinates implement-
ing management decisions, while subordinates may believe they have
been left no discretion and no alternatives. Put these conditions to-
gether and you have a recipe for organizational wrongdoing that will
never trouble the conscience of anyone within the organization. Indi-
viduals within the organization do not know, or perhaps do not want
to know, what their actions add up to.
Recent psychological and sociological research on wrongdoing in
organizations has examined the pressures individuals feel from their
superiors, their peers, and the norms of corporate culture to engage in
wrongful conduct. This research has yielded profound insight into the
subtle but powerful coercive forces at work in organizations. It has
not paid sufficient attention, however, to the cognitive aspects of obe-
dience and conformity, the structural features of large organizations
that prevent individuals from obtaining the knowledge they need to
make informed moral decisions and resist pressure to obey and con-
form. Individuals in organizations frequently lack awareness of the
role their acts play in the larger corporate undertaking; their igno-
rance complicates both the moral assessment of and the practical re-
sponse to the wrongs they help commit. Analyzing the problem of
fragmented knowledge (as we shall call it) is critical for an adequate
philosophical analysis of organizational wrongdoing and for an effec-
tive practical response to it.
We contend that traditional accounts of morality have failed to
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2356 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2357
C. Historical Perspective
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2358 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
recognized, and lamented, for the past 150 years. The erosion of indi-
vidual responsibility and the evils of bureaucracy have engaged con-
servative writers since the advent of the industrial revolution. Over a
century ago, Karl Marx likewise criticized what he called "the real
mindlessness of the state." "The bureaucracy is a circle from which
no one can escape," Marx contended. "The highest point entrusts the
understanding of particulars to the lower echelons, whereas these, on
the other hand, credit the highest with an understanding in regard to
the universal; and thus they deceive one another."23 In 1932, Rein-
hold Niebuhr wrote his classic treatise Moral Man and Immoral Soci-
ety, in which he argued that
[i]ndividual men may be moral .... They are endowed by nature with a
measure of sympathy and consideration for their kind, the breadth of
which may be extended by an astute social pedagogy .... But all these
achievements are more difficult, if not impossible, for human societies
and social groups. In every human group there is less reason to guide
and to check impulse, less capacity for self-transcendence, less ability to
comprehend the needs of others and therefore more unrestrained egoism
than the individuals, who compose the group, reveal in their personal
relationships.24
23. KARL MARX, CRITIQUE OF HEGEL'S "PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT" 46-47 (Joseph O'Malley
ed., Annette Jolin & Joseph O'Malley trans., 1970).
24. REINHOLD NIEBUHR, MORAL MAN AND IMMORAL SOCIETY xi-xii (rev. ed. 1960).
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2359
were out of their hands and that they were just filling out questionnaires
. .., though in reality each form was the equivalent of a death warrant
.... The personnel at the end of the line excused themselves on the basis
that they were under compulsion, had no power of decision, and were
merely performing a function. Thousands of people were involved, but
each considered himself nothing but a cog in the machine and reasoned
that it was the machine, not he, that was responsible.25
The horrors of Nazism are without parallel, but the bureaucratic pat-
tern of organization that fragments the knowledge required for moral
decisionmaking is common to large institutions throughout contempo-
rary society. Jackall describes the typical corporate structure in terms
not unlike those Marx used to characterize "the real mindlessness of
the state":
Power is concentrated at the top in the person of the chief executive
officer (CEO) and is simultaneously decentralized; that is, responsibility
for decisions and profits is pushed as far down the organizational line as
possible.
the latest and perhaps most formidable form of... dominion: bureau-
cracy or the rule of an intricate system of bureaus in which no men,
neither one nor the best, neither the few nor the many, can be held re-
sponsible, and which could be properly called rule by Nobody. (If, in
accord with traditional political thought, we identify tyranny as govern-
ment that is not held to give account of itself, rule by Nobody is clearly
the most tyrannical of all, since there is no one left who could even be
asked to answer for what is being done. It is ... impossible to localize
responsibility and to identify the enemy ... .)27
Such rumors of the demise of responsibility may be exaggerated; yet
Arendt's description has the ring of familiarity. A graphic contempo-
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2360 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
28. In re A.H. Robins Co. "Dalkon Shield" IUD Prods. Liab. Litig., 575 F. Supp. 718, 724
(D. Kan. 1983).
29. John Braithwaite, Passing the Buck for Corporate Crime, AUSTL. SOCY., Apr. 1991, at 3,
3.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2361
31. More recently, Herbert Kelman and Lee Hamilton have offered a detailed psychological
analysis of the dynamics of obedience and the social structures that contribute to it. See HER-
BERT C. KELMAN & V. LEE HAMILTON, CRIMES OF OBEDIENCE: TOWARD A SOCIAL PSY-
CHOLOGY OF AUTHORITY AND RESPONSIBILITY (1989).
32. MILGRAM, supra note 30, at 61.
33. Id. at 35.
34. KELMAN & HAMILTON, supra note 31, at 165.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2362 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
ety of other tasks without having to consider the final product of their
efforts.35
Seeing the connection between one's action and its destructive conse-
quences clearly has a strong emotional component, but it also has crit-
ical cognitive significance; it removes any doubts about the effect of the
individual's obedience.
Another form of ignorance that appears to have played a signifi-
cant role in Milgram's experiments was the absence of a clear-cut mo-
ment of decision. Few subjects would have hesitated to give a mild,
tingling shock; most probably would have refused to give an initial
shock of maximum voltage. The gradual escalation of voltage was in-
sidious because it deprived subjects of an obvious stopping point, en-
couraging them to defer resistance until they saw themselves as
committed, or as compromised. This kind of slippery slope may char-
acterize many of the decisions made in contemporary organizations.
Another variant of the Milgram experiments, however, provides
some encouragement that resistance and reform may be possible in
organizational settings. In this study, the subject was assigned to a
team administering the shocks, while the other team members were
really confederates of the experimenter. Milgram discovered that
compliance was extraordinarily sensitive to peer pressure. When the
other team members refused to proceed with the experiment, only ten
percent of the subjects remained obedient to the experimenter and
"went all the way." Conversely, when a teammate rather than the
subject took charge of physically administering the shock, 92.5% of
the subjects went along with the experiment up to the maximum
shock.36 In Niebuhr's terms, we may think of moral man made less
moral by an immoral society, but more moral by a society of his
betters.
While there are obviously other factors at work, we believe that in
this experiment the compliance or resistance of others served an im-
portant cognitive function. As Kelman and Hamilton argue, "[t]he
most important effect of the confederates' disobedience ... was proba-
bly in providing the cognitive and motivational conditions that al-
lowed the participant to redefine the situation in which he found
himself."37
The Milgram studies, then, suggest the role of imperfect and frag-
mented knowledge in organizational misconduct. The less individuals
appreciate the consequences of their acts, the need to decide, and the
35. Id.
36. MILGRAM, supra note 30, at 119.
37. KELMAN & HAMILTON, supra note 31, at 160.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2363
Most moral theories take as their central cases the moral choices
confronting individuals deliberating alone and in full knowledge of the
morally relevant circumstances - including, indeed, that the choice
they face is morally charged. Standard moral theories may be viewed,
in effect, as structures of three concentric circles. At the center lie the
core precepts, which presuppose full knowledge on the part of agents.
Limiting these precepts are principles of mitigation, including mitiga-
tion when full knowledge is absent. Qualifying these, in turn, is an
account of culpable ignorance. The phenomenon of culpable igno-
rance lies at the periphery of concern in such a moral theory, and is
typically restricted to a small range of exceptional cases.
Reflection on organizational settings suggests that knowledge and
ignorance must play a more central role in moral theory. We believe
that the specter of fragmented knowledge, divided responsibility, am-
biguous orders, and unknown consequences is inadequately addressed
in the moral discourse of Western societies. Virtually every approach
to normative ethics, from the Ten Commandments to the latest wrin-
kles in philosophy journals, focuses primary attention on moral
problems in which four knowledge conditions are satisfied - knowl-
edge conditions that are frequently absent in individual decisionmak-
ing and almost never found in organizational settings.
First, the decisionmaker recognizes that he or she has come to a
fork in the road: The decisionmaker knows that a decision must be
made. Do I or don't I cheat on the examination? Do I or don't I
protest when I hear an acquaintance tell an anti-Semitic joke? Situa-
tions such as these are readily identifiable as moral decisions. Typi-
cally, when we face one of these questions, we know that we face it.
Second, the decisionmaker recognizes that he or she must make the
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2364 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2365
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2366 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
Some might argue that "deeds without doers" are a tragic fact of
modern life. We really do live under the "rule by Nobody" discussed
by Hannah Arendt, so assigning responsibility to some individual -
whether a natural or organizational person - is simply an anachro-
nism. This we call the skeptical approach: "skeptical," because it de-
nies that the problem of fragmented knowledge has a solution.
Various postmoder philosophers and psychologists have suggested
that the very idea of individual responsibility rests on a discredited
picture of autonomous subjects or selves making rational choices.
Thus, Kenneth Gergen asserts in The Saturated Self: "To be sure,
individuals break the law, but from the postmodern perspective, such
actions should be attributed not to the individual alone but to the ar-
ray of relationships in which he or she is a part."38 Unlike a corpora-
tion or government, an "array of relationships" does not look even
superficially like an entity we could meaningfully praise or blame. We
are left where we began, with deeds that lack doers.
Under this skeptical view, we can no more condemn organizational
wrongdoing on moral grounds than we can cancer or AIDS. Suppose
that an epidemic of an unknown disease rendered the entire human
race psychotic and homicidal. A great deal of death would result, but
no one could truly be held accountable. The skeptical, postmodern
view analogizes bureaucratic organization to this imaginary epidemic.
The analogy suggests two problems with the skeptical view. First,
the argument overstates the difficulty of imputing responsibility to in-
dividuals or the organizations to which they belong or help to create.
Individuals in an organization may be ignorant, confused, anxious, or
intimidated, but they are not in the grip of an irresistible malady. Bu-
reaucratic organization is not a renegade virus: it results from con-
scious human decisions, and it possesses some of the features of a
conscious entity that make it susceptible to praise and blame.
Second, even if the analogy were descriptively correct, the skeptic's
prescription of passivity or acquiescence would hardly follow. The
theoretical difficulty of ascribing responsibility for egregious miscon-
duct to individuals or organizations might instead provide a compel-
ling reason for overhauling the basic structure of organizations in
order to restore accountability. Our working hypothesis amounts to
what might be dubbed a law of conservation of responsibility: moral
responsibility for organizational actions cannot and should not be con-
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2367
jured out of existence. It must lie with the organization itself, with the
individuals in the organization, or with the institutions that permit
responsibility to be endlessly circulated.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2368 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
43. Peter A. French, The Corporation as a Moral Person, 16 AM. PHIL. Q. 207, 213-14
(1979).
44. THOMAS DONALDSON, CORPORATIONS AND MORALITY 20-23 (1982); see also Thomas
Donaldson, Personalizing Corporate Ontology: The French Way, in SHAME, RESPONSIBILITY,
AND THE CORPORATION 101, 101-12 (Hugh Curtler ed., 1986). For a cogently argued interpre-
tation of choice and deliberation that would place animals and corporations outside the realm of
entities that can choose, see ALAN DONAGAN, CHOICE: THE ESSENTIAL ELEMENT IN HUMAN
ACTION (1987). For a view interestingly similar to Donagan's, see Manuel G. Velasquez, Why
Corporations Are Not Morally Responsible for Anything They Do, 2 Bus. & PROF. ETHICS J.,
Spring 1983, at 7. Velasquez argues that, in order to be a person, one must have the unity of
consciousness that would allow one to initiate an action, and that corporations lack this charac-
teristic. Id. at 8-9; see also WOLGAST, supra note 40, at 79-95.
45. See FRENCH, supra note 41, at 166.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2369
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2370 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
46. While we call this implication absurd, there is no reason to think that French would
agree.
47. For an illuminating analysis of these issues, see Joel Feinberg, Collective Responsibility,
65 J. PHIL. 674 (1968).
48. A sophisticated version of this view is developed in MAY, supra note 40.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2371
49. MEIR DAN-COHEN, RIGHTS, PERSONS, AND ORGANIZATIONS: A LEGAL THEORY FOR
BUREAUCRATIC SOCIETY 46-51 (1986); John Ladd, Morality and the Ideal of Rationality in For-
mal Organizations, 54 THE MONIST 488 (1970). Ladd, however, denies that corporations can be
morally responsible. Id. at 498-500.
50. See Virginia Held, Corporations, Persons, and Responsibility, in SHAME, RESPONSIBILITY,
AND THE CORPORATION, supra note 44, at 161-81.
51. See FRENCH, supra note 41, at 145-63; Paul B. Thompson, Why Do We Need a Theory of
Corporate Responsibility?, in SHAME, RESPONSIBILITY, AND THE CORPORATION, supra note 44,
at 115-35.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2372 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
Zealand jet. French52 and Paul Thompson53 argue that while perhaps
no single individual was responsible for this crash, the airline corpora-
tion was responsible; indeed, these commentators suggest that the cor-
poration's responsibility may arise from facts that, in our terms,
involve fragmented knowledge.
The facts are as follows.54 Air New Zealand flew large jets over
Antarctica as part of a sightseeing package. The jets would fly at low
altitude so that the passengers could see the terrain. Apparently, Air
New Zealand used strange procedures to disseminate information
about the flight. These procedures fragmented knowledge about the
details of the flight plan and the obstacles to flight. Air New Zealand's
flight plans were programmed into on-board computers from a central
ground computer. There was no practice of including flight crews in
discussions of changes in the flight plan; hence, pilots were not in-
formed of a flight plan change before the flight occurred. Yet these
changes put the flight on a collision course with a mountain. The col-
lision killed everyone on the jet.
Since they believe that Air New Zealand employees acted consci-
entiously, French and Thompson maintain that the responsibility for
the crash should not be attributed to any individual employee or man-
ager. Instead, they argue, the corporate policy itself was at fault for
the crash. These authors thus approve of a government report which
concluded that the cause of the air disaster had an "organizational
nexus," and that it was wrong to attribute moral responsibility to any
individual associated with Air New Zealand.55
It is difficult to believe that no individual associated with Air New
Zealand did anything wrong. If the accident occurred because of bad
corporate policy, then we must wonder whether the person or persons
responsible for the policy should also be blamed for the accident. One
wonders whether those in charge of designing the communication pro-
cedures properly discharged their duties, and if they did not, whether
doing so would have prevented the accident. In many ways, to sup-
pose that the accident might have occurred despite the fact that all
involved properly discharged their duties seems a piece of science
fiction.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2373
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2374 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2375
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2376 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
56. See generally WAYNE R. LAFAVE & AUSTIN W. SCOTT, JR., CRIMINAL LAW ? 6.4, at
530 (2d ed. 1986).
57. MODEL PENAL CODE ? 5.03 comment on criminal conspiracy (Tent. Draft No. 10,
1960).
58. Note, The Conspiracy Dilemma: Prosecution of Group Crime, 62 HARV. L. REV. 276,
283-84 (1948) (footnotes omitted).
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2377
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2378 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2379
Greeks recognized the excuse, "I didn't realize what I was doing!"
When Agamemnon apologizes to Achilles in book 9 of the Iliad, he
attempts to mollify Achilles by explaining that a blindness had come
over him when he seized Briseis.61 It is hard to imagine any culture
for which the agent's intention is simply irrelevant to the moral classi-
fication of acts; as Holmes observed, even a dog knows the difference
between being tripped over and being kicked.
A.W.H. Adkins has argued that it was principally in the context of
wrongful acts involving the religious notion of pollution that the
Greeks regarded the agent's intentions as irrelevant.62 The notion of
pollution, however, seems to have no place in a world that does not
believe in demons, Furies, or vengeful ghosts howling for blood; the
Greek conception of strict moral liability, so closely tied to cultic and
chthonic religions, appears to hold little promise for us. Reinforcing
this conclusion is the fact that the analogous notion of strict liability
for criminal offenses is widely regarded as a jurisprudential aberration
with no place in a civilized legal system.
Yet the argument cannot be quite so quick or straightforward. For
one thing, the concept of pollution has by no means vanished from
contemporary, secular moral discourse, as the postwar debate over the
dimensions of German "metaphysical guilt" makes clear.63 Anthony
Appiah has noted that many of those advocating Western divestment
of South African holdings until the end of apartheid base their argu-
ments explicitly on the idea that, regardless of the practical efficacy of
divestment, possessing South African holdings amounts to a form of
pollution.64 Moreover, in recent years moral philosophers have paid
increasing attention to the phenomenon of moral luck,65 the possibility
that matters beyond our control may affect our moral blameworthi-
ness. Philosophers who believe in moral luck must be prepared to
weaken the requirement of evil intent in attributions of moral blame.
Finally, as George Fletcher points out, the concept of pollution has
61. HOMER, THE ILIAD bk. IX, lines 136-45 (Robert Fugles trans., 1990).
62. ARTHUR W.H. ADKINS, MERIT AND RESPONSIBILITY: A STUDY IN GREEK VALUES
92-104 (1960). Some acts, such as murder, rendered the perpetrator loathsome in the eyes of the
gods. One thus polluted could not perform prayers and sacrifices without first undergoing expia-
tion and ritual purification.
63. See KARL JASPERS, THE QUESTION OF GERMAN GUILT (E.B. Ashton trans., 1947).
64. Anthony Appiah, Racism and Moral Pollution, 18 PHIL. F. 185 (1987), reprinted in COL-
LECTIVE RESPONSIBILITY: FIVE DECADES OF DEBATE IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ETHICS
219 (Larry May & Stacey Hoffman eds., 1991).
65. See, e.g., THOMAS NAGEL, Moral Luck, in MORTAL QUESTIONS 24 (1979); MARTHA C.
NUSSBAUM, THE FRAGILITY OF GOODNESS: LUCK AND ETHICS IN GREEK TRAGEDY AND
PHILOSOPHY (1986); BERNARD WILLIAMS, MORAL LUCK (1981).
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2380 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2381
who affixed these labels to the boxes, the trucker who delivered them,
the stevedore who loaded them onto a ship, the UPS driver who deliv-
ered them to physicians' offices, and the physician's receptionist all
played a causal role in the wrongful distribution of the product. Yet it
seems outrageous to insist that their causal role in wrongdoing morally
polluted all these individuals.
This suggests that if the concept of pollution is to be used at all, it
demands fine-grained distinctions of degree. One might distinguish,
for example, between investors (and employees' relatives) who are pol-
luted because they unknowingly benefited from organizational wrong-
doing, employees who are polluted merely by virtue of working for an
organization involved in wrongdoing, employees who are polluted be-
cause they played an unintentional causal role in the wrongdoing, em-
ployees who are polluted because they knew of the wrongful act and
did nothing (though they did not participate in it), and employees who
are polluted because they knowingly or intentionally participated in
the wrongful act. Ordinarily, we would regard the last category as a
worse form of pollution than its predecessors; the list proceeds in
roughly ascending order of pollution.
If that is the strategy, however, the concept of pollution does not
solve the problem of fragmented knowledge - it merely restates that
problem. True, the concept of pollution provides a resource by which
we can in some sense condemn nonintentional involvements in wrong-
doing. But under conditions of bureaucratic fragmentation of knowl-
edge, the worst form of moral pollution - pollution by intentional
wrongdoing - seems to disappear, so that bureaucracy seems able to
conjure it out of existence. Thus, even when the concept of pollution
fortifies our moral repertoire, bureaucratic fragmentation of knowl-
edge blocks the severest and most characteristic form of moral criti-
cism. That is the problem of fragmented knowledge.
To summarize, we may either resolve the problem of fragmented
knowledge by employing an undifferentiated notion of moral pollution
that is hopelessly overbroad or distinguish gradations of pollutions, in
which case the problem of fragmented knowledge has merely been re-
stated rather than resolved.
Let us return to Kundera's example. The most striking fact about
the Czech Communists he discusses is that they were not simply igno-
rant of what they were doing in the way Oedipus was ignorant when
he married Jocasta. They were "enthusiasts convinced they had dis-
covered the only road to paradise. They defended that road so val-
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2382 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
iantly that they were forced to execute many people."68 They had
embarked on a course of political action that involved recognizable
moral risks. They knowingly collaborated with a powerful foreign
power in order to bring their own country under its dominion, bank-
ing on the Soviets' claim to represent the party of humanity. If they
did not know what they were doing, they should have found out.
Thus, to analyze Kundera's problem correctly, we should not hold
the Communists strictly morally liable, like Oedipus. Rather, we must
understand that they took voluntary part in an organizational enter-
prise engaged in risky business, giving them special and stringent obli-
gations to comprehend the import of their actions. Tomas is right to
find Did they know or did they not? a "second-rate" question69 - not
because, as with Oedipus, knowledge is irrelevant, but because the
right question is Should they have known? Accordingly, we propose to
give the concept of culpable ignorance a more central role in assigning
responsibility for organizational wrongdoing.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2383
that he did not know about the SS's murderous activities, we may wish
to insist that his ignorance is blameworthy. He should have known
what he was joining.
The drunk driving analogy suggests that we can hold people re-
sponsible for getting into the very predicament that at first glance
seems to relieve them of responsibility. If we focus on the act of drink-
ing, this suggests that an employee is responsible for the predicament
he gets into by joining an organization that fragments relevant knowl-
edge. Except in the case of outlaw groups like the SS, however, we do
not want to treat the act of joining an organization, like the act of
heavy drinking, as suspect or presumptively wrong.
We would do better to focus on the driving aspect of the drunk
driving analogy. Driving is a valuable activity, and our licensing pro-
cedures are designed to make it widely available. Because of the lethal
potential of the automobile, however, the privilege of driving hinges on
an exercise of alertness, caution, and self-restraint that we do not re-
quire of pedestrians or passengers. We allow pedestrians and passen-
gers to impair their reflexes and judgment with alcohol, but we treat it
as a legal and moral offense for a driver or prospective driver to do so.
Analogously, because of the great potential for harm arising from
the division of labor and fragmentation of knowledge in a corporate or
bureaucratic organization, employees may acquire duties far more de-
manding than doing no evil. They must look and listen for evil and
attempt to thwart it if they discover it. These duties, however, are not
as limited and well-defined as those imposed on the driver. We expect
prospective drivers to "just say no," but we cannot expect organiza-
tional employees to know everything about the operation in which
they are involved. While drinking is a gratuitous impediment to driv-
ing, fragmented knowledge inheres in the structure of the organization
itself. We are left with a question that does not arise in the context of
drunk driving: What and how much precaution do we require of the
individual employee?
We cannot answer this question definitively, but we can begin by
suggesting several obligations that arise from the specific risk of orga-
nizational enterprise: the risk that an individual will do or contribute
to great harm without knowing it.
1. Obligations of investigation. The first, most obvious, possibility
is to hold individuals in organizational settings morally responsible for
discerning the nature of their own projects and for discovering what
other employees are doing with their work products. The idea is obvi-
ous because it remedies the absence of knowledge in the most straight-
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2384 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
71. MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT Rule 5.1 (1983); see also John Braithwaite,
Enforced Self-Regulation: A New Strategy for Corporate Crime Control, 80 MICH. L. REV. 1466
(1982).
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2385
these obligations? There are some things we could not have learned,
communicated, or prevented even by the most vigilant inquiry, and if
should have does not imply could have, we are back to strict liability.
Second, how much vigilance is enough? The standard for liability can
be onerous even if it is not strict.
As we have described them, the moral obligations of the individual
employee seem to fall somewhere between perfect duties like not kill-
ing, with fairly precise boundaries, and imperfect duties like charity or
self-improvement, that require only some indeterminate effort. If we
attempt to make these duties perfect, through more precise formula-
tion, we risk defining them too narrowly; if we attempt to make them
imperfect, by demanding a "reasonable" effort, we risk making them
too vague.
Similar questions arise in settings where the law recognizes an af-
firmative duty to prevent harm: where the agent has a special duty to
care for the victim, has contributed to the victim's peril, has initiated
rescue, or has a responsibility to control the threatened harm. In these
settings, we hold the agent culpable for not trying to prevent harm,
but not strictly liable for its occurrence. This leaves the question of
how much of an attempt to prevent harm the agent must make. Legal
norms are hard to discover, because few courts actually recognize a
duty to aid, and in the cases where they do, the defendant has usually
failed to make even a token effort to render assistance.72
This may be more problematic when assigning criminal than moral
responsibility, since the notice requirement of criminal law compels us
to draw a clear line between required and merely permitted assist-
ance.73 One might think that moral appraisal could tolerate more
vagueness. Why should a conscientious agent need a sharp line be-
tween required and supererogatory precautions rather than an indefi-
nite duty to be as cautious and vigilant as possible? If we treat the
fulfillment of these duties as a matter of degree, however, we raise the
problem of deciding how the degree of fulfillment affects the individ-
ual's responsibility for organizational wrongs that greater effort might
have averted.
This raises the second question: What is an individual responsible
for in failing to fulfill these preemptive duties, as we shall call the obli-
gations of investigation, communication, protection, and precaution?
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2386 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
Should we blame her only for the breach of the preemptive duty, or
should we blame her for the resulting offense as if she had known all
the relevant facts (and thus hold her immune from censure if no harm
results)? Is the employee responsible just for failing to investigate (at
the time she fails to do so), or does she lose her excuse of ignorance
with respect to any facts the investigation would have yielded?
Neither approach seems fully satisfactory. In limiting responsibil-
ity to the breach of preemptive duties, we impose the same blame or
punishment regardless of what wrongs result; in withholding the ex-
cuse of ignorance for the offense, we treat a negligent employee as if
she were responsible for intentional wrongdoing. And if we assign re-
sponsibility only when a wrong is actually done, we fail to censure
those lucky enough to ignore their special obligations without adverse
effect.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2387
74. Paul H. Robinson, Causing the Conditions of One's Own Defense: A Study in the Limits
of Theory in Criminal Law Doctrine, 71 VA. L. REV. 1 (1985).
75. Similarly, if a person negligently provoked another to use deadly force, he would not lose
his right to kill in self-defense. If he exercised that right, however, he would be guilty of negli-
gent homicide for creating the need for self-defense. If he provoked another in order to give
himself a legal justification for killing that person, he would be guilty of intentional homicide.
To bear any responsibility for the ultimate offense, the agent must be at fault for creating the
specific excusing or justifying condition he relies on. If he negligently provoked someone without
reason to expect that she would resort to deadly force, he would not be guilty of homicide in
creating the need for self-defense. He would be responsible at most for negligent provocation and
the use of nondeadly defensive force.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2388 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
her duty but whether, by failing to perform it, she intentionally, reck-
lessly, or negligently facilitated the wrongdoing.
Thus, if an employee should have known that by investigating a
new project before it commenced, she could ascertain whether it in-
volved exporting toxic substances, and there was some reason to sus-
pect that it might, she would be responsible for negligently exporting
those substances, even if, by the time she exported them, the most
diligent inquiry would not have revealed their toxic character. Had
she actually known that an investigation could have revealed that in-
formation, but failed to investigate, she would be responsible for reck-
lessly exporting toxic substances, even if, by the time she exported
them, she was no longer able to ascertain their toxic character.
In some cases, this approach may lead us to hold employees who
act in ignorance responsible for intentional wrongdoing. If the em-
ployee deliberately insulated herself from knowledge about the ex-
ports, intending to export toxic substances without being told that
specific exports were toxic, she would be responsible for their inten-
tional export despite her ignorance at the time she exported them. But
if she deliberately insulated herself from such knowledge only because
she hated confrontations, she would be responsible for no more than
reckless export, since she did not know the character of the substances
or intend or hope that they might be toxic. This approach, then,
avoids the harshness of denying an employee an excuse for organiza-
tional wrongdoing if she has any fault for creating the excuse. It treats
her as responsible for wrongdoing only to the extent that she is at fault
for excusing or justifying its commission.
Applying this approach to organizational wrongdoing, however,
involves complexities. In the examples Robinson discusses, a person
gives himself an excuse of ignorance by an action that impairs his abil-
ity to obtain information critical to the safe performance of his task: a
driver drinks himself insensible, a police officer leaves his glasses home
when he goes on duty. In such cases, the risks of acting in the im-
paired condition seem obvious; to regard the driver or police officer as
reckless in disregarding those risks makes sense. But the risks of pro-
ceeding in ignorance may not be so obvious in an organizational set-
ting. Those risks depend on what the organization does, what it can
or might do wrong, and how the employee's own action can or might
contribute to those wrongs. Acquiring this background knowledge
may itself require extensive inquiry, and the question then becomes
what should trigger such an inquiry. The strength of the employee's
preemptive duties will depend on the risks they serve to preempt, but
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2389
the employee may not be able to appreciate those risks without having
already fulfilled those duties.
When we consider this problem less abstractly, we do not face a
regress or a bootstrap. We merely face the need to condition the du-
ties we impose on what the (prospective) employee knows or should
know at the outset about the organization, its work, and her role in it.
For example, an employee's duty of investigation and precaution will
be much greater if she has heard rumors that the import-export busi-
ness to which she has applied is a CIA front, or if she knows that
similar businesses in that part of the world have often been used as
CIA fronts. Because so much depends on what the employee knew or
should have known, suspected or should have suspected, at various
times, we must be very cautious in assigning individual responsibility
for organizational wrongdoing. Frankly, we will often lack the infor-
mation necessary to do so. But such epistemic limits to faultfinding
are hardly unique to the organizational setting.
The devices we have suggested for extending individual responsi-
bility may be too demanding because they require a debilitating level
of caution, wariness, and investigation in routine organization work.
Alternatively, they may fail to justify the ascription of responsibility to
individuals in many common organizational settings. But until the at-
tempt has been made to broaden and adapt the notion of individual
responsibility, news of its death will be premature.
CONCLUSION
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2390 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
lines we have suggested, but also that individual executives within the
organizations are morally blameworthy for failing to implement such
policies and that individual employees and executives are morally
blameworthy for violating preemptive obligations even in the absence
of policies implementing them.
The latter point is particularly significant, because it implicates the
moral culture of organizations as well as their formal policies. One
could imagine an organization enacting Exxon-style regulations while
preserving a moral culture that discouraged the whistleblowing that
the regulations require; in that case, employees would fear to go over
their supervisors' heads, and the regulations would function primarily
to insure that lower- or middle-level employees took the fall when
things went wrong.77 To insist as we do that the preemptive obliga-
tions form part of our moral responsibilities is to insist on the spirit as
well as the letter of preemptive regulations.
Thus, our proposal amounts to a reconfiguration of the dimensions
of individual moral responsibility as well as a reconfiguration of the
structure and culture of bureaucratic organizations. Earlier, we ar-
gued that familiar moral theories cannot handle the problem of frag-
mented knowledge. Not only do their first-order precepts presuppose
the four knowledge conditions, but they typically marginalize the phe-
nomenon of culpable ignorance. We conclude with some brief reflec-
tions on how our proposal differs from these familiar moral theories.
The account we propose retains the concentric-circles structure of
familiar moral theories: a core of first-order precepts; a surrounding
layer of mitigations and excuses; and an outer layer of conditions de-
feating those mitigations and excuses. In effect, the modification we
propose relocates the notion of culpable ignorance from the category
of conditions defeating mitigations and excuses to the first-order
precepts. That is, we place preemptive obligations among the basic
moral duties of the individual in bureaucratic settings. In one sense,
then, our proposal may be regarded as a minor modification, or
friendly amendment, to familiar accounts of morality.
In another sense, however, the change is fundamental, for it in-
volves a different model of the moral life. Traditional moral theories
presuppose an episodic or picaresque model: the moral life consists of
77. John Braithwaite has reported that American pharmaceutical company executives re-
peatedly told him in interviews that someone's job was "vice-president responsible for going to
jail": his duty was to take the fall for his superiors, and after several years in this position he
would be rewarded by moving to a well-compensated "safe" job. See Braithwaite, supra note 29,
at 3. In such an institutional culture it is hardly farfetched to assume that Exxon-style regula-
tions might be instituted for purposes of liability screening rather than avoiding fragmented
knowledge.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
August 1992] Moral Responsibility 2391
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2392 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 90:2348
moral trials may be less intense but more protracted; if we are heroes,
we will be heroes by virtue of the quantity rather than the quality of
our efforts. The institutionalization of everyday life may demand
fewer of the virtues of a soldier or saint and more of the virtues of a
detective, a scientist, or a trial lawyer aiming to reconstruct shards of
evidence into a coherent theory.
That takes us back to Kafka. In its form, The Trial seems like a
picaresque novel in which Joseph K. progresses from one episodic en-
counter to the next. At each stage, however, the moral test in the
encounter is the same: can Joseph K. fend off distraction and obfusca-
tion to learn what he is accused of and what he can do about it? His
trial, on our account, consists precisely of this repeated test, and his
crime consists of his failure to meet the challenge. His obligation is to
find his way through a nightmare of fragmented knowledge: to reas-
semble the misshapen pieces of his experience into a picture that tells
him at last where he stands in the order of guilt and innocence. Under
our view of morality, Joseph K.'s predicament is ours. His failure is
our failure as well.
This content downloaded from 104.28.88.131 on Wed, 09 Apr 2025 10:03:37 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms