(eBook PDF) Weather: A Concise Introduction download
(eBook PDF) Weather: A Concise Introduction download
download
https://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-weather-a-concise-
introduction/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-a-concise-introduction-
to-ethics/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/original-pdf-canadian-democracy-a-
concise-introduction/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-psychology-a-concise-
introduction-5th-edition/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-canadian-democracy-a-
concise-introduction-2nd-edition/
(eBook PDF) A Concise Introduction to Logic 13th
Edition
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-a-concise-introduction-
to-logic-13th-edition/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-a-concise-introduction-
to-linguistics-5th-edition/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-weather-and-climate-an-
introduction-2nd-edition/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-a-concise-introduction-
to-world-religion-3rd-edition/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-a-concise-introduction-
to-world-religions-4th-edition/
Summary
2.4 Radar
2.5 Satellites
2.5.1 Visible Satellite Images
2.5.2 Infrared Satellite Images
2.5.3 Water Vapor Images
2.5.4 Geostationary Satellites
2.5.5 Polar-Orbiting Satellites
Summary
3.1 Aspect
3.2 Composition
8
3.3 Origin and Evolution
4.1 Conduction
4.2 Convection
4.3 Radiation
4.3.1 The Nature of Electromagnetic Radiation
4.3.2 Temperature and Radiation
9
4.5.4 The Influence of Clouds
4.5.5 Land–Ocean Contrasts
Summary
CHAPTER 5 Water
5.2 Saturation
5.3 Humidity
10
6.3 Dry Adiabatic Lapse Rate
6.9 Convection
6.9.1 Stable Air
6.9.2 Unstable Air and Thermals
6.9.3 Stable vs. Unstable
6.9.4 Fair-Weather Cumulus Clouds
6.9.5 Conditional Instability and Cumulonimbus
Summary
CHAPTER 7 Precipitation
11
CHAPTER 8 Wind
8.8 Friction
8.9 Topography
8.9.1 Mountain Breeze and Valley Breeze
8.9.2 Katabatic Winds
Summary
12
9.4 Some Large-Scale Circulations
9.4.1 West Coast vs. East Coast
9.4.2 Antarctica
9.4.3 The Sahel
9.4.4 The Indian Monsoon
9.4.5 El Niño
Summary
10.2 Fronts
10.2.1 Stationary Fronts
10.2.2 Cold Fronts
10.2.3 Warm Fronts
10.2.4 Occluded Fronts
10.2.5 Large-Scale Influences on Cyclone Structure, and the
T-bone Model
13
11.1 Ordinary Thunderstorm
11.4 Supercells
11.5 Tornadoes
11.5.1 Description
11.5.2 Tornado Development
11.5.3 Tornado Alley
Summary
14
13.2 Prognostic Equations
14.1 Pollutants
14.1.1 Gases and Compounds
14.1.2 Particulates
14.1.3 Photochemical Smog
14.4 Topography
Summary
15
15.4 An Altered Water Cycle
Glossary
References
Credits
Index
16
Preface
Having taught introductory classes on weather many times, we came to see
the need for a textbook on the subject that covers the foundations of
meteorology in a concise, clear, and engaging manner. We set out to create
an informative, cost-effective text that meets the needs of students who
may not have any background in mathematics and science. The result –
Weather: A Concise Introduction – is an introductory meteorology
textbook designed from scratch to provide students with a strong
foundation in the physical, dynamical, and chemical processes taking place
in the atmosphere.
This textbook is unique in that it:
Features
17
Case Study: February 2014 Cyclone
The main concepts of the book are illustrated in Chapters 2–13 by a single
case study: a midlatitude cyclone that swept through the eastern half of the
USA between February 19 and 22, 2014. This rich case study serves as a
common thread throughout the book, allowing students to study it from
multiple perspectives. Viewing the storm in the context of different topics
provides a familiar setting for mastering new subjects and for developing
an holistic understanding of midlatitude cyclones.
Summary
18
A summary of key points has been included at the end of each chapter so
that students can, at a glance, confirm that they have understood the
significant take-away facts and ideas.
SI Units
We have consistently used SI units throughout the book, while providing
alternative units whenever possible or relevant.
Organization
19
The first two chapters provide a general overview of key variables and
weather maps used by meteorologists, which facilitates daily weather map
discussions early in the course. We have found that motivating lecture
topics with real-time examples using weather map discussions is a very
effective way to engage students in the lecture material, and it allows
instructors to introduce aspects of weather forecasting at their discretion
well in advance of discussing the material more completely in Chapter 13.
As a result, students are more invested in adding to their knowledge, which
builds systematically toward understanding and predicting weather
systems.
Chapters 3–8 provide foundational material on the composition and
structure of the atmosphere, along with the application of the laws of
classical physics to emphasize and explain the role of energy, water, and
wind in weather systems.
Chapters 9–12 apply the foundational material to understanding the
general circulation of the atmosphere (Chapter 9), midlatitude cyclones
and fronts (Chapter 10), thunderstorms (Chapter 11), and tropical cyclones
(Chapter 12).
Chapters 13–15 build further on the first twelve chapters by applying
the concepts developed to explain processes that affect how weather
forecasts are made (Chapter 13), air pollution (Chapter 14), and climate
change (Chapter 15).
Instructor Resources
A companion website at www.cambridge.org/weather contains PowerPoint
slides of the figures in the text as well as a testbank of questions.
20
Acknowledgments
We thank: NOAA, NASA, and ECMWF for providing access to data and
images; Reto Knutti, Jan Sedlacek, and Urs Beyerle for providing access
to IPCC data; Rick Kohrs from the University of Wisconsin-Madison for
providing global composite satellite imagery; and Paul Sirvatka from the
College of DuPage for providing radar imagery.
We also thank Ángel Adames, Becky Alexander, Ileana Blade, Peter
Blossey, Michael Diamond, Ralph Foster, Dargan Frierson, Qiang Fu,
Dennis Hartmann, Lynn McMurdie, Paul Markowski, Cliff Mass, Max
Menchaca, Yumin Moon, Scott Powell, Virginia Rux, David Schultz,
Justin Sharp, Brian Smoliak, Mike Warner, Steve Warren, Rachel White,
Darren Wilton, Matt Wyant, and Qi Zhong, as well as 13 anonymous
reviewers, for their help in the preparation of this book.
This project would not have come to life without the support, help,
influence, and constructive criticism from many fellow professors,
teaching assistants, and students. We cannot acknowledge them all here by
name, but we thank them nevertheless for the important role they have
played in shaping the development of this book.
21
Introduction
Why should we study our atmosphere? Why should we learn about the
causes and mechanisms of our weather? Weather affects our daily life: the
clothes we wear (rain coat, shorts, hat, should we take an umbrella or
sunglasses...?), the means of transportation we choose (walk, take a bus,
ride our bike...?), our activities (ski, sail, water our plants, read a book in a
coffee shop...?), and probably more. But beyond our daily concerns,
weather affects society at large. Schools close when snow impedes traffic.
Visitors to ski resorts might be more impatient for snow, while the ski
instructors will be keeping an eye on the possibility of avalanches. Rangers
are concerned with fog, thunderstorms, and flash floods. Fire patrols look
for weather patterns that are conducive to forest fires (dryness, wind).
Electricity providers are concerned by wind storms that can damage the
infrastructure of the electrical grid and, on larger timescales, also need to
plan how weather will affect upcoming energy needs (minimum
temperatures impact heating, while maximum temperatures impact air-
conditioning). Weather averages, such as prevailing winds, the typical
temperature range, and mean precipitation determine how we build our
homes and what locations are sensitive to extreme events, such as
droughts, floods, hurricanes, tornadoes, etc. On longer timescales, we can
ask how humans are changing the atmosphere, and what those changes
imply for the weather and climate of the future.
To start answering those questions, we need to understand how the
atmosphere works. We need to identify the basic processes that drive the
atmosphere, and the laws that govern atmospheric processes. By doing so,
we will be able to explain the weather phenomena we experience around
the year and throughout the world. Furthermore, we will also be able to
apply these laws to the current state of the atmosphere, and predict how it
will evolve in the future.
22
© Caroline Planque
There is a lot of value in becoming a knowledgeable observer of the
atmosphere. After reading this book, you will look at the sky differently,
you will gain an understanding of weather and climate that will make you
more attentive to the world around you. You will have a basic
understanding of weather phenomena, of cyclones, thunderstorms, and
hurricanes, and you will understand the basic aspects of weather
forecasting. You will see beyond the weather forecast you get on your
phone, radio, TV, or the internet, and you will be able to make your own
forecast in many situations.
23
Before we continue, let us clarify an important distinction between
weather and climate. Weather is the condition of the atmosphere at a
particular time and location. Weather varies on timescales of minutes to
days. Climate, by contrast, is an average of the weather. It varies on
timescales of decades to centuries and beyond. In this textbook, we will be
mostly concerned with weather – even though many of the concepts have
direct application to climate.
Getting Started
Our exploration of weather will start with a quick overview of important
weather elements that we can observe or measure, and analyze. The choice
of variables to observe is influenced by the laws of physics that govern the
atmosphere. As we will see shortly, the atmosphere is made of matter (air
and water etc.), it contains energy (heat), and it is in motion (wind,
convection). Our understanding of weather is based on the fundamental
notion that matter, energy, and motion obey conservation laws. To apply
these conservation laws to the atmosphere requires observations of
temperature (conservation of energy), pressure (conservation of mass),
wind (conservation of momentum), along with humidity, precipitation, and
clouds. One step at a time, and one building block over another, we will
then investigate the physical processes that underlie the atmosphere at
work. Finally, we will articulate these processes together to build a picture
of weather systems such as midlatitude cyclones, thunderstorms, and
hurricanes. In doing so, we will follow the precepts of René Descartes,
who advocated, as early as 1637, that every difficult problem should be
divided into small parts, and that one should always proceed from the
more simple to the more complex. This cornerstone of the scientific
24
method, still in favor today, will be an important aspect of our exploration
as we elaborate a thorough understanding of the atmosphere from its most
fundamental constituents at the molecular scale to its most complex inner
workings as a system for moving heat at the global scale.
25
Another Random Scribd Document
with Unrelated Content
73. We are so accustomed to associate the revival of astronomy,
as of other branches of natural science, with increased care in the
collection of observed facts, and to think of Coppernicus as the chief
agent in the revival, that it is worth while here to emphasise the fact
that he was in no sense a great observer. His instruments, which
were mostly of his own construction, were far inferior to those of
Nassir Eddin and of Ulugh Begh (chapter iii., §§ 62, 63), and not
even as good as those which he could have procured if he had
wished from the workshops of Nürnberg; his observations were not
at all numerous (only 27, which occur in his book, and a dozen or
two besides being known), and he appears to have made no serious
attempt to secure great accuracy. His determination of the position
of one star, which was extensively used by him as a standard of
reference and was therefore of special importance, was in error to
the extent of nearly 40′ (more than the apparent breadth of the sun
or moon), an error which Hipparchus would have considered very
serious. His pupil Rheticus (§ 74) reports an interesting discussion
between his master and himself, in which the pupil urged the
importance of making observations with all imaginable accuracy;
Coppernicus answered that minute accuracy was not to be looked
for at that time, and that a rough agreement between theory and
observation was all that he could hope to attain. Coppernicus
moreover points out in more than one place that the high latitude of
Frauenburg and the thickness of the air were so detrimental to good
observation that, for example, though he had occasionally been able
to see the planet Mercury, he had never been able to observe it
properly.
Although he published nothing of importance till towards the end
of his life, his reputation as an astronomer and mathematician
appears to have been established among experts from the date of
his leaving Italy, and to have steadily increased as time went on.
In 1515 he was consulted by a committee appointed by the
Lateran Council to consider the reform of the calendar, which had
now fallen into some confusion (chapter ii., § 22), but he declined to
give any advice on the ground that the motions of the sun and moon
were as yet too imperfectly known for a satisfactory reform to be
possible. A few years later (1524) he wrote an open letter, intended
for publication, to one of his Cracow friends, in reply to a tract on
precession, in which, after the manner of the time, he used strong
language about the errors of his opponent.46
It was meanwhile gradually becoming known that he held the
novel doctrine that the earth was in motion and the sun and stars at
rest, a doctrine which was sufficiently startling to attract notice
outside astronomical circles. About 1531 he had the distinction of
being ridiculed on the stage at some popular performance in the
neighbourhood; and it is interesting to note (especially in view of the
famous persecution of Galilei at Rome a century later) that Luther in
his Table Talk frankly described Coppernicus as a fool for holding
such opinions, which were obviously contrary to the Bible, and that
Melanchthon, perhaps the most learned of the Reformers, added to
a somewhat similar criticism a broad hint that such opinions should
not be tolerated. Coppernicus appears to have taken no notice of
these or similar attacks, and still continued to publish nothing. No
observation made later than 1529 occurs in his great book, which
seems to have been nearly in its final form by that date; and to
about this time belongs an extremely interesting paper, known as
the Commentariolus, which contains a short account of his system of
the world, with some of the evidence for it, but without any
calculations. It was apparently written to be shewn or lent to friends,
and was not published; the manuscript disappeared after the death
of the author and was only rediscovered in 1878. The
Commentariolus was probably the basis of a lecture on the ideas of
Coppernicus given in 1533 by one of the Roman astronomers at the
request of Pope Clement VII. Three years later Cardinal Schomberg
wrote to ask Coppernicus for further information as to his views, the
letter showing that the chief features were already pretty accurately
known.
74. Similar requests must have been made by others, but his final
decision to publish his ideas seems to have been due to the arrival
at Frauenburg in 1539 of the enthusiastic young astronomer
generally known as Rheticus.47 Born in 1514, he studied astronomy
under Schoner at Nürnberg, and was appointed in 1536 to one of
the chairs of mathematics created by the influence of Melanchthon
at Wittenberg, at that time the chief Protestant University.
Having heard, probably through the Commentariolus, of
Coppernicus and his doctrines, he was so much interested in them
that he decided to visit the great astronomer at Frauenburg.
Coppernicus received him with extreme kindness, and the visit,
which was originally intended to last a few days or weeks, extended
over nearly two years. Rheticus set to work to study Coppernicus’s
manuscript, and wrote within a few weeks of his arrival an extremely
interesting and valuable account of it, known as the First Narrative
(Prima Narratio), in the form of an open letter to his old master
Schoner, a letter which was printed in the following spring and was
the first easily accessible account of the new doctrines.48
When Rheticus returned to Wittenberg, towards the end of 1541,
he took with him a copy of a purely mathematical section of the
great book, and had it printed as a textbook of the subject
(Trigonometry); it had probably been already settled that he was to
superintend the printing of the complete book itself. Coppernicus,
who was now an old man and would naturally feel that his end was
approaching, sent the manuscript to his friend Giese, Bishop of
Kulm, to do what he pleased with. Giese sent it at once to Rheticus,
who made arrangements for having it printed at Nürnberg.
Unfortunately Rheticus was not able to see it all through the press,
and the work had to be entrusted to Osiander, a Lutheran preacher
interested in astronomy. Osiander appears to have been much
alarmed at the thought of the disturbance which the heretical ideas
of Coppernicus would cause, and added a prefatory note of his own
(which he omitted to sign), praising the book in a vulgar way, and
declaring (what was quite contrary to the views of the author) that
the fundamental principles laid down in it were merely abstract
hypotheses convenient for purposes of calculation; he also gave the
book the title De Revolutionibus Orbium Celestium (On the
Revolutions of the Celestial Spheres), the last two words of which
were probably his own addition. The printing was finished in the
winter 1542-3, and the author received a copy of his book on the
day of his death (May 24th, 1543), when his memory and mental
vigour had already gone.
75. The central idea with which the name of Coppernicus is
associated, and which makes the De Revolutionibus one of the most
important books in all astronomical literature, by the side of which
perhaps only the Almagest and Newton’s Principia (chapter ix.,
§§ 177 seqq.) can be placed, is that the apparent motions of the
celestial bodies are to a great extent not real motions, but are due to
the motion of the earth carrying the observer with it. Coppernicus
tells us that he had long been struck by the unsatisfactory nature of
the current explanations of astronomical observations, and that,
while searching in philosophical writings for some better explanation,
he had found a reference of Cicero to the opinion of Hicetas that the
earth turned round on its axis daily. He found similar views held by
other Pythagoreans, while Philolaus and Aristarchus of Samos had
also held that the earth not only rotates, but moves bodily round the
sun or some other centre (cf. chapter ii., § 24). The opinion that the
earth is not the sole centre of motion, but that Venus and Mercury
revolve round the sun, he found to be an old Egyptian belief,
supported also by Martianus Capella, who wrote a compendium of
science and philosophy in the 5th or 6th century a.d. A more modern
authority, Nicholas of Cusa (1401-1464), a mystic writer who refers
to a possible motion of the earth, was ignored or not noticed by
Coppernicus. None of the writers here named, with the possible
exception of Aristarchus of Samos, to whom Coppernicus apparently
paid little attention, presented the opinions quoted as more than
vague speculations; none of them gave any substantial reasons for,
much less a proof of, their views; and Coppernicus, though he may
have been glad, after the fashion of the age, to have the support of
recognised authorities, had practically to make a fresh start and
elaborate his own evidence for his opinions.
It has sometimes been said that Coppernicus proved what earlier
writers had guessed at or suggested; it would perhaps be truer to
say that he took up certain floating ideas, which were extremely
vague and had never been worked out scientifically, based on them
certain definite fundamental principles, and from these principles
developed mathematically an astronomical system which he shewed
to be at least as capable of explaining the observed celestial motions
as any existing variety of the traditional Ptolemaic system. The
Coppernican system, as it left the hands of the author, was in fact
decidedly superior to its rivals as an explanation of ordinary
observations, an advantage which it owed quite as much to the
mathematical skill with which it was developed as to its first
principles; it was in many respects very much simpler; and it avoided
certain fundamental difficulties of the older system. It was however
liable to certain serious objections, which were only overcome by
fresh evidence which was subsequently brought to light. For the
predecessors of Coppernicus there was, apart from variations of
minor importance, but one scientific system which made any serious
attempt to account for known facts; for his immediate successors
there were two, the newer of which would to an impartial mind
appear on the whole the more satisfactory, and the further study of
the two systems, with a view to the discovery of fresh arguments or
fresh observations tending to support the one or the other, was
immediately suggested as an inquiry of first-rate importance.
76. The plan of the De Revolutionibus bears a general
resemblance to that of the Almagest. In form at least the book is not
primarily an argument in favour of the motion of the earth, and it is
possible to read much of it without ever noticing the presence of this
doctrine.
Coppernicus, like Ptolemy, begins with certain first principles or
postulates, but on account of their novelty takes a little more trouble
than his predecessor (cf. chapter ii., § 47) to make them at once
appear probable. With these postulates as a basis he proceeds to
develop, by means of elaborate and rather tedious mathematical
reasoning, aided here and there by references to observations,
detailed schemes of the various celestial motions; and it is by the
agreement of these calculations with observations, far more than by
the general reasoning given at the beginning, that the various
postulates are in effect justified.
His first postulate, that the universe is spherical, is supported by
vague and inconclusive reasons similar to those given by Ptolemy
and others; for the spherical form of the earth he gives several of
the usual valid arguments, one of his proofs for its curvature from
east to west being the fact that eclipses visible at one place are not
visible at another. A third postulate, that the motions of the celestial
bodies are uniform circular motions or are compounded of such
motions, is, as might be expected, supported only by reasons of the
most unsatisfactory character. He argues, for example, that any want
of uniformity in motion
77. The discussion of the possibility that the earth may move, and
may even have more than one motion, then follows, and is more
satisfactory though by no means conclusive. Coppernicus has a firm
grasp of the principle, which Aristotle had also enunciated,
sometimes known as that of relative motion, which he states
somewhat as follows:—
83. Coppernicus devotes the first eleven chapters of the first book
to this preliminary sketch of his system; the remainder of this book
he fills with some mathematical propositions and tables, which, as
previously mentioned (§ 74), had already been separately printed by
Rheticus. The second book contains chiefly a number of the usual
results relating to the celestial sphere and its apparent daily motion,
treated much as by earlier writers, but with greater mathematical
skill. Incidentally Coppernicus gives his measurement of the obliquity
of the ecliptic, and infers from a comparison with earlier
observations that the obliquity had decreased, which was in fact the
case, though to a much less extent than his imperfect observations
indicated. The book ends with a catalogue of stars, which is
Ptolemy’s catalogue, occasionally corrected by fresh observations,
and rearranged so as to avoid the effects of precession.53 When, as
frequently happened, the Greek and Latin versions of the Almagest
gave, owing to copyists’ or printers’ errors, different results,
Coppernicus appears to have followed sometimes the Latin and
sometimes the Greek version, without in general attempting to
ascertain by fresh observations which was right.
84. The third book begins with an elaborate discussion of the
precession of the equinoxes (chapter ii., § 42). From a comparison
of results obtained by Timocharis, by later Greek astronomers, and
by Albategnius, Coppernicus infers that the amount of precession
has varied, but that its average value is 50″·2 annually (almost
exactly the true value), and accepts accordingly Tabit ben Korra’s
unhappy suggestion of the trepidation (chapter iii., § 58). An
examination of the data used by Coppernicus shews that the
erroneous or fraudulent observations of Ptolemy (chapter ii., § 50)
are chiefly responsible for the perpetuation of this mistake.
Of much more interest than the detailed discussion of trepidation
and of geometrical schemes for representing it is the interpretation
of precession as the result of a motion of the earth’s axis. Precession
was originally recognised by Hipparchus as a motion of the celestial
equator, in which its inclination to the ecliptic was sensibly
unchanged. Now the ideas of Coppernicus make the celestial
equator dependent on the equator of the earth, and hence on its
axis; it is in fact a great circle of the celestial sphere which is always
perpendicular to the axis about which the earth rotates daily. Hence
precession, on the theory of Coppernicus, arises from a slow motion
of the axis of the earth, which moves so as always to remain inclined
at the same angle to the ecliptic, and to return to its original position
after a period of about 26,000 years (since a motion of 50″·2
annually is equivalent to 360° or a complete circuit in that period); in
other words, the earth’s axis has a slow conical motion, the central
line (or axis) of the cone being at right angles to the plane of the
ecliptic.
85. Precession being dealt with, the greater part of the remainder
of the third book is devoted to a discussion in detail of the apparent
annual motion of the sun round the earth, corresponding to the real
annual motion of the earth round the sun. The geometrical theory of
the Almagest was capable of being immediately applied to the new
system, and Coppernicus, like Ptolemy, uses an eccentric. He makes
the calculations afresh, arrives at a smaller and more accurate value
of the eccentricity (about 1∕31 instead of 1∕24), fixes the position of
the apogee and perigee (chapter ii., § 39), or rather of the
equivalent aphelion and perihelion (i.e. the points in the earth’s
orbit where it is respectively farthest from and nearest to the sun),
and thus verifies Albategnius’s discovery (chapter iii., § 59) of the
motion of the line of apses. The theory of the earth’s motion is
worked out in some detail, and tables are given whereby the
apparent place of the sun at any time can be easily computed.
The fourth book deals with the theory of the moon. As has been
already noticed, the moon was the only celestial body the position of
which in the universe was substantially unchanged by Coppernicus,
and it might hence have been expected that little alteration would
have been required in the traditional theory. Actually, however, there
is scarcely any part of the subject in which Coppernicus did more to
diminish the discrepancies between theory and observation. He
rejects Ptolemy’s equant (chapter ii., § 51), partly on the ground
that it produces an irregular motion unsuitable for the heavenly
bodies, partly on the more substantial ground that, as already
pointed out (chapter ii., § 48), Ptolemy’s theory makes the apparent
size of the moon at times twice as great as at others. By an
arrangement of epicycles Coppernicus succeeded in representing the
chief irregularities in the moon’s motion, including evection, but
without Ptolemy’s prosneusis (chapter ii., § 48) or Abul Wafa’s
inequality (chapter iii., § 60), while he made the changes in the
moon’s distance, and consequently in its apparent size, not very
much greater than those which actually take place, the difference
being imperceptible by the rough methods of observation which he
used.54
In discussing the distances and sizes of the sun and moon
Coppernicus follows Ptolemy closely (chapter ii., § 49; cf. also fig.
20); he arrives at substantially the same estimate of the distance of
the moon, but makes the sun’s distance 1,500 times the earth’s
radius, thus improving to some extent on the traditional estimate,
which was based on Ptolemy’s. He also develops in some detail the
effect of parallax on the apparent place of the moon, and the
variations in the apparent size, owing to the variations in distance:
and the book ends with a discussion of eclipses.
86. The last two books (V. and VI.) deal at length with the motion
of the planets.
In the cases of Mercury and Venus, Ptolemy’s explanation of the
motion could with little difficulty be rearranged so as to fit the ideas
of Coppernicus. We have seen (chapter ii., § 51) that, minor
irregularities being ignored, the motion of either of these planets
could be represented by means of an epicycle moving on a deferent,
the centre of the epicycle being always in the direction of the sun,
the ratio of the sizes of the epicycle and deferent being fixed, but
the actual dimensions being practically arbitrary. Ptolemy preferred
on the whole to regard the epicycles of both these planets as lying
between the earth and the sun. The idea of making the sun a centre
of motion having once been accepted, it was an obvious
simplification to make the centre of the epicycle not merely lie in the
direction of the sun, but actually be the sun. In fact, if the planet in
question revolved round the sun at the proper distance and at the
proper rate, the same appearances would be produced as by
Ptolemy’s epicycle and deferent, the path of the planet round the
sun replacing the epicycle, and the apparent path of the sun round
the earth (or the path of the earth round the sun) replacing the
deferent.
Fig. 46.—The relative sizes of the orbits of the earth and of a superior
planet.
ebooksecure.com