ssrn-2575841
ssrn-2575841
in WEIGHING LIVES: COMBATANTS & CIVILIANS IN WAR (Jens David Ohlin, Larry May,
Claire Finkelstein eds., forthcoming 2016).
the Protection of Victims of International Armed Conflicts, 8 June 1977 (Protocol I) art 51(5).
See also International Committee of the Red Cross, Customary International Humanitarian
Law, vol 1 (CUP 2009) 46.
Electroniccopy
Electronic copy available
available at:
at:https://ssrn.com/abstract=2575841
http://ssrn.com/abstract=2575841
My account of jus in bello proportionality is in one way more
determinate than existing accounts — for example, it does not compare
incommensurable values but instead compares immediate losses to civilians
and future losses to civilians and to attacking forces. At the same time, my
account must still grapple with the predictive uncertainty inherent in
determining whether immediate losses inflicted will be redeemed by future
losses avoided. Accordingly, I explore a number of decision procedures and
rules of engagement that officers may use to make the best possible decision
given the limited information available to them.
Legal Aspects (2015) 185 (‘As long as there is no significant imbalance between the expected
collateral damage and the anticipated military advantage, no excessiveness exists’); Geoffrey
S Corn & Gary P Corn, ‘The Law of Operational Targeting: Viewing the LOAC Through an
Operational Lens’ (2012) 47 Tex. Int'l L.J. 337, 365 (writing that ‘an attack does not become
[unlawful] when the collateral damage or incidental injury is slightly greater than the
military advantage anticipated (what is suggested by the term ‘disproportionate’) but only
when those effects are excessive’).
4 See, eg, Merriam-Webster Dictionary (defining ‘excessive’ as ‘exceeding what is
usual, proper, necessary, or normal’); Oxford English Dictionary (‘More than is necessary,
normal, or desirable’).
5 Cf Commentary on the HPCR Manual on International Law Applicable to Air and
Electroniccopy
Electronic copy available
available at:
at:https://ssrn.com/abstract=2575841
http://ssrn.com/abstract=2575841
attack will cause excessive civilian losses and to cancel or suspend an attack
if it becomes apparent that it will do so.6 It follows that
6 Protocol I arts 57(2)(a)(iii) & 57(2)(b); ICRC, Customary IHL Study 58 & 60.
7 ICTY, Prosecutor v. Galić, Judgment, IT-98-29, Trial Chamber, December 5, 2003,
para 58.
8 Commentary on the HPCR Manual 45.
9 Ibid.
10 ICRC, Protocol I Commentary para 2209.
11 See, eg, Elements of Crimes n. 36.
12 See, eg, UK Ministry of Defense, Law of Armed Conflict Manual (OUP 2005)
5.33.5; ICRC, Protocol I Commentary para 2218.
13 US Dep’t of Defense, Law of War Manual 5.12.3.
14 See ICTY, Prosecutor v Prlic, Judgment, IT-04-74, Trial Chamber, May 29, 2013,
paras 1582-84.
15 Environmental damage raises interesting issues. For example, Protocol I prohibits
methods or means of warfare which may be expected to cause widespread, long-term and
severe damage to the natural environment. Protocol I, art 55(1). Accordingly, environmental
damage is prohibited if it is severe even if it is not excessive, but is not prohibited if it is
excessive but not severe.
In contrast, the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court recognizes a war
crime of knowingly inflicting ‘widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural
environment which would be clearly excessive in relation to the concrete and direct overall
military advantage anticipated’. Rome Statute, art 8(2)(b)(iv). Accordingly, environmental
damage is punishable only if it is both severe and clearly excessive.
Finally, the ICRC takes the view that customary international law prohibits attacks
‘which may be expected to cause incidental damage to the environment which would be
excessive in relation to the concrete and direct military advantage anticipated’. ICRC,
Customary IHL Study 143. Accordingly, environmental damage is prohibited if it is
excessive even if it is not severe. I will not attempt to reconcile these approaches here.
See also Eliav Lieblich, ‘Beyond Life and Limb: Exploring Incidental Mental Harm
under International Humanitarian Law’, in Derek Jinks, Jackson Nyamuya Maogoto &
Solon Solomon (eds), Applying International Humanitarian Law in Judicial and Quasi-
Judicial Bodies: International and Domestic Aspects (TMC Asser 2014) 185.
16 For more on prioritarianism, see Derek Parfit, ‘Equality and priority’ (1997) 10
Ratio 202–21.
17 See, eg, APV Rogers, Law on the Battlefield (1996) 17 (‘Some delegations at the
diplomatic conference at which Protocol I was negotiated ... were reluctant to include any
reference to the proportionality rule because of the difficulty of comparing things that were
not comparable (i.e. military advantage and civilian losses)’); Michael N Schmitt, ‘The
Principle of Discrimination in 21st Century Warfare’ (1999) 2 Yale Hum. Rts. & Dev. L.J. 143,
151 (‘Optimally, balancing tests compare like values. However, proportionality calculations
are heterogeneous, because dissimilar value genres — military and humanitarian — are
being weighed against each other. How, for example, does one objectively calculate the
relative weight of an aircraft, tank, ship, or vantage point in terms of human casualties?’).
18 See Ruth Chang, ‘Introduction’ in Ruth Chang (ed), Incommensurability,
Incomparability, and Practical Reason (1997) 14 (noting that incommensurable values often
permit ‘nominal-notable’ comparisons in extreme cases).
19 Henry Shue, ‘Proportionality in War’ in Gordon Martel (ed), The Encyclopedia of
War (2012) 6.
20 ICRC, Protocol I Commentary para 2214.
21 HCJ 769/02, Pub. Comm. Against Torture in Israel v. Gov't of Israel, Judgment,
Dec. 11, 2005, para 46. See also HCJ 2056/04, Beit Sourik Village Council v. Israel,
Judgment, June 30, 2004, para 41.
Thomas Hurka and Jeff McMahan reject the view that civilian losses and
military advantages are incommensurable values on the grounds that
military advantages have no intrinsic value at all.23 Indeed, soldiers ought
not harm opposing combatants, capture strategic territory, or destroy
military equipment for its own sake. Such military advantages have
instrumental or derivative value only if they contribute to some further,
intrinsically valuable state of affairs. Importantly, the defeat of an opposing
armed force has intrinsic value only if one fights for a just cause — such as
national self-defense or humanitarian intervention — that morally justifies
resorting to or continuing the use of military force.
Hurka and McMahan conclude that the value of a military advantage,
if any, lies in the contribution that it makes to the achievement of a just
cause. Conversely, a military advantage that contributes to an unjust cause
has no moral value. Hurka and McMahan therefore reject the independence
of jus ad bellum just cause and jus in bello proportionality and with it the
symmetrical application of jus in bello proportionality. Put another way, jus
in bello proportionality is just a special application of jus ad bellum
proportionality. Just as jus ad bellum proportionality compares civilian
losses inflicted by the war as a whole with the importance of a just cause, jus
in bello proportionality compares civilian losses inflicted by a particular
military operation with the contribution of that operation to the achievement
of the same just cause.
For just combatants, this moral standard makes for an impossible
decision procedure. Soldiers would first have to measure the moral
importance of their war aims, since a similar contribution to a more
important war aim would justify more extensive civilian losses. Soldiers
23 See Thomas Hurka, ‘Proportionality in the Morality of War’, Philosophy & Public
Affairs 33 (2005) 34; Jeff McMahan, ‘Proportionality and Necessity in Jus in Bello’, in Helen
Frowe and Seth Lazar (eds), The Oxford Handbook of the Ethics of War (OUP 2016);
McMahan, ‘Proportionate Defense’ (2013-2014) 23 Journal of Transnational Law and Policy 1,
20-21.
24 US Joint Chiefs of Staff, Joint Publication 3-60: Joint Targeting (2007) D-2–D-4.
We can now see where, on my account, the value of a military advantage lies.
Let X represent the total losses that one’s own forces and civilians will suffer
in the remainder of the conflict if a military advantage — say, destroying a
munitions factory or killing an insurgent leader — is not achieved. Let Y
represent the total losses that one’s own forces and civilians will suffer in the
remainder of the conflict if that military advantage is achieved. The value of
the military advantage is the difference between X and Y, that is, the total
overall losses prevented by achieving the advantage. Let Z be the losses that
26US v List (American Military Tribunal, Nuremberg, 1948), 11 NMT 1230, 1253.
27See, eg, Allied Joint Publication AJP-5, Allied Joint Doctrine for Operational-Level
Planning, 26 June 2013, 3-37; US Naval War College, Workbook on Joint Operations
Planning Process, NWC 4111H, 21 January 2008.
28 Note that full moral justification requires a comparison between campaigns that
each satisfies the jus ad bellum and other jus in bello norms. Certainly, an attack cannot be
morally justified on the grounds that if the attack is not carried out then the attackers will
pursue a campaign that violates other moral or legal standards.
29 Seth Lazar suggested to me that attacks that secure such necessary advantages
necessarily satisfy jus in bello proportionality because if the war aim is achieved then the
war will end, thereby avoiding all the harm that would have occurred had the war continued.
Unfortunately, wars do not always end when one party achieves its aims.
30 US v List (American Military Tribunal, Nuremberg, 1948), 11 NMT 1230, at 1272
para 128.
31 See, eg, Dapo Akande & Thomas Liefländer, ‘Clarifying Necessity, Imminence, and
Proportionality in the Law of Self-Defense’ (2013) 107 American Journal of International
Law 563, 566; David Kretzmer, The Inherent Right to Self-Defence and Proportionality in
Jus Ad Bellum’ (2013) 24 European Journal of International Law 235, 278-79. See also Tom
Ruys, ‘Armed Attack’ and Article 51 of the UN Charter (CUP 2010) 121-22 (‘Defensive action
resulting in large numbers of civilian casualties has unvariably evoked strong negative
reactions from the international community and has frequently been condemned by the
Security Council and/or the General Assembly’). Note that the condemnations cited by Ruys
typically refer to the disproportionate use of force, invoking the jus ad bellum, not to the
disproportionate conduct of hostilities, which would invoke the jus in bello.
Before moving on, let me take a moment to distinguish my view from one
that McMahan effectively criticizes, namely the view that jus in bello
proportionality compares harms inflicted on civilians with harms avoided to
combatants in the very same engagement.35 On this view, just combatants
may inflict harm on civilians if such harm is a necessary and proportionate
side-effect of using defensive force against unjust combatants. This view
could at most explain the permissibility of unit self-defense, that is, of force
used to repel a direct attack on particular combatants. However, as
McMahan observes, this view would preclude all offensive operations, since if
a party refrains from offensive operations then the necessity to use defensive
force on behalf of its members often will not arise. In particular, McMahan
argues that this view would preclude humanitarian military interventions.
Since attacking forces could simply not intervene, attacking forces will inflict
losses on civilians that are not strictly necessary to protect their members. In
addition, it is not clear how this view would apply to targeted killing
operations in which the attacking force is never in danger.
My view is not subject to these objections. On my view, we hold
constant the war aim of the attacking force and ask whether an attack is a
32 See, eg, Yoram Dinstein, War, Aggression and Self-Defence (CUP 2005) 237-42.
33 United Nations Charter, preamble.
34 See SS “Lotus” (Fr v Turk), Judgment, 1927 PCIJ (ser A) No 10, at 18 (Sept. 7).
35 Jeff McMahan, ‘War Crimes and Wrongdoing in War’, in RA Duff et al (eds), The
Cardozo Law Review 2481, 2493 (‘A partially justified act is, therefore, a wrongful act that,
due to certain mitigating circumstances, is less wrongful than that required by the charged
offense’).
‘anticipated’ military advantage, for these purposes, mean that that outcome is probable, i.e.
more likely than not’).
Nevertheless, we can still determine whether or not the attack will probably
result in a proportionate outcome. For example, there is only a 33% chance
that the attack will prevent at least three times more harm than it will inflict.
These possible outcomes are indicated in bold. It follows that if harming is at
least three times worse than allowing harm then the attack will probably not
prove proportionate and is therefore epistemically impermissible.
Alternatively, there is an additional 34% chance that the attack will prevent
twice the harm that it will inflict. These possible outcomes are indicated in
italics. It follows that if harming is less than twice as bad as allowing harm
then there is a 67% chance that the attack will prove proportionate and is
therefore epistemically permissible. If the possible harm inflicted and the
possible harm prevented are not independent in this way then the attacking
force would have to determine the likelihood of each possible outcome and
then determine whether the attack will probably result in one of the
proportionate outcomes.
Any serious account of jus in bello proportionality will require
attackers to make similar probabilistic judgments with respect to both
civilian losses and military advantages, however the latter are understood.
Nevertheless, such probabilistic judgments may seem too complicated for
attacking forces to perform in many situations. Often the probabilities
themselves are uncertain or the possible outcomes too numerous to carefully
examine. In such cases, attacking forces may be unable to determine the
epistemic permissibility — let alone the objective permissibility — of their
actions. Attacking forces will have no choice but to base their decisions on
presumptions, heuristics, and other mental shortcuts.
Moral Uncertainty
40 See, eg, Helen Frowe, ‘Claims Rights, Duties and Lesser Evil Obligations’ (2015) 89
the disproportion between losses and damages caused and the military
advantages anticipated raises a delicate problem; in some situations
there will be no room for doubt, while in other situations there may be
reason for hesitation. In such situations [of doubt] the interests of the
civilian population should prevail.42
Ours = Theirs: Do not carry out an attack that will endanger foreign
civilians unless you would accept the same risk to your own civilians.
Ask yourself: Will the attack harm civilians? If so, would you carry
out the attack even if they were your own civilians? If you would not,
then DO NOT carry out the attack.
Hopefully, these proposed ROE will provide military officers with practical
decision procedures that are simpler and more direct than the proportionality
principle itself.
Of course, these ROE are only decision procedures and not moral or
legal standards. For one thing, much like the Golden Rule, these ROE
depend for their application on the subjective values of the applicant. The
less value an officer places on the lives of his own forces, the less value these
ROE require him to place on the lives of civilians. These ROE only tell us to
place equal value on the lives of our own forces and the lives of civilians.
They do not tell us how much absolute value to place on the lives of anyone.
At the same time, since most attackers — consciously or subconsciously —
place as much or more value on their troops than on foreign civilians, most
attackers will act less wrongfully if they follow these ROE than if they allow
their implicit biases to affect their targeting decisions.
43 Henderson 229.
44 Protocol I art 57(2)(a)(iii).
are not a defense to war crimes if the defendant did not believe that the orders were lawful or
if the orders were manifestly unlawful).
48 Cf Raz, The Morality of Freedom 42-46.
49 Ibid.
50 Cf Commentary on the HPCR Manual 94 (‘Anyone with the ability and authority to
suspend, abort or cancel an attack, must do so once he reaches the conclusion that the
expected collateral damage would be excessive in relation to the anticipated military
advantage. For instance, a pilot who has the target in view and unexpectedly observes
civilians in the target area — who were not supposed to be there, based on the information
provided to him during the briefing preceding the attack — must assess the collateral
damage expected to befall them and cancel the attack if he concludes that the principle of
proportionality will be violated’); Quéguiner 805 (‘[I]f, before launching a first salvo against a
bridge, a tank driver notices that a crowd of fleeing civilians have taken refuge under the
targeted bridge, the driver cannot assume that the planners have correctly considered the
principle of proportionality and continue his mission in wilful blindness and impunity. He
must, at the very least, suspend his attack in order to allow the civilians to evacuate, or to
request that his orders be confirmed in the light of these new circumstances’).
51 See Bureau of Investigative Journalism, ‘Covert Drone War’,
http://www.thebureauinvestigates.com/category/projects/drones/.
Conclusion
52 For a similar conclusion reached on strategic rather than moral or legal grounds,
see David Petraeus, U.S. Dep’t of Def., The U.S. Army and Marine Corps Counterinsurgency
Field Manual, para 7-32 (U.S. Army Field Manual No. 3-24, 2006) (‘In COIN environments,
the number of civilian lives lost and property destroyed needs to be measured against how
much harm the targeted insurgent could do if allowed to escape. If the target in question is
relatively inconsequential, then proportionality requires combatants to forego severe action,
or seek non-combative means of engagement’).
53 Cf Michael N Schmitt, ‘Unmanned Combat Aircraft Systems and International
Humanitarian Law: Simplifying the Oft Benighted Debate’ (2012) 30 BU Int’l LJ 595, 616
(‘Multiple civilian casualties may not be excessive when attacking a senior leader of the
enemy forces, but even a single civilian casualty may be excessive if the enemy soldiers killed
are of little importance or pose no threat’).