Lecture13v2
Lecture13v2
Lecture 13
Anshumaan Tuteja
Assistant professor of Economics
Ashoka University
* Welfare Theorems
* Conclusions
1 / 32
Welfare Theorems I
We have discussed several models with centralized and decentralized systems. Let’s do
a quick review:
▶ Under certain conditions, the two solutions match! They are the topic of
discussion in two famous welfare theorems in Economics
2 / 32
Welfare Theorems II
▶ Proof of the First Welfare Theorem based on two intuitive ideas.
1. If another allocation Pareto dominates the competitive equilibrium, then it must be
non-affordable in the competitive equilibrium.
2. Profit-maximization implies that any competitive equilibrium already contains the
maximal set of affordable allocations.
▶ Also the more important of the two theorems: stronger results that any Pareto
optimal allocation can be decentralized.
▶ Motivates many to look for the set of Pareto optimal allocations instead of
explicitly characterizing competitive equilibria.
▶ Real power of the Theorem in dynamic macro models comes when we combine it
with models that admit a representative household.
* Welfare Theorems
* Conclusions
5 / 32
Overlapping generations models
▶ How to model households in infinite horizon?
1. “infinitely lived” or consisting of overlapping generations with full altruism linking
generations→infinite planning horizon
2. overlapping generations→finite planning horizon (generally...).
▶ So far, we have looked at models with representative households living finite or
infinite horizons
▶ In many situations, the assumption of a representative household is not
appropriate because
1. households do not have an infinite planning horizon
2. new households arrive (or are born) over time.
▶ Tractable model but inconsistent with overlapping dynasties
▶ A structure of overlapping generations implies older generation affect prices faced
by younger generation
6 / 32
Growth with Overlapping Generations
1. Capture potential interaction of different generations of individuals in the
marketplace;
2. Provide tractable alternative to infinite-horizon representative agent models;
3. Some key implications different from neoclassical growth model;
4. Dynamics in some special cases quite similar to Solow model rather than the
neoclassical model;
5. Generate new insights about the role of national debt and Social Security in the
economy.
7 / 32
Problems of Infinity
▶ An example can show that the First Welfare Theorem does not apply in OLG
models
▶ This is because there are infinite number of HHs and infinite number of
commodities
▶ Source of the problem must be related to the infinite number of commodities.
▶ Extended version of the First Welfare Theorem covers infinite number of
commodities, but only assuming ∞ ∗
P
j=0 pj ωj < ∞ (written with the aggregate
endowment ωj ).
▶ Here theonly endowment is labor, and thus pj∗ = 1 for all j ∈ N, so that
P∞ ∗
j=0 pj ωj = ∞
8 / 32
Lecture outline
* Welfare Theorems
* Conclusions
9 / 32
The Baseline Overlapping Generations Model
▶ Time is discrete and runs to infinity.
▶ Each individual lives for two periods.
▶ Individuals born at time t live for dates t and t + 1.
▶ Assume a general (separable) utility function for individuals born at date t,
Lt = (1 + n)t L0 . (2)
10 / 32
Demographics, Preferences and Technology I
▶ Production side same as before: competitive firms, constant returns to scale
aggregate production function, satisfying Assumptions 1 and 2:
Yt = F (Kt , Lt ) .
1 + rt = Rt = f ′ (kt ) , (3)
11 / 32
Consumption Decisions I
▶ Savings by an individual of generation t, st , is determined as a solution to
max u (c1,t ) + βu (c2,t+1 )
c1,t ,c2,t+1 ,st
subject to
c1,t + st ≤ wt
and
c2,t+1 ≤ Rt+1 st ,
▶ Old individuals rent their savings of time t as capital to firms at time t + 1, and
receive gross rate of return Rt+1 = 1 + rt+1
▶ Since u (·) is strictly increasing, both constraints will hold as equalities.
▶ Thus first-order condition for a maximum can be written in the familiar form of
the consumption Euler equation,
u ′ (c1,t ) = βRt+1 u ′ (c2,t+1 ) . (5)
▶ Solving for consumption and thus for savings,
st = s (wt , Rt+1 ) , (6)
12 / 32
Consumption Decisions II
▶ s : R2+ → R is strictly increasing in its first argument and may be increasing or
decreasing in its second argument.
▶ Total savings in the economy will be equal to
St = st Lt ,
13 / 32
Equilibrium I
Definition A competitive equilibrium can be represented by a sequence of aggregate
capital stocks, individual consumption and factor prices,
{Kt , c1,t , c2,t , Rt , wt }∞ ∞
t=0 , such that the factor price sequence {Rt , wt }t=0
is given by (3) and (4), individual consumption decisions {c1,t , c2,t }∞ t=0
are given by (5) and (6), and the aggregate capital stock, {Kt }∞ t=0 ,
evolves according to (7).
▶ Steady-state equilibrium defined as usual: an equilibrium in which k ≡ K /L is
constant.
▶ To characterize the equilibrium, divide (7) by Lt+1 = (1 + n) Lt ,
s (wt , Rt+1 )
kt+1 = .
1+n
▶ Now substituting for Rt+1 and wt from (3) and (4),
15 / 32
Restrictions on Utility and Production Functions I
▶ The CRRA utility simplifies the first-order condition for consumer optimization,
c2,t+1
= (βRt+1 )1/θ .
c1,t
▶ This Euler equation can be alternatively expressed in terms of savings as
st−θ βRt+1
1−θ
= (wt − st )−θ , (11)
where
−(1−θ)/θ
ψ ≡ [1 + β −1/θ Rt+1 ] > 1,
▶ Ensures that savings are always less than earnings.
16 / 32
Restrictions on Utility and Production Functions II
▶ The impact of factor prices on savings is summarized by the following and
derivatives:
∂st 1
sw ≡ = ∈ (0, 1) ,
∂wt ψt+1
∂st 1−θ st
sR ≡ = (βRt+1 )−1/θ .
∂Rt+1 θ ψt+1
▶ Since ψ(.) > 1, we also have that 0 < sw < 1.
▶ Moreover, in this case sR > 0 if θ > 1, sR < 0 if θ < 1, and sR = 0 if θ = 1.
▶ Reflects counteracting influences of income and substitution effects.
▶ Case of θ = 1 (log preferences) is of special importance, may deserve to be called
the canonical overlapping generations model.
17 / 32
Restrictions on Utility and Production Functions III
▶ Equation (8) implies
st
kt+1 = (13)
(1 + n)
wt
= ,
(1 + n)ψt+1
▶ Or more explicitly,
f (kt ) − kt f ′ (kt )
kt+1 = (14)
(1 + n) [1 + β −1/θ f ′ (kt+1 )−(1−θ)/θ ]
▶ The steady state then involves a solution to the following implicit equation:
f (k ∗ ) − k ∗ f ′ (k ∗ )
k∗ = .
(1 + n) [1 + β −1/θ f ′ (k ∗ )−(1−θ)/θ ]
18 / 32
Restrictions on Utility and Production Functions IV
▶ Now using the Cobb-Douglas formula, steady state is the solution to the equation
h (θ−1)/θ i
(1 + n) 1 + β −1/θ α(k ∗ )α−1 = (1 − α)(k ∗ )α−1 . (15)
* Welfare Theorems
* Conclusions
20 / 32
Canonical Model I
▶ Even the model with CRRA utility and Cobb-Douglas production function is
relatively messy. Many of the applications use log preferences (θ = 1).
▶ Changes in the interest rate (and thus in the capital-labor ratio of the economy)
have no effect on the saving rate: Income and substitution effects exactly cancel
each other.
▶ Utility of the household and generation t is,
23 / 32
Lecture outline
* Welfare Theorems
* Conclusions
24 / 32
Overaccumulation I
▶ Compare the overlapping-generations equilibrium to the choice of a social planner
wishing to maximize a weighted average of all generations’ utilities.
▶ Suppose that the social planner maximizes
X∞
βSt Ut
t=0
▶ βS is the discount factor of the social planner, which reflects how she values the
utilities of different generations.
▶ Substituting from (1), this implies:
∞
X
βSt (u (c1,t ) + βu (c2,t+1 ))
t=0
subject to the resource constraint
F (Kt , Lt ) = Kt+1 + Lt c1,t + Lt−1 c2,t
▶ Dividing this by Lt and using (2),
c2,t
f (kt ) = (1 + n) kt+1 + c1,t + .
1+n
25 / 32
Overaccumulation II
▶ Social planner’s maximization problem then implies the following first-order
necessary condition:
u ′ (c1,t ) = βf ′ (kt+1 ) u ′ (c2,t+1 ) .
▶ Since Rt+1 = f ′ (kt+1 ), this is identical to (5).
▶ Not surprising: allocate consumption of a given individual in exactly the same way
as the individual himself would do.
▶ No “market failures” in the over-time allocation of consumption at given prices.
▶ However, the allocations across generations may differ from the competitive
equilibrium: planner is giving different weights to different generations
▶ In particular, competitive equilibrium is Pareto suboptimal when k ∗ > kgold ,
26 / 32
Overaccumulation III
▶ When k ∗ > kgold , reducing savings can increase consumption for every generation.
▶ More specifically, note that in steady state
27 / 32
Overaccumulation IV
▶ Now if k ∗ > kgold , then ∂c ∗ /∂k ∗ < 0: reducing savings can increase (total)
consumption for everybody.
▶ If this is the case, the economy is referred to as dynamically inefficient—it
involves overaccumulation.
▶ Another way of expressing dynamic inefficiency is that
r ∗ < n,
28 / 32
Overaccumulation V
▶ Consider the following variation: change next period’s capital stock by −∆k,
where ∆k > 0, and from then on, we immediately move to a new steady state
(clearly feasible).
▶ This implies the following changes in consumption levels:
∆cT = (1 + n) ∆k > 0
= − f ′ (k ∗ − ∆k) − (1 + n) ∆k for all t > T
∆ct
▶ The first expression reflects the direct increase in consumption due to the decrease
in savings.
▶ In addition, since k ∗ > kgold , for small enough ∆k, f ′ (k ∗ − ∆k) − (1 + n) < 0,
thus ∆ct > 0 for all t ≥ T .
▶ The increase in consumption for each generation can be allocated equally during
the two periods of their lives, thus necessarily increasing the utility of all
generations.
29 / 32
Interpretation
▶ Intuition for dynamic inefficiency:
▶ Individuals who live at time t face prices determined by the capital stock with which
they are working.
▶ Capital stock is the outcome of actions taken by previous generations.
▶ Pecuniary externality from the actions of previous generations affecting welfare of
current generation.
▶ Pecuniary externalities typically second-order and do not matter for welfare.
▶ But not when an infinite stream of newborn agents joining the economy are affected.
▶ It is possible to rearrange in a way that these pecuniary externalities can be exploited.
▶ Complementary intuition:
▶ Dynamic inefficiency arises from overaccumulation.
▶ Results from current young generation needs to save for old age.
▶ However, the more they save, the lower is the rate of return and may encourage to
save even more.
▶ Effect on future rate of return to capital is a pecuniary externality on next generation
▶ If alternative ways of providing consumption to individuals in old age were
introduced, overaccumulation could be ameliorated.
30 / 32
Lecture outline
* Welfare Theorems
* Conclusions
31 / 32
Conclusions
▶ Overlapping generations of the more realistic than infinity-lived representative
agents.
▶ Models with overlapping generations fall outside the scope of the First Welfare
Theorem:
▶ they were partly motivated by the possibility of Pareto suboptimal allocations.
▶ Equilibria may be “dynamically inefficient” and feature overaccumulation:
unfunded Social Security can ameliorate the problem.
▶ Overaccumulation and Pareto suboptimality: pecuniary externalities created on
individuals that are not yet in the marketplace.
32 / 32