McCormick Ch. 2
McCormick Ch. 2
Belief as Emotion. Miriam Schleifer Mccormick, Oxford University Press. © Miriam Schleifer McCormick 2025.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198875826.003.0002
16 BELIEF AS EMOTION
1 Some will allow that this cognitive element is a judgment, but others will call these elements
“construals” or “appraisals” of the world being a certain way, so as to stave off the worry of being
overly intellectual. For an overview of the literature and for some ways in which these ingredi-
ents are described, see De Sousa & Scarantino (2021); they end their entry by listing ten points
that emotion theorists agree on; they also state that “most of the dominant accounts in the phil-
osophy of emotions now qualify as hybrids of cognitivist and feeling theories.” For an overview
of the challenges that a number of theories face, see the first chapter of Tappolet (2016).
2 See Helm (2001) for further discussion on this point. He says of emotions that they “are uni-
tary and not compound states of evaluative feeling, states involving elements of both cognition
and conation simultaneously” (2001, 59). Helm realizes that describing emotions as feelings of
this very particular kind runs afoul of the cognitive–conative divide—i.e., the view that all states
must be either one or the other—and argues that the divide should be rejected because an ad-
equate account of the phenomenology of emotions cannot be provided while it remains. I agree,
and one upshot of my view is that an adequate account of the phenomenology of belief cannot be
provided while it remains.
3 Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting this analogy.
BELIEF AS A BLENDED STATE 17
emotions. This is very difficult to account for if they are seen as passive sensa-
tions, akin to having a headache.4
Perhaps the feeling theorist could say there is a primitive feeling of fear
that is only fitting if it is caused by something dangerous, and so if the feeling
4 As Grzankowski puts the problem, “One must not understand emotions in such a way as to
land in incoherence or contradiction, but one must also find room for the sense in which cases
of recalcitrance present inconsistency. Theorists about the emotions must find ‘conflict without
contradiction,’ and this looks to be no easy task” (2020, 503–504).
5 See Tappolet (2016, 37– 38) for a discussion of the plasticity of our emotional systems,
which allows us to influence our emotional dispositions.
6 Milona argues that the charge of irrationality is not appropriate in many cases of recalci-
trant emotions. He says of someone’s reactions in Skywalk that they “don’t seem criticizable.”
That we can explain the subject’s fear by appeal to the functioning of a system developed for
adaptive purposes does not tell us that the subject is immune from criticism. Even if a certain
type of male aggression can be explained by mechanisms that were evolutionarily beneficial,
this would not mean that one displaying such aggression (or even having such aggressive feel-
ings that one fails to act on) is immune from criticism. Milona can respond to this worry by ar-
guing that the male aggression is not well functioning. Even if this disposition toward anger has
evolutionary roots, it doesn’t seem to be the output of dispositions such as to typically produce
accurate representations of value. On his view, “well functioning” goes beyond “adaptive” and is
an irreducibly evaluative term. I find it difficult to make sense of the system “well functioning”
in the Skywalk case, but not the aggression case. In both cases, one has reasons to attenuate one’s
emotions.
18 BELIEF AS EMOTION
7 I am quite confident that Deonna and Teroni’s “attitudinal” theory can accommodate the
idea that beliefs are emotions, given that they are feelings directed toward states of affairs. They
take emotions to be “intimately connected with types of action readiness, or more, precisely, felt
action readiness” (2012, 79). That these feelings of action readiness consist in attitudes that are
felt in the body might seem problematic for my view, but many of the calmer emotions are less
obviously felt in the body, but are still allowed, on their view, to be felt. I will return to a consid-
eration of how their view, as well as some other prominent theories, would describe the emotion
I am calling “belief ” at the end of this chapter.
8 See also Teroni (2007) and Cova & Deonna (2014).
9 At a workshop on an early draft of this book, Aude Bandini suggested I was offering an
“emotion-first” approach to mental states. The various “x-first” projects differ in various ways
but they all take the “x” as being fundamentally explanatory (and often primitive), endorsing a
view that is more ambitious than the one I have here. Cognitive phenomenologists would agree
that feelings cannot be separated from any mental states, but this does not mean they can be re-
duced to them or that all other states can be explained in terms of feelings.
20 BELIEF AS EMOTION
2.1.1 Intentionality
Of the five criteria, I take this to be the least troubling. No one denies that be-
liefs are about something. Indeed, it is a dominant view among theorists of
2.1.2 Motivation
of protection. Also, it is not clear that all emotions need to have any tie to
motivation at all. Most emotion-theorists agree that admiration is an emo-
tion, but does admiring a landscape require that one act at all? More complex
motivation theories try to address this worry by expanding the idea of what
Many (though not all) theorists claim that emotions are distinguished from
one another by what is often called their formal object. The formal object
of fear is danger, though the specific object feared can range from a dog to
escalation of the war in the Middle East. The formal object of anger is some-
thing like offense, but the specific object that angers me can range from my
spouse to the Supreme Court’s decision on abortion. The formal object of be-
lief is accuracy, though the specific object of what is believed can range from
a complex historical argument to simple perception. Why have I identified
the formal object of accuracy and not truth? There is clearly something right
about appealing to truth when identifying the “correctness conditions” of be-
lief; if what you believe can be stated as a proposition, and that proposition
is false, then your belief is faulty. As Bernard Williams puts it, “Truth and
falsehood are a ‘dimension of assessment of beliefs as opposed to many other
psychological states of dispositions’ ” (1973, 136).
An important difference between truth and accuracy is that the latter ad-
mits of degrees. Just as something can be represented as more or less dan-
gerous, and the associated feelings will be more or less strong depending on
22 BELIEF AS EMOTION
10 Wlodek Rabinowicz has recently argued that we should view probability as a value—
namely, as an evaluative property: “it does seem that probability may well be viewed as a value. It
might be noted, by the way, that in the classical Latin probabilis was often used to mean ‘worthy
of approval, pleasing, agreeable, acceptable, commendable, laudable, good, fit.’ That ‘probabilis’
was a term of evaluation must have been evident to the Romans” (2020, 77).
11 Thompson & Morsanyi (2012).
BELIEF AS A BLENDED STATE 23
One may object that the bearer of the evaluative property of accuracy dif-
fers in a significant way from the bearer of the evaluative properties of other
emotions. In the previous paragraph, I said that to believe is to feel some-
thing accurate, but what is this “something”? When I represent the dog as
you can accept the content for practical purposes, and can rely on it being the
case while being prepared for or open to revision.
belief consists not in the peculiar nature or order of ideas, but in the
manner of their conception and in their feeling in the mind. I confess that
12 See Andrew Moon (2018) for an extensive defense of the view that belief and doubt are
compatible. Hawthorne et al. (2016) and Rothschild (2019) argue that much linguistic data sup-
ports the view that the way we ordinarily use the word “belief ” supports the idea that believing
something only requires thinking it likely.
BELIEF AS A BLENDED STATE 25
where I am aware of the sadness or belief. How the awareness is raised will
likely vary in these cases. A picture of my friend or a text from her son may
bring sadness to my attention, while someone asking me what the capital of
Canada is or hearing someone mistakenly say it is Toronto may bring the
Feeling something to be true or accurate sounds like the way the phe-
nomenology of seemings is described. In a recent discussion of the nature of
seemings, McCain and Moretti say this:
In what sense, then, do the lines still seem to be different lengths? Well,
they look like different lengths and so there is a perceptual seeming or ap-
pearance that exerts some kind of force. I think this force is enough to consti-
tute an inclination to believe, given how often one’s sense perceptions reveal
2.1.5 Attention
Those who are impressed with emotions’ role in action have also pointed
out that emotions direct our attention to features of the environment that
are of concern to us. Indeed, some take it that emotions exhibit “control pre-
cedence,” in that when we experience an emotion, it exerts a kind of control
and demand of our attention. This view of emotion is one that can be tied to
the idea that one is “acting emotionally” in a way that shows the emotion to
be dominating, and diminishing of cooler reactions and actions. It seems ob-
vious that we can have many low-level perceptual or background beliefs that
do not command our attention.
It is important to note that this condition poses a problem for “weak”
background emotions, “mild emotions such as light fear,” as well as for ones
of which one is not conscious, and so is controversial among philosophers
of emotion. As Tappolet puts it, “the problem is that there are cases of mild
emotional episodes, which have low control precedence but which nonethe-
less count as emotion” (2023, 81). And so, if there is not a way for beliefs
to satisfy this condition, it would not thereby mean beliefs cannot count as
emotions, if one would not reject the idea that mild emotions are indeed
emotions.
It may be, however, that there are different ways to think about attention
which would allow both beliefs and other “weak” emotions to contain this
feature. This idea has recently been introduced by Stephane Lemaire (2022),
13 Yet, once aware of the illusion, one might think that there is an intellectual seeming that re-
who distinguishes between the object of the emotion being made salient
on the one hand and the object being one on which we focus on the other
Attention as salience, in this context, refers not to the focus of attention on
the object, but to the object functioning as a stimulus or trigger of the emo-
I have now shown how beliefs can satisfy the criteria that many take as ne-
cessary for a state to be categorized as an emotion. These are necessary but
likely not sufficient conditions, so this discussion has only shown that there
is no obvious barrier to belief ’s inclusion based on widely accepted criteria
for what counts as an emotion. The rest of this book will show how this clas-
sification can bear a lot of theoretical fruit. Before turning to how viewing be-
liefs as emotions can help us resist non-doxasticism in a number of domains,
and can illuminate some puzzling phenomena in the doxastic realm, I will
address some further questions and concerns, and consider how some prom-
inent theories of emotion would each characterize belief.
thinking has a certain feel, so maybe the dividing line is not as clear. For em-
bodied beings, it may be that pure thought is not a possibility. Still, I think
there are differences between beliefs as I have been describing them, and
other states that are usually included on the cognitive side—ones that do not
14 I discuss what kind of control we have over belief in Schleifer McCormick (2011; 2015, ch.
6). For a recent discussion that brings up some problems with my view, see Osbourne (2021).
BELIEF AS A BLENDED STATE 31
(ii) If beliefs are emotions, can the reasons to hold them be universal?
There seem to be logical relations between beliefs that do not hold
between emotions.
An important difference one may see between beliefs and emotions has to
Kelly argues, however, that when it comes to beliefs, we cannot make similar
assumptions: “there is simply no cognitive goal or goals, which is plausible
to attribute to people generally, which is sufficient to account for the relative
phenomena. Individuals do not typically have this goal: believing the truth”
believe, even when such beliefs are inferred from or based on other consid-
erations (which may be other beliefs), can be done in an automatic manner
and to reconstruct what takes place in such mental transitions as something
akin to an explicit argument with premises and conclusions is misleading.
arguments: “I am not here talking about inference as argument: that is as a set of propositions,
with some designated as ‘premises’ and one designated as the ‘conclusion’. I am talking about in-
ference as reasoning, as the psychological transition from one (for example) belief to another”
(2019, 101).
16 Jonathan Way (2016) defends this view.
17 For more detail on the view of how beliefs can be based on non-e vidential reasons, see
18 This claim should be somewhat qualified. If artificial intelligence reaches a point where
It is this last feature of belief which led Bernard Williams to claim that ma-
chines cannot have beliefs. He imagines a machine which can gather infor-
mation from its environment, and print out propositions, and has a device
which distinguishes between true propositions and ones that are only hy-
19 Siri is the name of Apple’s “assistant” that provides Iphone users with information
when asked.
20 When I asked Chat-GTP if it has beliefs, the answer was “no,” but it claimed to have a lot of
22 There has been substantial push back to the idea that mental representations are best
claim: namely, that one can believe something one knows is false. This does not seem possible.
If you believe something that can be stated in the form of the proposition, then you take it to be
true. You can recognize that it is possible it is false, but you cannot know that it is false.
BELIEF AS A BLENDED STATE 37
displays a kind of normative defect. Beliefs, like fears, if central and powerful,
can persist even when one’s reflective evaluations indicate one should not
believe as one does. Consider someone who has grown up in a fundamen-
talist tradition and believes that the Bible is literally true. This person may
dispositions will not do. We sometimes run away or attack out of fear, but
what we do when we experience fear is of course much more varied” (91).
Rather, she argues emotions give us reasons for action but often such action
will result from an agent deliberating and deciding what to do, if anything.
2.4 Summary