批判藝術教育學:後現代藝術教育的基礎Critical Art Pedagogy - Foundations for Postmodern Art Education (PDFDrive)
批判藝術教育學:後現代藝術教育的基礎Critical Art Pedagogy - Foundations for Postmodern Art Education (PDFDrive)
RICHARD CARY
First published by Garland Publishing, Inc.
Routledge Routledge
Taylor & Francis Group Taylor & Francis Group
711 Third Avenue 2 Park Square, Milton Park
New York, N Y 10017 Abingdon, Oxon 0X14 4RN
Chapter Two 63
A Critical History of Art Education:
Dangerous Memories and Critical Consciousness
Resources 345
Index 357
CRITICAL ART PEDAGOGY
Chapter One
Critical Theory:
A Philosophy for Praxis in Art Education
Critical Consciousness
The mind of critical theory develops critiques of social condi-
tions based on analyses that responded to what John Dewey
(1933) called, "a felt difficulty." Perception of problematic
social conditions or discernment of injustices do not emerge
spontaneously in the natural order of things. A critical con-
sciousness develops out of and then applies an awareness of
the malign effects of coercive illusions, structures often so
deeply embedded in social experience as to be invisible there.
A critical consciousness is attuned to such deeply embedded
forms of injustice as those that emanate from racial, gender or
class distinctions. Thus, critical pedagogy aims to create then
expand critical consciousness as a form of knowledge. Critical
pedagogy provides one intervention that fosters critical con-
sciousness. Critical art pedagogy conceives of ways to engage
art so as to promote critical consciousness. Embracing the
postmodern concept of art's value and meaning as socially
contextualized and relational instead of autonomous is one of
critical art pedagogy's primary strategies.
Deconstruction
Deconstruction, a major intellectual asset of the mind of
critical theory, is one means by which critical analysis illumi-
nates tacit coercive conditions. French philosopher Jacques
Derrida (1982), who has developed the most comprehensive
statements about deconstruction, advocates its use as a
method of intellectual analysis for creating critical awareness
and engaging in critical resistance. Deconstruction unveils
those hidden influences that have shaped knowledge by identi-
fying, questioning and subverting false dichotomies called
"binary oppositions." Deconstruction acknowledges no such
22 Critical Art Pedagogy
Mass Culture
The application of those naive Marxist theories that resulted
in the Stalinist version of Communism recognized the power
of art. The Marxist theory of zhdanovism stipulates that the
elite can use art, music, theater, dance, and similar cultural
forms as instruments for controlling the masses (Berger,
1995). In the Stalinist era, this theory became the basis for
the policy that art should serve only the interests of the state.
A vapid, poster-like style of social realism ensued. It cele-
brated by literal visual depiction the heroics of Communist
workers and glorified labor as service to the people and the
Soviet state.
Neo-Marxism, of course, rejects the Communist embodi-
ment of zhdanovism, yet retains the concept as theory.
Particularly through its emergence from the Frankfurt School
as an influence on contemporary critical theory, neo-Marxism
underscores the idea that art and other cultural forms may
indeed take on ideological functions, especially in a capitalist
society. Further, the assignment of ideological functions often
proceeds tacitly. The purpose of incorporating ideological
function in an art form is to maintain the status quo a socio-
politico-economic hierarchy prefers by covertly manipulating
or suppressing critical awareness among the people. Contem-
porary critical theorists recognize that this concept works
most effectively in mass culture and the mass media. Critical
art pedagogy recognizes that traditional art education serves
as a vector of this type of control.
Among neo-Marxism's contributions to critical art peda-
gogy is its suspicion of the mass media, especially with regard
to their promotion of consumer mindsets and escapist enter-
tainment. These effects obscure the need to develop critical
consciousness and distract people from the task of revealing
and resisting tacit hegemonizing structures, especially in such
institutions as schools, museums, and other aspects of the art
world. B y unconsciously and uncritically acquiescing in the
blandishments of a corrupt mass media, people develop the
habit of conformity and eventually, they loose the will, vision
and means to become critical agents.
By providing the means to challenge the colonizing influ-
ences of the mass media, critical art pedagogy and other
Critical Theory 45
Class
The construct of class is fundamental to neo-Marxist social
and educational criticism. "Class" refers to the formation of
subgroups of people according to their economic resources.
Thus, class is influenced by the theory of base-superstructure
relations. Whereas the base determines class membership,
particular cultural characteristics and other aspects of super-
structure tend to be associated with each class so as to
differentiate it from other classes. For example, education,
dietary practices, recreational pursuits, vocational choices,
artistic and aesthetic preferences—these are distinguishing
features of classes shaped by economic resources.
Neo-Marxist social criticism focuses on those inequalities
among classes that result from an unequal distribution of
wealth and power. Nason (1992) estimated that 1 percent of
the U . S . population controls 40 percent of the country's
wealth. Critical theorists embrace this neo-Marxist theme to
challenge the popular myths that opportunities to succeed are
equally open to all, that justice disregards class, that educa-
tional achievement is accessible to everyone, and that hard
work can overcome class-bound limitations if the worker is
motivated and talented enough.
This last myth, a residual effect of nineteenth century
social Darwinism, explains the insidious, disingenuous, com-
mon-sense wisdom that those who fail simply lack the
necessary ability, values and determination. Furthermore, as
Berger (1995) observed, this belief may lead to the conclusion
that such forms of governmental or institutional support as
educational support for lower income groups are unnecessary,
wasteful, and ineffective since, with equal opportunity, people
succeed and people fail because of their individual merit. This
belief often infects the classroom where teachers' expecta-
tions of and attention to individual students often reflects
their class differences.
Rosenthall and Jacobson (1968) conducted an experiment
in which teachers at the Oak-Hall School were told that some
students identified by a specious test that Rosenthall and
46 Critical Art Pedagogy
Alienation
Economic inequity produces another problem of interest to
contemporary critique: alienation. In a society dominated by a
bourgeoisie, workers gradually lose their sense of connection
to a class identity, to other workers, to the elite classes, and
to work itself. Work ceases to be a source of meaning or plea-
sure when the worker becomes a tool for economic production
destined to benefit the bourgeoisie far more than the worker.
The alienation economic inequalities produce is both a
social and a psychological phenomenon. For the individual,
alienation is an emotionally palpable experience that Berger
(1995) described as a feeling of hollowness. Seeking to
mitigate the effects of alienation—to fill the internal void it
creates—the individual distracts himself or herself with such
jollifying strategies of the consumer culture as commodity
48 Critical Art Pedagogy
Interpellation
Cultural forms like the visual arts, the mass media, and school-
ing tend to incorporate ideological commitments and then
covertly pass them on to participants. From an earlier age,
Critical Theory 49
Hegemony
Hegemony is a process closely related to interpellation. In the
neo-Marxist context, Antonio Gramsci first used this term,
and it now appears frequently in contemporary critical dis-
course (Berger, 1995). Its original meaning referred to the
domination of one sovereign state by another. Applied to
culture and society, "hegemony" is the process of dominating
or controlling groups of people so that they unconsciously
assent to and participate in their own domination. Its victims
consider their situations to be the natural order of things.
Hegemony pervades the entire culture and social structure and
operates in the everyday lives of us all. It is far more amor-
phous, widespread, and embedded than interpellation. But both
are the instruments of cultural imperialism.
Cultural Imperialism
"Cultural imperialism" refers to the imposition of bourgeois
values, particularly those common in the contemporary U.S.,
on people who do not share them. The United States wages
cultural imperialism surreptitiously by exporting its popular
culture, including art, films, music, advertizing, styles of
clothing, fast food, and so forth. These colonizing com-
modities often masquerade as signs of progress, modernity, or
generous wealth sharing. One problem with cultural imperi-
alism is that the colonized cultures, typically fragile and lack-
ing the means of resistance, become distorted and dependent.
Ideology
The Marxist concept of ideology represents yet another point
that differentiates neo-Marxist critique from the earlier inter-
pretations of Marxist theory that culminated in totalitarian
50 Critical Art Pedagogy
(1974) and Arthur Danto (1981). Dickie's book Art and the
Aesthetic and Danto's The Transfiguration of the Common-
place, along with his many articles and essays, develop the
theoretical construct of the artworld. Institutional theory
describes the social transaction by which an object gains desig-
nation as art. A n object is art because of the context in which
it is encountered or presented. Dickie referred to the art world
as "the rich structure" which serves as the context for particu-
lar art objects. Danto called the artworld an "atmosphere of
artistic theory." A n artifact is accepted as art by the con-
sensus of two groups, the presentation group and the art world
public. Dickie resorted to theater for a metaphor: It takes
"both sides of the footlights," the players and the expectant
audience, to have a play. The presentation group includes the
artist, the maker of the artifact who intends it to be classified
as art. The artworld public includes persons such as art
historians, curators, gallery owners, critics, and others knowl-
edgeable about art.
Institutional theory stipulates that both parties be more or
less knowledgeable about and experienced with art, its theories
and history. Prior knowledge and experience provide the bases
for defining a newly encountered artifact as an art object. The
art world supplies an interaction between personal experience
and broad-based cultural determinants. It brings to its
appraisals the personal experience of culturally determined
foundations on which knowledge, attitude, and perceptions
about art are constructed. It supplies a paradigm, a predis-
position, and a set of precedents that enable one to recognize
and experience art—to make sense of an object as art.
Institutional theory conceives of art as an open concept,
a fuzzy set, or—in Wittgenstein's terminology, which we
discussed earlier—a family resemblance concept in which a set
or class or category is composed of members that may share
differing amounts of particular traits or characteristics. N o
one ingredient is essential for inclusion in that class, and
institutional theory does not require formalist, visual, or other
physically observable criteria to confer the status of art on an
object. Likewise, it stipulates no conditions before an observer
can feel a certain aesthetic emotion or some other internal
response. Institutional theory admits that formal properties
Critical Theory 57
Introduction
As we saw in Chapter One, the heart and mind of critical
theory are the two principle foundations upon which art educa-
tors and students can build new understandings that will lead to
the creation of a critical arts pedagogy and its application in
their classrooms. The critical practice of art education will, in
turn, grant art educators and art students a more influential
voice in contemporary educational discourse. A third founda-
tion for art educators in the postmodern era is a critical
knowledge of art education's history. A critical history of art
education imbues art teachers, their students, and others
involved in the project of establishing art as critical praxis
with dangerous memories. A dangerous memory—recall that
Henry Giroux coined the expression—is the critical awareness
of the historical roots of a discipline, including all the implicit
and explicit influences that shaped current conditions. This
form of memory often establishes the rationale for a radical
re-conceptualization of education and a new visualization of
its possibilities for the future. Chapter One identified and
discussed three forms of student art-world colonization. Re-
sponses to these vectors of hegemony inform a critical ver-
sion of the history of art education.
To particularize the general thesis of critical historical
analysis, traditional art instruction occupies a place in the
school culture and curriculum commensurate with the extent
to which art instruction can help dominant groups achieve
various non-art educational outcomes. Further, the eco-
nomically and politically powerful groups inclined to co-opt
64 Critical Art Pedagogy
of art and criteria for aesthetic and critical values changed ac-
cordingly. Thus, the interests of elite groups influenced the
curricular status of art instruction. Art and art instruction was
valued most highly when those in power could use it to
achieve socio-economic and political purposes congruent with
their interests. Consequently, social institutions and practices
evolved that provided control over the arts. These included
patronage systems, art education, and various forms of
outright censorship. Throughout the history of art and art
education, the effectiveness of each and the interrelationships
between them continually changed. What remained constant
was an oligarchic authority over these controls, and their un-
broken association with dominant groups or powerful indivi-
duals provides valuable insight for a critical history of art
education.
ideal state only those artists and poets whose art glorified the
gods and celebrated the deeds of good men and heroes. For
Plato, then, the one type of art with value was the art that
helped maintain social control and sustain the power structure
by avoiding any emotional arousal and by celebrating those
who maintained the hierarchy and those few at its apex. Advo-
cates of the critical theory perspective argue that concepts
like "good men," "wisdom," "rational social action," do not
qualify as absolutes. Rather, the power elite construe them so
that they form the keystone of hegemony. These problematic
power relations were hardly unique to Plato's Republic. In
fact, they operate throughout the history of art and art
education as factors that promote its marginalization.
Plato realized that art functions as a social institution and
has deeply rooted interrelationships with other elements of
the social-political complex. It does not exist independently
on a rarefied plane remote from human experience. Thus, a
second important point in Plato's theory of art is that art is a
socially grounded phenomenon. Engaging in art, especially
through critical art pedagogy, can have consequences, out-
comes, effects, and implications for those outside the art
world. When viewed in this way, as a socio-political institu-
tion, art possesses the capacity to promote agency. It can be a
cause, an instrument, a determinant, a means of inciting
action toward emancipatory ends. Plato viewed this property
with suspicion. But contemporary art educators interested in
developing a critical arts pedagogy see the ability to promote
agency as a positive feature. The idea of agency through art is
an essential feature of critical instrumentalism and a key
function of critical art pedagogy.
Aristotle also saw in art a potential for social control. But
in the Poetics, the compilation of his aesthetic ideas written
between 347 and 342 B.C., Aristotle seems somewhat more
optimistic than Plato in his regard for art's potential in
human affairs. Aristotle's word "catharsis" refers to a psychic
power in tragic poetry to release negative emotional energy.
This emotional release benefitted the individual and, in turn,
society.
Aristotle's concept of leisure provides an early example
of the awareness that art and art education could be valued for
A Critical History of Art Education 71
The Renaissance
The Renaissance brought intellectual and social changes that
engendered a new concept of the artist's role, and these
changes have significant implications for a critical analysis of
the history of art education. N o longer anonymous workmen,
Renaissance artists such as Michelangelo, Leonardo, and
Raphael, gained renown as individual geniuses possessed of spe-
cial skills and unique understandings. The new artists modeled
themselves after the humanist scholars of the day rather than
the workmen of the guilds. Albrecht Durer was such a new
artist. After visiting Italy in 1494 and 1495, he followed the
model of the artist as a humanist gentleman-scholar and em-
braced the concept of art as an intellectually engaged activity
belonging to the liberal arts (Janson, 1991). Humanists, of
course, considered the world and the place of human thought
and experience in it important sources of truth. Such humanist
scholars such as Ficino, whose patrons included members of
the Medici family, celebrated great artists as god-like geniuses
in their powers of creation and expression. This proposition
stood in stark contrast to the artist-as-craft-worker model of
the guild system and monasteries. Thus, artists became indi-
viduals permitted to design, execute, and sign their names to
works of art.
The recognition of an individual artist's involvement in
the composition of the artwork obviously changed—and en-
hanced—the artist's role. Another important change was an
acknowledgment of the role of the artist's passion or
creativity. Only the greatest artists could boast the quality of
terribilita, the capacity to feel sublime, divine emotion and
the forcefulness to channel it into artistic expression.
74 Critical Art Pedagogy
Moral Instrumentalism
The critical perspective recognizes another significant ele-
ment implicit in the art world changes during the Renaissance.
Leone Battista Alberti's book, On Painting (1435) set forth
new criteria for art, and one of them stressed the association
between the artistic and intellectual domains. Alberti specified
that an artwork should have an istoria, a theme or story from
classical or theological literature. The acceptance of this pro-
A Critical History of Art Education 75
Academies of Art
The new concepts of art and the role of the Renaissance artist
ultimately failed to foster an egalitarian art education,
especially in terms of access to instruction. The new concepts
also failed to advance art education toward authenticity,
engagement with art as a valued component of human ex-
perience, or the production of art works with aesthetic
properties associated with increased critical awareness and
emancipation.
In 1562, Georgio Vasari founded a Florentine academy of
art specifically to develop artists to take the places of the
great masters like Michelangelo, Leonardo and Raphael.
Vasari intended to train artists by having them imitate the
great masters in mechanical ways, and he devised then codified
a system of rules based on the art of the great Renaissance
masters (Efland, 1990). Another academy established by the
Caracci brothers in Bologna also featured rigid codes of art
instruction based on absolute rules drawn from undisputed
authorities. But these academies ultimately failed to advance
art and to train artists to produce art for their patrons. In
fact, "mannerism," a term reflecting Vasari's attempts to
teach his students to produce art "in the manner of. . . ,"
became a derogatory term for that group of sixteenth century
painters who sought to imitate Michelangelo and others. For
the most part, art historians and critics consider mannerist art
inferior to that of the high Renaissance. Those who take the
critical perspective when analyzing art education notice that
the aesthetic quality of art declines with its increased use as an
76 Critical Art Pedagogy
Schools of Design
In 1836, the British Parliament agreed to appropriate funds to
establish the Normal School of Design, with William Dyce as
director. As Gustave Waagen had recommended, the school
followed the German system with its clear distinction between
art and craft. Parliament clearly intended for the arts to sup-
port business and industry, a priority that governed not only
who received instruction, but also whether that instruction
emphasized high art or the lowly crafts. Accordingly, the
Normal School of Design reproduced and sustained the social
stratifications that initially determinant sorted out students
suitable for each type of instruction. Art historians find no
indication that Parliament mentioned the educational and
A Critical History of Art Education 83
get one a job. Today, art—at least our latest version of it—is
often considered a frill of little use in accomplishing what
many consider the mission of schooling—that is, educating
students to get jobs. This is, of course, the so-called common-
sense (or pragmatic) view of schooling's purpose that unravels
under the scrutiny of critical consciousness. The question of
whose interests actually take priority when education ascribes
to the job relevance rationale has a disquieting answer.
Although economic instrumentalism began to loose status
as the predominant rationale for art in the schools, its effects
remain deeply embedded in practice. As scholars like Spring,
Bowles, and Gintis have shown, the use of all subjects in
schooling, art included, for economic and political purposes
quite removed from the goal of the education of the individual
is an entrenched structural reality today.
Conclusion
Teachers, students, artists, scholars, and others concerned
with the institution of art instruction in our contemporary
culture can create the time and space for change by reflecting
on the history of art education, particularly a history pre-
sented from the critical theory perspective. A history that
looks beyond the celebration of the colonizing functions of
power becomes a dangerous memory and sets the stage for an
art education praxis that transcends the dichotomy between
theory and practice characterizing an art education con-
scripted into the service of economic or power interests.
Dangerous memories are awakened in particular places and
times, not by official accounts published, certified, then
shelved in libraries. A critical art education praxis—a critical
art pedagogy—begins with the evocation of dangerous
memories among individuals in actual living contexts.
The dangerous memory and critical consciousness are
essential foundations of critical art pedagogy. Teachers,
students, and others involved in establishing a critical art
pedagogy can access both by incorporating into their practice
some knowledge of the critical history of art education.
Critical art pedagogy does not seek to replace economic instru-
mentalism and moral instrumentalism with a case-hardened
new official model for practice. Nor does it seek to isolate
itself from social, political, and historical processes. Instead, it
seeks to evoke a sense of "critical instrumentalism" and
encourage the subversion of oppressive models of practice.
Chanter Three
Language
Language is another theme of cognitive psychology that
promises meaningful contributions for developing the
theoretical foundations of a critical arts pedagogy. Both
spoken and written language involve human functions crucial
to cognition's role in artistic experience. Both forms of
language permit communication between and among human
beings. Both forms allow one to store information beyond the
present and in amounts larger than the capacity of memory.
Language also provides symbols and the procedures for using
them to construct and convey meaning. In essence, language
provides the content and the structure of thinking.
Psychologists and other scholars and researchers have
identified the components of oral language, and the most basic
component is the phoneme. In fact, phonemes are the most
basic unit of language. They are the sounds that differentiate
words from one another. In the set of words hog, dog, jog and
bog, the h, d,j and b are phonemes. Typically, phonemes
have no meanings per se. When one combines sound units in
114 Critical Art Pedagogy
cant. One can observe the social forces that impinge on the
individual's experience in the particular context.
typically says that the taller container holds more than the
shorter one holding the same amount. A n older child will
typically identify them as equal. Cognitive psychologists like
Piaget and Jerome Bruner pointed out that for one to under-
stand the equality of the differently shaped volumes, signifi-
cant higher order mental processing must take place. They
held that this processing extends beyond simple perception.
Arnheim (1974) agreed that higher order mental processing
takes place when the child realizes that the differently shaped
volumes are identical. He maintained, however, that rather
than being transcended, perception remains a critical part of
this thinking process. The better explanation is that the older
child has acquired an ability to take into account multiple
perceptions, in this case height and width, and use them
interactively. The height and width of the container are both
visual perceptions. The thinking processes, Arnheim main-
tained, never abandon perceptual functioning. Thinking
cannot occur separately from perception. Arnheim's motto
became "Perception equals conception."
Rudolf Arnheim's ideas are valuable as a foundation for
critical arts pedagogy because he demonstrated that engage-
ment in art—including art production, criticism, aesthetics,
and history—involve the same kinds of higher order cognitive
processes once exclusively assigned to supposedly more
intellectual and "basic" academic subjects such as math,
science, and history. The connection between perception and
conception is most readily accessed by the arts. In fact,
Arnheim's (1969) pipe-dream version of the ideal university
curriculum consisted of only three subjects: philosophy,
poetry, and studio art. Philosophy would provide training in
logic, art would refine thinking processes, and poetry would
invest students with a language suitable for thinking in visual
images.
Although Arnheim presented his curriculum with some
irony, he hoped educators would consider his musings a serious
resource. His work now invites critical educators to challenge
two undesirable conditions in today's schools: (1) the rele-
gation of the arts to the margins of the curriculum on the
questionable bases fashioned from positivist research driven by
economic interests of favored groups; and (2) the primacy
Psychologies for Critical Art Pedagogy 139
New Psychologies
A great deal of scholarly effort has been expended attacking
behaviorism, so much that a lengthy examination of its short-
comings tailored for teachers interested in critical art peda-
gogy is quite unnecessary. With its myopic exclusion of all but
observable and quantifiable outward behaviors, behaviorism has
long dominated the field and, in so doing, has compromised
psychology's theoretical contribution to educational practice.
It now stands revealed as incapable of promoting critical art
pedagogy's aim of engaging students with art and the art world
so as to achieve critical awareness and emancipation. Beha-
viorism provides a description of the learner which is too
impoverished for inclusion in the foundations of critical art
pedagogy. It is vapid and incomplete at best. It is misleading
and malfeasant at worst. In short, it lacks ecological validity
—that is to say, any relevance to real life. It fails to
acknowledge the complexities that people living their lives
experience. At least part of the failure of behaviorism's contri-
bution to education lies in its lack of an appropriate approach
to aesthetic experience and cognitive operations. Reductionis-
ts, mechanistic approaches to human affairs like behaviorism
invariably preclude access to the fullness of life experience.
As behaviorism's narrow concepts lost their allure, and as
cognitive models of mind emerged, psychologists, educators,
and other consumers of theory-based research began to realize
that meaning, not behavior, was the essence of, the funda-
mental unit of learning. A n increasingly important subject of
inquiry in psychology is, for want of a better term, "psycho-
logical epistemology." Psychological epistemology differs
from learning theory, which operates at a more applied level
and preoccupies itself with understanding learning as behavi-
146 Critical Art Pedagogy
Narrative Psychology
A temptation always arise to confuse narrative psychology
with "grand narrative," the self authorized, hegemonic "group-
think" tacitly imposed on society as the official version of the
way things are and that critical pedagogy seeks to subvert. B y
contrast, the basic idea of narrative psychology is that
narrative—that is to say, a story—is fundamental in human
mental life. Much of what we "know," what we accept as
knowledge, comes to us in the form of stories. Not surprising-
ly, narrative psychology includes a number of definitions of
narrative. But for our present purposes, we can assume nar-
rative to be a communicable description of experiences in-
volving meaning formation. Thought, or knowledge making,
is a form of storytelling. The mind's structure and features
result from meanings formed in the structure of a narrative.
The individual's internal cognitive representations of experi-
ences in the world take the form of narrative. Narratives
occur in our everyday lives as well in cultural artifacts like
154 Critical Art Pedagogy
Discursive Psychology
Discursive psychology shares with narrative psychology and
architectonic psychology the post-positivist and post-beha-
viorist sensibility which focuses on mind and meaning rather
than on the reductionistic operationalization of observable
behaviors. Language, and particularly its cognitive aspects, is
central to both the narrative and discursive perspectives.
But discursive psychology and narrative psychology differ
in several ways. Narrative psychology views human experi-
ence as a story or verbal representation of sequenced events.
These events may be independent from agency—that is,
external to the individual. The question of agency is
secondary in narrative psychology. Discursive psychology, by
contrast, views the individual as an actor-agent who drives the
creation of narrative through the actions of discourse. As
agent, the individual engages in purposive communication
with others. The former psychology proposes a script-writing
model; the latter proposes one that resembles extempora-
neous acting.
Another difference between discursive and most other
systems of psychology, especially the traditional ones, is that
it declines to view discursive phenomena as outward manifesta-
tions of an individual's deeper psyche. Instead, discursive acts
Psychologies for Critical A r t Pedagogy 165
positivist research methods, yet they can still enrich our pro-
fessional understanding and practice.
This "style of research" terminology connotes a
deliberately considered conglomeration of characteristics that
operates like a family-resemblance category. No single charac-
teristic is absolutely requisite for membership; but each mem-
ber possesses several features that resemble the features of
other members. Stylistic characteristics cluster in more or less
consistent ways, but, as in art, they freely vary and assume
novel configurations.
In critical art pedagogy, we think of research styles as per-
spectives leading to knowledge formation. As the plural form
suggests, critical art pedagogy promises to rely on a multi-
plicity of research styles intended to be interactively deployed
by individuals engaged in the pursuit of dangerous knowledge
through art and about art. As the art world admits a multi-
plicity of art styles, the conjunction between it and critical
pedagogy must admit a multiplicity of knowledge styles.
Critical art pedagogy also guards against the threat that one
research style will become a meta-style or grand method. Each
style of research may be enacted in a different way in dif-
ferent contexts.
"Style of research" is also an apt term in critical arts
pedagogy also because its open-endedness is analogous to the
open-endedness of art styles. Style in art is, of course, a
construct that assumes different meanings at different times.
But in general, it operates in an open-ended way, which means
that resemblance to the familiar and the possibility of the
novel coexist and mutually define one another. Stylistic resem-
blance among art works changes as new works are produced.
Styles merge, emerge, and become passe.
We would probably prefer this "research style" phrasing i f
only because it implies agency for participants in the art
education setting. Styles of both art production and knowledge
production amount to perspectives or tendencies toward ac-
tion or dialogue instead of prescribed steps to follow. Style
implies engagement in processes of making or becoming or
happening.
Finally, in critical art pedagogy, the research methodology
and teaching methodology domains interact. Research is an
Semiotics, Deconstruction, and Qualitative M e t h o d o l o g y 185
Semiotics
The research style known as semiotics can certainly contri-
bute to this foundation for critical practice in art education.
Critical practice in education incorporates the postmodern
concept that education, like other academic disciplines, should
be described as a dialogue, as opposed to a set of rules
governing practice. This section reviews and explicates
selected important concepts of semiotics, locates its philo-
sophical and historical roots, and explores its implications for
critical art pedagogy.
The term "semiotics" derives from semeion, the Greek
word meaning "sign." Semiotics, then, is the study of signs—
namely, how we use them to communicate, and how they em-
body meaning in the culture. "Semiosis" is the set of pro-
cesses, operations, actions, and interplay of signs (Deeley,
1990). The awareness that signs, like implicit meanings, are
ubiquitous in our lives is fundamental to critical art pedagogy.
In a sense, an overriding concern in any critical pedagogy is
Semiotics, Deconstruction, and Qualitative Methodology 189
C.S. P i e r c e
The work of Charles Sanders Pierce (1839-1914) marks the
beginning of modern semiotics. Unlike his precursors whose
semiotic thought was typically ancillary to other philoso-
phical inquiries, Pierce approached the project of semiotics as
a subject worthy of serious sustained philosophical analysis in
and of itself. Although now recognized as one of America's
most influential intellects, Pierce remained largely unknown in
his lifetime, working for years as a scientist with the U . S.
Geological Survey and writing philosophy in his spare time.
Mentioned briefly in Ogden and Richard's influential treat-
ment of semantics, The M e a n i n g of M e a n i n g (1923), Pierce's
semiotics was brought into the mainstream of linguistics by
Semiotics, Deconstruction, and Qualitative Methodology 2 0 9
F e r d i n a n d de Saussure
Whereas C. S. Pierce's semiotics originated within a philoso-
phical perspective, Ferdinand de Saussure approached semio-
tics as subsidiary of linguistics. Saussure is regarded as the
father of modern linguistics for his work in that field, but his
contributions to modern semiotics are usually considered less
consequential than those of Pierce. Saussure lived from 1857
212 Critical Art Pedagogy
Deconstruction
Among the barriers to understanding deconstruction, the tacit
assumptions and expectations that accompany typical descrip-
tions of traditional research methodologies, both qualitative
and quantitative, may be the greatest. Deconstruction eschews
a bounded set of concepts and procedures arranged into a
sequence of steps designed to answer a narrowly defined re-
search question. Instead, deconstruction provides a general
S e m i o t i c s , D e c o n s t r u c t i o n , a n d Q u a l i t a t i v e M e t h o d o l o g y 215
like all texts, of signs. These signs, like all signs, legitimately
assume multiple meanings. These meanings, like all meanings,
do not depend on a single author-artist. Communication, even
including communication in the modalities of visual art, re-
quires an interpreter-viewer-reader. Thus, we cannot assume
beauty—like its counterparts absolute truth, final interpreta-
tion, and summary meaning—to be self-evident or to operate
beyond the interplay of signs. In the text of landscape, signs
must become animate in experience to be interpreted as
beauty. Beauty is a process, an activity suffused with the inter-
play of signs.
Remember that deconstruction does not deny the pos-
sibility of the experience of beauty in nature or anywhere else.
Instead, its goal is to show how we take the experience of beau-
ty for granted, and how distorted assumptions about beauty
can lie beneath its surface.
As the landscape genre sought to access beauty in nature,
the distinction grew more marked between sites of lived experi-
ence and the idealized visions of nature "out there" portrayed
in landscape art. The ineffable, the sublime, the exalted in
landscape art contrast forcefully with the ordinary, the com-
monplace, the mundane, and the undifferentiated tedium of
quotidian reality. Mirroring Derrida's PRESENCE-absence, the
binary opposition THERE-here becomes a perturbing factor in
landscape art. Nature is split by the binary opposition the
problematic concept of beauty produces. This re-ordering of
nature into a hierarchy has also produced the wilderness
construct which, in association with the concept of beauty, is
implicated in a number of serious contemporary problems,
especially environmental crises.
This root hierarchy in landscape art has many variations:
REMOTE-accessible, NOVEL-familiar, NATURAL GRANDEUR-banali-
ty, PICTURESQUE T E R R A I N TO PRESERVE-wasteland to exploit,
NATURE-urban environment, and N A T U R E WHERE H U M A N S ARE
FOREIGNERS-nature where humans are interested partners.
Barry Lopez (1990) described the binary opposition impli-
cit in the concept of wilderness as HOLY GROUND-profane
ground. As one of its deleterious consequences, the myth of
wilderness invites the ruinous exploitation of the profane
grounds. Since profane grounds tend not to be breathtakingly
Semiotics, Deconstruction, and Qualitative Methodology 231
The codes we glean from our art world provides the means to
interpret them. Recent art produced by digitally manipulating
photographic images oddly juxtaposes the certainty of visual
witness with conceptual skepticism. The cliche "Seeing is
believing" becomes "I see this, but it may not be real." As a
result, we can no longer take for granted the literalness of
photographs, i f we ever could. Digital imaging presents a
widespread legitimation crisis. The recognition that photo-
graphs present unreliable representations of reality formerly
circulated among only a small intelligentsia. Now, it is be-
coming common knowledge. Virtually everyone in the popu-
lar culture learns to doubt the adage, "Seeing is believing."
O f course, from the critical perspective, we realize that
photographs actually never were entirely truthful renderings.
They record subjective selections, and the transcendental van-
tage point for determining visual truth in photographs was
itself a mirage. The realizations emerging from a critical
appraisal of the new digital photographic art exemplify the ap-
plication of deconstruction to art and art learning. This
application also furnishes an example of the idea that the
privileged member of a binary opposition contains a trace of
its supplementary member. The binary opposition SCIENTIFIC
A N D TECHNOLOGICAL KNOWLEDGE-art is so widely accepted that
it is practically a shibboleth in education and society. But
digital photographic art exploits contemporary computer
technology in order to produce disconcerting, perturbing,
fantastic, subtle illusions instead of the uncontestable cold,
hard truths once assumed to issue reliably from the domain of
scientific and technical objectivity. Consequently, this develop-
ment calls into question the visual terms of reality, objectivity
and truth. We can not trust even photographs anymore. The
SCIENTIFIC A N D T E C H N O L O G I C A L element's inevitable self-
betrayal thus undermines the hierarchical relationship of the
binary opposition.
The presence of deconstruction and semiotics among the
theoretical foundations of critical art pedagogy commits it
fully to the concept of the visual art object as text. A c -
cordingly, teachers and students must consciously reject ac-
culturated tendencies to look for the absolutes of the a r c h e -
d e s i g n and the a r c h e - a e s t h e t i c . A critical consciousness about
Semiotics, Deconstruction, and Qualitative Methodology 237
1. D e f i n i t i o n s of Q u a l i t a t i v e r e s e a r c h
Jacob (1987) suggested that the attempts to enunciate a
general definition of qualitative research covering all the
varied types has produced a confusion that has, in turn, dimin-
ished its legitimacy relative to the quantitative paradigm. This
diversity is evident in Bogdan and Biklen's (1982) definition
of qualitative research. They delineate its parts, characterizing
qualitative research as an umbrella term that subsumes a
number of strategies for knowledge making that happen to
share certain features. These features most often include par-
ticipant observation, lengthy interviews, case studies, field or
Semiotics, Deconstruction, a n d Qualitative Methodology 241
2. P h i l o s o p h i c a l F o u n d a t i o n s of Q u a l i t a t i v e Research
A l l qualitative research strategies share a phenomenological
orientation. The major principle of phenomenology that
provides this common ground is that meaning, knowledge and
truth are relative and depend on the particular perspective of
the individual. Object perception provides a useful analogy.
Humans viewing a three-dimensional object see only that part
of the object consistent with or visible from their particular
place. The side of the object opposite the person is, of course,
invisible, and without moving, that person has no way to
attain absolute certainty about that part of the object. Any
knowledge about the invisible part is provisional. But moving
to another vantage point provides a new perspective and, ac-
242 Critical A r t Pedagogy
Ida Tarbell, Jacob Riis, and Lewis Hine who exposed for the
general public the depth of its social problems in ways that
shocked the American consciousness. In addition to vivid and
hyperbolic prose, they pioneered the practice of incorpor-
ating photographic images into their reporting for the mass
audience. Photographs added drama to their unabashed, tren-
chant, subjective sympathy for the people immersed in these
social problems. In fact, one could say that the emergence of
a social conscience was the accretionary effect of their jour-
nalistic exposes. They provoked a new awareness that the
problems faced by individuals in the silent, invisible classes
pose problems for all of society.
A t the turn of the century, an early form of qualitative
research called the social survey, more methodologically rigor-
ous than muckraking journalism, began to hint at later social-
scientific research methods in anthropology and sociology.
Social surveys followed organized data collection programs in
particular, usually urban communities, aimed at determining
the extent of the social problems and the nature of the opini-
ons in that community. The rise of the natural sciences in the
nineteenth century prompted attempts to address social issues
from a scientific, rather than a philosophical perspective. But
social surveys had been conducted earlier in Europe. Examples
include Frederick LePlay's (1879) studies of French working
class families, Les Ouvriers Europeans, and Henry Mayhew's
(1851) London Labour and the London Poor, These studies
used extensive and thorough interviews of subject-participants
asked to describe their everyday lives.
Anthropology's contribution to the emergence of qualita-
tive methodology as a theoretical foundation for education
began with Frans Boas and his associates in 1898, who were
probably the first anthropologists to do significant fieldwork in
the natural setting alongside their subjects. Boas's methods
included many still characteristic of qualitative research. More-
over, he presciently advocated the concept of culture as
relative.
Goetz and Lecompte (1984) observed that despite the
similarities between these notable incipient examples and the
qualitative methodologies of today, the early researchers fell
far short o f producing sound scholarship. This observation
258 Critical Art Pedagogy
7. are out-
P R O G R A M A N D INSTRUCTIONAL E V A L U A T I O N H O W
comes assessed? How is creativity assessed? How do assess-
ment practices differ across age, socio-economic status,
gender, and racial groups?
world is, you recall, the total set of meanings, codes, ideas,
criteria and historical references—all those factors supplied by
the culture—that permits one to recognize or define an object
as art or a phenomenon as aesthetic and then determine the
relative value (aesthetic and economic) that ensues from this
definition. We transact the art world in lived experience.
When integrated with critical consciousness and emancipatory
action, connections between personal art worlds and life
worlds and between life worlds and the school art world be-
come the defining features of critical art pedagogy: individual
engagement in art-as-praxis.
Adorno's connection between the particular and the
universal furthers the processes of critical aesthetic valuing
and knowledge making because it emphasizes the importance
of the formal properties of the art object in critical art peda-
gogy. Horkheimer, Marcuse and Benjamin believed with
Adorno that the art object's formal properties portray the
particular world in various ways. In high art, this portrayal
refers to or enacts the ideal world. High art transcends the
banality of present particulars, rejects conventional ways of
seeing them, and thus escapes the reification of the formal
properties inherent in the modernist-inspired processes that
result in commodification of the art object, and ultimately, in
a capitulation to forces of domination that marginalize art
and art education. If critical art pedagogy embraces Adorno's
conception of the struggle in art of the particular against the
universal, then art can realize its potential to open aesthetic
ways of knowing and valuing, to the alternatives available to
codified ways of knowing and valuing in the "real world."
Artistic and aesthetic knowing and valuing have subversive
functions and emancipatory potential.
A naive, reactionary suspicion of technology clouded the
Frankfurt School's aesthetic understandings. In the 1930s and
even in the 1940s, much of the technological milieu remained
oriented to the nineteenth century, and it made sense to view
mechanical reproduction of artifacts—photographs, for exam-
ple—as a devaluing, vulgarizing social force appealing only to
bourgeois tastes. Other ways to understand photographs had
yet to be realized. The members of the Frankfurt School took
at face value the words of French painter Paul Delaroche who,
Aesthetics for Critical Praxis 299
cized gaps between personal art worlds, the school art world,
and the high culture art world of the archive. A s the gaps
close, individuals question how their personal art worlds are
formed and malformed. They also come to understand how
the art world reserves art for the reproduction of the status
quo through an art education system and culture industry that
downloads decontextualized expert opinion as aesthetic au-
thenticity and positions these versions as ultimate endpoints
toward which the many lumpen-proles must strive but only
the talented few will gain.
fable, the sublime and the timeless, which are aesthetic values
or forms of aesthetic experience necessary to a modernist aes-
thetics that considers the art object independent from experi-
ence. Critical aesthetics incorporates a discourse that uses figur-
ative language to connect disparate experiences or entities
into meaningful wholes. One entity is like another; therefore,
the two are related in experience. Metaphoric or connotative
language constructs connectedness.
Discourse
The incorporation of semiotics and discursive, cognitive and
critical constructivist components into critical aesthetics as a
foundation for art pedagogy deepens the question of the
nature of aesthetic experience. As we have seen, the modern-
ist-positivist models defined aesthetic experience as pleasure
and pleasure, in turn, as isolated, temporarily heightened ex-
perience. This definition confined pleasure to more or less ob-
servable behavioral manifestations.
The critical aesthetic model of aesthetic experience ex-
changes pleasure as a peak experience for a sense of connect-
edness as the prototype, criterion, or primary form of aesthet-
ic experience.
Pleasure remains an important form of aesthetic ex-
perience in critical aesthetics, which, however, refocuses it on
connectedness. Connectedness can be felt as an expanding one-
ness, or a unity in variety, or the intimate knowing of that
property of the whole which transcends the sum of its parts.
It is the experience of seeing how disparate entities reflect one
another. Critical aesthetics proposes connectedness as a felt,
demonstrable phenomenon arising from the recognition of
unity in diversity. It is the recognition of shared interests and
compatibilities. It is also the realization of the correlation be-
tween the particular and the general. Furthermore, unlike the
modernist notion of aesthetic experience as a peak experience,
it is sustainable. Sustainability makes aesthetic experience a
more accessible presence in the critical art classroom.
Art-As-Praxis
As art education starts to find its critical voice, a critical
aesthetics begins to create the terms for art-as-praxis.
"Praxis" means informed action directed toward emancipa-
tory ends. The concepts of art as aesthetic knowing and art-
as-praxis move beyond art as mere object-making and object-
seeing. Art-as-praxis implies the integration of art making
with reflecting about art and aesthetic experience as means of
knowing. In critical art pedagogy, the act o f making art
merges with critical consciousness of the complex relations
between the processes and techniques of making art, the art ob-
ject, the ideas and iconic elements, and the relevant but often
Aesthetics for Critical Praxis 311
Summary
In postmodern critical aesthetics, meaning and values join
beauty as primary concerns. Aesthetic experience can occur
with art, artifacts, or natural phenomena. Beauty, meaning, and
value are relational, constructed and contextual. They arise
out of interactions between individual experiences and cultural
processes, and they are open-ended. These tenets of post-
modern aesthetics move aesthetics out of the strictures of the
modernist cultural paradigm that reserves the art world for
promoting exclusive interests. Traditional aesthetics carries
out this process by defining beauty, aesthetic value, and mean-
ing (iconography) in restricted terms—that is, as facts to be
received or downloaded. These restricted definitions receive
sanction under the aegis of expert connoisseurs who regulate
access to art, art education, and aesthetic experience and
thereby preserve the art world they create as an instrument
for the private use of a small power elite. Art and aesthetic
experience can be powerful motive and emotive forces in
human relations, and defining art and aesthetic experience in
absolute terms keeps access to the high art archive away from
the undeserving and makes of it a tool for promoting the
interests of dominant groups. Expanding the scope of aesthet-
ics beyond beauty to include meaning decenters the conversa-
tion, subverting the high art world's hierarchy, and reveals the
high art world's one-dimensional socioeconomic functions.
Critical art pedagogy also centers art and aesthetics at the
core of living human experience. It focuses on the nature of
aesthetic experience in daily life rather than on the abstruse
formulations of art and beauty, most of them supposedly self-
referential, self evident, self-validating, and removed from
314 Critical Art Pedagogy
ARTS PROPEL
A R T S P R O P E L is an instructional model developed under the
aegis of the Harvard Graduate School of Education's Project
Zero, the ongoing research group that studies issues relating to
320 Critical Art Pedagogy
Cultural Paradigms
Artist-teachers understand how broad-based cultural move-
ments relate to art. They believe—and try to teach their stu-
dents—that the art process operates within the context of a
cultural paradigm rather than in a vacuum. It shapes and is
shaped by broadly accepted cultural and social values. Art
visualizes, translates, theorizes, forms meanings, uncovers,
confronts, and challenges all in order to make art objects or
events that somehow "belong to" a given cultural or intel-
lectual mode. This is not to say that art always operates along
a neat dialectic or is always logically integrated into one under-
standing, one voice and one grand narrative. Rather, critical
art pedagogy holds that art and art education operate within a
socially grounded context. They are, in fact, constructed in a
social context rich with interactions, complexities, influences,
causes, effects, possibilities, and impossibilities, like most
other human enterprises. Postmodern art and art pedagogy are
parts of a socio-cultural "ecology" in which the dominant
theme is connectedness. Critical art pedagogy also considers it
better for artist-teachers to be explicitly committed to con-
nectedness than to invest by default in the modernist myths
of the independent and self-referential art object and its
legacy, a socio-culturally detached art world isolated from
history and human transaction.
The histories of art, music and literature are, to an extent,
the histories of cultural paradigms. Art and cultural paradigms
continually interact and continually change one another.
Further, history can shape cultural-intellectual movements.
Typically, we discern, understand, intellectually chronicle, and
label each ism long after the actual occurrence of the phe-
nomena that manifest the values and meanings of particular
cultural paradigm. Moreover, cultural-intellectual movements
operate like philosophical or scientific paradigms. According
to Thomas Kuhn (1962), paradigms change in ragged, disorder-
ly ways, far from the neat, logical dialectical syntheses the
traditional historiographical perspective, with its modernist-
positivist distortions, suggests. Further, paradigms are neither
monolithic nor homogeneous with respect to time and place.
We know from the history of art, for example, that the Late
Connecting to Postmodernism 327
between mind and body, a binary opposition that led to the di-
chotomy between the subjective and the objective realms that
persists today.
The realist mind-set embraces the idea of continuity. The
logic of objectivity requires that tangible, perceptible objects
occupy fixed points in time and space and operate according
to principles logic and science can reveal. The objective realm
remains stable in the sense that, assuming their normality,
different persons will experience the characteristics of objects
in essentially the same ways. Everyone, for example, per-
ceives a ripe Winesap apple red.
But certain problems attend the epistemology of Modern-
ism. Ironically, science and the culture of positivism, pillars of
the Modernist paradigm, also tease out Modernism's fraying
edges. From physics, the Heisenberg Uncertainly Principle pro-
vides disconcerting evidence that objects long assumed
(logically) to have tangible, immutable, physical objective exist-
ence may actually be changed by being observed or measured.
Werner Heisenberg (1958), a German physicist, observed that
some subatomic particles change their behavior in response to
being measured so that they occupy different places at the
same instant. This observation contradicts the objective con-
tinuity principle so essential to realist and science-based
thought systems. Heisenberg's findings suggest that physical
objects react differently to different forms of measurement.
We can also take his observation to mean that characteristics
of an entity can depend on perspective—that is, how and
where we observe it (Honderich, 1997). Interestingly enough,
physics produced a finding artists and art teachers have long
known: the color of the Winesap apple actually depends on
the color balance of the light that illuminates it. Try looking
at an apple under a sodium vapor street light and then under
the tungsten illumination of, say, the lamp inside a refrigera-
tor. Red is not always red.
In 1962, Thomas Kuhn's book, The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions, further questioned Modernism's glorification of
objective knowledge by carefully tracing scientific change.
Seminal changes in science, Kuhn observed, occur not in
smoothly functioning, dispassionate, rational, neatly dialec-
tical steps. Instead, scientific knowledge changes come by
Connecting to Postmodernism 333
ragged jerks he called "paradigm shifts." A scientific paradigm
is a small-scale equivalent to such broad-based cultural move-
ments as Romanticism or Neoclassicism discussed earlier. It is
a general set of more or less consistent and often implicit
assumptions that constitute a perspective, style, or way to
recognize data and make knowledge. It amounts to a predis-
position to interpret observations about the world in certain
ways. For example, educators who believe in intelligence as a
single, unified trait share the same paradigm and they develop
strategies of instruction and forms of authorized knowledge
that reflect their belief. A paradigm shift occurs when enough
contradictory evidence accumulates among a sizable number
of scholars or practitioners to oust one belief and install
another. The challenge Howard Gardner's (1983) theory of
multiple intelligences posses to the construct of intelligence as
a general, unified, innate capacity to learn exemplifies a para-
digm shift currently underway in education and psychology.
As paradigms change, some cling like shipwreck survivors
to the old paradigm and its truth criteria. Some in the avant
garde rush ahead to subvert the old paradigm and embrace the
uncertainty of the new. Kuhn never spoke of absolute
scientific proof. Instead, he saw "true scientific facts" as
observations believers in a particular paradigm consider
sensible—that is, consistent with the paradigm's assumptions
and its criteria for truth. Scientific observations depend on
particular perspectives or predispositions, like Heisenberg's
findings and the discovery that an object's color changes
according on the nature of its illumination. Scientists who
measure phenomena quantitatively stay within the quanti-
tative paradigm. Scholars who make interpretations based on
lived experiences as expressed by their subjects subscribe to
the qualitative paradigm.
Subverting Modernism
As we examine how cultural paradigms influence art and how
we teach art, the realization emerges that, as a human phe-
nomenon, art is linked in important ways to other human
phenomena. Thus, we also see that the doctrine of the in-
dependent, self-validating art object assumes a deathly pallor.
It seems counterintuitive, no longer palpably obvious, that art
334 Critical Art Pedagogy
and political reality. Nor has simple isolation been the only
consequence. Modernism developed its credo of the autono-
mous art object into the doctrine of "art for art's sake." and
in so doing, denied the legitimate art object a utilitarian func-
tion, then excluded objects with utilitarian functions from art.
Modern art might well possess intellectual, political, econom-
ic, social, philosophical, even domestic decorative functions,
but these qualities exist outside the aesthetic experience of the
art object. Only art's formal elements elicit aesthetic experi-
ence according to Modernism.
In fact, from the Modernist perspective, utilitarian func-
tions may be so distracting as to prevent aesthetic experience.
The rationale for art must, then, admit of only the goal of the
experience of art itself. This doctrine implicitly denies legiti-
macy to the rich world of craft—ceramics, glass, woodwork-
ing, weaving, jewelry, and so on. Likewise, women's art, much
of the art produced by ethnic minorities and racial groups, and
the so-called "naive," "outsider" art and folk arts are exclud-
ed. Modernism's disdain for these art forms has changed how
their practitioners produce them. Seeking inclusion in the se-
lective and remunerative art world, they adopt such Modernist
forms of expression, stylistic elements, and conventions as
abstraction and expressionism, leaving behind their traditions,
contexts, and connections with contemporary life.
Modernism never conceived of art as a socially situated
practice, but rather as an individual expression of the artist's
unique inner force—the terribilita, creativity, inspiration, and
so forth. Only the few possessed of such rare qualities can
achieve "real" art. So why teach it at all in the public schools
and colleges?
The Modernist insistence on an aesthetic purity untainted
by utilitarian function enfeebles art as an expression of the
very cultural paradigm that produced it. Thus, the Modernist
impulse fails to address today's concerns about bringing multi-
ple voices and diverse experiences into the discourses on educa-
tion in general and art education in particular. Critical art
pedagogy, in fact, sees little potential in an art or art edu-
cation divorced from the social, political, ideological dis-
courses of the contemporary art world. Critical theory invests
its efforts in promoting social justice, and its legacy, critical
Connecting to Postmodernism 337
Lakoff, George, 116, 117, 194 literacy, 72; politics of, 213
Lambert, Johann, 205, 206 literary criticism, 216
Lancelot, 202 literature, 192, 327
landscape 225-228, 232; as a literia, 156
text, 229; photography, 225, local narratives, 106
227-229 Locke, John, 204, 206
Langer, Suzanne K., 206, 276, Locke, 107
290, 291, 311 logic, 9, 116
language, 36, 113, 114, 115, Logical Positivism, 329
118, 161, 163, 164, 169, logistics, 251
197, 202, 204, 206, 212, logocentric assumption, 234
213, 223; oral, 113, 220; as logocentrism, 219, 234
sign system, 224; written, Lopez, Barry, 230, 232
220 Lyotard, Jean-Francois, 106, 325
Le Corbusier, 330
Leacock, 259 machine, 330, 331
learner, 146 macro-aesthetics, 295-297
lebensweldt, 268 Malevich, Kasimir, 341
LeBrun, Charles, 76, 77 Malinowski, Bronislaw, 258
LeCompte, M , 239, 256-258 Man Ray, 235
legitimation crisis, 33 Man Who Flew into Space from
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 203 his Apartment, 341
leisure, 71 Manet, 330
lekton, 199, 200 manifest destiny, 227
Leonardo, 73, 75 Mann, Horace, 90
Leondar, B., 140 mannerism, 75
LePlay, Fredrick, 257 manuscript, 72; illumination, 71
LeVau, Louis, 76 Mao, 42
liberation, 8, 35, 260, 269 Marcus Aurelius, 52
Lickert scales, 293 Marcuse, Herbert, 295, 296, 298
life world, 29, 264, 268, 269, marginalization, 12, 40
297, 305; colonization of, Marin, 170
308 Marx, 7, 29, 35, 38, 42
life stories, 161 Marxism, 30, 31-34, 36, 40, 42,
Lincoln, Y., 19, 20, 239, 243, 43, 46, 49, 50, 285, 318
246, 248, 251, 254, 255, masculine epistemology, 130
line, 99, 101 mass: culture, 44; market, 80;
linear: causality, 245; media, 30, 48, 50, 213
perspective, 17 Massachusetts Drawing Act of
linguistics, 211 1870, 91-95
Index 367
Plato, 23, 68, 69, 74, 198, 201, interests, 279; King's, 76;
215,278,283,302; Republic relations, 196, 212, 224;
of, 70 structures, 7
pleasure, 302, 303, 307 pragmatics, 207
plot, 157, 158 praktike, 204
poetry, 327 praxis, 3, 28, 33, 37, 38, 61,
poiesis, 149, 150, 151 103, 122, 149-151, 197,
Poinsot, John, 203 300, 310; critical, 63, 64,
Polanyi, Michael, 14, 185 301, 302, 311
Polkinghorne, Donald, 154, 161- pre-positivism, 243
164 President of Space, 341
polysemy, 108, 156, 228 presupposition, 157
Popes, 76 primacy, 118
Porter, Eliot, 228 primary apparition, 290, 311
position, 167 printing press, 72
positionings, 174 probabilistic, 116
positivism, 10, 18, 20, 31, 99, problem solving, 109-112
122, 105, 142, 146, 148, processfolio, 321
149, 171, 181, 243-245, processing, 107
271, 275, 276, 290, 291; production competency, 320
critique of, 19, 243; cult of, profit, 31
182; culture of, 127, 332 Project Zero, 139, 140, 320, 321
positivist: inquiry, 242; research proletariat, 46
methodologies, 181 propaganda, 78
post-formal: operations, 122; Protestantism, 97
thinking, 126, 130, 132, prototype primacy, 118
134, 135; theory, 131 prototypes, 117
post-positivist era, 246 The Psalter of King Louis IXJ2
postmodern: era, 38, 63; psychological epistemology,
paradigm, 106; 145, 146
pyschologies, 130 psychology, 20, 105
postmodernism, 7, 32, 52, 61, public relations, 213
122, 262, 277, 318, 325,
337-344; critical, 262 qualitative: data, 17, 20;
Poussin, Nicolas, 16, 77 methodology, 13, 181;
power, 5, 8, 14, 16, 51, 53, 54, paradigm, 187
72, 130, 207, 261, 338, qualitative research, 147, 239-
339; art as instrument of, 85, 241, 245, 247, 248, 255,
108; elite, 40, 74, 75, 76, 256, 258, 260;
313; of empathy, 134; characteristics, 247, 264;
370 Index