Geometry and Its Applications 3rd Edition Walter J Meyer pdf download
Geometry and Its Applications 3rd Edition Walter J Meyer pdf download
https://ebookmeta.com/product/geometry-and-its-applications-3rd-
edition-walter-j-meyer/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/international-business-3rd-edition-
meyer/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/combinatorics-of-permutations-
discrete-mathematics-and-its-applications-3rd-edition-miklos-
bona/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/internet-of-things-and-its-
applications/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/maginot-line-gun-turrets-and-
french-gun-turret-development-1880-1940-new-vanguard-donnell/
A Community Based Mangrove Planting Handbook for Papua
New Guinea 1st Edition Asian Development Bank
https://ebookmeta.com/product/a-community-based-mangrove-
planting-handbook-for-papua-new-guinea-1st-edition-asian-
development-bank/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/blood-debt-kingdom-of-blood-1-1st-
edition-callie-rose/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/feature-engineering-and-selection-
a-practical-approach-for-predictive-models-1st-edition-max-kuhn/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/managing-change-creativity-and-
innovation-3rd-edition-patrick-dawson-constantine-andriopoulos/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/enzyme-kinetics-in-drug-metabolism-
fundamentals-and-applications-second-edition-upendra-a-argikar/
Software Architecture Patterns Understanding Common
Architectural Styles and When to Use Them 2nd Edition
Mark Richards
https://ebookmeta.com/product/software-architecture-patterns-
understanding-common-architectural-styles-and-when-to-use-
them-2nd-edition-mark-richards/
Geometry and Its
Applications
Geometry and Its
Applications
Third Edition
Walter J. Meyer
Third edition published 2022
by CRC Press
6000 Broken Sound Parkway NW, Suite 300, Boca Raton, FL 33487-2742
and by CRC Press
4 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN
© 2022 Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
[First edition published by Elsevier 1999]
[Second edition published by Elsevier 2006]
CRC Press is an imprint of Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
The right of Walter Meyer to be identified as author of this work has been
asserted by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs,
and Patents Act 1988.
Reasonable efforts have been made to publish reliable data and information, but
the author and publisher cannot assume responsibility for the validity of all
materials or the consequences of their use. The authors and publishers have
attempted to trace the copyright holders of all material reproduced in this
publication — we apologize to copyright holders if permission to publish in this
form has not been obtained. If any copyright material has not been
acknowledged, please write and let us know so we may rectify it in any future
reprint.
Except as permitted under US Copyright Law, no part of this book may be
reprinted, reproduced, transmitted, or utilized in any form by any electronic,
mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including
photocopying, microfilming, and recording, or in any information storage or
retrieval system, without written permission from the publishers.
For permission to photocopy or use material electronically from this work, access
www.copyright.com or contact the Copyright Clearance Center, Inc. (CCC), 222
Rosewood Drive, Danvers, MA 01923, 978-750-8400. For works that are not
available on CCC please contact [email protected]
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered
trademarks and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to
infringe.
DOI: 10.1201/9780429198328
Typeset in Palatino
by MPS Limited, Dehradun
Contents
3. Non-Euclidean Geometry........................................................................... 79
Section 1. Hyperbolic and Other Non-Euclidean Geometries.............. 79
Section 2. Spherical Geometry – A Three‐Dimensional View.............. 93
Section 3. Spherical Geometry – An Axiomatic View .........................106
Section 4. The Relative Consistency of Hyperbolic Geometry...........115
v
vi Contents
vii
viii To the Instructor
The main novelty of this book is that it presents a wider view of geometry
than the Euclidean geometry you will recall from high school. Here, you
will find modern as well as ancient geometry, applied as well as pure
geometry, all spiced with historical vignettes.
There are a number of advantages from this presentation of geometry:
1. Most of the topics are useful. Many of them are being applied
today, for example, in software we use everyday. An important
objective of this book is to introduce applications of geometry,
including the study of symmetry (useful in graphic design),
chemistry, topics in computer science and robotics. About half the
pages of the book concern an application or are part of the theory
that supports an application.
2. There are a few long and complicated calculations where learning
the steps is the main task but understanding the ideas is just as
important.
3. There are parts of this book that help prepare you for advanced
mathematics courses, especially abstract algebra.
4. There are jobs that use geometry—especially the vector geometry of
Chapters 5, 6 and 7.
5. Euclid is well-represented for those who wish to become secondary
school teachers.
ix
x To the Student
A bonus
This book is one of the most student-centred courses of study you will
encounter in college. In most courses, you have to accept a lot of what
you are told because you don’t have the time, the energy, or the resources
to verify it for yourself. Is water really composed of hydrogen and
oxygen? Are the Great Lakes salty? Save yourself the trouble and ask
your instructor.
But you can check out the facts of geometry as we present them in this
book. The method is called ’proof’, and you can learn it.
There is a lot in this book and we hope you will take advantage of it.
Dependencies
Ch. 2. The
Euclidean Heritage
Ch. 5. Vectors in
Ch. 4. Transformation Geometry
Ch. 3. Non-Euclidean Geometry I: Isometries
Geometry and Symmetries
xi
Course Outlines
Applied Geometry
For students of the applied sciences, especially computer science
students wishing to take a mathematics course with applications.
xiii
xiv Course Outlines
Glimpses of Applications
Glimpses of History
xv
xvi Glimpses
Main Applications
We human beings are at home with the physical world—our senses guide
our movements and help us estimate sizes. But from earliest times, we have
wanted to know things about our physical world that our senses and
measuring instruments could not tell us—for example, what is the cir-
cumference of the earth? For this, we needed the kinds of geometry we will
explore in this book: axiomatic geometry. This means that we start with
assumptions people are willing to accept as true (perhaps “for the sake of
argument”) and use logical arguments based on these agreed-upon prin-
ciples, instead of our senses. The process is called deduction and the starting
principles are called axioms.
Geometry, that of Euclid in particular (which we start with), has paid
dividends for over 2,000 years, but there are still frontiers to explore. For
example, the development of robots has led to the desire to mimic whatever
mysterious processes our human minds do, through geometry, to move
about in the world safely and effectively.
Prerequisites:
high school mathematics,
the notation of set theory (in just a few places)
1. Euclid phrases his axioms in a way which is hard for the modern
reader to appreciate.
2. It has been necessary to add axioms to Euclid’s set to be able to give
rigorous proofs of many Euclidean theorems.
DOI: 10.1201/9780429198328-1 1
2 Geometry and Its Applications
Given any two different points, there is exactly one line which contains
them.
We denote the line connecting A and B by AB . Our first theorem about lines
uses proof by contradiction or indirect proof. It is based on the idea that the
truths of Euclidean geometry do not contradict one another; if you reason
correctly on true statements, then you can never deduce a statement that
contradicts another which is known to be true. If you do find a contra-
diction, then one of the statements you have been reasoning from must be
false. In our proof, we will make a supposition and show that it leads to a
contradiction. This proves the supposition false.
Our next axiom is just a mathematical way of saying what everyone who
has ever used a ruler will find familiar: a line “comes with” a set of nu-
merical markings we can use for calculations and proofs.
The Axiomatic Method in Geometry 3
For any line, there exists a 1-1 correspondence f between the points of the
line and the real numbers. This means:
1. Every point A on the line has a number f(A) associated with it.
2. Different points have different numbers associated with them.
3. Every number, positive or negative, has some point to which it is
associated.
The function f is called the ruler function for that line. The number f(A) is
called the coordinate of A.
This axiom allows us to use the properties of the real numbers to find out
things about lines. For example, there are infinitely many real numbers, so
we must have infinitely many corresponding points on a line. The ruler
axiom also allows us to define the key geometric ideas of distance and
betweenness.
1. We say B is between A and C if either f(A) < f(B) < f(C) or f(C) < f(B) < f(A).
We write A-B-C to indicate that B is between A and C. C-B-A is the same
as A-B-C.
2. The segment from A to B, denoted AB, is defined to be the set
consisting of A, B, and all points X where A-X-B.
3. The distance from A to B is defined to be |f(B) − f(A)| and we denote
this distance by AB. Note that if A and B designate the same point,
AB = 0.
4. If AB = CD, then the segments AB and CD are called congruent.
Theorem 1.2:
1. AB = BA
2. If A-B-C, then AB + BC = AC
3. If A, B, C are three different points on a line, exactly one of them is
between the other two.
Proof:
If A and B are any two points, then the segment AB can be extended by any
positive distance on either side of segment AB (Figure 1.1).
Proof: Let e > 0 be the amount of extension wanted. Let’s say we want to
extend past B to a point C, so that B is between A and C and BC = e. Let a
and b be the real numbers f(A) and f(B) under the ruler function for the
line AB .
Case 1: a < b (Figure 1.1). Then, define c = b + e. By part 3 of the ruler axiom,
there is a point C which corresponds to the number c. C is the point we want
since:
FIGURE 1.1
The Ruler Function helps extend segment AB.
The Axiomatic Method in Geometry 5
FIGURE 1.2
Statue of Giordano Bruno. (Photograph by the author.)
6 Geometry and Its Applications
The statue shown here shows an Italian scholar of the 16th century,
Giordano Bruno. It stands in the Campo de Florio in Rome, where tourists
crowd the many restaurants at night. No doubt that they find it pleasing to
dine in the shadow of history, having no idea that what is commemorated
by the statue is gruesome. Bruno was burnt alive in this very spot because
he professed many ideas that were deeply upsetting to the power structure
of the time. One of Bruno’s heretical ideas comes right from Euclid—our
Theorem 1.3. Bruno deduced from Euclid’s version that the universe must
be infinite if you can always extend segments to be longer. He concluded
further (and this is not in Euclid) that in an infinite universe, there would be
many worlds like our own. This contradicted the prevailing idea that the
earth was the centre of—and the very reason for—God’s creation of the
universe. ■
Every segment has a midpoint. That is, for any points A and B, there is a
point M on segment AB so that AM = (1/2)AB. ■
Proof: We leave this as an exercise. ■
Definition: If A and B are distinct points, the ray from A through B, denoted
AB , is the set of all points C on line AB , such that A is not between B and C.
We call A the endpoint of the ray.
B B B
B B
A C
A A
C A
A Line
↔ ↔
AB Segment AB Ray AB Angle ∠BAC Triangle ABC
FIGURE 1.4
The cast of characters.
When we hear “angle”, we often think of it as the space between the rays that
border it. Our definition of an angle does not capture that idea. We will need a
separate definition of the interior of an angle, and base it on the next axiom.
Separation
Axiom 3: Pasch’s Separation Axiom for a Line
Given a line L in the plane, the points in the plane which are not on L form
two sets, H1 and H2, called half-planes, so that:
H1 and H2 are also called sides of L. L is called the boundary line of H1 and H2.
Notice that the half-planes mentioned in Pasch’s axiom do not contain their
boundary line. They are sometimes referred to as open half-planes for this reason.
Pasch’s Axiom was only added to the axiom set for Euclidean geometry in
the late 19th century when geometers became aware that, for many geo-
metric figures, there was no way to rigorously define the inside or outside of
the figure, much less prove theorems about them. For example, if you had
8 Geometry and Its Applications
FIGURE 1.5
An angle and its interior.
asked Euclid to prove that a line containing a point on the inside of an angle
crosses at least one of the rays making the angle, he would have been unable
to do so. He would undoubtedly have been unconcerned about this,
thinking this theorem to be too obvious to bother with.
Theorem 1.6: If a ray AB has endpoint A on line L, but B does not lie on L,
then all points of the ray, except for A, lie on the same side of L as B.
Proof: The proof is indirect. Assume there is a point C on the ray so that C
and B are on opposite sides of L. By Pasch’s Axiom, BC crosses L at some
point. This must be A since BC AB and, by Theorem 1.1, AB crosses L in
just one point, namely A. Since A is not B or C, the fact that A is in BC means
B-A-C. But this means C is not in AB by the definition of a ray. ■
1. A-C-D
2. B-M-C
3. A-M-E
then, E is in the interior of ∠BCD.
The Axiomatic Method in Geometry 9
FIGURE 1.6
Illustrating Theorem 1.7.
To every angle, there corresponds a real number between 0° and 180° called
its measure or size. We denote the measure of ∠BAC by m∠BAC.
Definition: If m∠BAC = m∠PQR, then we say ∠BAC and ∠PQR are
congruent angles.
Axiom 5: The Angle Construction Axiom.
10 Geometry and Its Applications
B
D A
X
A’
α β
A B C B’
FIGURE 1.7
Supplementary angles α + β = 180°. b) ∠AXB and ∠A’XB’ are vertical angles; ∠BXA’ and ∠B’XA
are vertical angles.
Let AB lie entirely on the boundary line L of some half-plane H. For every
number r where 0° < r < 180°, there is exactly one ray AC where C ε H and
m∠CAB = r.
Axiom 6: The Angle Addition Axiom.
Now, consider two lines crossing at X, making four angles as in the right-
hand side of Figure 1.7. Each angle has two neighbouring angles and one
which is “across” from it. For example, ∠AXB is across ∠A’XB’. An angle
and the one across from it are said to be vertical angles or form a vertical pair.
A technical definition goes like this: if A and A’ are points on one line where
A-X-A’ and B and B’ are on the other line with B-X-B’, then ∠AXB and
∠A’XB’ are vertical angles. Notice that an angle cannot be vertical by it-
self—it is only vertical in relation to another.
If
Given a point P of a line L, there is at most one line in the plane through P
not meeting L.
Given any three points, there is at least one plane containing them. If the
points are not collinear, there is exactly one plane passing through them.
For every line, there is a point not on it. For every plane, there is a point not
on it.
If two points of a line are in a plane, then the line lies entirely in that plane.
Given a plane N, the points which are not on N form two sets, S1 and S2,
called half-spaces, with the properties:
S1 and S2 are also called sides of N. N is called the boundary plane of S1 and S2.
Exercises
Axioms About Points on Lines
Separation
FIGURE 1.8
Three 4‐sided figures. Are they all quadrilaterals?
The Axiomatic Method in Geometry 15
Our main objective in this chapter is to study how some key theorems in
Euclidean geometry arise from the axioms in Chapter 1. To make quicker
progress, we relax slightly the degree of rigour used in the last section of
Chapter 1, to a standard closer to Euclid’s Elements.
The Side-Angle-Side (SAS) Axiom will play a huge role and, in the third
section, Euclid’s Parallel Axiom. Students with a firm grasp of how proofs
are constructed in geometry may go quickly through this. Although the
theorems of this chapter are old, our applications span the from ancient to
modern.
Prerequisites:
Section 1. Congruence
To say that figures are congruent means, in non-technical language, that
they have the same size and shape even though they may be in different
positions (Figure 2.1). There is a more to say to make this precise and useful,
so in this section, we will flesh this out with a detailed theory for triangles in
the plane. However, the attention to triangles shouldn’t obscure the fact that
the concept also applies to figures other than triangles. It is entirely rea-
sonable to ask whether two quadrilaterals are congruent and to ask what
evidence would convince us of it. The triangle theory can help with
quadrilaterals, pentagons, and so on. You might like to think about whether
it helps us with curved figures.
It is quite possible that the human mind does three-dimensional congruence
checking to recognize familiar people or objects. If you are sitting in front of
your computer, how do you know it is your computer and not the microwave
oven? The computer has a certain size and shape which is recorded in your
mind. Even if you are seeing it from a new angle right now—an angle you
have never seen if it has tipped over—you can somehow compare the current
view to the recalled image and tell that they differ just by position.
DOI: 10.1201/9780429198328-2 17
18 Geometry and Its Applications
C
Q
√2
45° √2 R 45°
1
45°
1
90° 45° 90°
1
A 1 B
P
FIGURE 2.1
Two congruent triangles.
Example 2.1: In Figure 2.1, there are two 1-1 correspondences that show
congruence:
A P, B Q, C R
A P, B R, C Q
If
FIGURE 2.2
Side-Angle-Side Axiom. (Given parts in solid lines).
In Figure 2.2, suppose m∠A = m∠A’, AB = A’B’, and AC = A’C’ (note that we
have used solid lines in the figure to indicate the known parts). It seems
obvious that the given information implies that BC = B’C’, m∠B = m∠B’, and
m∠C = m∠C’. As an informal argument for this conclusion, imagine moving
triangle ABC so that vertex A falls on vertex A’, AB falls on top of A B , and
AC falls on top of A C . Clearly, B, in its new position, is the same point as
B’. Likewise, C, in its new position, is the same point as C’. In other words,
the two triangles coincide exactly. Now, the motion of the first triangle
doesn’t change its length or the measures of any angles. Consequently, the
parts of the original ABC are congruent to the corresponding parts of
A’B’C’—the triangles are congruent.
The argument given seems a lot like a proof of the SAS Axiom, but we have
not labelled the SAS principle a theorem—which we would do if we had
proof of it. The reason our argument is not a proof is that it relies on the
assumption that figures can be moved without changing the sizes of their
sides and angles. There is no reason that such an axiom could not be added to
our set of axioms—it is ,after all, quite believable. However, it is common to
exclude ideas of motion from the axioms of Euclidean geometry (but not
from our intuitions about geometry) and we shall follow this tradition. ■
Here is our first deduction from the SAS axiom: the well-known theorem
that base angles of isosceles triangles are congruent. Recall that a triangle is
isosceles if it has two congruent sides.
FIGURE 2.3
Base angles of an isosceles triangle are congruent.
Our proof of Theorem 2.1 sometimes strikes readers as odd, even invalid,
since it deals with a congruence of a triangle with itself. For this reason, this
proof has rarely appeared in geometry texts. It is true that most times we
deal with congruence we are handling different triangles, but there is
nothing about our definition of congruence or the SAS axiom that requires
this. This proof seems first to have been found by Pappus around 300 AD.
There is a story that a computer program, which was designed to find
proofs of theorems in geometry, produced this proof rather than any of the
proofs commonly included in geometry texts.
We will prove that if the diagonals of a quadrilateral bisect each other, the
opposite sides are congruent (Figure 2.4).
Proof: In Figure 2.4, we will use SAS to show that triangle ABC is congruent
to triangle EDC, with the 1-1 correspondence A → E, B → D, C → C. We
have AC = CE and BC = CD by hypothesis. We also have α = β since they are
vertical angles. Thus, SAS implies that the triangles are congruent. Then, the
corresponding sides are congruent so AB = DE.
A similar proof will show BE = AD. ■
If we have a triangle, such as ABC at the top of Figure 2.5, if we extend side
AC by some unspecified amount past C to D, then ∠BCD, whose measure is
θ, is called an exterior angle of the triangle. We could make another exterior
angle at C by extending BC . There are two exterior angles per vertex, which
happen to be vertical angles, so six exterior angles in all for the whole tri-
angle. The usual angles at A, B, and C are called interior angles. The ones
that do not touch C, namely ∠A and ∠B, are called remote from the exterior
22 Geometry and Its Applications
FIGURE 2.4
Diagonals of a quadrilateral bisecting each other.
FIGURE 2.5
Illustrating the Exterior Angle Inequality.
angle labelled θ. In the top picture it seems clear that the exterior angle
labelled θ is greater than either of the remote interior angles ∠A and ∠B, but
in other pictures (like the bottom of Figure 2.5), the inequality seems less
obvious. We would like to be convinced of this inequality without drawing
hundreds of triangles and measuring their angles, so here is a proof.
The Euclidean Heritage 23
FIGURE 2.6
Proving the Exterior Angle Inequality.
Proof: We will only show m∠B < θ and will leave the proof that m∠A < θ as
an exercise.
Let M be the midpoint of segment AC . We don’t have to actually
construct this midpoint using instruments like a ruler and compass—it is
enough to know that it exists. Now, imagine segment AM extended an
equal amount to a point E. Finally, connect E to C, thereby splitting the
exterior angle θ (maybe not evenly).
Our strategy now is to show that triangles ABM and ECM are congruent
(you’ll see in a minute how this helps us with the exterior angle). Since α
and β are vertical angles, they are congruent. Next, we deal with segments.
BM = MC by construction and, likewise, MA = ME. By the SAS axiom, we
have the congruence we wanted. Consequently, m∠B = m∠ECM but
m∠ECM < θ. Therefore, m∠B < θ. ■
There is one lapse from complete rigour in the given proof. We need to
prove (not just observe visually) that E is situated in such a way that
m∠ECM < θ—see exercise 8.
In thinking about this theorem, you might be tempted to give a different
proof, like this: m∠A + m∠B + m∠C = 180°, so m∠B = 180° − m∠A − m∠C <
180° − m∠C = θ. This would be based on your recollection that the sum of
the measures of the angles of a triangle is 180°. We have not yet proved the
principle about the “angle sum” of a triangle, so such a proof for the
Exterior Angle Inequality would be incorrect at this point. In our chapter on
non-Euclidean Geometry, we will find it important to have proved the
Exterior Angle Inequality without relying on the angle sum of a triangle.
FIGURE 2.7
The AAS Congruence Principle.
ABC in Figure 2.7 (ignore segment DC ), visiting an angle ∠A, the next angle
∠B, then the side after the last visited angle BC , and we do the same in
another triangle in a way that the parts visited in the two triangles are the
same in size (m∠A = m∠A’, m∠B = m∠B’, BC = B’C’), then the triangles are
said to have the angle-angle-side relationship. We abbreviate this as AAS.
The key thing is that this implies the triangles are congruent.
Here are two more congruence principles with proofs we leave as exercises.
FIGURE 2.8
Isosceles triangle and a simple carpenter’s level.
Figure 2.9 shows just one of many structures built with simple geometric
instruments and Euclidean geometry in ancient times. This aqueduct was
built during the second half of the first century. To bring water to the city
of Nimes, the level must be just a bit off horizontally—if it were exactly
horizontal, the water wouldn’t flow and if it were too steep there would be
a flood.
2,000 years later and mathematics has much more to offer to builders and
architects. Perhaps, the most radical innovation is that it is no longer
26 Geometry and Its Applications
FIGURE 2.9
(a) Aqueduct that brought water in ancient times from the Eure River to the City of Nimes in
Southern France. (b) A building by Frank Gehry at Bard College, going beyond the flat and the
straight.
The Euclidean Heritage 27
FIGURE 2.10
Using ASA to estimate distance AC.
28 Geometry and Its Applications
Exercises
Congruence and Correspondences
1. List all the possible 1-1 correspondences between the two triangles
of Figure 2.1. Which of these is a congruence?
2. Show an example of two triangles where there are at least three
different 1-1 correspondences showing congruence.
3. Let ABC and PQR be two triangles and suppose that both of the
following correspondences is a congruence.
i. A → P, B → Q, C → R
ii. A → P, B → R, C → Q
Explain why ABC must be isosceles. (Hint: feel free to use exercise 18.)
4. If there are two different 1-1 correspondences which demonstrate
congruence between triangles ABC and PQR, must the triangles be
isosceles? If not, give an example. If so, give a proof. (Hint: study
the previous exercise.)
5. If there are three different 1-1 correspondences which demonstrate
congruence between triangle ABC and a second triangle, must the
triangles be equilateral? If not, give an example. If so, give a proof.
It was not a particularly brilliant prospect; all the hard work and
dangerous labor was to be performed by Jones, and the glory was to
be reaped by the French frigates; but, with a noble disinterestedness
in his desire to serve his country, he at once expressed his perfect
willingness to co-operate. Before anything came of it, however,
Franklin offered him the command of the Indien, in the following
letter:
(Private.)
"I was much pleased with reading your journal, which we received
yesterday."
"If by this means you can get a good new crew, I think it would
be best that you are quite free of the old, for a mixture might
introduce the infection of that sickness you complain of. But this may
be left to your own discretion. Perhaps we shall join you with the
Providence, Captain Whipple, a new Continental ship of thirty guns,
which, in coming out of the river of Providence, gave the two
frigates that were posted to intercept her each of them so heavy a
dose of her 18- and 12-pounders that they had not the courage or
were not able to pursue her. It seems to be desired that you will
step up to Versailles (where one will meet you), in order to such a
settlement of matters and plans with those who have the direction
as can not well be done by letter. I wish it may be convenient to you
to do it immediately.
"The project of giving you the command of this ship pleases me
the more as it is a probable opening to the higher preferment you so
justly merit."
His state of mind may well be understood from this citation: "I
have, to show my gratitude to France, lost so much time, and with it
such opportunities as I can not regain. I have almost killed myself
with grief."
His intense, burning desire for action, however, did not permit him
to degrade, as he thought, his Government and station by accepting
the command of a privateer which was tendered to him. In the
command of a speedy, smart privateer there is no limit to the
plundering he might have done and the treasure he might have
gained, if that had been what he wished. Many naval officers before
and since his time have done this and thought it not derogatory to
their dignity. It is therefore to Jones' credit that he was very jealous
in this and many other instances on the point of honor of serving in
no ship, under no flag, and with no commission save that of the
United States. We shall see this spirit again and again. The citizen of
the world was beginning to feel that the world as his country was
hardly adequate to his needs; in theory it was a very pretty
proposition, but in practice it was necessary to form and maintain a
more definite and particular relationship. As a final effort to better
his condition and secure that opportunity for which he thirsted, he
prepared the following letter to the king:
"I was to act with unlimited orders under the commission and flag
of America; and the Prince de Nassau proposed to accompany me
on the ocean.
"I was deeply penetrated with the sense of the honour done me
by this generous proposition, as well as of the favour your Majesty
intended thereby to confer on America. And I accepted the offer
with the greater pleasure as the Congress had sent me to Europe in
the Ranger to command the Indien before the ownership of that
vessel was changed.
"I am, with perfect gratitude and profound respect, Sire, your
Majesty's very obliged, very obedient, and very humble servant,
It was not the custom to harry, plunder, and ravage the seacoasts
in the wars between France and England. Military or naval forces
were the sole objects of attack, and by a specific though unwritten
law of custom, the efforts of the rival combatants were confined to
ships of war, fortifications, and armies, and, of course, to merchant
vessels belonging to the enemy. The peaceful seashore towns were
generally let alone unless the inhabitants in exposed localities
provoked retaliation by aggression--a thing they usually took good
care not to do. To introduce the practice would be unfortunate and
nothing would be gained, by France especially. The King of France,
however, was more than willing to have the coasts of his neighbor
ravaged, if no retaliation on his own unprotected shores were
provoked thereby. No convention of any sort, expressed or
understood, existed between Great Britain and the United States
which would prevent such action on the part of the Americans. Great
Britain was making a bloody ravaging warfare on the coasts of North
America, and, never dreaming of reprisal, paid no attention
whatever to this law of war, save when it suited her to do so, on our
seaboard. Franklin and the commissioners wisely realized that the
only way to stop this merciless and brutal burning and plundering
was to let the enemy experience the thing himself. They were
therefore in entire accord with the desire of the French king. To
produce the result he would furnish the squadron, they the flag. It
was a charming arrangement from the king's point of view.
Consequently the reason for the encouragement given Jones is
apparent, and the determination of the minister is therefore
explained and understood.
Meanwhile he was at his wits' end. The year had nearly passed
and nothing had been done. He had been put off with promises until
he was desperate. Chance, it is stated, threw in his way one day, as
he sat idle at Nantes, gloomily ruminating on the prospect, or lack of
it, and almost making up his mind to go back to the United States in
the first vessel that offered and seek such opportunity for service as
might arise there, a copy of Franklin's famous book of maxims,
called Poor Richard's Almanac. As the harassed little captain sat
listlessly turning its pages, his eyes fell upon this significant
aphorism:
"If a man wishes to have any business faithfully and expeditiously
performed, let him go on it himself; otherwise he may send."
The truth of the saying inspired him to one final effort before he
abandoned European waters. He went to Versailles in November,
1778, for one last visit, and there settled the matter. His
determination and persistence at last, as it had many times before,
brought him success. De Sartine directed the purchase of the Duras,
which Jones, from his love for Franklin and the circumstance just
related, with the consent of the minister, renamed the Bon Homme
Richard, that being the French equivalent for Poor Richard, or Good
Man Richard, which was the caption of the almanac.
The squadron sailed on the 19th of June, 1779. During the night
of the 20th the Alliance ran foul of the Richard, and as a result of
the collision the mizzenmast of the Alliance was carried away, while
the Richard lost her head, cutwater, jib boom, etc. The blame for the
accident mainly rested on Landais, who, it was afterward developed,
had behaved disgracefully on this occasion, showing such a lack of
presence of mind and seamanly aptitude, coupled with such timidity
and shrinking from duty, that, when the accident occurred, he not
only gave no orders, but basely ran below to load his pistols, leaving
the ship to be extricated from her critical situation by the junior
officers. Perhaps he was afraid that the infuriated Jones would attack
him for the mishandling of his ship. Jones, who had been below
when the accident occurred, immediately assumed charge of the
Richard, and by prompt action averted a more serious disaster. To do
Landais justice, however, the officer of the watch on the Richard also
must have been culpable, for he was subsequently court-martialed
and broken for his lack of conduct on this occasion.
On the last day of June the squadron put into L'Orient again to
repair damages. During the cruise it is interesting to note that Jones
dispatched thirty pounds, in the shape of a draft, through a friend in
Dublin, to Scotland for the use of his family. He frequently made
them remittances from his scanty supplies of money, and, in fact, he
never forgot them, however busy with great undertakings he may
have been.
The officers and crew of the Pallas, Vengeance, and Cerf were
French in toto, the officers all holding French commissions. The
squadron was entirely at the charges of the French Government,
although each of the officers sailed with a supplementary American
commission issued by Franklin and his confrères, and all the vessels
were under the American flag.
CHAPTER IX.
THE CRUISE OF THE SQUADRON.