GT Lecture Notes Set 1
GT Lecture Notes Set 1
SPRING 2022
Eleftherios Filippiadis
Office: ΓΔ3, 310
Phone number: 2310-891770
Email: [email protected]
What Is Game Theory* …?
2
*Game Theory is a misnomer for Multi-person Decision Theory
Some Applications Of Game Theory
➢ Oligopolistic competition, where one firm’s price or quantity choices
affect another firm’s profits through a common market demand.
➢ Auctions, where one bidder’s bid affects another bidder’s profit.
➢ Bilateral and multilateral bargaining.
➢ Externalities where, by definition, one agent’s action affects another
agent’s well-being.
➢ Contract theory where a contract has to be designed in an incentive
compatible fashion.
➢ Moral hazard problem occurs when the actions of one party may
change to the detriment of another after a financial transaction has
taken place (informational asymmetry, principal-agent problem).
➢ Market design (one-sided/two-sided, one-to-one, many-to-one
matchings).
➢ Coalition formation (cartels, international environmental
agreements, clubs, trading blocks, coalitional governments). 3
9
Dominant and Dominated Strategies
It is possible that
• it is always to the best interest of a player to choose the same
action/strategy → strictly dominant action
• it is never to the best interest of a player to choose a specific
action/strategy → strictly dominated action
Definitions:
1) A strategy 𝒔ො 𝒊 for player 𝒊 is strictly dominant if
𝒖𝒊 𝒔ො 𝒊 , 𝒔−𝒊 > 𝒖𝒊 𝒔𝒊 , 𝒔−𝒊 for all 𝒔−𝒊 ∈ 𝑺−𝒊 and for all 𝒔𝒊 ≠ 𝒔ො 𝒊 ∈
𝑺𝒊
2) A strategy 𝒔ത 𝒊 for player 𝒊 is strictly dominated if there exists
some 𝒔∗𝒊 ∈ 𝑺𝒊 such that 𝒖𝒊 𝒔ത 𝒊 , 𝒔−𝒊 < 𝒖𝒊 𝒔∗𝒊 , 𝒔−𝒊 for all 𝒔−𝒊 ∈
𝑺−𝒊 10
•
Dominant and Dominated Strategies
11
Dominant and Dominated Strategies
Note: If a game has a strictly dominant strategy for every player, the
collection of these strategies is a (logical) solution of the game. For
example, in the prisoner’s dilemma game we get
• For player 1
𝒖𝟏 𝑪, 𝑳 = 𝟎 > 𝒖𝟏 𝑳, 𝑳 = −𝟏
𝒖𝟏 𝑪, 𝑪 = −𝟔 > 𝒖𝟏 𝑳, 𝑪 = −𝟗
→ player 1 has a strictly dominant strategy to confess (no matter if her
partner confesses or lies!).
• For player 2
𝒖𝟐 𝑳, 𝑪 = 𝟎 > 𝒖𝟐 𝑳, 𝑳 = −𝟏
𝒖𝟐 𝑪, 𝑪 = −𝟔 > 𝒖𝟐 𝑳, 𝑪 = −𝟗
→ player 2 has a strictly dominant strategy to confess (no matter if his
partner confesses or lies!).
**Hence, a logical solution/outcome of the prisoner’s dilemma game is
that BOTH players choose to confess.
• Is this concept enough to analyze all games? NO. There can be
infinitely many games without a strictly dominant strategy for all 12
players.
Iterated Elimination of Strictly Dominated Strategies
Rational players DO NOT play strictly dominated strategies.
Therefore, in a game we can eliminate all strictly dominated
strategies.
• be careful: once strictly dominated strategies have been
eliminated one should check if, on the remaining non-eliminated
strategies space, there are “revealed” strictly dominated
strategies.
Example
Use the iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies on
the following game
Player 2
Left Middle Right
Up 1, 0 1, 2 0, 1
Player 1
Down 0, 3 0, 1 2, 0
Two caveats: The process of iterated elimination of s.d.s.
1. additional assumptions about players’ rationality should be 13
imposed.
2. need not lead to a “solution” of the game
Nash Equilibrium
The idea behind the Nash Equilibrium (NE) concept is simple:
given the choices of all other players (no matter if these
choices are “best,” “rational,” etc.) should I change my choice?
No, I shouldn’t IF I have chosen the action that yields the best
for me (BEST RESPONSE) for the given choices of others!
15
Example 1’: Consider again the typical “prisoner’s dilemma”
game as in the table below
Player 2
Lie Confess
Lie -1, -1 -9, 0
Player 1
Confess 0, -9 -6, -6
16
Example 2’: Consider again a duopoly where firms produce an
identical product (at zero per unit cost) and “simultaneously”
choose quantities (i.e., competition à la Cournot). Let the inverse
market demand be 𝒑 = 𝟏 − 𝒒𝟏 − 𝒒𝟐 .
17
Nash Equilibrium: None, one, or many?
In the examples we have previously discussed we identified a unique
Nash Equilibrium in each one. Is it always the case?
Example 3
Battle of the Sexes
Player 2
UFC Opera
UFC 2, 1 0, 0
Player 1
Opera 0, 0 1, 2
(an example with two Nash equilibria)
Example 4
Matching the Pennies
Player 2
Heads Tails
Heads 1, -1 -1, 1
Player 1
Tails -1, 1 1, -1 18
(an example with no (?) Nash Equilibrium)
Nash Equilibrium: None, one, or many?
Implications of example 3:
⁻ When there are multiple Nash equilbria there is a tiny little
problem! We cannot be sure as to which Nash equilibrium
will prevail (or, IF any of the Nash equilibria will be realized at
the end!).
⁻ We will discuss later the problem of coordination failure.
Implications of example 4:
⁻ In many cases it is essential to identify if a game has a
solution (i.e., Nash equilibrium) or not!
⁻ However, we will see that the game of “matching the
pennies” has actually a Nash Equilibrium.
19
Time to practice!
Consider a Cournot triopoly where firms have zero marginal and
zero fixed costs and the inverse demand is described by
𝟑
𝑨 − 𝒒𝟏 − 𝒒𝟐 − 𝒒𝟑 , 𝒊𝒇 𝒒𝒊 ≤ 𝑨
𝒑= 𝒊=𝟏
𝟎, 𝒐𝒕𝒉𝒆𝒓𝒘𝒊𝒔𝒆
20