Walter Benjamin Images The Creaturely And The Holy Sigrid Weigel pdf download
Walter Benjamin Images The Creaturely And The Holy Sigrid Weigel pdf download
https://ebookbell.com/product/walter-benjamin-images-the-
creaturely-and-the-holy-sigrid-weigel-51942230
https://ebookbell.com/product/walter-benjamins-concept-of-the-image-
benjamin-walter-ross-5288802
https://ebookbell.com/product/walter-benjamins-archive-images-texts-
signs-walter-benjamin-ursula-marx-5316304
https://ebookbell.com/product/the-arcades-project-walter-
benjamin-2435612
https://ebookbell.com/product/walter-benjamin-selected-writings-
vol-4-19381940-first-edition-benjamin-26429476
On Hashish 1st Walter Benjamin
https://ebookbell.com/product/on-hashish-1st-walter-benjamin-5478458
https://ebookbell.com/product/origin-of-the-german-trauerspiel-1st-
edition-walter-benjamin-54996836
https://ebookbell.com/product/on-photography-walter-benjamin-10665374
https://ebookbell.com/product/the-storyteller-essays-walter-
benjamin-33980836
https://ebookbell.com/product/on-photography-walter-benjamin-38032620
WALTER BENJAMIN
Cultural Memory
Present
Sigrid Weigel
STANFORD, CALIFORNIA
Stanford University Press
Stanford, California
English translation © 20!3 by Sigrid Weigel. All rights reserved.
Walter Benjamin: Images, the Creaturely, and the Holy was originally published in
German under the tide Die Kreatur, das Heilige, die Bilder © S. Fischer Verlag
GmbH, Frankfurt am Main, 2008.
This translation has been made possible by the support of the German Federal
Ministry of Education and Research.
No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any
means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or in any
information storage or retrieval system without the prior written permission of
Stanford University Press.
Illustrations Xl
Acknowledgments XVll
Foreword XlX
Appendix
Documentation ofthe Correspondence on the Odyssey
Taken by Benjamin's Trauerspiel Book in the KBW:
Extracts from the Letters
Illustrations
CHAPTER 8
Illustration I: Wiener Genesis (series 5r) I87
Illustration 2: Ira, detail from Le Virtu e i Vizi, around I305,
Fresco, Padua, Cappella degli Scrovegni I88
CHAPTER 9
Illustration I: Albrecht Durer, Melencolia I (I5I4), engraving 212
Illustration 2: Paul Klee, Angelus Novus (I920), oil crayon
printed on watercolor 2I3
Illustration 3: Matthias Grunewald, Isenheimer Altar (I5I5),
first panel 222
Illustration 4: Panel of the Resurrection, high altar 223
Illustration 5: Concert of Angels 224
Illustration 6: Charles Meryon, Les nuits de mai (I87I), engraving 227
Illustration 7: Gustave Courbet, La vague (I87o), oil on canvas 227
Illustration 8: Wiener Genesis, Pol. I4r (illustration 27) 23I
Illustration 9: Wiener Genesis, Pol. I5r (illustration 29) 23I
CHAPTER IO
Illustration I: David Octavius Hill, In Greyfriar Cemetery
in Edinburgh, I843-I848 256
Illustration 2: Felix Nadar, The Paris Sewer, around I86o 257
Illustration 3: August Sander, Catholic Cleric/Clergyman, I927 258
Illustration 4: Eugene Atget, 9I rue de Turenne, I9II 259
Illustration 5: Karl Blossfeldt, Ur-forms ofArt, Tritonia crocosmiflora
und Delphinuim, I928 260
APPENDIX
Title page from Benjamin's The Origin ofthe German Mourning
Play, with Warburg's dedication to Saxl (WIA) 271
Explanation ofTranslation and Citation
holiness is an order reserved for life means that the concept 'life' refers pre-
cisely to that dimension that transcends mere natura/life to the order of the
holy. It is through a reference to the divine order that the concept of life
first accrues a meaning that makes it more than bare life. This super-natu-
ral (uber-naturliche) dimension of the concept of life relies on the biblical
notion that human life is part of divine Creation. It maintains its particu-
lar contours within the idea inherent to this tradition that man was made
in the divine image, even when this 'more-than-natural-life' has then been
transformed into philosophical, ethical, or other principles after the bible
lost its claim to authority and validity (Chapter 3). A world apart, human
activity is fundamentally different from Creation: the fruits or products
of human production are artifacts, or as Benjamin says, formed structures
(Gebilde).
Yet as a part of creation, itself a creature ( Geschiipf), the human has
a share in the world of creaturely 1-so long as humans are situated in the
state of Creation. The concept, understanding, and interpretation of hu-
mans as creaturely are leitmotifs in the ideas, texts, and images from both
the baroque and modernity that are Benjamin's objects of investigation. In
his commentary on the topic, he interprets the concept of the creaturely as
both an expression and an indication (Anzeichen) of a "counter-historical"
stance-not a-historic, but rather an attitude in contradiction to a histori-
cal understanding. It comes from the wish to return to the state of Cre-
ation, and to this end it leads to history's conversion back into a kind of
state of nature. The concept of the creature is, in this way, a symptom of
a confusion of the state of Creation with the state of nature (Chapter I).
His remark that the attribute of holiness is but a belletristic cliche
certainly does not mean that in Benjamin's view the holy is unimport-
r. During the constitution of the German language, when Latin words were translated
by inventing new German words, it often happened that the Latin word got integrated into
the lexicon as well, with the result a semantic differentiation between the foreign word and
its German equivalent. The translation of Latin creatura into 'Schopfung' (Creation) and
'Geschopf' (creation) is part of Luther's German and refers to a biblical context; its con-
notation stems from the expression 'Gottes Geschopf'(God's creation). In distinction to
'Geschopf' the word 'Kreatur' has acquired another connotation that is more linked to the
natural, bodily, or animallike state of living beings, including humans. Since the difference
between the meanings is central for the whole argument of the book, we will use creation
for 'Geschopf,' creature/ creaturely for 'Kreatur,' and Creation for 'Schopfung.'
Foreword xx1
ant for poetical works (Dichtung). 2 Quite the opposite. Benjamin's cri-
tique is in fact aimed against programs of art that sacralize poetic creation
and thereby attribute a divine mandate, as it were, to the poet. Benjamin,
rather, sees the poet as a descendant of cultic practices that are lost in his-
tory (understood as the distance from Creation) and considers Dichtung
more as a refuge for concerns that have slipped away from theology. The
latter is less due to the poet than it has to do with language, because every
language (at least in European history) to some degree stands in the lineage
of biblical language, which is the medium of revelation, although this is
the case mainly in the mode of loss, translation, and conventionalization,
that is, in the mode of distance and disfigurement (Entstellung). 3 Benjamin
treats the distance from Creation, in which language also partakes in his-
tory, as a structural distinction between it and revelation. If, however, po-
etic engagement with language is reminiscent of the Heiligung des Namem,
because the words are "called by their names," poetic works become the site
of a breach through which meanings that originate in a higher order can
enter. Nevertheless, poetic works never become identical with the higher
order; nor do they become its secular substitute (Chapter 4).
Taking center stage in this book is Benjamin's recognition of the fact
that not the least, but actually the weightiest, concepts and ideas in Euro-
pean thought (such as life, the human, and justice) arise from biblical tra-
dition. Also of primary concern, however, are the consequences that this
recognition has for the formation of his theory and his engagement with
language and history, and with literature and art. Today, Benjamin's rhe-
torical question, quoted above in the letter to Scholem, demands a clear
and decisive answer: it is necessary. Considering the fact that he actually
considered commentary on the holy to be superfluous, it is surprising how
heavily the reception of Benjamin troubles itself with his engagement with
theology, religion, and the divine (Chapter r). In this regard, a structural
2. Benjamin uses both words 'Dichtung' and 'Literatur,' the latter having a more pro-
fane meaning and including all sorts of texts, whereas 'Dichtung' is reserved for art and dis-
cussed in respect of its complex relationship to sacred scriptures.
3· The Freudian term for dreamwork Entstellung will be translated in this book as 'dis-
figurement' instead of 'distortion,' which belongs to the repeatedly criticized translated
terms in Standard Edition of Freud. As regards the other two terms ofdreamwork, this book
follows the Standard Edition in taking 'displacement' for Verschiebung and 'condensation'
for Verdichtung.
xx11 Foreword
consciousness for biblical language, holy orders, and the idea of salvation
without being tied to it through confession. That the terms of the divine
order have singular meanings that may not be transferred into the secular
order of human action and social communication is a fixed point within
his thought. This acceptance of biblical language absent faith may be de-
scribed as jewish thinking in a world without God, to borrow the wonderful
title of the Festschrift for Stephane Moses (Festschrift 2000). This thinking
is not to be confused with negative theology, in which the Deus abscondicus
itself becomes the center of, and point of reference for, a religious com-
portment. Nor should it be aligned with a variant of negative theology
critical of capitalism that makes the bourgeois world in the image of hell
into the object of a quasi-religious evocation (Chapter 5).
Blumenberg once remarked that the God of philosophers is unfeel-
ing, while that of the bible is hypersensitive: "therefore the theologians
speak in the idiom of philosophy in order to spare their God: could he bear
the language of the Bible?" (Blumenberg 1998, 19, my trans.) With Benja-
min, one must object to this interpretation to the extent that in his view,
theology as speech about God has already been differentiated from bibli-
cal language, since it always implies a speaking in history after the "Fall of
language-mind," at a distance from creation, so that this fact can rather
clarifY the closeness the theological idiom has to the language of philoso-
phy. Contrarily, Benjamin is adamant that there is an afterlife of biblical
language, and indeed in poetic works. Dichtung does not inherit the tradi-
tion in such a way that it can be possessed as a resource at Dichtung's dis-
posal, but rather in the sense that poetic works provide a site for a breach
through which "something beyond the poet interrupts the language of po-
etry" (Chapter 4). In this way, his engagement with the tradition does not
conform to the opposition of theology to philosophy. Benjamin's position
beyond theology and philosophy finds expression mainly in his figures of
speech, thought-images, and dialectic images. The genuinely Benjaminian
use of language systematically disappears in most translations of his writ-
ings into other languages. Because the thought-images are translated either
as metaphors or as concepts, his theory often loses its specific signature in
international reception. Whereas, because of this elision, his reflections
appear to be a great deal more easily compatible with current theoretical
discourses, it is often the case that the dimension of language that recalls
religious quotations is unrecognizable (Chapter 7).
xx1v Foreword
Forgotten Images:
The Significance of Art in Benjamin's Epistemology
4· Ursprung des deutschen Trauerspiels, often referred to as Origin ofGerman Tragic Drama.
The latter mistakes an important argument: In two early essays, written in 1916 just before his
language theory, Benjamin discussed the contrast between Tragodie (tragic drama) and Trauer-
spiel (mourning play) in respect of totally different concepts of time, language, and emotion.
There, he already emphasized mourning and the relation of history and nature in Trauerspiel,
which later on became leitmotifs of his book on the baroque mourning play.
5· Translator's note: The Habilitationsschrift is the postdoctoral, professional disserta-
tion required by German universities to obtain the rank of professor and then lecture at a
universi ry.
xxv1 Foreword
sponse. His response certainly does not take place under the banner of
legitimacy, but rather of the responsibility of acting subjects. Subsequent to
the assertion that "[t]hose who base a condemnation of all violent killing
of one person by another on the commandment are therefore mistaken,"
he writes: "it [the prohibition-S.W] exists not as a criterion of judgment,
but as a guideline for acting of persons or communities who have to en-
gage with it in solitude and, in monstrous cases (in ungeheuren Fallen), to
take on themselves the responsibility to disregard it (von ihm abzusehen)"
(250, transl. mod.; Chapter 3).
The question will not be addressed here as to from which motives
Benjamin's discussion of the aloneness in which one must take the respon-
sibility in disregarding the commandment "Thou shall not kill" is virtually
ignored or bypassed in a systematic way. With reference to his famous dec-
laration "detour is method," however, it can be asserted that circumvention
also is and has a method. In this case, it seems to be a necessary precon-
dition to be able to position Benjamin's reflections on violence in close
proximity to a theory of the state ofexception and thereby to integrate the
"Critique ofViolence" within the paradigms of political theology. At pres-
ent, the author who gives this positioning the greatest weight is Giorgio
Agamben. He claims that though Benjamin "does not name the state of
exception in the essay," he nevertheless proceeds, retrenching his argument
slightly: "though he does use the term Ernstfoll, which appears in Schmitt
as a synonym for Ausnahmezustand." In interpreting the appearance of
Ernstjall as evidence, Agamben adds another indication for the claimed af-
finity to Schmitt: "But another technical term from Schmitt's vocabulary
is present in the text: Entscheidung, 'decision.' Law, Benjamin writes, 'ac-
knowledges in the "decision" determined by place and time a metaphysical
category"' (Agamben, State ofException 53).
The claim that Benjamin uses Schmitt's terms and concepts is an
important cornerstone both for Agamben's reading of an "exoteric debate
between Benjamin and Schmitt" (55) and for his interpretation of the rela-
tionship between the two theories, which amounts to a distinction of two
sides of the law, both on this side and beyond, in dealing with violence in
the state of exception: "While Schmitt attempts every time to re-inscribe
violence within a juridical context, Benjamin responds to this gesture by
seeking every time to assure-as pure violence-an existence outside the
law" (Agamben, State ofException 53). Yet in Agamben's summary, not only
XXVlll Foreword
Dialectic of Secularization
1. This is also the case in my own earlier reading of the Kraus essay as a critique of the
paradigm of 'mind versus sex' and as a theory of Eros and language: "Eros and Language.
Benjamin's Kraus Essay," in Benjamin's Ghosts, ed. Gerhard Richter (Stanford UP 2002). An
exception is Alexander Honold's recent article on Karl Kraus for the Benjamin handbook.
Honold had already examined the central significance of Benjamin's literary quotations in
his study onDer Leser Walter Benjamin (Berlin: Vorwerk 8 20oo).
4 On the Threshold Between Creation and Last judgment
Tacitly, in these famous sentences, the holy has given place to the modest yet ques-
tionable concept oflaw. But this nature of Stifter's and his moral universe are trans-
parent enough to escape any confusion with Kant, and to be still recognizable in
their core as creature. 2
Though appearing harmless at first glance, Benjamin singles out the fact
that Stifter describes natural phenomena as the effect of "far higher laws"
and thus discovers therein a far-from-harmless operation: a tacit substitu-
tion of the holy with a concept of law whose origin in religion is to be dis-
cerned only in the attribute "higher." He continues:
This insolently secularized thunder and lightning, storms, surf, and earthquakes-
cosmic man has won them back for Creation by making them its answer, like a
statement of the Last Judgment, to the criminal existence of men; only that the
span between Creation and the Last Judgment finds no redemptive fulfillment
here, let alone a historical overcoming. (II.I/340; Se!Wr 1.437; emphasis S.W) 3
2. Our modified translation gives creature or creaturely instead of creation for German
Kreatur. Benjamin's essay reflects on the relations and tensions between Kreaturlcreature,
Geschiipf/creation, and Schiipfung/Creation in the sense of Genesis. This leitmotif gets lost
in translation since all English translations of the Kraus essay translate Kreatur by "creation."
For the problem of translations of Benjamin's writings, see here Chapter 7· Benjamin's
Kreatur emphasizes the relatedness of human beings to animals, i.e., to creaturely life, where-
as Geschiipf means a product of God's Creation. In addition to this the discussed relation-
ship between Genesis/ Schiipfung, generation/ Erzeugung, and procreation/Zeugung opens the
door to sexual connotations. For this see my earlier article on "Eros and Language" (note 1).
J. Our modified translation gives "like a statement of the Last Judgment" instead of
'world-historical' for the German weltgerichtlich, which seemingly has been mistaken as
weltgeschichtlich. Benjamin's reference to Weltgericht in its double meaning of Last Judg-
ment and worldly court is crucial for the whole essay in which he illuminates the biblical
legacy in Kraus's references to justice and to worldly courts/laws. What is at stake here is
The Creaturely and the Holy 5
What instantly catches one's attention here is the word 'insolently' (schnode).
It separates Stifter's version of a poetic secularization of natural phenomena
both from a secularization that would somehow not be insolent, and from
one that would be more than insolent, perhaps contemptible. Notable,
too, is the characterization of the concept of law as "modest yet question-
able" (dem bescheidenen, doch bedenklichen Begriffdes Gesetzes). The ambi-
guity of the attribute bescheiden, which means 'moderate' but might also
be read as 'scanty' or 'insufficient,' is echoed in the oscillation of bedenklich
between 'requiring interrogation' and 'dubious,' even 'discreditable.'
Benjamin's commentary on this insolent secularization consists of
two arguments. The first is that in speaking of the 'effects of far higher
laws,' Stifter replaces the concept of the holy with the concept of law, a
substitution that, since it has occurred 'tacitly,' remains concealed. The
questionable (bedenkliche) character of the concept of law is not least the
result of the tacit substitution through which the formulation 'higher laws'
can continue to profit from the allusion to the holy even as law seems to
have left the sphere of the holy behind. The second argument is initiated
with the word 'but' and highlights the transparency of Stifter's concept of
nature and of his moral universe, through which their creaturely status
remains discernible: this is why they therefore cannot be confused with
the Kantian moral universe. Benjamin does not undertake a closer exami-
nation of the opposite form, that is, of a form of appearance that would
be obscure and not transparent, so that the creatureliness of Stifter's na-
ture would then not be recognizable. At most, such a contrast is hinted
at through the reference to the Kantian moral universe, lest it concern
Stifter's nature alone. The pathos formula of the "two things" that "fill the
mind with ever new and increasing admiration and awe" that we find in
the Critique of Practical Reason in the form of the much-quoted phrase
"the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me" 4 is contra-
dicted in Bunte Steine by the way in which Stifter distinguishes between
these "two things." Stifter views "conspicuous events" in nature as mani-
festations of general laws that act silently and incessantly, while "the mir-
acles of the moment when deeds are performed" are for him only small
the notion of a Last Judgment that already casts its shadow on all notions of justice within
this world.
4· Immanuel Kant, Critique of Practical Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1999), 161.
6 On the Threshold Between Creation and Last judgment
signs of a general power. This power is the moral law, which, in Stifter's
view, "acts silently, animating the soul through the infinite intercourse of
human beings" (SelWr 1.437). Hence admiration in the face of natural laws
is distinguished from admiration owing to moral laws. By means of his
commentary on Stifter, Benjamin indirectly criticizes Kant's ethics, which,
in assuming a life of 'intelligence' independent of the entire world of the
senses, 5 fail to recognize the creaturely core of nature-including human
nature. Although Benjamin emphasizes the greater transparency in Stifter's
differentiation between nature and moral universe, what still troubles him
in the text is the use of the concept of law to function as a term projected
onto nature that, like a screen, conceals the notion of the holy.
The definition of a form of non-insolent secularization remains a
void in Benjamin's text, and the task of imagining it is left to his read-
ers. This much is clear, however: the question concerning the possibil-
ity of different forms of secularization that is automatically posed by the
word 'insolently' points toward the issue of the cognizability of the substi-
tutions through which secularizing operations take place. Benjamin's ob-
servation that Stifter's substitution has taken place 'tacitly' implies that
another linguistic or rhetorical mode would be required if it were to be-
come cognizable. Secularization that does not operate insolently is thus
implicitly defined as a reflexive stance in one's dealings with the legacies of
religion in the modern age. The argument up to this point may be sum-
marized as follows: in the context of secularization, Benjamin criticizes the
concept of the law as a screen term to the extent that it conceals within it
the precise relationship between the holy and the creaturely. Thus the pas-
sage gathers together the three central terms-the law, the holy, and the
creaturely-that have been the object of widespread interest in recent Ben-
jamin scholarship.
In order to clarify the importance of insolent secularization for the
work on Karl Kraus, the context of the passage needs to be explained. The
quoted sentences occur in the first part of the essay Karl Kraus of 1931,
which is composed as a triptych whose three chapters are titled Allmensch,
Damon, and Unmensch. Translated in the English edition as 'Cosmic Man,'
'Demon,' and 'Monster,' the pair of ambiguous words All- and Unmensch
(profiting from the tension between the prefixes all and un, and literally
meaning 'every men' and 'an a-human being') is strongly determined since
5. Kant, r6rff.
The Creaturely and the Holy 7
cosmos' (stemming from Greek KO<JJ..LO<;, the order of the world or the
state) emphasizes the aspect of order or universe and 'monster' carries a
negative connotation. Unmensch, on the other hand, personifies the lack
of all ordinary human attributes and attitudes; he is less a monster than an
a-human being similar to the angel and the envoy (Bote).
In Benjamin's essay, Kraus is presented as a polemicist with an atti-
tude that Benjamin characterizes as noblesse in armor. Kraus's criterion for
world-historical villainy, according to Benjamin, lies beyond any bourgeois
respectability, which he sees as only being capable of plain (home-made)
villainy. His criterion is instead described by Benjamin as a 'theological
tact.' Tact is thus understood not as a skill that eases social interaction but
as "the capacity to treat social relationships, though not departing from
them, as natural, even paradisiac, relationships, and so not only to ap-
proach the king as if he had been born with the crown on his brow, but the
lackey like an Adam in livery" (Il.J/339; SelWr 2.436ff.) This means that
tact is, far from adherence to a social norm, a means of treating the crea-
ture as a divine Creation.
6. Benjamin's usage of allmenschlich connotes not only cosmos (All) but also the ordi-
nary notion of human in the sense of menscheln.
8 On the Threshold Between Creation and Last judgment
tory are mistaken for the innocence of paradise and where "purity'' is dis-
cerned in, of all things, animals. The name 'creature' stands precisely for
this projection of the state of Creation onto history. When the human
being sees its own face in the mirror image of the animal creature, Cre-
ation and history merge into one. fu emblems of Kraus's attitude, Benja-
min discovers something "infinitely questionable" in the animals, above
all because they are his own creations, "recruited solely from those whom
Kraus himself first called intellectually to life, whom he conceived (zeugte)
and convinced (iiberzeugte) in one and the same act" (438). Here Benja-
min takes Kraus's work as an example of an autopoetic system wherein
his own imaginative projections are regarded as the embodiments of Cre-
ation, and in whose mirrorings a reflection of the Creation falls back
upon the author. The critique is then intensified in Benjamin's image of
the "temple of creature." Benjamin poses a grave objection against such a
procedure, one central to present-day debates about fictionalized works of
Holocaust witness: 7 "His testimony can determine only those for whom
it can never become an act of procreation (Bestimmen kann sein Zeugnis
nur die, denen es Zeugung nie werden kann)" (II.I/341; SelWr 2.438). With
this statement, Benjamin criticizes reference to animals as the represen-
tatives of a creaturely state of innocence, as if conferred upon them by
divine Creation, a reference that disregards the real living animals. In-
stead Benjamin reserves the act of witnessing (Zeugnis) for a constellation
free of'intellectual' procreation (Zeugung), that is, the generation of'life'
through an act of imagination.
His commentary on the ambiguity of meaning that is character-
istic of Karl Kraus's speeches and writings cannot be discussed in detail
here. However, in the course of his discussion of the concrete themes, ob-
jects, and motifs in Kraus's texts, Benjamin comes back again and again
to the basic structure of a significant historico-philosophical topography:
the "span between Creation and Last Judgment." For Benjamin, Kraus
embodies a stance that-in the midst of modernity and its technological
features-takes up a relation to the theological inheritance through such
7. In respect of the aftermath of the Holocaust, I have analyzed the concept of Zeugnis by
differentiating between the gesture of witness and the historical and legal notion of testimo-
ny; see my article "Zeugnis und Zeugenschaft. Klage und Anklage. Zur Geste des Bezeugens
in der Differenz von identity politics, juristischem und historiographischem Diskurs," in
Zeugnis und Zeugenschaft. Einstein Forum jahrbuch I999 (Berlin: Akademie 2000), m-13 5.
10 On the Threshold Between Creation and Last judgment
In Benjamin's book the Baroque serves as the site and stage of the sov-
ereign prince who, on account of his Janus-like stance between "the unlim-
ited hierarchical dignity, with which he is divinely invested" and his state
as a poor human being, can develop in both directions: to become a tyrant
as well as a "victim to the disproportion" between the two states (Origins
70). Yet also in this book, the creature takes on a similar significance to that
in the Kraus essay:
The creature is the mirror within whose frame alone the moral world was revealed
to the baroque. A concave mirror; for this was not possible without distortion.
Since it was the view of the age that all historical life was lacking in virtue, virtue
became of no significance also for the inner constitution of the dramatis personae
themselves. It has never taken a more uninteresting form than in the heroes of
these Trauerspiele, in which the only response to the call of history is the physical
pain of martyrdom. And just as the inner life of the person in the creaturely condi-
tion has to attain mystical fulfillment, even in mortal pain, so do authors attempt
to freeze the historical events. The sequence of dramatic actions unfolds as in the
days ofCreation, when it was not history which was taking place. (I.I/2 70; Origins
91; emphasis S.W)
In the conditions of history in which virtue and historical life have become
separated, the person reverts to the creaturely condition-a constellation
which for Benjamin is characterized by three elements: the standstill of his-
tory, physical pain, and the meaninglessness of inner virtue. This descrip-
tion may help to explain Benjamin's barely comprehensible interpretation
of the Baroque as the complete secularization of the historical in the state
of Creation (Origins 92).
The Origin ofthe German Mourning Play occupies a particular position
in Benjamin's works as in it he writes explicitly of secularization, using the
term itsel£ It is admittedly less striking when he calls the Baroque Trauer-
spiel a "secularized Christian drama'' (78) or when he refers to the king in
the Spanish Baroque drama as a "secularized redemptive power." The no-
table formulation concerning the "comprehensive secularization of the his-
torical in the state of Creation," which he describes as the last word in the
escapism of the Baroque, is, however, not so easy to understand. The un-
usual reference to the "secularization of the historical," which runs coun-
12 On the Threshold Between Creation and Last judgment
history back into nature, or, more precisely, into the "iron constitution of
the laws of nature" (Origins 74) whereby standstill, in the sense of petri-
faction, is seen as both the ideal and goal of dictatorial force. The image
of a counterhistorical or antihistorical stance appears as a leitmotif in the
Baroque drama, establishing the framework within which the Baroque is
constituted without being able to lessen its distance from the "innocent
first day of Creation." Since there can be no return to the paradisiacal state
in which nature and Creation were still identical, the world image that is
the product of an antihistorical attitude bears the features of an (in the
final analysis impossible) imitation of Creation: "The sequence of dramatic
actions unfolds as in the days of Creation, when it was not history which
was taking place" (91). Benjamin speaks in this context of an antihistorical
re-creation. This renewed creation is not only directed against history but
also presumes, in opposition to history, to be able to orient itself in respect
of the world of Creation.
One example of the embodiment of an "antihistorical new-creation"
is for him the case of the "chaste princess" of the martyr-drama, who, like
Gryphius's Catharina, resists the tyrant despite being subjected to torture.
Her "chastity'' is as far removed from "innocence" as nature is from para-
dise. Rather, it is the result of a stoic technique, not dissimilar to the "iron
laws of nature" the tyrant attempts to substitute for history. The difference
is that, unlike in the case of the tyrant, it is the result not of unlimited ab-
solutist power but rather of a kind of empowerment to "a state of excep-
tion of the soul, the rule of affects," through "stoic technique" (I.I/253;
Origins 74). Analogies to this in the Kraus essay are biblical pathos and the
phrasings described by Benjamin as a "spawn of technology" (II.I/336ff.;
SelWr 2.435).
In comparison to the complex constellation of secularization in The
Origin ofthe German Mourning Play, the relevance of secularization to mo-
dernity in the Kraus essay is patently reduced, whereas the theological heri-
tage of the Baroque is above all tied to the concept of creature. Perhaps this
also helps to explain why in "Karl Kraus" he speaks only of an insolent secu-
larization. In claiming that theAllmensch has won back for Creation the "in-
solently secularized thunder and lightning, storms, surf, and earthquakes"
by turning them into a Last Judgment's answer to the criminal existence of
men, Benjamin here emphasizes the other side of secularization. It is char-
acterized less by the withdrawal of a supernatural significance in the state of
14 On the Threshold Between Creation and Last judgment
When one reads the Kraus essay, a number of aspects and strands
of the critical reception of Benjamin's works come into play. There is in
the first place the debate about Benjamin's position vis-a-vis theology
and secularization, which began with the diagnosis of the "rescuing aban-
donment of theology, its unrestrained secularization," as Adorno formu-
lated it in his introduction to the first, two-volume edition of Benjamin's
Schriften of 1955. 8 It was continued, for example, by Hans Heinz Holz,
who thought to have discovered in Benjamin's work a connection between
a "metaphysics grounded in a philosophy of religion" and Marxist philos-
ophy of history, 9 and with Heinz-Dieter Kittsteiner's refusal "to interpret
Benjamin theologically." 10 Gerhard Kaiser intervened in this debate, turn-
ing above all against Adorno and arguing that Benjamin does not belong
in the intellectual history of secularization since his thought moves in a
counterdirection that draws very clear distinctions between the profane
and the messianic. 11 At the same time he observed in Benjamin a freedom
"to think strictly theologically while at the same time, without there being
any contradiction to this approach, surrendering the human being to his
,12
autonomy.
This debate is largely founded upon the paradigm of transferal,
whereby secularization is understood as the transferal of religious or theo-
logical meanings into worldly affairs. It is motivated by an opposition
between messianism and history and in large part circles around the ques-
tion of which side is given priority in Benjamin's writings-though Benja-
min himself, as the so-called Theological-Political Fragment demonstrates,
has shaped the relationship between the two as an interacting counter-
striving constellation. In 1992, Uwe Steiner rescued the issue of seculariza-
tion from the two opposing camps (the supporters of theology on the one
hand and those of Marxism on the other) by trimming it back to the ques-
tion of secularization as a descriptive historical category. 13 It was a reason-
able and liberating step for critical reception of Benjamin's work in view
of the previous deadlock, but it circumvented the problem that there can
be no contribution to the history of secularization that does not adopt a
position vis-a-vis its preconditions, because theories of secularization al-
ways imply certain ways of addressing concepts derived from the spheres
of cults, theology, Holy Scripture, and religion. This is certainly true in
Benjamin's case.
This was already noticeable at the beginning of the controversy, for
example when Adorno suggested that Benjamin's position is close to that
of Karl Kraus: "Reading profane texts as if they were holy ones is not the
least of the operations by which theology is secularized for the sake of its
own salvation. This was the basis of Benjamin's elective affinity with Karl
Kraus." However, when Adorno argues that the historical appears in Ben-
jamin's work "as if it were nature," then he is overlooking the fact that
Benjamin talks of the secularization of the historical, not of theology. The
same can be said of Adorno's diagnosis of a mythical trend in the "imagis-
tic character of Benjamin's speculations," which, he argues, comes from the
fact that "beneath the contemplative gaze what was historical was trans-
formed into nature on account of its own frailty and everything that was
natural into a piece of the story of Creation." 14 Here he fails to see that
Benjamin ascribes this process to the "escapism of the baroque" and does
not subscribe to it himself.
At the heart of this reading is a misunderstanding of the concept of
nature in Benjamin's book on the Trauerspiel. Adorno reads it as evidence
of a "deep, somewhat antiquarian allegiance of Benjamin's to Kant, above
13. Uwe Steiner, "Sakularisierung. Oberlegungen zum Ursprung und zu einigen Implika-
tionen des Begriffs bei Benjamin," in Walter Benjamin, r892-I940, ed. U. Steiner, Uwe (Bern:
Peter Lang 1992), 141.
14. Adorno (note 9), p. xvi.
16 On the Threshold Between Creation and Last judgment
all to his conclusive distinction between nature and the supernatural," and
he claims to discover in Benjamin an "involuntary reformulation and alien-
ation'' of Kantian categories, whereby he additionally equates Benjamin's
idea of the supernatural with reconciliation. 15 Yet although the category of
the supernatural in Kant's essay "The Only Possible Argument in Support
of a Demonstration of the Existence of God" (1763) is relevant to the su-
pernatural character of divine Creation, Benjamin uses this word in order
to discuss the double meaning of the term "life": as mere and higher life, or
as natural and supernatural, as can be seen in his essay on Goethe's Elective
Affinities (SelWr 1.308).
An offshoot of the controversy concerning Benjamin's position vis-
a-vis theology is the debate over his relation to Schmitt, which has in part
picked up the confessional gesture that meanwhile has cooled down in the
arguments over theology. Although this debate is still conducted in terms
of pros and cons, the aspects of the two writers' references to one another
as well as their major differences have nevertheless been usefully elucidated
in a number of contributions dealing with the differences between Benja-
min's interpretation of Baroque sovereignty and Schmitt's theory of mod-
ern sovereignty, as well as those between their specific conceptualizations
of the state of exception. It must be said, however, that the consequences
these differences have for the understanding of and the approach to secu-
larization have not yet been analyzed.
A further development of the controversy about theology is to be
found in the discussion of Benjamin's stance vis-a-vis Jewish tradition and
doctrine. At the center of debate here is Benjamin's complicated dialogue
with his friend Gershom Scholem, which will be analyzed in the sixth
chapter of my book. The controversy touches upon the demarcation line
between the Jewish and the Christian traditions, which in Scholem's view
needs to be strictly observed, 16 but which Benjamin constantly crosses in
his work, in particular when referring to biblical or Adamite language.
The most important site of this argument is Benjamin's essay on Kafka
and the differences in their understanding of Kafka that emerged between
Scholem and Benjamin in its wake. Stephane Moses recently provided
a lengthy account of the intellectual dialogue between the two dissimi-
In addition to the triad of the law, the holy, and the creature, the
concepts discussed in the Kraus essay include justice, the relation between
Last judgment and Creation, and that between witness and procreation.
With these concepts, the themes of the various strands of the reception
of Benjamin discussed above become entangled in a single site. Various
traces of Benjamin's work on a dialectic of secularization, addressed in
earlier essays in relation to single themes using a number of registers, such
as Eros, language, justice, history, sovereignty, also converge in this essay.
If one looks back from the Kraus essay over these preceding texts, then the
work on a dialectic of secularization becomes visible as a constant motif
in Benjamin's writings. It pertains to the theory of language in his early
texts, one derived from the caesura between Adamite language and the
language of signs. This dialectic is relevant to his interpretation of transla-
tion as the measure of the distance from pure language ("The Task of the
Translator"), his analysis of the relation between justice and the law ("Cri-
tique ofViolence"), and the development of the figuration, instructive for
the theory of history, of the counterstriving constellation of the profane
and the messianic-all of which come from the early 1920s. It is relevant,
too, to his critique of the attempt to appropriate a divine mandate into
the theology of poetry propagated by Stefan George and his disciples, the
discussion of the idea of a nexus of guilt among the living (in the essay
on Goethe that followed a few years later), the examination of the Janus-
like figure of the sovereign and of allegory in The Origin of the German
Mourning Play, and the figure of profane illumination found in the essay
on surrealism from the late 1920s-to mention only the most important
points during this period. And of course the trail continues even after the
Kraus essay, in the way Benjamin elucidates the afterlife of such theo-
logical concepts as inherited sin, guilt, and shame in the world of Kafka's
Trial, for example. This world appears to Kafka's characters, who have lost
the doctrines and knowledge of the theological origins of their concepts,
as a purely creaturely world. The trail also runs through the "Urgeschichte
der Moderne'' (an ur-history or archaic history of modernity) in which the
phenomena of a world saturated with technology and machines appear
to those who have produced them as natural history and modernity itself
becomes the time of hell, and finally through the concept of the Now or
jetztzeit, as the model of messianic time, in the theses "On the Concept
of History."
Random documents with unrelated
content Scribd suggests to you:
Naturally enough, when private libraries were the fashion there
were numerous public libraries as well. According to Publius Victor,
there were no fewer than twenty-nine of these public libraries in
Rome. Asinius Pollio, the friend of Cæsar, and the famous patron of
literature of his time, who died in the year 6 b.c., was credited with
being the founder of the first public library, although there is a
tradition that Orielus Paullus, the conqueror of Macedonia, brought
back with him to Rome a large collection of books in 168 b.c. Be that
as it may, there probably was no very great taste for reading in
Rome at that early period, and it was not until the time of Augustus
that public libraries began to assume real importance.
Augustus himself, carrying out the intention of Julius Cæsar,
founded two public libraries, one called the Octavian, and the other
the Palatine. From that time the founding of public libraries became
a fashion with the emperors, Tiberius, Vespasian, Domitian, and
Trajan successively adding to the number, the most famous
collection of all being the Ulpian library of Trajan. No available data
have come down to us as to the exact size of these libraries, but the
respectable proportions of some of the private collections make it a
safe inference that some, at least, of these public libraries must have
contained hundreds of thousands of books, since we can hardly
suppose that a private library would be allowed to outrival the
imperial collections.
When one reflects on this prevalence of books, the very natural
query arises as to how they were produced, and the answer throws
a vivid light on the social conditions in Rome. The enormous output
of books, almost rivalling the productions of the modern press, was
possible solely because of the great number of slaves in Rome.
Book-making was a profession, but it was a profession apparently
followed almost exclusively by slaves, who were known as librarii.
These educated slaves were usually Greeks, and a large publishing
house, of which there were several in Rome, would keep a great
number of them for purposes both of making the materials for
books, and of transcribing the books themselves.
It is known that shorthand was practised extensively in Rome, and
it has been supposed that a very large number of the current books
were written in this abbreviated hand. This supposition, however,
appears more than doubtful, for it is hardly to be supposed that the
general public took the trouble to learn the Tironian system, by
which name the shorthand script was known; Tiron, the secretary of
Cicero, being commonly, though no doubt incorrectly, credited with
its invention. As to the latter point, there are various references in
the Greek classical authors to the practice of shorthand in ancient
times. It is said even that Xenophon took down the lectures of
Socrates in this way, and whether or not that statement is true, the
existence of the rumour is in itself evidence of the prevalence of the
custom from an early day. Very probably Tiron developed a modified
and greatly improved system of shorthand writing, and doubtless
this became popular, since lexicons were written interpreting the
Tironian script in terms of ordinary Latin. But, as has been said, all
this does not make it probable that the average reader understood
the script, and it seems much more likely that the popular authors
were represented in the ordinary script, subject, however, to
numerous abbreviations. The writers who were most in vogue in
imperial Rome are said to have been Ovid, Propertius, and Martial
among the satirists; Homer, Virgil, and Horace among the poets; and
Cicero, Livy, and Pliny among prose writers. It is alleged that the
works of most of these were in every private collection. Of all this
great store of literary treasures not a single line has been preserved
in the original manuscript, save only a few rolls from the library at
Herculaneum, and most of these are charred and damaged beyond
recognition.
Thanks to the use of slave labour, it would appear that the Roman
publisher was able, not merely to put out large editions of books,
but to sell these at a very reasonable price. According to a statement
of Martial himself, a very good copy of the first book of his epigrams
could be purchased for five denarii. This presumably must refer to
the cheapest edition, probably a papyrus roll, though no definite
data as to the relative cost of papyrus and parchment are available.
Naturally, there were more expensive editions put out for those who
could afford them. It was customary, for example, to tint the back of
the parchment roll with purple; at a later day the inscribed part itself
was sometimes tinted with the same colour, and this custom also
may have prevailed as early as the Roman time. Certain books were
illustrated with pictures, as appears from a remark of Pliny; but this
practice was undoubtedly very exceptional. It may not have been
unusual, however, to ornament or emphasise portions of the
manuscript by using red ink, for the ink wells illustrated in the
paintings of Pompeii are often shown to be double, and the
presumable object of this was to facilitate the use of ink of two
colours.
The pen employed by the Roman scribe was made of a reed and
known as a calamus. It was sharpened and split, not unlike a
modern quill pen. The question has been raised many times as to
whether the Romans did not employ the quill pen itself. Certain
pictures seem to suggest that the quill pen was used not merely by
the Romans, but by the Egyptians as well. There seems little ground
for this supposition, however, and the first specific reference to a
quill pen was in the writings of Isidorus, who died in 636 a.d. This
proves that the use of quills had begun not later than the seventh
century, but it is extremely doubtful whether the Romans employed
them, though the quill seems so obvious a substitute for the reed
that its non-employment causes wonder. But the history of all simple
inventions shows how fallacious would be any argument drawn from
this obvious inference. Incidentally it may be noted that the reed
pen held its own against the quill for some centuries after the
invention of the latter. Even in the late Middle Ages the reed was still
employed for particular kinds of writing in preference to the quill,
and no doubt a certain number of people for generations continued
to prefer the reed, just as there are people now who prefer a quill
pen to the steel pens that were perfected in 1830. Every desk in the
reading room at the British Museum to-day is supplied with a quill as
well as a steel pen; and a fair proportion of the readers there seem
to prefer the former.
It would not do to leave the subject of Roman books without at
least incidental mention of the tablets which were in universal use.
These were probably not employed in writing books for the market,
but it is quite probable that many authors used them in making the
first drafts of their books. The so-called wax tablet was really made
of wood, quite in the form of a modern child’s slate, the wax to
receive the writing being put upon the portion that corresponds to
the slate proper. These tablets were usually bound together in twos
or threes, and only the inner surfaces were employed to receive the
writing, the outer surface being reserved for a title in the case of
business documents, or for the address when the tablet was used as
a letter. When used as business records or in correspondence, the
tablets were bound together with a cord, upon which a seal was
placed. It was quite the rule for a Roman citizen to carry a tablet
about with him for the purpose of making notes. The implement
used in writing was a pointed metal needle known as the stylus. It
was almost dagger-like in proportions, and was sometimes used as a
weapon. It was said that Cæsar once transfixed the arm of Cassius
with his stylus in a fit of anger in the senate chamber itself. The
other end of the stylus was curved or flattened, and was used to
erase the writing on the tablet for corrections or to prepare the
surface for a new inscription.j
Turning from the practicalities of literature to a yet more important
phase of everyday life, let us witness
The guests having risen from this at fall of night, the deductio
begins. The bride is taken from the arms of her mother and
conducted in solemn procession to the new house, the procession
including not only the guests but also the interested public. Flute-
players and torch-bearers lead the way, the procession sings a
fescennine song and echoes the cry talasse; the boys bid the
bridegroom strew walnuts as he is now taking leave of the games of
childhood. The bride is accompanied by three pueri patrimi et
matrimi, one of them bearing a torch in front, the other two leading
the bride; after her are borne distaff and spinning-wheel. The
bridegroom’s torch is not, like the others, made of fine resin, but of
white thorn (Spina alba), which is sacred to Ceres and a charm
against witchery; it is captured by the guests and carried away by
violence. The procession having reached the new house, the bride
anoints the door-posts with fat or oil and binds them with woollen
fillets; then she is borne over the threshold of the house and
received in the atrium by her husband into the common possession
of fire and water; that is to say, she is made a partner in domestic
life and the service of the gods. In the atrium, her future living
room, opposite the door, the lectus genialis is made ready by the
pronuba; here she prays to the gods of the new home for a happy
marriage. On the day after the wedding she receives relations at the
feast of repotia as a matron and presents her first sacrifice to the
gods of the house.f
ebookbell.com