Borer 2009 roots_and_categories
Borer 2009 roots_and_categories
1. Introduction
1.1. A general outline of the system
1. There is only one computational component, call it Syntax, which is responsible for hierarchy forming
and constituent manipulation operations in the grammar. These include such operations when they
are associated with word-internal structure (and specifically, for our purposes, operations which create
complex word derivatives such as trans-form-ation-al or kitchen towel rack (i.e., operations of so called
derivational morphology).
2. A substantive Word, as conventionally conceived, is a syntactic constituent which (happens) to
correspond to a phonological unit of a given size (e.g., for the assignment of primary stress). While it is
likely that there are some universal constraints on what syntactic constituents can correspond to such
phonological units, beyond that, the mapping is language specific, and syntactic constituents of equal
complexity may or may not be phonological-stress units. Crucially, then, substantive Words are not
syntactic primitives or atomic in any meaningful sense.
3. Roots (listemes, in Borer (2005a,b) do not have any internal grammatical structure, and are devoid of
any syntactic value:
a. No category
b. No morphological marking
c. No argument structure (either external or internal).
4. Roots need not correspond to well-formed phonological words.
5. Grammatical Functors (both FL and FF ) are members of the Functor Lexicon (=vocabulary items in
DM).
a. FF : a grammatical functor that projects and licenses a functional node: theD, three#, willT, <pst>T,
<pl>DIV etc.)
b. FLs: a grammatical functor that projects a lexical node: -alA, -ationN, -izeV, -lyAdv, onP
6. English derivational suffixes, instances of FL, merge syntactically with their semantic (functorial) and
syntactic properties. At times, such a bundle of syntactic and functorial properties defines a unique
affix in a language, e.g., English –{i/a}ble, with the result that whether or not it is inserted with a
phonological index or not is immaterial. At other times, such a bundle defines a set of morphemic
allomorphs (e.g. deverbal nominals of the {–ation class}: -ation/-ion, -ment, -ance/ence, -al).
7. Extended Projections must have an L core (definitionally).
8. Roots merge as phonological indices. Phonological indices are exactly specific enough to ensure
phonological faithfulness in the syntactic derivation, thereby excluding the derivation of show from
see or an event-denoting noun such as lesson from some abstract non-existing verbal entry. A
complete phonological matrix for a root is inserted on the basis of the index in the syntactic context
created by the derivation.
9. Roots merge with functors (FL or FF ), and are categorized contextually by their merger environment.
Consequently, bare roots, without a category label, are not a syntactic option.
Roots and Categories
10. English does not have (productive) -FLs (zero n, v, a etc. as categorizers1).
2. One simple argument for (some) early root phonology (cf. Borer 2003)
15. a. EAT ] /eat/
b. [V CAUSE EAT ] /feed/
16. AS-nominals (Grimshaw’s 1990 Complex Event Nominals) are nominalizations of a verbal structure
(Hazout, 1991, 1995; Borer 1993, 1999, 2003; Engelhardt, 2000; Alexiadou, 2007; Harley 2006; Sichel
2007 among others, differing executions immaterial here.)
17. There are no AS-nominals in English (Hebrew, Greek) whose head is not morphologically
(transparently) derived from a verb (or adjective).2
1
To be distinguished from, e.g. v as an event-structure node, which the present claim is silent about.
2
With English aggression being an exception that clearly proves the rule.
Borer 2/23
Roots and Categories
18. But if roots do not contain at least some phonological information, AS-nominals without a verbal
source cannot be excluded.
19. a. The lesson lasted several hours
b. The lesson took place from 7am to 8am
20. a. *the lesson of geometry by an incompetent teacher
b. *the lesson of geometry for several hours
c. *the lesson of geometry in order to understand the most recent proof
21. a. ha-šinui šel merkaz ha-'ir 'al yedey ha-'iriya
the-transformation/change of center the-city by the-city administration
b. ha-šinuy haya madhim
the-change/transformation was amazing
22. a. *ha-transformacia šel merkaz ha-'ir 'al yedey ha-'iriya
the-transformation of center the-city by the-city administration
b. ha-transformacia hayta madhima
the-transformation was amazing
23. All and only phonology that impacts the derivation (see Acquaviva 2008 for a relevant discussion).3
SUBJ4 (aux) cross(TENSE) DEM (A) bridge3(PL) when pron4 (ADV) come(TENSE) to pron3
3
The logical conclusion is that suppletive pairs such as go/went constitute two, rather than one, roots with
phonological gaps.
Borer 3/23
Roots and Categories
is assigned, it is carried along throughout the derivation” (Arad 2003, based on Marantz 2000, 2001).
note conceptual affinity with Lexical Phonology and Morphology where meaning changes are
restricted to level I affixation, which, by definition, is 'inside' level II affixation which cannot change
meaning).
28. a. A root inventory with basic meaning
b. A mechanism allowing the assignment of non-compositional meaning in a restricted syntactic
environment (for Arad, op. cit: at categorizing, possibly defining a phase).
29. Pairs such as transmission (the act of transmitting) vs. transmission (car gear), have distinct structures
(cf. Embick and Marantz 2008):
a. [[[transmit] v]-tionn] b. [[transmit] -tionn]
3.2.1. Some general queries:
30. What is the status, in this system, of the 'basic meaning of roots'?
a. If they do have a basic meaning, is it reanalyzed when the root+category combination is assigned a
distinct meaning (e.g., transmission)?
b. If they don't have a basic meaning altogether, what does it mean to claim that roots take internal
arguments?
31. Whenever FL attaches to an uncategorized root, it only does so providing in some (parallel) derivation
that root is categorized as a specific category type, and with a zero FL. (e.g., whenever –tion attaches
to a root to give rise to a 'non-compositional' meaning, it can also attach to that same root, providing it
has been verbalized with a -FL). That is a rather curious coincidence.
3.2.2. Empirical problems
32. Arad’s (2003) evidence: Hebrew verbs derived from roots may have idiosyncratic meanings.
Denominal verbs have predictable meanings.
33. a. Root: X.Š.B (roughly cognitive process) [N xešbon ] [V hitxašben]
'arithmetic' 'settle accounts'
'account' ‘retaliate’
'calculus' (Arad, op cit), .
But Hebrew xešbon ‘account’, does not have the ‘settle account/retaliate’ reading (e.g. with
any light verb)! This may be literally translated from the English idiom, rather than derived from
the Hebrew noun.4
b. Underived noun: [N bayit] [V biyet]
5
'house' 'domesticate'
but also: [V hitbayet]
'focus in on something'
Again may be a literal translation from English ‘home in on’, but the noun bayit ‘house’ is
impossible in that meaning context (e.g., no 'homing pigeons'-type of expression).
34. [[Vtrans[form]]-ation]
[N [N[Vre[act]] tion] ary]]
[N[A [glob] al] ize ]-ation]
4
ose (li/iti) xešbon(ot), lit. ‘makes (to me/with me) account’ means ‘keep record of wrongdoings’, not 'retaliate'
5
See Bat El (1994) inter alia for extensive argumentation that bayit ‘house’ is not derived from a root.
Borer 4/23
Roots and Categories
Borer 5/23
Roots and Categories
-ationN -ationN
2 2
-ationN [L=V transform] -ationN [L=V transform]
2
(unordered merge) [L=V transform] -ationN
(English adjoins to the left; by Uniformity what moves cannot project;
suffixes are listed phonologically as such)
[1FORM]
[TRANS [ FORM] ] [2 TRANSFORM]
[[TRANS [ FORM] ] ATION] [3 TRANSFORMATION](AL-IZE-ATION)
43. a. Only non-compositional constructs in Hebrew are systematically consistent with the grammatical
properties of incorporated structures
b. Only non-compositional constructs can head another construct (i.e., create a left branching
structure).
Non-compositional Meaning requires incorporation thereby creating an en-searchable domain (cf.
Borer, 2008)
44. [beyt-sefer] sade; [begged-yam] meši; [yošev-roš] mo'aca [yom huledet] šlošim6
house book field suit sea silk sitter head council day birth thirty
'field school' 'silk bathing suit' 'council chairman' ’30th birthday’
45. *[beyt ‘ec] sade; *[xulcat (ha-)mora] meši;
house wood field blouse (the-)teacher silk
(field wooden house) (silken teacher’s blouse)
46. A very simplified structures for construct and compounds in Hebrew:
a. [DP [#P beyt [FF [DP mora] beyt [DivP beyt [NP beyt ] ‘a teacher’s house’
house teacher
b. [DP [#P beyt [FF [NP 'ec] beyt [DivP beyt [NP beyt ] ‘a wood house
house wood
47. [DP [#P [Nbeyt [N sefer]] [FF [NP sefer] [DivP beyt [NP beyt ] (right adjunction) ‘school’
house book book
6
Cf. šnat alpayim 'year 2000', where the feminine form šana 'year' takes a construct form, for evidence that
numerical of this sort require a construct formation.
Borer 6/23
Roots and Categories
48. And note, as well: begged, 'suit' 'clothing item' is already categorized (as N, by the vowel combination);
yošev, a participle, ‘sitter’, is already categorized. Yet they give rise, in compounding, to non-
compositional meaning, in turn associated with a single N dominating constituent.
3.4. Evidence or phonological representations feeding the encyclopedia
49. a. The selective transmission of historical documents
b. scanning and transmittal of documents or parts of documents (US Patent office publication)
c. A camera system for processing documents for measurement of reflectance and/or
transmittance of documents
50. a. Deferment of student loans
b. The department shall grant a deferral of interest and principal payments
51. a. Several groups … monitor the sale and transportation of seed
b. "The transportal of seeds in the wool or fur of quadrupeds." –a C. Darwin article
52. a. the slight transference of red pigments from the skins
b. "Transferral of bread “sponge” from dough mixer to trough prior to fermentation"
53. a. public transportation
b. *public transportal
54. a. the car's transmission
b. *the car's transmittal
c. *the car's transmittance
55. a. "Understanding transference and counter transference"
b. *Understanding transferral and counter transferral
7
Possibly also some aspectual markers (e.g. Slavic perfective prefixes), which may contribute to the formation of
non-compositional meaning without losing their grammatical function.
Borer 7/23
Roots and Categories
60. a. Lola taped the poster to the wall with band aids/mailing labels
b. screw the fixture on the wall with nails Kiparsky, 1982) – ok if nails are twisted to affix the fixture
(Harley and Haugen, 2007)
61. Bento boxes of the week: Lacquered with bitter persimmon juice (Google search)
62. a. I taped the picture with a ??(duct) tape
b. I hammered in the nails with a ??(big) hammer (Harley and Haugen, 2007)
5. Synthetic Compounds
5.1. The Conundrums
63. a. If compounds are en-searchable and may return a non-compositional meaning, they cannot (when
non-compositional, at the very least) be derived from structures containing FF.
b. Synthetic compounds (or things that look an awful lot like them) most certainly can be non-
compositional: crystal-gazing, card carrying, line producing; globe trotting, sharp shooting, head
hunting, face lifting, shop lifting, sleep walking, home making, war mongering
c. A conundrum for some models (Borer, 1999, 2003, 2005; Alexiadou 2007, Sichel, 2007): if internal
arguments come from event structure, then the(apparent) internal argument in synthetic
compounds must come from functional event structure. But synthetic compounds do not have an
event interpretation (cf. 63(64)-(65)). So where does the internal argument interpretation come
from?
d. A conundrum for the present proposal – if internal arguments come from functional event
structure, how can synthetic compounds have a non- compositional meaning?
e. Another conundrum for some models (Marantz, 1997; Alexiadou, 2007): if –ing, in derived
nominals, triggers the projection of some particular functional structure (v, for Marantz; VoiceP for
Alexiadou) which effectively forces –ing nominals to be AS-nominals and excludes them as R-
nominals, how are synthetic compounds with –ing but without an event reading possible?
f. Suppose internal arguments are properties of roots, and not of structure (Marantz, 1997,
Harley, 2006, 2008). A number of prima facie conundrum nevertheless arises: first, if roots have an
internal argument (in which case, note, they do have meaning), where does it disappear to in R-
nominals? And wouldn't having an argument mean, effectively, that the root is a verb? (cf.
Acquaviva, 2008). Second, derived verbs have internal arguments (e.g. verbalize), which could
hardly come from the root. But if internal arguments are licensed structurally for verbalize, why
can't they be licensed structurally across the board without root-related information?
64. a. The breaking of the door by Mary in seven minutes in order to collect the insurance
b. (I watched) the door breaking (*by Mary) (*in seven minutes) (*in order to collect the
insurance)
65. The breaker of the door (*in seven minutes) (*in order to collect the insurance)
5.2. Harely (2008)
66. Synthetic compounds are the result of the incorporation of a complement into an a-categorial root
head, with subsequent categorization applying to the result of the incorporation:
Borer 8/23
Roots and Categories
67. Assumptions:
a. roots are listed with complements (also possible: [Pact fast]) for fast acting
b. complements are always realized prior to categorization of the root
c. the root incorporates into the categorial node (n, v)
68. But derived verbs give rise to synthetic compounds. It therefore follows that synthetic compounds
cannot be derived (just) from a root plus its complement.
69. Alas, it is exactly the internal argument that cannot form a synthetic compound with the verb unless
the verb has its transitive meaning:
a. ship sinking – transitive reading only
b. tomato growing – transitive reading only (and compare with tomato growth)
c. *tree falling
d. *train arriving (and compare with train arrival)
5.3. Back to Basics: The First Sister Principle?
70. a. truck driver truck driving man driven
b. letter writer letter writing secretary written
c. bread eater bread eating moth eaten
71. a. fast acting; strong smelling; happy looking
b. quick-fried, slow-roasted
c. pan frying; church going
72. a. *chef maker/making (of cakes); *man driver/driving (of trucks)
b. *cake baked; *letter written; *church gone
73. First Sister Principle (Roeper and Siegel, 1978):
All verbal compounds are formed by incorporation of a word in first sister position of the verb
(presupposed demotion of the external argument and promotion of the internal argument in passive)8
74. a. vacuum cleaner; breech loader; line producer;
b. *fast actor; *strong smeller; *beautifully dancer; *quick fryer
c. *beautiful dancing; vs. quick frying;
d. home-made by hand; sun-baked (too) quickly by us; fire-brewed by boy scouts
e. mountain-grown; garden-tested; field-harvested; night stalker
f. pan fried/pan frying; oven roasted/oven roasting; mountain growing; garden testing; field
harvesting; sun baking; fire brewing
8 The proposal has a number of execution problems if we try to adapt it to present day accounts, e.g., the fact
that in pan frying pan is an adjunct and not a complement. We set these aside, however, for the sake of streamlining
the discussion.
Borer 9/23
Roots and Categories
6. -ing
6.1. More evidence that synthetic –ing compounds do not derive from –ing AS-nominals
80. a. *the mongering of war
b. *the sitting of (a) baby
c. *the loading of breech
d. *the lifting of faces
e. *the making of (a) home
f. *the producing of (a) line
g. *the sharp shooting (of the target)
h. *the gazing of crystal (compositional only)
i. *to going of church
9
Discussion of –en, an adjectival head, is set aside here. We further set aside cases of –er which are not
agentive, and which, to the best of my knowledge, are not attested with so-called synthetic compounds. Marantz
(p.c.) notes that these are not licit, typically, in non-modified contexts (e.g., roaster vs. oven-roaster), providing us with
some test for distinguishing between the occurrences.
Borer 10/23
Roots and Categories
Borer 11/23
Roots and Categories
Borer 12/23
Roots and Categories
7. Back to synthetic nominals – some more on why synthetic nominals are not AS
nominals
103. Compounds: transitive reading only AS Nominals: intransitive reading possible
tomato growing the growing of the tomato
ship sinking the sinking of the ship
#guest departing the departing of the guest
#flower wilting the wilting of the flower
#standard slipping the slipping of standards
104. fence-touching *wall *stative, activity
stew smelling *stative, activity
(under relevant reading. ‘smells like stew’ is ok)
105. tomato grower
ship sinker
fence toucher
stew smeller
106. This kind of growing, sinking, dropping, disappearing, all allow, indeed appear to prefer, an
intransitive, but activity reading.
107. It cannot be that nominal -ing always forces a little v or an active VoiceP reading.
108. Transitive reading only for synthetic compounds - problem for:
a. The assumption that the transitivity of, e.g., grow derives from a projected v or CAUSE
b. Any account based on the First Sister Principle which subscribes to the unaccusative hypothesis
c. Any account based on the First Sister Principle which subscribes to the view that causative are
derived from adding structure to inchoatives (acknowledged by Harley, 2008)
109. The growing of the tomato
a. -ingoriginator [EP (expl) [FsP the tomato ]] transitive, activity
participant
b. -ingoriginator [EP the tomato ] intransitive, activity
originator2
Borer 13/23
Roots and Categories
A1. Introduction
115. Grimshaw (1990): English -nominalizers do not allow for event structure and are hence, by and large,
excluded as AS-nominals.
116. change (and exchange), release, use, (among others)
117. A run, a stand, a sit in, a lie down, a walk, a ride, a dance, a turn, a twist, a smoke, a smile, a laugh, a
frown, love, hate, a kiss, a lift, a roll, a rock, a hold, a climb, a descent, a kill, a raid, an arrest, a follow-
up, a chase, an export, an import, a think…… (and see below for more examples)
118. *the walk of the dog for three hours
*the dance of the group for a whole evening
*the kiss of the beloved in order to seal the marriage
Borer 14/23
Roots and Categories
119. a. T b. D c. Vize
3 3 3 33
FUT [L=VFORM] det [L=NFORM] Aal Vize aal
PST 3
[L=N√FORM] AAal
120. Nothing formally merges directly with a root, nor are roots, as such, well-defined syntactic objects. As
the root is, definitionally, a member of a specific category in the context of the functor selecting it, be
it an L-functor or an F-functor, all mergers are, posteriori, minimally, to L.
121. English does not have (productive) FLs. There is, in other words, no correlate of '-ize' or a
correlate of '-ation', such that when they attach to a root they convert it, effectively, to a noun or to a
verb without any overt affixation to mark such a change.
122. Contra Kiparsky (1982, 1997), and contra DM.
Borer 15/23
Roots and Categories
a. vize b. vize
124.
3 3
aal vize aal vize
3 3
n aal √FORM aal
3
√FORM n
c. nation d. nation willT
3 3 3 3
v nation √FORM nation
willT v
3 3
√FORM v
e. n willT
3 3
v n willT v
3 3
√FORM v (??)
125. Non-compositional meaning is available for (124d) but not for (124c) (is this a falsifiable claim?)
126. form, a noun, is as morphologically complex as formation (Kiparsky, DM);
form, the verb, is as morphologically complex as liquefy (DM, but not Kiparsky).
a. [N*√FORM+ n] [N*√FORM+ nation]
b. [V*√FORM+ v] [V*√LIQUI+ vify]
127. In XSM, neither the noun nor the verb form are morphologically complex.
128. government, in DM:
a. n -ment / √GOVERN ____
[V*√GOVERN] v] ____
b. -ment only attaches to v: *[V*√GOVERN] v-] (e.g., vify, vize, vate etc.)
Query 1: why does –ment only attach to roots which may otherwise be verbalized with a v? Why
not to roots that are otherwise nominalized or adjectivized?
Query 2: why should the root GOVERN and the verb GOVERN systematically select the same
nominalizer?
129. In XSM:
a. N -ment / [LGOVERN] ____
b. ment verbalizes its complement.
Borer 16/23
Roots and Categories
Borer 17/23
Roots and Categories
138. Similar problem with –ation (when contrasted with –ence, -al, -ment), which is the only form available
following (non-zero) verbalizers (e.g., -ate, -ify, and –ize), but which, given zero categorizers, are as
complex making a non-local statement necessary.
A2. An Alternative.
139. a. [T [L=V √FORM++; [Asp [L=V √FORM++ etc.
b. [D [L=N √FORM++; [DIV [L=N √FORM++ etc.
In the absence of zero affixation, overt affixation is necessary to turn nouns into verbs and vice verse.
In the absence of such additional overt affixation, embedding, e.g. formalize in a nominal context quite
simply leads to a contradiction: the L is already a verb, but is interpreted, contextually, as a noun.
Conversely, formation, when embedded in a verbal context, is interpreted as V-equivalent, but as it is
already a noun, contradiction and hence ungrammaticality result:
140. a. *[T [N formation]]; *[Asp [N formation]] etc.
b. *[D [V formalize]]; *[DIV [V formalize]]
Borer 18/23
Roots and Categories
Borer 19/23
Roots and Categories
152. a. *the form of 2 special committees (by the board of directors) (in order to oversee the elections).
b. the formation of 2 special committees by the board of directors in order to
oversee the elections.
c. the forming of 2 special committees by the board of directors in order to
oversee the elections
153. a. *the admit of 3 graduate students (in order to just teach Russian) is not a good idea.
b. the admission of 3 graduate students (in order to just teach Russian) is not
a good idea
c. our admitting of 3 graduate students (in order to just teach Russian) is not
a good idea.
A3. Rebutting some Potential Counter Arguments
154. a. a portion, a position, a condition, a proposition, an audition, a ration, a question, a motion, an air
condition
b. to portion, to position, to condition, to proposition, to audition, to ration, to question, to motion,
to air condition
155. a. port-, cond- rat-, mot-
b. to pose, to propose, to audit, to quest)
156. a. the model posed in front of the camera for several hours
b. Mary proposed a solution in two minutes
c. The authorities audited my tax records for several years
d. John quested for love for years
157. a. the posing of the model in front of the camera for several hours
b. Mary's proposal of a solution in two minutes
c. The authorities' auditing of my tax records for several years
d. the questing for love for years on the part of adult males
158. a. the position of the model in front of the camera (*for several hours)
b. Mary's proposition of a solution (*in two minutes)
c. The authorities' audition of my tax records (*for several years)
d. *the question (for years) for love on the part of adult males
= with the intended reading as events associated with ( 156a-d)
159. The nouns in (154a) have exactly the cluster of properties we typically find with underived nouns:
a. They alternate freely with verbal forms
b. They may not function as AS-nominals.
c. They only nominalize with an overt suffix
160. a. The condition *(ing) of certain responses by certain works of literature
b. John's proposition *(ing) of Mary
c. Mary's question *(ing) of John
d. Kim's audition *(ing) of the candidate
A4. Kiparsky's (1982, 1997) arguments
161. There are two zero categorial affixes in English, one which derives verbs from nouns and which is a
level I affix, and another one which derives verbs from nouns, and which is a level II affix.
Borer 20/23
Roots and Categories
162. a. Contrary to XSM but in line with DM, there are (two distinct) abstract categorizers in English.
b. Contrary to DM and XSM, zero verbs and zero nouns are not derived independently from
roots, but from each other.
A4.1. Two denominal verbs in English? - cf. discussion above (58)-(62)
A4.2. Morpho-phonological arguments?
A4.2.1. Productivity
163. Level II affixation takes as its input phonological words and is very productive.
Level I affixation takes as its input either words or non-word stems, and is (potentially) less
productive.
But consider (164a-b). Stress has shifted in (164a) but not in (164b)
Two zero-affixes associated with VN?
The existence of stress shift in some syntactic contexts but not in others is entirely compatible with
a system that allows for roots that are phonologically underspecified, together with the late
insertion of fully specified phonological information.
A4.2.3. Ordering
166. Kiparsky’s claim: Cases such as (154), in which verbs are formed from –ation affixed words, argue for
NV later than –tion affixation. NV in compounds likewise argues for a late NV rule, |but an
early VN rule
But Kiparsky cannot account for the systematic ungrammaticality of “to transformation”, “to
friendship” or “to union brotherhood”, all predicted to be possible by his logic.
167. Underived verbs (within his system) may receive Level I affixation, but not so (zero) derived verbs,
formed by assumption at Level II:
contract-ual, murder-ous, rebeli-ous
By this logic, the noun market is derived from the verb market, and the noun question
from the verb question (which is actually a contradiction in his system):
Borer 21/23
Roots and Categories
As it turns out, however, NVN triplets do occur (as Kiparsky himself notes):
K.’s explanation: there are two distinct rules deriving nouns from verbs, both applying at Level I:
Rule 1: VResult N (to) sweatV (have) a sweatN
Rule 2: V Substance N (to) sweatV (smelly) sweatN
Note further the presupposition that sweatN is derived from sweatV, shitN from shitV etc.
169. a. I sank the boat
b. that was quite a sink! (viewing the action in (a)
c. I bought a new sink
d. I am going to (re-)sink the kitchen
170. Ironically, tape and screw may be both a substance and a result:
a I just got my hair cut and asked for a tape up
b. Visualization of the flow through a screw-down valve
But that would mean that they are derived from verbs, in contradiction with the purported
properties of tape vs. hammer.
References
Acquaviva, P. 2008. Roots and lexicality in Distributed Morphology. Ms. University College Dublin/Universität
Konstanz.
Alexiadou, A. 2007. On the role of syntactic locality in morphological processes: the case of (Greek) derived nominals.
To appear in A. Giannakidou & M. Rathert, eds. Quantification, Definiteness and Nominalization. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Alexiadou, A. 2001. Functional Structure in Nominals: Nominalizations and Ergativity. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Arad, Maya. 2003. Locality constraints on the interpretation of roots: The case of Hebrew denominal verbs NLLT 21:
737-778
Bat El, O. 1994. Stem modification and cluster transfer in Modern Hebrew. NLLT 12: 571-596.
Borer, H. 1991/1993. "Derived Nominals." Ms., University of Massachusetts, Amherst.
Borer, H. 1999. The form, the forming and the formation of nominals. Talk given at ZAS, Berlin.
Borer, H. 2003. Exo-skeletal vs. endo-skeletal explanation: Syntactic projection and the lexicon. In J. Moor and M.
Polinsky, eds. The Nature of Explanation in Linguistic Theory. Stanford: CSLI
Borer, H. 2005a,b. Structuring Sense Vols. I, II. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Borer, H. 2008. Compounds: The view from Hebrew. To appear in R. Lieber and P. Stekauer, eds. The Oxford Handbook
of Compounds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Embick, D. and A. Marantz. 2008. Architecture and blocking. Linguistic Inquiry 39.1.
Borer 22/23
Roots and Categories
Engelhardt, M. 2000. "The Projection of Argument-taking Nominals", Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 18 (1).
41-88.
Grimshaw, J. 1990. Argument Structure. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Harley, H. 2006. The morphology of nominalizations and the syntax of vP. Ms. University of Arizona
Harley, H. and J. Haugen, 2007. http://www.ledonline.it/snippets/allegati/snippets9002.pdf “Are there really
two different classes of instrumental denominal verbs in English?” Snippets: Issue 15
Harley, H. 2006. The morphology of nominalizations and the syntax of vP. In M Rathert and A. Giannadikou. Eds. DP,
QP and Nominalizations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Harley, H. 2008. Compounding in distributed morphology. To appear in R. Lieber and P. Stekauer, eds. The Oxford
Handbook of Compounds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Harley, H. and R. Noyer. 2000. Licensing in a non-lexicalist lexicon. In B. Peeters, ed. The Lexicon Encyclopedia
Interface. Amsterdam: Elsevier 349-374
Hazout, I. 1991. Verbal Nouns in Hebrew and Arabic. PhD dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.
Hazout, I. 1995. Action nominalization and the Lexicalist Hypothesis. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 13: 355-
404.
Kiparsky, P. 1982. Lexical Morphology and Phonology in Linguistics in the Morning Calm, Hanshin Publishing Company,
Seoul, Korea.
Kiparsky, P. 1997. Remarks on denominal verbs. In A. Alsina, J. Bresnan and P. Sells. eds. Complex Predicates.
Stanford: CSLI Publications.
Marantz, A. 1996. “Cat as a Phrasal Idiom", ms. MIT.
Marantz, A. 1997. "No Escape from Syntax," In A. Dimitriadis, I. Siegel et. al, (eds.) University of Pennsylvania
Working Papers in Linguistics. 4.2., pp. 201-225.
Marantz , A. 2000. Roots: The universality of roots and pattern morphology. Paper presented at the conference on
Afro-Asiatic languages, University of Paris VII.
Marantz, A. 2001. Words and things. Ms. MIT.
Roeper, T. and D. Siegel. 1978. A lexical transformation for verbal compounds. LI 9, 199-160.
Sichel, I. 2007. Agent exclusivity in nominalizations. Paper presented at the Workshop on Bare Nouns and
Nominalizations, Stuttgart, June 2007
Snyder, W. 1998. On the aspectual properties of English derived nominals. In U. Sauerland and O. Percus, eds. The
Interpretive Tract: Working Papers in Syntax and Semantics (MITWPL Volume 25), pp.125-139. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Working Papers in Linguistics.
Hagit Borer
Department of Linguistics
University of Southern California
Los Angeles, CA 90089-1693
USA
[email protected]
http://www-rcf.usc.edu/~borer
Borer 23/23