South African Constitutional La - Pierre de Vos Warren Freedman Z-1
South African Constitutional La - Pierre de Vos Warren Freedman Z-1
Acknowledgements
Publisher: Penny Lane
Development editor: Edward Ndiloseh
Project manager: Jeané de Bruin
Copy editor: Language Mechanics
Reference proofreader: Chantelle Hough Louw
Permissions researcher: Patricia Rademeyer
Proofreader: Chantelle Hough Louw
Indexer: Astrid Schwenke
Typesetter: QBS Learning
Cover: Design Studio
The authors and publisher gratefully acknowledge permission to reproduce copyright material in this
book.
Every effort has been made to trace copyright holders, but if any copyright infringements have been
made,
the publisher would be grateful for information that would enable any omissions or errors to be
corrected in subsequent impressions.
Links to third-party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only.
Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials contained in any third party website referenced
in this work.
To my partner, Lwando Scott
Pierre de Vos
Warren Freedman
PART ONE PRINCIPLES AND STRUCTURES OF GOVERNMENT
CHAPTER 11 LIMITATION
PART TWO THE BILL OF RIGHTS AND THE ENFORCEMENT OF THE CONSTITUTION
CHAPTER 11 LIMITATION
11.1 Introduction
11.2 Two-stage enquiry
11.3 Evolution of the general limitation clause
11.4 The first stage: Has the right been infringed?
11.4.1 Introduction
11.4.2 The content and scope of the protected right
11.4.2.1 Introduction
11.4.2.2 Internal modifiers
11.4.3 The meaning and effect of the impugned law or conduct
11.5 The limitation analysis
11.5.1 Introduction
11.5.2 Law of general application
11.5.2.1 Introduction
11.5.2.2 The limitation must take the form of a law
11.5.2.3 The content of the law must be generally applicable
11.6 Reasonable and justifiable in an open and democratic society based on
human dignity, equality and freedom
11.6.1 Reconsidering the role of proportionality
11.6.2 The purpose of the limitation
11.6.3 The rational connection requirement
11.6.4 Less restrictive, alternative means of achieving the end
11.6.5 Balancing and proportionality proper
11.6.5.1 Introduction
11.6.5.2 Stacking the rights side of the balancing scales
11.6.5.3 Stacking the limiting measure’s side of the balancing
scales
11.6.5.4 Balancing and proportionality proper
11.6.5.5 Reasonable accommodation
11.7 The burden of justification
11.8 Special limitations
11.9 The limitation of rights by other constitutional provisions
Summary
LIST OF REFERENCES
TABLE OF CASES
TABLE OF LEGISLATION
GLOSSARY
INDEX
The 1997 Australian comedy, The Castle, tells the story of the Kerrigan
family’s fight against the compulsory acquisition by the government of
their home to make way for an expanded runway at the airport. The
father, Darryl Kerrigan, hires an incompetent lawyer acquaintance,
Dennis Denuto, to assist the family, but when asked by the judge what
section of the Constitution he is invoking to challenge the
expropriation, Dennis is unable to assist the court. ‘There is no one
section,’ he hesitantly tells the court. ‘It’s just the vibe of the thing, your
Honour.’
After the Kerrigans lost the case, Lawrence Hammill, a retired
Queen’s Counsel, decides to argue it pro bono on appeal before the
High Court of Australia. Lawrence makes a persuasive case that the
Kerrigans have the right to just compensation under section 51(xxxi) of
the Australian Constitution and closes by paraphrasing Darryl’s own
comments that his house is more than just a structure of bricks and
mortar: it is a home built with love and shared memories. The Court
rules in favour of the Kerrigans and their case becomes a landmark
precedent.
To some extent, this textbook takes its inspiration from The Castle. It
recognises that a proper appreciation of South Africa’s Constitution
requires a keen understanding of both the ‘vibe’ of the Constitution,
specifically its broad aims of preventing a recurrence of the horrors of
colonialism and apartheid and of promoting the social and economic
transformation of our society, and a detailed and precise understanding
of the individual provisions of the Constitution, as fleshed out by the
jurisprudence of the Constitutional Court. At the same time, the
textbook also recognises that constitutional rules must be evaluated
with reference to their impact on the quality of governance, and on the
lives of all the people who live in South Africa.
This textbook, therefore, aims to provide students (and others
interested in the manner in which the Constitution must be interpreted
and applied) with a relatively succinct, yet comprehensive, overview of
the constitutional law of South Africa. The text is premised on the fact
that South Africa’s colonial and apartheid past continues to exert an
influence on the attitudes and social and economic circumstances of
those who live in the country as well as on the prevailing political
culture. It embraces the notion that ours is a transformative
Constitution aimed at facilitating the creation of a fair, equitable and
just society in which the human dignity of every person is respected and
protected. At the same time, it raises critical questions about the
limitations of transformative constitutionalism.
Work on this second edition started in 2018, with most contributions
completed towards the end of 2019. The editing was completed in the
second half of 2020 while South Africa was under various levels of
lockdown due to the Covid-19 pandemic. Since the publication of the
first edition in 2013, the Constitutional Court has continued to deliver
ground-breaking judgments, several of which have deepened our
understanding of the role of the National Parliament in holding the
executive to account, the duties of the President and the national
executive, the powers of the Public Protector, and the role of the
National Prosecuting Authority, and these new developments are all
reflected in the book. A new chapter on the role of traditional leadership
in the governance system has also been added. Apart from the role of
traditional leaders in the governance systems, this edition also includes
new sections on the right to bodily integrity, the right to property and
the land question, as well as the right to education.
Despite these major revisions, the basic premise of the book
remains the same, namely that the study of South African constitutional
law cannot profitably be undertaken in the abstract and needs to be
situated within the political, social and economic context of present-day
South Africa to enable readers better to understand the provisions of
the Constitution and their interpretation, especially by the
Constitutional Court. The book aims to achieve this purpose by
including tables, diagrams and ‘learning boxes’ containing relevant
factual information about the socio-economic and political realities in
the country and its history, opinions from a wide array of sources as
well as excerpts from academic writing (which are also aimed at
encouraging critical thinking about the Constitution and its
interpretation). A special effort was made to include more critical voices
of the constitutional project and of individual Constitutional Court
judgments in the second edition of the book.
We hope that it provides a crisp yet detailed overview of most of the
pressing constitutional law issues in South Africa today, issues which
are not normally addressed in other courses in the standard LLB
curriculum. We further hope that the book signals that many
constitutional law issues can be approached from different angles, thus
encouraging further reading and critical analysis and engagement with
many of the most pressing constitutional law issues that are often hotly
debated in the South African media.
The editors deliberately recruited a team of dedicated authors with
different levels of experience and different perspectives from many
different academic institutions in order to utilise and showcase the
diverse talents of constitutional law academics in South Africa. It is not
surprising that working with a large team of authors presented some
challenges. The editors worked hard to ensure that the contextual focus
is retained throughout the book and that the book retains a coherent
tone and an even level of complexity. We hope that the end result
reflects at least some of this hard work. However, the book would not
have been possible without the assistance of the authors whose
dedication, we hope, is reflected in the final product. We would
therefore like to thank Zsa Zsa Boggenpoel, Lisa Draga, Karthy
Govender, Sindiso Mnisi-Weeks, Khulekani Moyo, Catherine Namakula,
Nomthandazo Ntlama, Douglas Mailula, Sanele Sibanda and Lee Stone
for their hard work in making this book a reality.
Apart from the authors, we would also like to thank the staff of
Oxford University Press, and especially Penny Lane, Jeané de Bruin and
Edward Ndiloseh. Thanks are also due to the staff of Language
Mechanics and especially Kobie Ferreira.
Pierre de Vos and Warren Freedman
December 2020
PIERRE DE VOS (Editor)
BCom, LLB, LLM (Stellenbosch), LLM (Columbia), LLD (Western Cape)
Pierre de Vos is the incumbent of the Claude Leon Foundation Chair in
Constitutional Governance, and Head of the Department of Public Law,
at the University of Cape Town, where he teaches constitutional law,
social justice and the constitution, and governing under the
constitution. His research focuses on the impact of the past on the
current failure to realise human rights, with a specific focus on non-
discrimination law, queer theory and LGBTQ rights, freedom of
expression and its limits, and social and economic inequality. He writes
a blog entitled Constitutionally Speaking (syndicated to the Daily
Maverick) and commentates widely in the media on constitutional
questions. He serves on the advisory council of the Council for the
Advancement of the South African Constitution (CASAC), and is a
board member of PEN South Africa.
LISA DRAGA
LLB (Western Cape), LLM (Missouri)
Lisa Draga is a lecturer in the Department of Public Law and
Jurisprudence at the University of the Western Cape, where she teaches
constitutional law and human rights law. Her research focuses on
education law. Prior to her appointment at the University of the
Western Cape, Lisa served as a social justice lawyer at the Equal
Education Law Centre where she engaged in legal advocacy,
community lawyering, public interest litigation and basic education
policy work. She has been involved in high profile education related
cases in the High Courts and the Constitutional Court of South Africa.
Lisa also worked as a law clerk at the Constitutional Court of South
Africa and completed her articles of clerkship at the Legal Resources
Centre.
CHRISTOPHER GEVERS
LLB (KwaZulu-Natal), MSc (London School of Economics)
Christopher Gevers is a lecturer in the School of Law at the University of
KwaZulu-Natal, where he teaches international law, legal theory and
related subjects. His research focusses on black internationalism, third
world approaches to international law, critical race theory, and law and
literature. Chris has been a faculty member of the Institute for Global
Law & Policy at Harvard Law School since 2015 and has held visiting
fellowships at Harvard Law School and the University of Oxford.
KARTHIGASEN GOVENDER
LLB (London), LLB (KwaZulu-Natal), LLM (Michigan)
Karthigasen Govender was a Professor in the School of Law at the
University of KwaZulu-Natal and is currently a senior research associate
at the same institution. His research focuses on constitutional and
administrative law. Karthigasen was appointed to the South African
Human Rights Commission by former President Mandela in 1996, and
was reappointed for a second term by former President Mbeki in 2002.
He is a Senior Arbitrator for the South African Local Government
Bargaining Council, a Barrister (Middle Temple, Inns of Court, United
Kingdom), and an Advocate of the High Court of South Africa.
Karthigasen has also acted as a Judge of the High Court of South Africa,
and was appointed to the SA Law Reform Commission for a five-year
term in 2018.
PATRICIA LENAGHAN
BLC LLB (Pretoria), LLM, LLD (Western Cape)
Patricia Lenaghan is Associate Professor in the Department of
Mercantile and Labour Law at the University of the Western Cape. Her
current areas of interest include international trade law, regional
integration and development, and European Union law. Patricia
practised in Gauteng as an Attorney, Notary and Conveyancer of the
High Court of South Africa before joining the University of the Western
Cape to pursue her academic interests.
KHULEKANI MOYO
LLB (Hons) (Zimbabwe), LLM (Oslo), LLD (Stellenbosch), Diploma in
the International Protection of Human Rights and Diploma in the
Justiciability of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (Åbo Akademi,
Finland)
Khulekani Moyo is a Senior Lecturer in the School of Law at the
University of the Witwatersrand. His research focuses on constitutional
law, international law, international criminal law, international human
rights law, business and human rights, and regional integration law.
Prior to his appoint at the University of the Witwatersrand, Khulekani
served as the Head of Research at the South African Human Rights
Commission, as a Senior Lecturer in the Nelson R Mandela School of
Law at the University of Fort Hare, and as a researcher at the Norwegian
Centre for Human Rights.
DOUGLAS MAILULA
B Proc, LLB, LLM, LLD (South Africa)
Douglas Mailula is a Senior Lecturer in the Faculty of Law at the
University of Venda. His research focuses on constitutional law,
customary law, child law, and mining and mineral law. Prior to his
appointment at the University of Venda, he served as Chair of the
Department of Public, Constitutional and International Law at the
University of South Africa and as the Deputy Director of Mineral Policy
Development in the erstwhile Department of Minerals and Energy.
Douglas is a member of the editorial committee of the Comparative and
International Law Journal of Southern Africa.
CATHERINE S NAMAKULA
LLB (Hons) (Makerere), LLM (Nottingham), PhD (Witwatersrand)
Catherine Namakula is a lecturer in the Nelson R Mandela School of
Law at the University of Fort Hare, where she teaches constitutional law.
Her research focuses on human rights and criminal justice, the
structure of a human right, the human rights mandate of the prosecutor
in international criminal trials, and the right to a fair hearing in
international criminal trials.
NOMTHANDAZO NTLAMA
B Juris, LLB (Fort Hare), Certificate in Comparative Human Rights, LLM
(Stellenbosch), LLD (UNISA)
Nomthandazo Ntlama is a Professor and Acting Head of the UNESCO
‘Oliver Tambo’ Chair of Human Rights in the Nelson R Mandela School
of Law at the University of Fort Hare. Her research focuses on
constitutional law, human rights and customary/indigenous law. Prior
to her current appointment, Nomthandazo served as Head of Research
at the Nelson R Mandela School of Law, where she Coordinated the
Outreach Programmes on Human Rights at the UNESCO ‘Oliver Tambo’
Chair of Human Rights, at the University of South Africa, and at the
University of KwaZulu-Natal. She has also served as a Researcher on
Equality at the South African Human Rights Commission (SAHRC), and
acted as a Judge of the Divisions of the High Courts in Bisho in the
Eastern Cape and Durban in KwaZulu-Natal. She has represented the
Society of Law Teachers of Southern Africa as a Commissioner in the
South African Judicial Services Commission (JSC), and served as a
board member of various academic journals: South African Women’s
Chapter: International Association of Women Judges Law Journal,
Southern African Public Law Journal, and the South African Judicial
Education Journal (SAJEI).
SANELE SIBANDA
BA, LLB (Cape Town), LLM, PhD (Witwatersrand)
Sanele Sibanda is a Senior Lecturer in the Faculty of Law at the
University of the Pretoria, where he teaches administrative law,
constitutional law, and jurisprudence. His research focuses on
constitutionalism, constitutional law, liberation theory and indigenous
law. In his work, which seeks to understand the state of contemporary
South African constitutionalism, Sanele deploys a critical historical
method that emphasises the structural, institutional, philosophical and
epistemic continuities that prevail and continue to define post-1994
South Africa. Sanele is a member of the editorial committee of the South
African Journal on Human Rights.
LEE STONE
LLB (Free State), LLM (Pretoria), PhD (Wits), Diploma in the
Justiciability of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (Abo, Finland)
Lee Stone is an Associate Professor in the Department of Public,
Constitutional and International Law at the University of South Africa,
where she teaches constitutional law and refugee law. Her research
focuses on international criminal law, the African regional human
rights system, refugee law, gender and the law, and constitutional and
human rights law. Lee is an Attorney of the High Court of South Africa,
and is the Chair of the Board of Directors of Agenda Feminist Media, a
feminist non-governmental organisation based in South Africa. Prior to
her appointment at UNISA, Lee held a research position for the Refugee
Rights Project at Lawyers for Human Rights, South Africa, worked for
the African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights in The Gambia,
was a Legal Officer at the Institute for Human Rights and Development
in Africa (a Pan-African NGO based in The Gambia), and worked at the
Legal Resources Centre in Durban. Lee was also a Senior Lecturer in the
School of Law at the University of KwaZulu-Natal.
South African Constitutional Law in Context offers a clear and
accessible guide to the principles and context of constitutional law in
South Africa, presenting a balanced approach that develops both
theoretical and applied knowledge. The text’s pedagogical design
supports readers to form a sound foundation of understanding and to
develop skills to engage independently and judiciously with legal
principles and developments.
Summary: This section maps the key areas and core topics that are
covered within each chapter in a succinct list of essential points.
Principles and
structures of
government
1.1 Introduction
Summary
1.1 Introduction
A constitution is often said to be the founding document of a nation as
the authority of the state is derived from it. It sets up the structures of
government and authorises as well as regulates the exercise of power by
the elected branches of government and the judiciary (and, in some
instances, private institutions and individuals). It also places limits on
the exercise of that power and sets out the ground rules according to
which a country must be governed. However, democratic constitutions
are not mere technical legal documents that contain detailed provisions
prescribing the manner in which the legislature, the executive, the
judiciary and other organs of state exercise public power and setting
limits on the exercise of those powers to protect citizens. Hence, we
cannot profitably study the constitutional law of a democratic state in
the abstract, as if the historical context out of which the constitution
emerged and the current social, economic and political realities of this
state have no bearing on an interpretation and evaluation of the various
provisions of a written constitution.1 Nor can we ignore the broader
global context within which the constitution operates. Constitutional
law, therefore, can arguably be described as the most ‘political’ branch
of the law.
In critically evaluating the manner in which constitutions actually
operate in practice and in judging the successes and failures of various
aspects of a constitutional design, we should start with, but cannot
exclusively rely on, the text of the constitution to gain a comprehensive
picture of how this constitution operates. We also need to consider the
wider context in which that constitutional text finds application.
Constitutions are often said to represent a snapshot of the hopes and
dreams of a nation at the time of its writing or – more cynically – to
represent a snapshot of the relative political power and influence of
various political formations (or elites) involved in the drafting of that
constitution.
However, constitutions are also living documents that judges have to
interpret and apply in an ever-changing political, economic and social
environment. A constitutional text often contains open-ended and
relatively general language. In constitutional democracies, therefore,
judges have to interpret, apply and flesh out the meaning of the
constitutional text. The interpretation and application of the various
provisions of a constitution will not necessarily remain static. Although
judges in countries like South Africa are bound by previous precedent,
this does not mean that they will not over time subtly reinterpret and
reapply the text of the Constitution, 1996 (hereinafter referred to as ‘the
Constitution’). These judges, after all, are human beings who do not
float above the world like disembodied ghosts completely untouched by
the society in which they live. They will, despite their best efforts,
interpret the often open-ended and general provisions of a constitution
in ways that are not entirely ‘objective’ and may change over time as
social, economic and political circumstances change. Many of the
justices of South Africa’s Constitutional Court have tentatively
acknowledged the open-ended nature of the language of the South
African Constitution. They have admitted that there may be a need to
refer to extra-legal values and texts, including the South African political
context and history, to justify their decisions.
After the Union of South Africa was established in 1910, the bifurcated
nature of the South African state led to the adoption of several laws by
the Union Parliament aimed at developing legal mechanisms to
entrench further a classic form of indirect colonial rule. The Black
Administration Act (BAA)42 was a lynchpin in this system which
reaffirmed the rule of chiefs within so-called ‘reserves’ and
subordinated their rule to the power of the ‘white’ government and its
officials.43 The BAA made the Governor-General the supreme chief with
the authority to create and divide tribes and appoint any person he
chose as chief or headman – even in the face of popular opposition from
a community.44 The BAA to some extent built on the Glen Grey Act and
further subverted traditional governance structures based on chiefs
selected via kinship. It allowed for the appointment of traditional
leaders from outside the ruling families, creating scope for a body of
government lackeys, who were compliant with entrenched party-
political interests, to assume the role of traditional leader. It has been
remarked that the BAA:
was intended to shore up the remains of chieftaincy in a country-wide policy of
indirect rule, which would allow for [racial] segregation in the administration
of justice. The policy was aptly named ‘retribalisation’, giving chiefs the
semblance of power and hoping that this would safeguard the allegiance and
acquiescence of the Reserve residents.45
A second important milestone was reached in 1988 when the ANC – one
of the prominent organisations fighting for liberation – published its
‘Constitutional Guidelines for a Democratic South Africa’61 The
Guidelines, which drew inspiration from the Freedom Charter, were
issued to encourage national debate on the form that a post-apartheid
society should take. According to the Guidelines: ‘The constitution shall
include a Bill of Rights based on the Freedom Charter. Such a Bill of
Rights shall guarantee the fundamental human rights of all citizens
irrespective of race, colour, sex or creed and shall provide appropriate
mechanisms for their enforcement.’62
As Dugard notes, nothing further is said about the ‘mechanisms for
enforcement’, which was probably the result of internal divisions within
the ANC on whether the courts or a special commission answerable to
Parliament would be best suited to monitor a bill of rights.63 The
publishing of the Guidelines was nevertheless significant because it
demonstrated a shift in the thinking of the dominant liberation
movement who now for the first time embraced the idea of including a
bill of rights in a post-apartheid constitution. The move arguably also
bolstered the standing of the ANC as the pre-eminent liberation
movement in the eyes of the international community. It was not
surprising, therefore, when a year later the ANC and its allies secured
the adoption by a subcommittee on Southern Africa of the Organisation
of African Unity (OAU) – later renamed the African Union – of the
Harare Declaration. The Declaration was also endorsed by the Non-
Aligned Movement (NAM), the Frontline States and (with some
modification) the General Assembly of the United Nations, further
internationalising the conflict in South Africa and bringing
international pressure to bear on the apartheid state. The Declaration
urged the apartheid regime to take measures to create a climate for
negotiations, to put an end to apartheid and define a new constitutional
order based on a set of democratic principles. These principles included
the following:
• All its people have the right to participate in the government and
administration of the country on the basis of a universal suffrage,
exercised through one person one vote, under a common voters’
roll.
• All shall have the right to form and join any political party of their
choice provided that this is not in furtherance of racism.
• All shall enjoy universally recognised human rights, freedoms and
civil liberties, protected under an entrenched Bill of Rights.
The Declaration also elaborated on the conditions for the negotiations
to start, which included the need for the apartheid regime to release all
political prisoners and lift the ban on all political parties and
movements.64 The internationalisation of the conflict, coupled with the
impact of economic sanctions as well as internal resistance, forced the
minority regime to take steps that would ultimately lead to the
negotiation of a transition to democracy. In the telling of South Africa’s
Constitutional Court, ‘remarkably’, the country’s political leaders
‘managed to avoid a cataclysm by negotiating a largely peaceful
transition from the rigidly controlled minority regime to a wholly
democratic constitutional dispensation’.65 Tentative and highly secretive
talks between members of the ANC and the NP commenced in mid-
1980. When FW de Klerk became President in 1989, he was able to build
on the previous secret negotiations with the imprisoned Nelson
Mandela. The first significant steps towards formal negotiations took
place in February 1990 with the unbanning of the ANC and other
organisations such as the PAC by State President FW de Klerk, and the
release of political leaders such as Nelson Mandela from prison.66 Exiled
leaders of the ANC and the PAC returned to South Africa and eventually
negotiations about the transition to democracy commenced.
In the run-up to the start of these negotiations, the ANC attempted
to seize the initiative from the apartheid regime by publishing its
proposed constitutional principles in a discussion document. This
document built on the organisation’s Constitutional Guidelines
published in 1988. Among the guidelines contained in this discussion
document was the call for a non-racial democratic state with a bill of
rights, an independent judiciary and other related issues.67 The
document proposed that the Constitution ‘should create mechanisms
for enforcing’ the rights in the Bill of Rights and that the courts should
have a primary role ‘in ensuring that the rights are operative’.68 This
presented another subtle shift on the part of the ANC who for the first
time suggested that the provisions of the Bill of Rights could be made
judicially enforceable. To some extent this was a surprise move as the
apartheid judiciary had been thoroughly discredited and for most
observers it seemed inconceivable that any of the liberation movements
would agree to entrust the enforcement of the provisions of a supreme
Constitution to the apartheid judiciary. Like many other sticking points,
this problem was eventually resolved by reaching a compromise about
the body empowered to enforce the supreme Constitution. But what
had now more or less been settled was that the Constitution would be
supreme and that an independent judicial body would be entrusted to
enforce it.
Negotiated before the first democratic election by Negotiated after the first democratic election by the
unelected MPNP. elected Constitutional Assembly.
Contained power-sharing agreement allowing the ANC Does not provide for any formal power-sharing
and the NP to share power for five years and provided agreement – after the 1999 election the winner of
for two Deputy Presidents – one from the ANC and the election governs the country on its own.
one from the NP.
Contained 34 Constitutional Principles and provisions Certified by the Constitutional Court as complying
to regulate the adoption of a final constitution, with 34 Constitutional Principles, but only after it
including provisions for the certification of the was initially rejected by that Court and sent back to
constitution by a newly created Constitutional Court. the Constitutional Assembly for redrafting.
Contained a Bill of Rights protecting all basic human Contains an extensive Bill of Rights protecting both
rights. civil and political as well as social and economic
rights.
The 1994 election – in which the Inkatha Freedom Party (IFP) along
with all other major parties decided to take part after a last-minute deal
– delivered an overwhelming majority for the ANC. However, the ANC
did not gain the two-thirds majority required to write the Constitution
without the support of other political parties. Table 1.2 indicates the
final election results and the number of seats gained by each party in
the National Assembly.
Table 1.2 The final 1994 election results 83
Party Votes % Seats
African National Congress (ANC) 12 237 655 62,65 252
Given that the ANC did not obtain a two-thirds majority and because its
negotiators were inclined to seek consensus, it tried hard to gain the
necessary support for the various provisions of the Constitution from its
long-standing opposition in the negotiating process, the NP. An
enormous public participation programme and a programme of
political discussions were also launched to ensure popular participation
in the negotiating process which, it was believed, would lead to popular
acceptance of the outcome reached.85 Despite the Assembly’s
commitment to transparency, meeting away from the watchful eye of
the press was probably essential to resolve some of the most
fundamental disagreements between the parties. Technical legal
advisers also played an important role in formulating alternative
options relating to some of the most controversial clauses.86 However, it
is widely accepted that the consensus, which ultimately emerged,
favoured the dominant party – the ANC.87
The interim Constitution contained several mechanisms to break
any deadlocks in the negotiations. A panel of constitutional experts,
consisting of lawyers, was empowered to advise the Assembly to try to
resolve deadlocks. The interim Constitution also provided that if a draft
constitution did not command two-thirds of the vote but did gain the
support of the majority of the members, it could nevertheless become
the country’s constitution if it was supported by 60% of the voters in a
referendum.88 However, neither of the major parties was keen to resort
to the referendum option and eventually the Constitutional Assembly
voted to pass the new Constitution with only two no votes and 10
abstentions.89
SUMMARY
1 Not all constitutions can be found in one or more formal written documents. For example,
the British or Westminster Constitution has evolved over a long period of time but has
never been fully codified in any written official form. See De Smith, SA and Brazier, R
(1994) Constitutional and Administrative Law 7th ed 6.
2 (CCT5/94) [1995] ZACC 1; 1995 (2) SA 642 (CC); 1995 (4) BCLR 401 (SA); 1995 (1) SACR
568; [1996] 2 CHRLD 244 (5 April 1995) para 17.
3 See Choudhry, S (2009) ‘He had a mandate’: The South African Constitutional Court and
the African National Congress in a dominant party democracy Constitutional Court Review
2:1–86.
4 See Currie, I and De Waal, J (eds) (2001) The New Constitutional and Administrative Law,
Vol 1 Constitutional Law 40–3.
5 See Kuper, A (1997) Review: The Mfecane Aftermath: Reconstructive Debates in Southern
African History by Carol Hamilton Current Anthropology 38(3):471–3; Woolman, S and
Swanepoel, J ‘Constitutional history’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2013)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed (rev service 5) 2.6.
6 Currie and De Waal (2001) 42.
7 Dugard, J (1978) Human rights and the South African legal order 14–8.
8 Hahlo, HR and Khan, E (1960) The Union of South Africa: The Development of its Laws and
Constitution 72–83. See generally Carpenter, G (1987) Introduction to South African
Constitutional Law 64–72.
9 In Cassim and Solomon v The State (1892) Cape Law Journal 9:58, the High Court of the
Orange Free State reviewed a law which prohibited ‘Asians’ from settling in the state
without permission of the President on the ground that it violated the guarantee of equality
before the law. However, the Court upheld the law, arguing that the constitutional
guarantee had to be ‘read in accordance with the mores of the Voortrekkers’. See Dugard
(1978) 19.
10 Klug, H (2010) The Constitution of South Africa: A Contextual Analysis 11.
11 Dugard (1978) 20.
12 Brown v Leyds NO (1897) 4 Off Rep 17.
13 Dugard (1978) 24.
14 Bennett, TW (2004) Customary Law in South Africa 103.
15 Bennett (2004) 104.
16 Bennett (2004) 104–5.
17 Deflem, M (1999) Warfare, political leadership, and state formation: The case of the Zulu
Kingdom, 1808–1879 Ethnology 38(4):371–91 at 376–7.
18 Act 25 of 1894.
19 Davenport, TRH (1987) South Africa: A Modern History 3rd ed 181.
20 Hendricks, F and Ntsebeza, L (1999) Chiefs and rural local government in post-apartheid
South Africa African Journal of Political Science 4(1):99–126 at 102.
21 Davenport (1987) 152.
22 Woolman and Swanepoel (2013) 2.14.
23 Klug (2010) 8; Davenport (1987) 112–15; Mamdani, M (1996) Citizen and Subject:
Contemporary Africa and the Legacy of Late Colonialism 67–9.
24 In the Cape Colony, every man over the age of 21 who was a British subject and who owned
property worth at least 25 pounds or who received a salary of at least 50 pounds per year
was granted the vote. Although few black men qualified, there was no formal racial
restriction in the Cape franchise and this was retained after unification. Similar provisions
applied to the Natal Colony. However, black men and women in the other two provinces
were not allowed to vote.
25 Chanock, M (2001) The Making of South African Legal Culture 1902–1936: Fear, Favour and
Prejudice 22.
26 Klug (2010) 9.
27 See, for example, Basson, DA and Viljoen, HP (1988) Suid-Afrikaanse Staatsreg 2de uitg 36–
7.
28 8 & 29 Vict. c. 63.
29 Currie and De Waal (2001) 44–5.
30 S 35 of the Union Constitution.
31 S 137 of the Union Constitution.
32 See Currie and De Waal (2001) 44–5.
33 Native Representative Act 12 of 1936. The Act was challenged in Ndlwana v Hofmeyr NO
and Others 1937 AD 229, but the courts refused to intervene.
34 Act 46 of 1951.
35 1952 (2) SA 428 (A).
36 1957 (1) SA 552 (A).
37 The only judge to dissent, Oliver Schreiner, was later twice overlooked when a new Chief
Justice had to be appointed. See Dugard (1978) 286; Haynie, SL (2003) Judging in Black and
White: Decision Making in the South African Appellate Division, 1950–1990 (Teaching Text
in Law and Politics).
38 Dugard (1978) 36. Dugard contrasts this extreme notion of parliamentary supremacy to
that which holds sway in the United Kingdom where political traditions, conventions and
respect for the rule of law act as a control on the system of parliamentary supremacy.
39 1934 AD 11.
40 S 1(12) of the Riotous Assemblies and Criminal Law Amendment Act 27 of 1914 as
amended by the Riotous Assemblies Amendment Act 19 of 1930.
41 Sachs v Minister of Justice; Diamond v Minister of Justice 1934 AD 11 paras 36–7.
42 Act 38 of 1927.
43 S 12 of the Constitution.
44 S 1 of the Constitution. See Mqeke, RB (1997) Basic Approaches to Problem Solving in
Customary Law: A Study of Conciliation and Consensus amongst the Cape Nguni 83–4.
45 Hendricks and Ntsebeza (1999) 104. See also Lacey, M (1981) Working for Boroko: The
Origins of a Coercive Labour System in South Africa 94–119.
46 Hendricks and Ntsebeza (1999) 104.
47 Act 68 of 1951.
48 The Promotion of Bantu Self-Government Act 46 of 1959.
49 Transkei in 1976, Bophuthatswana in 1976, Venda in 1979 and Ciskei in 1981.
50 Bennett (2004) 111.
51 Hendricks and Ntsebeza (1999) 106.
52 There is one exception, the Balobedu tribe. See further Pieterse, M (1999) Traditional
leaders win battle in undecided war SAJHR 15:179–187; Motshabi, KB and Volks, SG (1991)
Towards democratic chieftaincy: Principles and procedures Acta Juridica 104–15 at 104–5.
53 For a discussion of the controversial nature of chieftaincy, see Bennett (2004) 111–13 and
120–3; Pillay, N and Prinsloo, C (1995) The changing face of ‘traditional courts De Jure 1:383
at 383–4.
54 See Woolman and Swanepoel (2013) 2.21–2.22.
55 Republic of South Africa Constitution Act 110 of 1983.
56 S 14 of the 1983 Constitution. See Basson and Viljoen (1988) 152.
57 S 15 of the 1983 Constitution.
58 S 16 of the 1983 Constitution.
59 The notion of a Charter was first mooted at the annual Congress of the ANC in August 1953.
Prof ZK Mathews formally suggested convening a Congress of the People (COP) to draw up
the Freedom Charter. The idea was adopted by the allies of the ANC, the South African
Indian Congress, the South African Coloured People’s Organisation and the South African
Congress of Democrats.
60 Woolman and Swanepoel (2013) 2.28.
61 African National Congress (1989) ‘Constitutional Guidelines for a Democratic South Africa’
reprinted in SAJHR 5(2):129–32 at 129. For discussions of this document, see Nagan, WP
(1989) Law and Post-Apartheid South Africa Fordham International Law Journal 12(3):399–
451; and Dugard, J (1990) A Bill of Rights for South Africa Cornell International Law Journal
23(3):441.
62 Constitutional Guidelines at 131.
63 Dugard (1990) 450.
64 ‘The Harare declaration: The ANC’s chapter for negotiations’ (1990, 1 January) accessed on
6 March 2019 at https://www.africaportal.org/publications/the-harare-declaration-the-
ancs-chapter-for-negotiations/.
65 Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (CCT 23/96) [1996]
ZACC 26; 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC) (6 September 1996) (First
Certification) para 10.
66 Sparks, AH (1994) Tomorrow is Another Country: The Inside Story of South Africa’s
Revolution.
67 South African History Online ‘The ANC unveils its proposed constitutional principles’
accessed on 6 March 2019 at https://www.sahistory.org.za/dated-event/anc-unveils-its-
proposed-constitutional-principles.
68 ANC Constitutional Committee ‘A Discussion Document of Structures and Principles of a
Constitution for a Democratic South Africa’ (1991, 8 April) at 16, accessed on 7 March 2019
at https://dullahomarinstitute.org.za/about-us/our-historical-publications/anc-
discussion-document-on-structures-and-principles-of-a-constitution-for-democrcatic-
sa.pdf.
69 By the time the interim Constitution was finalised, the Inkatha Freedom Party (IFP) and its
allies in the Freedom Alliance (consisting of various Bantustan governments and pro-
apartheid white parties) had walked out of the negotiations.
70 See Venter, F (2010) Liberal democracy: The unintended consequence – South African
constitution-writing propelled by the winds of globalisation SAJHR 26(1):45–65 at 53.
Venter notes that this wording was developed by a working group of the Steering
Committee established by the 19 participating parties that committed themselves to
CODESA in the course of November and December 1991. It was partly foreshadowed in
chapter 1 of the National Peace Accord signed on 14 September 1991 by some 40 parties
and organisations.
71 Available at
https://omalley.nelsonmandela.org/omalley/index.php/site/q/03lv02039/04lv02046/05lv
02047/06lv02049/07lv02052.htm.
72 The MPNF emerged after intense negotiation which led to the Record of Understanding
signed on 26 September 1992, which is available at http://www.anc.org.za/show.php?
id=4206.
73 First Certification para 12.
74 Murray, C (2001) A constitutional beginning: Making South Africa’s final Constitution
University of Arkansas at Little Rock Law Review 23:809–38(3):809–38 at 813, available at
https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/lawreview/vol23/iss3/3.
75 The procedure for the adoption of the final Constitution was laid down in ss 68–73 of the
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 200 of 1993.
76 See also First Certification paras 16–19.
77 S 97(2)(a) of the interim Constitution.
78 S 99(3) of the interim Constitution.
79 S 99(4) of the interim Constitution read with s 99(5).
80 First Certification para 45.
81 S 71(3) of the interim Constitution.
82 Madlingozi, T (2018) South Africa’s first black lawyers, amaRespectables and the birth of
evolutionary constitution – a review of Tembeka Ngcukaitobi’s The Land is Ours: South
Africa’s First Black Lawyers and the Birth of Constitutionalism SAJHR 34(3):517–29 at 519–
20.
83 See South African History Online ‘Elections in post-apartheid South Africa’ available at
http://www.sahistory.org.za/elections-post-apartheid-south-africa.
84 The Democratic Party is the forerunner of the Democratic Alliance, that was formed when
the DP merged with the NP.
85 Murray (2001) 816. The Constitutional Assembly’s slogan, ‘You’ve made your mark now
have your say’, invited the many millions of South Africans who had voted for the first time
in 1994 to contribute to the country’s first democratic Constitution – and over two million
did so. See generally Ebrahim, H (1998) The Soul of a Nation: Constitution-making in South
Africa.
86 See ss 72–3 of the interim Constitution. A panel of constitutional experts comprising two
practising lawyers and five academic lawyers was to review the final Constitution. The
panel had a month to come up with ‘deadlock-breaking’ ideas.
87 Woolman and Swanepoel (2013) 2.41.
88 See s 73(8) of the interim Constitution.
89 Murray (2001) 832.
90 As quoted in Murray (2001) 821. This particular submission was dated 16 May 1995.
91 First Certification para 34.
92 First Certification paras 36–7.
93 First Certification para 44.
94 (CCT 23/96) [1996] ZACC 26; 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC) (6 September
1996).
95 See First Certification para 482.
96 (CCT37/96) [1996] ZACC 24; 1997 (1) BCLR 1; 1997 (2) SA 97 (CC) (4 December 1996).
97 S 1 of the Constitution.
98 S 2 of the Constitution.
99 S 7(2) of the Constitution.
100 S 211 of the Constitution.
101 S 212 of the Constitution.
102 See Klare, K (1998) Legal culture and transformative constitutionalism SAJHR 14(1):146–88;
Chaskalson, A (2000) The third Bram Fischer lecture: Human dignity as a foundational
value of our constitutional order SAJHR 16(2):193–205 at 199; Pieterse, M (2005) What do
we mean when we talk about transformative constitutionalism? SA Public Law 20:155–66;
Langa, P (2006) Transformative constitutionalism SLR 17(3):351–60; Moseneke, D (2009)
Transformative constitutionalism: Its implications for the law of contract SLR 20(1):3–13 at
4; Davis, DM and Klare, K (2010) Transformative constitutionalism and the common and
customary law SAJHR 26(3):403–509.
103 Mkontwana v Nelson Mandela Metropolitan Municipality and Another; Bissett and Others v
Buffalo City Municipality and Others; Transfer Rights Action Campaign and Others v MEC,
Local Government and Housing, Gauteng, and Others (Kwazulu-Natal Law Society and
Msunduzi Municipality as amici curiae) (CCT 57/03) [2004] ZACC 9; 2005 (1) SA 530 (CC);
2005 (2) BCLR 150 (CC) (6 October 2004) para 81; Soobramoney v Minister of Health
(Kwazulu-Natal) (CCT32/97) [1997] ZACC 17; 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC); 1997 (12) BCLR 1696
(CC) (27 November 1997) para 8; Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic Offences and
Others v Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd and Others In re: Hyundai Motor Distributors
(Pty) Ltd and Others v Smit NO and Others (CCT1/00) [2000] ZACC 12; 2000 (10) BCLR 1079
(CC); 2001 (1) SA 545 (CC) (25 August 2000) para 21.
104 S v Makwanyane and Another (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3; 1995 (6) BCLR 665 (CC); 1995 (3)
SA 391 (CC); 1995 (2) SACR 1 (CC) (6 June 1995) para 262.
105 See Davis, D (1999) Democracy and Deliberation: Transformation and the South African
Legal Order 44.
106 See ss 1 and 7 of the Constitution. The Constitution’s historically situated character has
been recognised in several Constitutional Court judgments. See, for example, The Azanian
People’s Organization (AZAPO) and Others v The President of the Republic of South Africa
and Others CCT17/96) [1996] ZACC 16; 1996 (8) BCLR 1015; 1996 (4) SA 672 (CC) (25 July
1996) para 50: ‘constitutional journey from the shame of the past to the promise of the
future’; para 42: ‘[w]hat the Constitution seeks to do is to facilitate the transition to a new
democratic order’. See also De Vos, P (2001) A bridge too far? History as context in the
interpretation of the South African Constitution SAJHR 17(1):1–33.
107 Klare (1998) 152.
108 See generally Klare (1998) 153–6.
109 See s 7(2) of the Constitution, which states that the state has a duty to respect, protect,
promote and fulfil the rights in the Bill of Rights, and Minister of Finance and Other v Van
Heerden (CCT 63/03) [2004] ZACC 3; 2004 (6) SA 121 (CC); 2004 (11) BCLR 1125 (CC) (29
July 2004) para 24.
110 See ss 26–8 of the Constitution.
111 See s 9(4) of the Constitution.
112 See, generally, ss 40(2) and 41(1). See also s 32 (access to information); s 33 (right to fair
and just administrative action); and ss 34 and 38 (access to courts) and s 234 (charters of
rights).
113 Makwanyane paras 224 and 263.
114 See National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality and Another v Minister of Justice and
Others (CCT11/98) [1998] ZACC 15; 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC); 1998 (12) BCLR 1517 (CC) (9
October 1998) para 135: ‘The Constitution acknowledges the variability of human beings
(genetic and socio-cultural), affirms the right to be different, and celebrates the diversity of
the nation.’
115 S 1(a); s 7(1); s 39(1) of the Constitution.
116 Modiri, J (2018) Conquest and constitutionalism: first thoughts on an alternative
jurisprudence SAJHR 34(3):300–25 at 310.
117 Andrews, P (2017, 4 July) South Africa’s problems lie in political negligence, not its
Constitution The Conversation accessed on 6 August 2019 at
https://theconversation.com/south-africas-problems-lie-in-political-negligence-not-its-
constitution-80474.
118 Sibanda, S (2011) Not Purpose-made! Transformative Constitutionalism, Post-
independence Constitutionalism and the Struggle to Eradicate Poverty Stellenbosch Law
Review (Jan 2011) 22(3):482–500 at 493. [Footnotes omitted]
119 Makwanyane para 321 per O’Regan J: the language of fundamental rights is ‘broad and
capable of different interpretations’; para 207 per Kriegler J: ‘… it would be foolish to deny
that the judicial process, especially in the field of constitutional adjudication, calls for value
judgments in which extra-legal considerations may loom large’; para 265 per Mahomed
DP: The Constitution must be examined with reference, inter alia, to the text, context and
the ‘factual and historical considerations’; para 382 per Sachs J: ‘in seeking the kind of
values which should inform the court’s approach to interpretation the “rational and
humane adjudicatory approach” must be preferred’.
120 See also Makwanyane para 207 per Kriegler J: ‘… methods to be used are essentially legal,
not moral or philosophical … it would be foolish to deny that the judicial process,
especially in the field of constitutional adjudication, calls for value judgments in which
extra-legal considerations may loom large. Nevertheless the starting point, the framework
and the outcome of the exercise must be legal’; para 349 per Sachs J: ‘Our function is to
interpret the text of the Constitution as it stands. Accordingly, whatever our personal views
on this fraught subject might be, our response must be a purely legal one’; para 265 per
Mahomed DP: ‘… difference between a political election made by a legislative organ and
decisions reached by a judicial organ, like the Constitutional Court, is crucial’.
121 See Klare (1998) 172–87 for examples of this kind of reasoning by the judges of the
Constitutional Court.
122 (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3; 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC); 1995 (6) BCLR 665; 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC);
1995 (2) SACR 1 (CC) (6 June 1995) para 265.
123 See the reference to R v Big M Drug Mart Ltd (1985) 18 DLR (4th) at 321 in S v Zuma and
Others (CCT 5/94); [1995] ZACC 1; 1995 (2) SA 642 (CC) ; 1995 (4) BCLR 401 (CC) (5 April
1995) para 15; President of the Republic of South Africa and Another v Hugo (CCT 11/96);
[1997] ZACC 4; 1997 (4) SA 1 (CC) ; 1997 (6) BCLR 708 (CC) (18 April 1997) para 41; Prinsloo
v Van der Linde and Another (CCT4/96) [1997] ZACC 5; 1997 (3) SA 1012 (CC); 1997 (6)
BCLR 759 (CC) (18 April 1997) para 32. On the use of history, see, for example, Zuma para
15 where Kentridge J stated that ‘… regard must be paid to the legal history, traditions and
usages of the country concerned …’; Makwanyane para 39 where Chaskalson P stated that
‘we are required to construe the South African Constitution … with due regard to our legal
system, our history and circumstances …’; para 264 where Mahomed DP stated ‘It is against
this historical background and ethos that the constitutionality of capital punishment must
be determined.’; and paras 322–23 where O’Regan J stated that ‘… the values urged upon
the Court are not those that have informed our past …’ and in ‘… interpreting the rights
enshrined in Chapter 3, therefore, the Court is directed to the future’. See also Executive
Council of the Western Cape Legislature and Others v President of the Republic of South
Africa and Others (CCT27/95) [1995] ZACC 8; 1995 (4) SA 877 (CC); 1995 (10) BCLR 1289
(CC) (22 September 1995) para 61 where Chaskalson P stated that the nature and extent of
the power of Parliament to delegate its legislative powers ultimately depends ‘on the
language of the Constitution, construed in the light of the country’s own history’.
124 For a short review of contextual interpretation by the Constitutional Court, see Currie, I and
De Waal, J (2013) The Bill of Rights Handbook 140–5.
125 See De Vos (2001).
126 Soobramoney paras 8–9.
127 See South Africa: 2019 National Assembly Election Results, IEC, available at
https://www.elections.org.za/NPEDashboard/app/dashboard.html.
128 See Choudhry (2009) 1–85. Whether South Africa can indeed be characterised in this
manner has been the subject of intense debate. See Southall, R (1994) The South African
elections of 1994: The remaking of a dominant-party state Journal of Modern African
Studies 32(4):629–55; Giliomee, H (1998) South Africa’s emerging dominant-party regime
Journal of Democracy 94:128; Southall, R (1998) The centralization and fragmentation of
South Africa’s dominant party system African Affairs 97(389):443–69; Friedman, S ‘No easy
stroll to dominance: Party dominance, opposition and civil society in South Africa’ in
Giliomee, H and Simkins, C (eds) (1999) The Awkward Embrace: One Party Domination
and Democracy in Industrialising Countries 97; Giliomee, H, Myburgh, J and Schlemmer, L
(2001) Dominant party rule, opposition parties and minorities in South Africa
Democratization 8(1):161–82; Southall, R (2001a) Opposition in South Africa: Issues and
problems Democratization 8(1):1–24; Southall, R (2001b) Conclusion: Emergent
perspectives on opposition in South Africa Democratization 8(1):275–84; Alence, R (2004)
South Africa after apartheid: The first decade Journal of Democracy 15(3):78–92 at 78;
Hamill, J (2004) The elephant and the mice: Election 2004 and the future of opposition
politics in South Africa The Round Table: The Commonwealth Journal of International
Affairs 93(377):691–708; Lodge, T (2004) The ANC and the development of party politics in
modern South Africa Journal of Modern African Studies 42(2):189–219; Southall, R (2005)
The ‘dominant party debate’ in South Africa Afrika Spectrum 40(1):61–82; Suttner, R (2006)
Party dominance theory: Of what value? Politikon: SA Journal of Political Studies 33(3):277–
97; Handley, A, Murray, C and Simeon, R ‘Learning to lose, learning to win: Government
and opposition in South Africa’s transition to democracy’ in Friedman, E and Wong, J (eds)
(2008) Political Transitions in Dominant Party Systems: Learning to Lose 191.
129 Lodge, T (2004) The ANC and the development of party politics in modern South Africa
Journal of Modern African Studies 42(2):205–207.
Basic concepts of constitutional
law
2.1 Introduction
2.2 Constitutionalism
2.2.1 Understanding the nature of constitutionalism
2.2.2 Constitutionalism understood descriptively
2.2.3 Constitutionalism understood prescriptively
2.2.4 Constitutionalism in South Africa: a brief overview
2.2.4.1 Introduction
2.2.4.2 The era of the dominance of the Westminster constitutional model
2.2.4.3 The era of constitutional supremacy
2.2.4.3.1 Introduction
2.2.4.3.2 Constitutional supremacy
2.2.4.3.3 A value-based constitutional system
2.2.4.3.4 Co-operative ‘federalism’
2.5 Democracy
2.5.1 Introduction
2.5.2 Conceptions of democracy
2.5.3 Direct democracy
2.5.4 Representative democracy
2.5.5 Participatory democracy
2.5.6 Constitutional democracy
Summary
2.1 Introduction
To obtain a sound command of South Africa’s system of constitutional
law, it is important that we consider certain fundamental concepts at
the outset. This is necessary to establish a common understanding of
the doctrines, concepts and principles that lie at the heart of the
Constitution, 1996 (hereinafter referred to as the ‘Constitution’), the
context in which it emerged and the context in which it operates. These
doctrines, concepts and principles are given concrete expression in
many of the provisions of the Constitution. When we study specific
aspects of the Constitution, therefore, we need to do so in the light of
the doctrines, concepts and principles discussed in this chapter.
The aim of this chapter is to introduce some of the overarching ideas
that are pivotal in both explaining and contextualising the development
of South Africa’s system of constitutional law. Although we focus on
constitutional developments that have taken place in the period after
South Africa’s transition to democracy, we also consider some
important constitutional moments from the colonial and apartheid
periods for purposes of context. We also locate these constitutional
developments within a broader historical and political context that
recognises the influence of the constitutional law and practices of other
countries.
2.2 Constitutionalism
In the light of the characteristics set out above, we can conclude that, in
essence, constitutionalism is about the notion that a constitution must
both structure and constrain state power. On the one hand, a
constitution must establish institutions and structures of governance
and allocate power to them for the effective governing of a state. On the
other hand, it must limit and disperse that power among the
institutions and structures of governance in an attempt to ensure that it
will not be abused.
While constitutionalism seeks to achieve what are clearly important,
if not sometimes conflicting, ideals, it is important to acknowledge that
the manner in which these ideals may be achieved differs from one
political community to the next. The system of constitutionalism
adopted by a political community and its relationship to other
important constitutional law concepts, such as the separation of
powers, the rule of law, democracy and the protection of human right
depends on a variety of factors. Perhaps the most important of these is
the political and social history of that community.
An important consequence of these diverse political and social
histories is that over the centuries during which the concept of
constitutionalism has evolved, different understandings and different
models have developed. These differences are reflected in the explicit or
implicit norms and values on which a particular constitution is based,
the manner in which a particular constitution structures and allocates
power and the way in which the text of the constitution has been
interpreted and applied by the judiciary and other bodies. We consider
some of these understandings and models below.
2.2.4.1 Introduction
We discussed South Africa’s constitutional history in chapter 1 and will
not repeat it here. As noted in chapter 1, we do not agree with the view
that South Africa’s constitutional history can be explained solely with
reference to the formal structures imposed by the colonial rulers and
that South Africa’s constitutional history started in 1910. Nor do we wish
readers to lose sight of the bifurcated nature of the constitutional
arrangements in place from 1910 to 1994. However, as the governance
traditions of indigenous South Africans have had a limited impact on
the provisions of the South African Constitution, we focus here on the
colonial history of constitutionalism in South Africa. We, therefore, do
not claim that the models considered here are the only ones that have
influenced South African constitutional developments, but it is
arguable that they have had the most significant and identifiable
influence on the constitutional structure and content of present-day
South Africa.
Given the bifurcated nature of the state and the apartheid policies of the
National Party (NP) which governed South Africa from 1948–1994, it is
not surprising that during this period the NP government used
parliamentary supremacy as a powerful instrument to secure political
power for the white minority. In addition, the NP government used
parliamentary supremacy to insulate the many legal provisions which
discriminated against black South Africans and which restricted the
basic rights of citizens from effective judicial scrutiny.
Having said this, however, we must be careful not to confuse the
substance of the Westminster constitutional model with the abuses to
which it was put and can potentially be put. The British experience with
parliamentary supremacy is markedly different from that of its former
colony South Africa and bears testimony to the fact that as a model of
constitutionalism, there is nothing inherently flawed or problematic
with the Westminster model. Like all other constitutional models, it has
its strengths and weaknesses, but any weaknesses it may have are not
directly responsible for the system of racial or gender exclusion and
apartheid. Often, such weaknesses can be traced back to problems with
the political culture and political parties and not necessarily with
constitutional structures.
However, the tainted history of the Westminster system in South
Africa most likely contributed to it not being wholly adopted as the
preferred model during constitutional negotiations in the early 1990s.23
While the end of apartheid brought with it an end to the era of
parliamentary supremacy in South Africa, aspects of the Westminster
system nevertheless found their way into the South African Constitution
in amended form.
2.2.4.3.1 Introduction
We discussed the history of the constitutional negotiations in chapter 1
and detailed the context that informed the choices made by the drafters
of the Constitution. In this section, we therefore describe and discuss
the prominent features of South Africa’s democratic Constitution that
arose from constitutional negotiations.
Apart from the clearly articulated values found in section 1, there are
also some unarticulated values embodied in the Constitution which,
together with those in section 1, form the normative basis of how the
South African Constitution is to be interpreted.36 In other words, our
Constitution does not simply set out the rules, processes and structures
that place limits on governmental power. The Constitution also
expresses itself on the ideals and characteristics to which we, as a
society, deem worthy to aspire. This idea should be familiar to us as it is
derived from the notion of a value-based democratic order as found in
the German model discussed above.37 In the South African context, the
courts have recognised the significance of the value-based
constitutional system where they have asserted that the democratic
constitutional order has established an ‘objective normative value
system’.38 However, this notion, while self-evidently important, has not
been the subject of much attention from the courts 39 or academic
commentators in South Africa.40
The principles set out above are generally accepted as the pillars on
which the doctrine of separation of powers is based. However, it is
acknowledged that no constitutional system encompasses a full
separation of governmental authority where power is exercised by each
individual branch of government in isolation from the others.47 Instead,
the division of power, functions and personnel, and the provision for
checks and balances, differ extensively among constitutions that
subscribe to the doctrine.
2.3.3.1 Introduction
As mentioned above, Constitutional Principle VI in the interim
Constitution required that the final Constitution incorporate a system of
separation of powers. However, this Principle was silent as to the exact
nature of the distribution of power between the three branches and the
institutional limits to be put in place on the exercise of power by each of
the branches. Instead, what Constitutional Principle VI did specify was
the purpose for which the separation of powers had to be incorporated
into the 1996 Constitution. This purpose was to uphold and safeguard
important democratic values and norms, namely ‘accountability,
responsiveness, and openness’.57 It was, therefore, left to the drafters of
the 1996 Constitution to determine how the South African model of
separation of powers was to be conceptualised and incorporated.
Note that there is no universal model of separation of powers.
Moreover, in democratic systems of government in which checks and
balances result in the imposition of restraints by one branch of
government on another, there is no separation that is absolute.58 The
concept can be incorporated in a constitution in different ways: it can
require a more or less strict separation of functions and personnel as
well as more or less powerful mechanisms that would allow one branch
of government to enforce checks and balances on another. In
interpreting the separation of powers in the South African context, what
is clear is that the Constitutional Court is reluctant to measure the South
African model against the standards of other countries or other models
of separation of powers. It is, therefore, important to recognise that we
must interpret and judge South Africa’s model of separation of powers
with our own historical experiences and political context in mind.59 The
Constitutional Court captured this idea crisply in De Lange v Smuts NO
and Others when Ackermann J wrote as follows:
I have no doubt that over time our courts will develop a distinctively South
African model of separation of powers, one that fits the particular system of
government provided for in the Constitution and that reflects a delicate
balancing, informed both by South Africa’s history and its new dispensation,
between the need, on the one hand, to control government by separating
powers and enforcing checks and balances, and, on the other, to avoid diffusing
power so completely that the government is unable to take timely measures in
the public interest.60
Table 2.1 The manner in which checks and balances are effected by each branch of government on the
others
2.3.3.5 The counter-majoritarian dilemma
In a constitutional democracy, like that established by the South African
Constitution, the Constitution and not Parliament is supreme. The
judiciary is independent and empowered to review and set aside the
actions of the other two branches of government. The judiciary thus
necessarily wields enormous power even though its members are not
democratically elected. Although this is a necessary result of the
particular system of separation of powers and judicial review adopted
by the drafters of the South African Constitution, this system raises
many conceptual and practical difficulties.
It is true that judicial review is an institution that is generally
accepted as being of central importance to the South African
constitutional project. However, judicial review, rather than serving to
answer or resolve important constitutional questions, raises many of its
own that go to the heart of our understanding of the relationship
between democracy and separation of powers. For example, if we
accept judicial review as being a legitimate practice in a constitutional
democracy, how do we account for the fact that judicial review allows
for the invalidation of laws supported by a majority? 116 How is it
possible that the judiciary can substitute its own decision for that of the
executive when declaring a particular government policy to be
unreasonable, even in instances where the executive has consulted
widely? 117 What makes the decision of a few unelected judges carry
more weight than the choices of the majority?
These questions taken together raise what is commonly referred to
as the counter-majoritarian dilemma or difficulty. The essence of the
dilemma is that judicial review, while recognised as having a legitimate
purpose in the main, involves the courts taking undemocratic decisions
that often go against the popular will.118 The obvious underlying
apprehension is that while the constitutional system may be founded
on democratic principles and practices, judicial review allows for the
democratic will to be displaced by unelected and seemingly
unaccountable judges.
Given that the Constitution of the United States does not make
explicit provision for judicial review, it is not surprising that the
institution of judicial review has, for a long time, been the subject of
much controversy among US constitutional law scholars.119 At its core,
the enduring controversy around judicial review relates to concerns
regarding the nature and extent of the power that it places in the hands
of an unelected judiciary and that allows judges (i) to make decisions
with overtly political consequences and (ii) to encroach on the domain
of the other branches. These controversies have led to much debate on
the precise nature of the democratic curtailment and the separation of
powers issues raised by judicial review and how to resolve them or
otherwise account for them as being somehow aligned with
democracy.120 In the main, attempts to account for counter-
majoritarianism have elicited three types of responses:
• Some view judicial review as being a severe constraint on the
participation of citizens in political decisions affecting them and, as
such, see judicial review as being irreconcilable with the ideals of
majoritarian democracy.121
• Others downplay the significance of the difficulties judicial review
poses. They instead regard encroachments occasioned by judicial
review as contributing to the democratic process.122
• Yet others attempt to establish a workable interpretative theory in
terms of which judicial review can be justified as legitimising
judicial interventions in a manner that contributes to the attainment
of substantive democratic ends.123
These arguments briefly set out above merely represent some of the
views that have been put forward in an attempt to justify or account for
the inclusion of the institution of judicial review in a democratic system
of government. In and of themselves, they can be challenged and can be
found wanting in as far as completely dispelling accusations that
judicial review does tend to curtail or subtract from majoritarian
democracy. However, judging by the acceptance of judicial review in
some democratic societies, including South Africa, we can conclude
that there is some level of acceptance of the idea that there should be a
branch of government that must be tasked with the role of interpreting
and upholding the Constitution and the rights of all citizens. Put
differently, there appears to be some acceptance that for constitutional
democracy to flourish, it is sometimes necessary to employ some
outwardly undemocratic means to achieve long-term democratic ideals
such as inclusiveness, broad representivity, accountability and
transparency. It has been suggested that instead of glossing over judicial
review’s democratic deficit, there is a need to think of constitutions such
as South Africa’s as being mixed constitutions. The mixture in this sense
is that such constitutions, although grounded in democratic principles
and practice by necessity, also include an anti-democratic practice such
as the inclusion of judicial review.132
Figure 2.2 The counter-majoritarian dilemma
2.4.1 Introduction
An elemental feature of South African constitutionalism is the principle
of respect for the rule of law. The importance of the rule of law in South
African constitutional law is clearly demonstrated by the fact that the
rule of law is a founding value entrenched in section 1 of the
Constitution. However, there is some difference of opinion about the
scope and content of the rule of law and this is the subject of much
debate among constitutional law scholars.133 Apart from being a value,
the rule of law is also recognised as a pathway to review in terms of
which the exercise of public power in its various forms can be
challenged. In this section we briefly consider the rule of law in order to
detail its historical understanding under apartheid and then its
development and how it has been received by the courts in the
constitutional era.
Having discussed freely and frankly the rule of law with particular
reference to Africa, and
Having reached conclusions regarding human rights in relation to
government security, human rights in relation to aspects of
criminal and administrative law, and the responsibility of the
judiciary and of the Bar for the protection of the rights of the
individual in society,
NOW SOLEMNLY
Declares:
From the Fedsure case and subsequent cases, it would appear that the
principle of legality has become possibly the most important and oft-
invoked principle of the rule of law.145 As the Constitutional Court
explained, the principle of legality can be used by the courts to control
the exercise of public power. Thus, in Affordable Medicines Trust and
Others v Minister of Health and Another, the Court held that:
The exercise of public power must therefore comply with the Constitution,
which is the supreme law, and the doctrine of legality, which is part of that law.
The doctrine of legality, which is an incident of the rule of law, is one of the
constitutional controls through which the exercise of public power is regulated
by the Constitution … In this sense the Constitution entrenches the principle of
legality and provides the foundation for the control of public power.146
The courts’ employment of the rule of law has not been limited to its
appeal to the principle of legality. The courts have also had occasion to
use the rule of law to demand that public officials not act in an arbitrary
way, or put positively, that they must exercise their powers in a rational
manner related to the purpose for which the power was given.153 In
Chief Lesapo v North West Agricultural Bank and Another, the legislative
provision in question allowed for the respondent bank to seize and sell
the property of defaulting debtors without any recourse to the courts.154
In the matter, Mokgoro J denounced the use of public power to perform
such acts and described them as self-help which is inimical to the rule
of law. In capturing the rule of law principle forbidding self-help,
Mokgoro J said the following:155
Self help, in this sense, is inimical to a society in which the rule of law prevails
… Taking the law into one’s own hands is thus inconsistent with the
fundamental principles of our law.156
There are numerous other instances where a court has invoked the rule
of law as a principle in deciding cases or in its reasoning of the cases. A
few examples of such instances are as follows. The rule of law has been
invoked to demand that rules must be conveyed in a clear and
accessible manner for them to comply with the standards required by
the Constitution.158 The rule of law has, further, been invoked to
challenge legislation for vagueness and uncertainty where the
provisions of the legislation in question conferred broad discretionary
powers on a Minister.159 The Constitutional Court has also held that
judicial independence and impartiality are implicit in our
understanding of the rule of law as a constitutional principle.160
Overall, the rule of law seems to occupy pride of place as a
constitutional value alongside that of constitutional supremacy. The
rule of law simultaneously operates as an independent and enforceable
principle with an important and equally useful derivative in the form of
the principle of legality. We can thus argue that the current conception
of the rule of law is one that builds on the Diceyean understanding.
Judging from the manner in which the rule of law has been invoked in
our case law, it is evident that under the rubric of the rule of law, we are
now also concerned with the impact of laws on those affected, the
substantive content of laws as well as how public officials and bodies
exercise their powers even in the face of enabling laws. In short, our
conception of the rule of law under the Constitution is an evolving one.
2.5 Democracy
2.5.1 Introduction
The word democracy is widely accepted as deriving from a combination
of the Greek words ‘demos’ meaning the people (the citizenry) and
‘kratos’ meaning rule. It is therefore unsurprising that one of the major
rallying ideas underpinning the struggle for liberation in South Africa
was the demand of ‘democracy for all’.162 As unambiguous an aspiration
as that sounded, what it concealed was the fact that the concept of
democracy is one that can and has been described as ‘controversial’ 163
or is at the very least contested.164 The supposed ‘controversy’
underlying democracy is related to the fact that as a concept,
democracy has proven immensely difficult to define in a singular and
uncontested manner, with many writers preferring to provide their own
definitions or understandings of the word. Contributing to the
supposed ‘controversy’ is the fact that the term ‘democracy’ is
commonly used in conjunction, and possibly synonymously, with other
concepts such as ‘liberal’, ‘constitutional’ or ‘majoritarian’. Despite this
supposed ‘controversy’, democracy’s pre-eminence as one of the
dominant and enduring political ideas of modern times is unassailable.
Certainly, in the South African Constitution, the idea of democracy is a
prominent one that permeates virtually all aspects of the Constitution.
Beyond the Preamble, section 1 of the Constitution ushers in
democracy by declaring South Africa to be ‘a sovereign, democratic
state’. Section 1(d) builds further on this by setting out the democratic
values and principles on which South Africa is founded, namely
‘[u]niversal adult suffrage, a national common voters roll, regular
elections and a multi-party system of democratic government, to ensure
accountability, responsiveness and openness’. While not defining what
democracy means in South Africa, the section goes a long way towards
making explicit those elements of democracy that are paramount in the
South African constitutional context.165 In this section, we consider the
idea of democracy and its place in the South African constitutional
system.
SUMMARY
This chapter deals with the basic concepts of constitutional law which
inform the more detailed discussion of the various aspects of the South
African Constitution in subsequent chapters.
Constitutionalism is a multifaceted term and is concerned with the
distribution and allocation of powers in an organised way within a
given political community in which a government is established. It
provides for the establishment of the institutions of governance, such as
the legislature, the executive and the courts, as well as the allocation of
powers, duties and functions to the various institutions of government
which legitimise the exercise of power – within the limits set by the
Constitution – of each of these institutions. Constitutionalism also plays
an important role in determining the nature and basis of relations as
they exist between institutions of government and those they govern.
The principle of the separation of powers deals with the division of
governmental power across the three branches, namely the legislative
branch (Parliament), the executive branch (president/prime minister
and cabinet) and the judicial branch (the courts). These branches
ordinarily have separate functions and are staffed by different
personnel. This allows the various branches to check the exercise of
power of the other branches and thus ensures accountability. There are,
however, several models of separation of powers and it is important to
study these models and to understand the specific model adopted by
the South African Constitution as well as the practical and legal
consequences that flow from the adoption of this model.
The counter-majoritarian dilemma arises in a constitutional
democracy (like that established in South Africa) in which the
constitution rather than Parliament is supreme and in which the
judiciary is independent and empowered to review and set aside the
actions of the other two branches of government. This is because the
system affords the power of judicial review to courts. It thus permits an
unelected and seemingly unaccountable judiciary to declare
unconstitutional and invalid laws made and actions taken by
democratically elected and accountable members of the legislature and
executive. This can appear to be anti-democratic. It is important to
engage with the arguments justifying the legitimacy of this system and
attempting to resolve the counter-majoritarian difficulty.
The rule of law is a founding value of the South African Constitution
and is based on the notion that the law is supreme. Hence, public power
can only be exercised in terms of the authority conferred by law and in a
non-arbitrary manner. Inherent in this concept is also the principle that
everyone is equal before the law, the law must be applied equally to all
persons irrespective of their status and all must be subject to the
jurisdiction of the ordinary courts. The rule of law can be
conceptualised in formalistic terms or it can entail a more substantive
notion.
The core idea at the heart of democracy is that decisions affecting
the members of a political community should be taken by the members
themselves or at least by elected representatives whose power to make
decisions ultimately derives from the members. Different, and
sometimes overlapping, forms of democracy can exist within a state:
direct democracy; representative democracy; participatory democracy
and constitutional democracy. It is important to be able to distinguish
the various forms of democracy and to understand how these forms of
democracy relate to one another.
3.1 Introduction
Summary
3.1 Introduction
A study of the different branches of government can best be done by
using the separation of powers doctrine as a lens through which to look
at how the three branches operate and how they relate to one another.
In this chapter we therefore introduce the distinctly South African
version of the doctrine of separation of powers. The judiciary is still
developing this doctrine through the interpretation of the Constitution,
1996 (hereinafter referred to as the ‘Constitution’). In Chapter 2 of this
book we discussed the scope and content of the doctrine of separation
of powers as it manifests in various constitutional systems in other parts
of the world and, briefly, as it has thus far been developed in South
Africa. In the next three chapters we focus more pertinently on the
various branches of government established by the South African
Constitution,1 namely the legislature, the executive and the judiciary as
well as Chapter 9 institutions2 and the National Prosecuting Authority.3
We explore the composition, powers and functions of these branches of
government and the nature of the relationship between the various
branches with specific emphasis on the notion that these branches
operate in accordance with a system of checks and balances.
The discussion of these separate branches of government and their
relationship to each other takes place against the background of the
particular South African context highlighted in chapter 1, most notably
by what has been described as a ‘surprise re-entry’ and ‘resurgence’ of
traditional leadership in South Africa in the post-apartheid era.4 One of
the most vexing constitutional questions in the democratic era relates to
the role of traditional leaders and traditional governance structures,
and where and how these structures fit into a scheme of separation of
powers with its three branches of government.5 We will address this
question as we discuss the various branches of government. We do so as
we contend that the resurgence of customary practices and leadership
institutions in the democratic era is not as surprising as some
commentators have argued. This is especially so given that ‘South Africa
is as rich in tenacious institutions with indigenous roots as other
African countries’ and that these institutions ‘were entrenched (albeit
in distorted ways) over many decades of segregationist and apartheid
rule’.6 Moreover, if viewed from a historical perspective, it is sometimes
argued that traditional authorities in southern Africa ‘have always
engaged assertively with other sites of authority and forms of
government’.7 Current-day supporters of the maintenance and
restoration of traditional governance institutions and customs have
argued that traditional leaders have provided continuity of governance
even though they are undoubtedly tainted by their association with
segregation and apartheid. This is particularly so in rural areas where
there were scant alternative governance structures and the influence of
the institutions of the democratic state is at its weakest.8 Others,
however, see the resurgence of traditional governance institutions as a
regressive step that undermines progress towards democratic
consolidation in South Africa because traditional governance structures
are inherently undemocratic, patriarchal and potentially oppressive.9
Whatever a person’s view on traditional leadership and traditional
governance institutions, it is nevertheless important to explore the
powers and functions of the various branches of government and the
relationship between these branches with reference to these
institutions. To this end, we also discuss the powers and functions of the
National House of Traditional Leaders. Parliament created this
institution via the National House of Traditional Leaders Act (the
National House Act)10 pursuant to section 212(2)(a) of the Constitution.
This section permits the promulgation of legislation to deal with matters
relating to issues of traditional leadership. We will also discuss the more
recent Traditional and Khoi-San Leadership Act, 11 which further
regulates traditional leadership in South Africa.
Traditional descriptions of South African constitutional law ignore
those aspects of the South African political and governance context that
do not neatly reflect the Western-style constitutional structures
established by the Constitution. In this book, we focus on these
structures but do so with an awareness that there are different centres of
power in South Africa. One is centred around the formal institutions of
the legislature, the executive and the judiciary, all of which are
described and regulated in the Constitution. Another is centred around
a more informal and ever-changing set of institutions such as
traditional leadership institutions.
Apart from discussing the various branches of government with
reference to the role played by traditional leaders, we will also discuss
the various branches of government with reference to the role played by
political parties in bringing the Constitution into operation. Power is
centred in such political parties – especially the leadership of the most
dominant political parties, the African National Congress (ANC), the
Democratic Alliance (DA) and the Economic Freedom Fighters (EFF).
The internal culture of these parties and the leadership style of their
leaders thus influence how especially the legislature and the executive
operate within the doctrine of separation of powers.
Lastly, we consider the composition, powers and functions of
various other constitutional institutions created to support
constitutional democracy. These are sometimes referred to collectively
as the Chapter 9 institutions. These constitutional bodies are required to
play an oversight role over the legislature, the executive and the
judiciary, and to deepen and safeguard democracy. However, we limit
our discussion in this regard to the following institutions: the Public
Protector;12 the Auditor-General;13 and the Electoral Commission.14 In
addition, we consider the Judicial Service Commission (JSC).15
In the following chapters, therefore, we deal with four interrelated
issues relating to the structures of government as these operate within a
system of separation of powers:
• The current chapter sets out and explains the framework within
which the three branches of government operate and provides a
brief overview of the historical origins of the doctrine of separation
of powers and its influence on South Africa’s new constitutional
dispensation.
• Chapter 4 deals with the composition and functioning of the
legislature and its relationship with the other branches of
government.
• Chapter 5 deals with the composition and functioning of the
executive and its relationship with the other branches of
government.
• Chapter 6 deals with the composition and functioning of the
judiciary and its independence from the other branches of
government as well as the prosecuting authority.
• Chapter 7 considers the role of certain Chapter 9 institutions.
• Chapter 9 considers traditional leadership and customary law,
which does not fit neatly within the separation of powers
framework.
The courts must exercise this vital task while at the same time
remaining conscious of the limits on judicial authority and the
Constitution’s design and must leave certain matters to other branches
of government. This means that the judiciary should not interfere in the
processes of other branches of government unless to do so is mandated
by the Constitution.27 Accordingly, the division of powers is not strictly
enforced if it appears, for example, that one sphere of government is
failing to comply with its constitutional obligations. The courts can
always intrude to check the other branches when they fail to comply
with their constitutional obligations.28
In this regard, the judgment in Glenister I is apposite where the
Court held that:
it is a necessary component of the doctrine of the separation of powers that
courts have a constitutional obligation to ensure that the exercise of power by
other branches of government occurs within constitutional bounds. But even
in these circumstances, courts must observe the limits of their powers.29
This is in accordance with the test formulated in Doctors for Life, which
provides that intervention by a court in the legislative process:
would only be appropriate if an applicant can show that there would be no
effective remedy available … once the legislative process is complete, as the
unlawful conduct will have achieved its object in the course of the process. The
applicant must show that the resultant harm will be material and irreversible.30
SUMMARY
The Constitution creates three branches of government – the legislature,
the executive and the judiciary – and the study of each of these
branches of government must be conducted with reference to the
relationship between the branch being studied and the other two
branches. It must also be understood with reference to the practices of
traditional leadership and the culture within dominant political parties.
Understanding the separation of powers doctrine is therefore pivotal for
understanding how the various branches of government work and what
the limits of the power of each branch are. In this regard, the judiciary
must be treated as unique as it requires a high degree of independence
from the other branches of government. The judiciary has the vital task
of enforcing the provisions of the Constitution and of ensuring that the
other branches of government act in accordance with its provisions.
However, this format does not easily accommodate other structures of
government such as traditional leadership or Chapter 9 institutions.
1 See generally chapters 4, 5 and 8 of the Constitution, which detail the provisions pertaining
to Parliament, the President and the national executive, and the judiciary respectively, read
with Chapters 3 (co-operative government), 6 (the provinces), 7 (local government) and
Schedules 4 and 5 that delineate areas of concurrent national and provincial, and exclusive
provincial legislative competences.
2 Sees ss 181–94 of the Constitution.
3 See s 179 of the Constitution.
4 Oomen, B (2005) Chiefs in South Africa, Law, Culture, and Power in the Post-Apartheid Era
11.
5 Addressing this problem is made even more difficult by the fact that many traditional
leaders were co-opted by the apartheid regime. At the time of writing there has been a
resurgence of support for traditional leadership institutions and the role of African
customary law. Evidence of the latter can be garnered from the promulgation of the
Communal Land Rights Act 11 of 2004 (CLaRA) and the subsequent constitutional
challenge to it in Tongoane and Others v National Minister for Agriculture and Land Affairs
and Others 2010 (6) SA 214 (CC). See also Pilane and Another v Pilane and Another 2013 (4)
BCLR 431 (CC). For the leading commentary on CLaRA, traditional leadership and
communal land, see Claassens, A and Cousins, B (eds) (2008) Land, Power, and Custom:
Controversies Generated by South Africa’s Communal Land Rights Act.
6 See Beall, J, Mkhize, S and Vawda, S (2005) Emergent democracy and ‘resurgent’ tradition:
Institutions, chieftaincy and transition in KwaZulu-Natal Journal of Southern African
Studies 31(4):755–71 at 756.
7 Beall et al (2005) 756.
8 Hobsbawm, E and Ranger, T (eds) (1983) The Invention of Tradition and Vail, L (ed) (1989)
The Creation of Tribalism in Southern Africa.
9 See Beall et al (2005) fn 5.
10 Act 22 of 2009.
11 Act 3 of 2019.
12 S 181(1)(a) of the Constitution.
13 S 181(1)(e) of the Constitution.
14 S 181(1)(f ) of the Constitution.
15 S 178 of the Constitution.
16 The Constitution of the Republic of South Africa 200 of 1993.
17 See s 1 read with s 7 of the Constitution. The metaphor of a bridge was first introduced into
South Africa’s constitutional lexicon by the postamble to the interim Constitution titled
‘National Unity and Reconciliation’. It was popularised by Etienne Mureinik – see Mureinik,
E (1994) A bridge to where? Introducing South Africa’s interim Bill of Rights SAJHR 10:30.
See also S v Makwanyane and Another 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) para 262 where Mohamed DP,
quoting in part the postamble to the interim Constitution, said: ‘The South African
Constitution is different: it retains from the past only what is defensible and represents a
decisive break from, and a ringing rejection of, that part of the past which is disgracefully
racist, authoritarian, insular, and repressive and a vigorous identification of and
commitment to a democratic, universalistic, caring and aspirationally egalitarian ethos,
expressly articulated in the Constitution … What the Constitution expressly aspires to do is
to provide a transition from these grossly unacceptable features of the past to a
conspicuously contrasting “future founded on the recognition of human rights, democracy
and peaceful co-existence and development opportunities for all South Africans,
irrespective of colour, race, class, belief or sex”.’
18 S v Makwanyane and Another 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) para 220.
19 S 165(1) and (2).
20 2009 (1) SA 287 (CC). This case is known as Glenister I as the Constitutional Court later
handed down judgment in a similar matter in Glenister v President of the Republic of South
Africa and Others 2011 (3) SA 347 (CC), known as Glenister II.
21 Glenister I paras 29–32.
22 2006 (6) SA 416 (CC) para 37. See also Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of
South Africa, 1996 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC) paras 106–113 where the Court held that the
provisions of the Constitution are structured in a way that makes provision for the
separation of powers, and South African Association of Personal Injury Lawyers v Heath and
Others 2001 (1) SA 883 (CC) para 22.
23 See, for example, s 172(1) of the Constitution which provides that a court: ‘(a) must declare
that any law or conduct that is inconsistent with the Constitution is invalid to the extent of
its inconsistency; and (b) may make any order that is just and equitable, including: (i) an
order limiting the retrospective effect of the declaration of invalidity; and (ii) an order
suspending the declaration of invalidity for any period and on any conditions, to allow the
competent authority to correct the defect.’
24 S 167(5) of the Constitution provides: ‘The Constitutional Court makes the final decision
whether an Act of Parliament, a provincial Act or conduct of the President is constitutional,
and must confirm any order of invalidity made by the Supreme Court of Appeal, the High
Court of South Africa, or a court of similar status, before that order has any force.’
25 S 1(c) read with s 8(1).
26 Doctors for Life International v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others 2006 (6) SA 416
(CC) para 38.
27 Doctors for Life para 37.
28 See Minister of Health and Others v Treatment Action Campaign and Others (No 2) 2002 (5)
SA 721 (CC) para 99 where the Court stated: ‘The primary duty of courts is to the
Constitution and the law, “which they must apply impartially and without fear, favour or
prejudice”. The Constitution requires the state to “respect, protect, promote, and fulfil the
rights in the Bill of Rights”. Where state policy is challenged as inconsistent with the
Constitution, courts have to consider whether in formulating and implementing such
policy the state has given effect to its constitutional obligations. If it should hold in any
given case that the state has failed to do so, it is obliged by the Constitution to say so. In so
far as that constitutes an intrusion into the domain of the executive, that is an intrusion
mandated by the Constitution itself.’
29 Glenister I para 33. See also Mazibuko v Sisulu and Another 2013 (6) SA 249 (CC) para 31
where the Constitutional Court affirmed is reluctance to interfere in the power of the NA to
determine its own internal arrangements, proceedings and procedures, and to make rules
and orders concerning its business.
30 Doctors for Life para 44. This test applies equally to executive decision-making and
execution of law and policy.
31 Glenister I para 35. See also Liebenberg, S (2010) Socio-Economic Rights Adjudication under
a Transformative Constitution 67.
32 Liebenberg (2010) 67.
33 Liebenberg (2010) 69, quoting Minow, M (1990) Making All the Difference: Inclusion,
Exclusion and American Law 361.
34 Liebenberg (2010) 71.
35 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC) paras 108–109. See also De Lange v Smuts NO and Others 1998 (3) SA
785 (CC) para 60 where Ackermann J stated: ‘I have no doubt that over time our Courts will
develop a distinctively South African model of separation of powers, one that fits the
particular system of government provided for in the Constitution and that reflects a
delicate balancing, informed both by South Africa’s history and its new dispensation,
between the need, on the one hand, to control government by separating powers and
enforcing checks and balances, and, on the other, to avoid diffusing power so completely
that the government is unable to take timely measures in the public interest.’
36 Doctors for Life para 70.
37 In S v Dodo 2001 (3) SA 382 (CC), the Constitutional Court found that the legislative
prescription requiring courts to impose mandatory minimum sentences in certain cases
did not necessarily infringe on the separation of powers doctrine. As checks and balances
constitute an integral part of the separation of powers principle and prevent one arm of the
state from becoming too powerful in the exercise of the powers allocated to it, legislation
on penal sentencing does not, per se, infringe the separation of powers principle between
the legislature and the judiciary.
38 De Vos, P (2011, 24 November) Cabinet statement on transformation of judicial system
Constitutionally Speaking available at http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/cabinet-
statement-on-transformation-of-judicial-system/.
39 See Yacoob, Z (2012, 12 March) ‘The Dynamic Constitution’, Keynote Address, University of
Cape Town Constitution Week, available at http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/justice-
zac-yacoob-on-the-dynamic-constitution/ where, in reference to the proposed
Department of Justice’s ‘review’ of the jurisprudence of South Africa’s Constitutional Court
and Supreme Court of Appeal and an evaluation of the contribution or lack thereof of
jurisprudence to the transformation of society, the Justice stated: ‘… this cannot be
intended to mean that the executive and the legislature should be able to discuss matters of
importance with the judiciary directly and outside a court hearing, in an effort to influence
it. If this is what is meant I would find it difficult to agree.’
Separation of powers and the
national legislature
4.1 Introduction
Summary
4.1 Introduction
As we noted in Chapter 2, one of the fundamental concepts on which
South Africa’s system of constitutional law is based is the separation of
powers. This concept seeks to curtail the abuse of public power by
distributing it among the legislative, executive and judicial branches of
government, which can then be held accountable for the manner in
which they have exercised their powers and performed their duties.
Although the Constitution does not expressly refer to the separation of
powers, it does divide the national government into three separate
branches, namely the national legislature or Parliament as it is referred
to by the Constitution, the national executive and the judiciary. In this
chapter we focus on Parliament. More specifically, we focus on the
structure, composition, functions, powers, duties and procedures of
Parliament. Before turning to consider these issues, however, it will be
helpful to discuss the constitutional responsibilities of Parliament.
The constitutional responsibilities of Parliament were summed up
by the Constitutional Court (in somewhat lofty language) in Economic
Freedom Fighters v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others;
Democratic Alliance v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others,1
where the Court held that, not only is Parliament ‘the embodiment of
the centuries-old dreams and legitimate aspirations of all our people’,
but is also ‘the voice of all South Africans, especially the poor, the
voiceless and the least-remembered’. In addition, Parliament is ‘the
watchdog of state resources, the enforcer of fiscal discipline and cost-
effectiveness for the common good of all our people’. Apart from these
responsibilities, the Court held further, Parliament is also responsible
for ‘holding the Executive accountable for the fulfilment of the promises
made to the populace …’ and for passing ‘legislation with due regard to
the needs and concerns of the broader South African public’. In light of
these dicta, it may be said that Parliament is responsible for:
• articulating the aspirations, concerns and desires of all South
Africans, especially of the poorest and most vulnerable
• ensuring that all executive organs of state in the national sphere of
government are accountable to it
• maintaining oversight of the exercise of national executive authority
and especially the authority to use state resources and spend public
money
• considering, passing, amending or rejecting legislation on any
subject that falls within its legislative authority.
The NCOP has a less defined role in holding the executive to account
and has no role in the appointment or dismissal of members of the
executive. Unlike the executive, which has its seat in Tshwane, the seat
of Parliament is in Cape Town.14 However, an Act of Parliament can
determine that the seat of Parliament is changed as long as the correct
procedure is followed.15 Sittings of the NA or the NCOP are permitted at
places other than the seat of Parliament, but only on the grounds of
public interest, security or convenience, and if provided for in the rules
and orders of the NA16 or the NCOP.17
Despite the Constitutional Court’s view in the UDM judgment that MPs
need to serve the people above their party, political parties and their
leaders still hold enormous power over elected members of the
legislature in South Africa. There are four interrelated reasons for this:
• First, we inherited our system of parliamentary government from
Britain. In this system the support of the majority party in
Parliament is required to form the government.30 Thus, the executive
requires the continued support of the majority of members of the
legislature to survive. This provides a strong incentive to members of
the legislature to ‘toe the party line’, regardless of any differences an
individual member of the legislature may have with the decisions or
actions of the political party leadership. If members of the governing
party fail to respect party discipline and vote with opposition parties
and against the majority party, and the government loses a vote in
Parliament, this can erode the democratic legitimacy of the
government and can even lead to the fall of that government.
• Second, we also inherited the convention of strict party discipline
from the Westminster system associated with the system of
parliamentary government.31 This convention places severe
restrictions on individual Members of Parliament (MPs) to disobey
party leaders when they engage in legislative or executive action.
The convention of strict party discipline was applied in pre-
democratic South Africa in the Westminster Parliament as well as in
the tricameral Parliament. When the new democratic system
replaced the old system, the convention of strict party discipline was
retained. Thus, this convention remains intact in democratic South
Africa and forms part of the parliamentary culture.
• Third, the internal culture of South African political parties places
great emphasis on internal party discipline. This type of internal
culture values and rewards party members who demonstrate loyalty
to the party and the decisions democratically arrived at by that
party. It also values respect for the leadership of the party and
rewards those who display such respect.32 At its most extreme, such
a culture can be said to be one of democratic centralism. This allows
internal party debate on an issue until the party has made a decision
on that issue. Once the decision has been taken, all members of the
party are required to support the decision and are not allowed to
criticise that decision or act in a way that would undermine the
authority of the party and the decision taken.
• Last, the electoral system in South Africa assists party leaders to
enforce strict discipline among members of the legislature. This is
because, as we shall see, members of the legislature depend on the
support of their various political parties to get elected to the
legislature and can also easily be removed from the legislature by
their respective political parties. Accordingly, members of the
legislature are, to some extent, beholden to the leadership of their
respective political parties and to the party machinery to retain their
positions. This means that the members of the legislature are not
free to act as they see fit in fulfilling their various duties as members
of the NA or the NCOP. Once the political party to whom a legislator
belongs has made a decision on a pertinent issue being considered
by the legislature, the members of that party are usually bound by
that decision and must follow it. For example, if a political party has
decided to vote in favour of a Bill before Parliament and has
instructed its legislators accordingly, they cannot refuse to vote for
the Bill because for some reason or another they oppose the Bill. The
members of that political party will usually be required to support
the Bill and vote in favour of it even if a member disagrees with the
position taken by his or her political party.33 The situation is more
fluid and complex in cases where the political party has not taken a
final public stance on an issue being considered by the legislature,
or where members of the legislature are legally expected to fulfil
their constitutional duty to consider and pass legislation, to hold the
members of the executive accountable and to oversee the work of
the executive in a diligent and responsible manner.
4.3.1 Introduction
The NA and the NCOP have the power to determine and control their
own internal arrangements, proceedings and procedures.39 The
Constitution thus authorises the NA and the NCOP to make joint rules
and orders concerning the joint business of the two Houses.40 It also
authorises the two Houses to make rules separately regarding their own
operations.41 In addition, the Constitution requires the NA and NCOP to
make rules and orders to provide for the composition, powers and
functioning of committees.42 When Parliament exercises this power, it
must do so in a manner that gives effect to the provisions of the
Constitution. Rules that clash with any section of the Constitution,
therefore, may be declared invalid by a court of law.43 The Constitutional
Court has also ruled that the failure by the NA to make rules when this
was required by a specific provision of the Constitution was in breach of
the Constitution.44
Both Houses of Parliament and their committees have wide-ranging
powers not dissimilar to those of a court of law and can summon any
person, including the President and Cabinet Ministers, to appear before
them to:
• give evidence under oath or affirmation, or to produce documents
• require any person or institution to report to it
• compel, in terms of national legislation or the rules and orders, any
person or institution to comply with a summons or requirement to
produce documents
• receive petitions, representations or submissions from any
interested persons or institutions.45
The fact that the Constitution requires both the NA and the NCOP to
conduct their business in an open manner and to hold their sittings and
those of their committees in public means that these events, as well as
any other business of Parliament, may not normally take place in secret
and neither may members of the public be prevented from attending
them. As the Constitutional Court stated in Doctors for Life
International v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others,57 these
sections of the Constitution may be classified as ‘manner and form
provision[s] equivalent to the provisions for a quorum, and the number
of votes required to take a decision’. Any failure to comply with them,
therefore, ‘would have grave implications for the validity of any conduct
that passes a law’.58
After making these points, the High Court went on to find that Ms De
Lille’s suspension unjustifiably infringed her constitutional rights to
freedom of expression (section 16), administrative justice (section 33)
and access to courts (section 34). It thus set her suspension aside.77
The Supreme Court of Appeal upheld the decision of the Western
Cape High Court, although on slightly narrower grounds.78 Like the
High Court, the Supreme Court of Appeal held that the decision to
suspend Ms De Lille, not for disrupting or obstructing the business of
the NA, but simply for something she said in the NA clearly inhibited
the privilege of freedom of speech guaranteed in section 58(1) of the
Constitution.79 Although section 58(2) states that other privileges and
immunities of the NA may be prescribed by national legislation such as
the Powers and Privileges of Parliament Act,80 it must not be interpreted
to detract from the privilege guaranteed in section 58(1).
What section 58(2) does do is authorise the adoption of national
legislation which will itself clearly and specifically articulate the
‘privileges and the immunities’ of the NA which affect the specific
guarantee of free speech for members in the NA. There was furthermore
nothing in the ‘rules and orders’ of the NA which qualified in any
relevant way the right to freedom of speech in the NA guaranteed by
section 58(1). Further, there is no constitutional authority for the NA to
punish any member via suspension in this context.81 As ‘the right of free
speech in the Assembly protected by section 58(1) is a fundamental
right crucial to representative government in a democratic society …
[i]ts tenor and spirit must conform to all other provisions of the
Constitution relevant to the conduct of proceedings in Parliament’.82 The
NA therefore had no constitutional authority to suspend Ms De Lille.83
The Rules of the National Assembly have since been amended to
provide the Speaker or Deputy Speaker with the authority to suspend a
member for a period of between five and twenty parliamentary working
days.84
The important role that the privilege of freedom of speech plays in
South Africa’s democracy and the weight that was attached to it by the
Supreme Court of Appeal in De Lille was confirmed by the
Constitutional Court in its subsequent judgment Democratic Alliance v
Speaker of the National Assembly and Others.85
In this case, President Zuma delivered the 2015 State of the National
Address to a joint sitting of both Houses of Parliament. During his
address, members of the Economic Freedom Fighters (EFF)
continuously interrupted President Zuma by asking him when he
intended to repay public money spent on non-security upgrades to his
private residence in Nkandla. As a result of these interruptions, the
Speaker asked the members of the EFF to leave the chamber. They,
however, refused to do so.
After the members of the EFF refused to obey the Speaker’s
instruction, she ordered the police to remove them forcibly in terms of
section 11 of the Powers, Privileges and Immunities of Parliament and
the Provincial Legislatures Act 4 of 2004 (PPI Act). This section provides
that a person who creates a disturbance in the precincts while
Parliament or a House or a committee is meeting may be arrested and
removed from the precincts on the orders of the Speaker or the
Chairperson of the National Council of Provinces.
Following the forced removal of the members of the EFF, the
Democratic Alliance applied to the Western Cape High Court for an
order declaring section 11 of the PPI Act to be unconstitutional and
invalid on the ground that it infringed the parliamentary privilege of
freedom of speech guaranteed in section 58(1)(a) of the Constitution.
After the High Court granted the order, it was referred to the
Constitutional Court for confirmation in terms of section 172(2) of the
Constitution. The Constitutional Court confirmed that section 11 was
unconstitutional and invalid.
In arriving at this decision, the Constitutional Court began by setting
out the purpose underlying the parliamentary privilege of freedom of
speech. In this respect, the Court held that its purpose is to promote the
pluralistic nature of Parliament by giving every member a right to
participate fully and meaningfully in the decision-making processes of
Parliament. By its very nature Parliament is a deliberative body. Debate
is key to the performance of its functions. In order for the debates and
deliberations of Parliament to be meaningful, it is important that the
individual members feel free to participate without the threat of being
arrested or imprisoned or sued.86
Although the parliamentary privilege of freedom of speech is a
crucial guarantee, the Constitutional Court held further, this does not
mean that it is absolute. Section 58(1) expressly states it can be limited
in terms of the rules and orders of the National Assembly. A member,
for example, is not entitled to exercise this privilege in a manner that
disrupts the proceedings of the National Assembly or unreasonably
impairs its ability to conduct its business in an orderly manner. The
National Assembly, therefore, may exclude a member who engages in
this sort of behaviour.87
After making these points, the Constitutional Court turned to focus
on section 11 of the PPI Act itself. In this respect, it held that even
though section 11 refers to ‘persons’ and not expressly to members of
the National Assembly, the word ‘person’ is wide enough to include
members of the National Assembly. This means that section 11 does
give the Speaker or the Chairperson the power to order the arrest or
removal of a member of the National Assembly or the NCOP who is
creating a disturbance.88
Given that section 11 of the Act applies only if a member was
creating a disturbance, it was important to define this concept. In this
respect, the Constitutional Court held that the concept of a disturbance
should not be interpreted broadly. This is because a broad
interpretation would include conduct that is protected by the
parliamentary privilege of freedom of speech, for example conduct that
annoys and tests the patience of the presiding officers or other
Members of Parliament. If this sort of conduct was included in the
concept of a disturbance, however, section 11 would clearly infringe the
parliamentary privilege and would be unconstitutional and invalid.89
The concept of a disturbance, therefore, had to be interpreted
narrowly to mean an interference that prevents Parliament from
conducting its business, with little possibility of resumption of business
within a reasonable period of time. Despite defining the concept of a
disturbance in this narrow manner, however, the Constitutional Court
went on to find that section 11 still infringed the parliamentary privilege
of freedom of speech. This is because section 11 had to be read with
sections 7 and 27 of the PPI Act which provided that creating or
participating in a disturbance was also a criminal offence and this had a
chilling effect on the parliamentary privilege of freedom of speech.90
Apart from the fact that section 11 of the PPI Act had a chilling effect
on the parliamentary privilege of freedom of speech, the Constitutional
Court found that it was unconstitutional for another reason as well,
namely that section 58(1) of the Constitution expressly provided that
the parliamentary privilege of freedom of speech could be limited only
by the internal rules and orders of Parliament and not by an Act of
Parliament. The reason for this is that when Parliament makes its rules
and order, it acts by itself. However, when Parliament makes law, it acts
with the executive branch of government.91
The difficulty with allowing the parliamentary freedom of speech to
be limited by an Act of Parliament, therefore, is that it would require
another branch of the state, namely the executive, to participate in a
process that the Constitution expressly states falls into the exclusive
domain of Parliament. The process of making rules and order, therefore,
is required to be a wholly internal one. In addition, at a practical level
the making of rules and orders by Parliament alone will inevitably be a
more streamlined exercise than the cumbersome process of passing
legislation.92
2. DA 84 20,77%
3. EFF 44 10,80%
4. IFP 14 3,38%
5. VF PLUS 10 2,38%
6. ACDP 4 0,84%
7. UDM 2 0,45%
8. NFP 2 0,35%
9. ATM 2 0,44%
The cases discussed above are an indication of the values of the new
dispensation in ensuring the role of the electorate in relation to the
corresponding responsibility of the state to create an environment that
is conducive for everyone to ensure the advancement of the ideals of
the new democratic order.
After an election, the first sitting of the NA must take place not more
than 14 days after the election results are finalised on a date determined
by the Chief Justice.200 The President will be elected from among the
members elected to the NA at this sitting.201 At the same sitting, the NA
will also elect a Speaker and a Deputy Speaker from among its
members.202 The NA may otherwise determine the time and duration of
its other sittings and its recess periods.203 An exception is that the
President may summon the NA to an extraordinary sitting at any time to
conduct special business.204 Sittings of the NA are permitted at places
other than the seat of Parliament, which is currently in Cape Town, only
‘on the grounds of public interest, security or convenience, and if
provided for in the rules and orders of the Assembly’.205
The rules thus permit the NA to sit at a place other than the seat of
Parliament in Cape Town. These rules distinguish between two
situations: first, those in which a sitting must be held somewhere else
because of an emergency and, second, those in which a sitting may be
held somewhere else because it is convenient or in the public interest to
do so.206
In so far as the first situation is concerned, NA Rule 43(1) provides
that the Speaker may, in an emergency or on the grounds of security,
direct that that the National Assembly sit at a place other than the seat
of Parliament in Cape Town or that a sitting of the National Assembly be
held, or resumed, in a different chamber within the precincts of
Parliament. Before issuing such a directive, however, the Speaker must
consult with the Leader of Government Business and the Chief Whips
or party representatives of each party represented in the National
Assembly.
In so far as the second situation is concerned, NA Rule 43(2)
provides that the National Assembly may, on the grounds of public
interest or convenience, resolve to sit at a place other than the seat of
Parliament in Cape Town. Apart from approving a change in venue,
however, such a resolution must also (a) identify the public interest or
convenience that is the reason for the change of venue and (b) approve
the change of venue to a specified place and for a specified period.
The powers of the NCOP vary according to the impact of the legislation
in question on provincial concerns and the nature of the legislation
being considered. If the legislation does not directly affect the
provinces, NCOP members each have an individual vote which they
cast in accordance with the wishes of their respective political parties.262
In all other cases – including when amending the Constitution or
dealing with Bills affecting the provinces – each provincial delegation
casts a single vote.263 It does so under instruction, also called a mandate,
from the provincial legislature of the province represented by the
delegation.264 As the Constitutional Court has explained in Certification
of the Amended Text of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa,
1996, the NCOP ‘is a council of provinces and not a chamber composed
of elected representatives. Voting by delegation reflects accurately the
support of the different provincial legislatures for a measure under
consideration’.265 ‘In this manner the provincial legislatures are given a
direct say in the national law-making process through the NCOP.’ 266
Unfortunately, the various NCOP delegations have found it difficult
to operate effectively, especially to obtain the requisite mandate from
their respective provincial legislatures in the short time often provided
for this task. There are a number of reasons for this. Given that
provincial legislative attention is so taken up with carrying out
mandates imposed on them from above, and because they are far
removed from the centre of political power in Parliament, they are ill
equipped in terms of information and expertise to pass judgment on
national legislation and to provide informed mandates to the respective
NCOP delegations. This problem is exacerbated by poor
communications between the NA and the NCOP and between NCOP
delegations and their provincial legislatures. Draft Bills are often
provided to the NCOP with little time for provinces to respond.267
In addition, NCOP members are supposed to provide a bridge
between the national legislature and provincial legislatures, but their
political links with both are often weak and ineffective. The technical
and human resources for close communication are often lacking.
Individual NCOP members, shuttling between Parliament in Cape
Town and remote provincial capitals, are placed under enormous
strain. It is highly unrealistic, and probably unnecessary, for provincial
legislatures to pay the same attention to national legislation as does the
NA. It is far more important for them to come to grips with local issues
and problems. However, it is critical that provinces are able to voice
their opinions when legislation directly affects the economic or social
interests of their region, and that they can ensure that national
legislation they will be required to implement is workable. Another
problem is that there is little linkage between the exchange of
information and ideas that goes on within the processes of executive
intergovernmental relations and exchanges at the parliamentary level
through the NCOP. Indeed, provincial executives take little interest in
NCOP matters. This differs greatly from the operation of the German
Bundesrat, the members of which are themselves provincial executives,
thus integrating legislative and executive intergovernmental relations.268
Given these practical difficulties as well as the limited powers and
functions formally bestowed on the NCOP, the NCOP, as the second
House of the national Parliament, is often viewed as the less powerful
and influential of the two chambers of the bicameral South African
Parliament. This is so because almost all Cabinet Ministers will be
members of the NA while NCOP members cannot serve as Cabinet
Ministers. Although Cabinet Ministers and Deputy Ministers may
attend and may speak in the NCOP, they may not vote in that
chamber.269 Moreover, unlike the NA, the NCOP is not given a clear
mandate to hold members of the Cabinet accountable or to maintain
oversight over the executive although the NCOP plays an important role
in the passing of legislation.
Nevertheless, the NCOP and its committees are, under section 69 of
the Constitution, given broad powers. They may ‘(a) summon any
person to appear before it to give evidence on oath or affirmation or to
produce documents; (b) require any institution or person to report to it;
(c) compel, in terms of national legislation or the rules and orders, any
person or institution to comply with a summons …; and (d) receive
petitions, representations or submissions from any interested persons
or institutions’.
4.6.1 Introduction
The Constitution bestows a number of functions on Parliament.
Perhaps the most important of these is to pass national legislation for
the Republic, usually in the form of an Act of Parliament. Although this
may be the most important function bestowed on Parliament, it is by no
means the only one. In addition, and on a more symbolic level,
Parliament is also required to act as a national forum for public debate
on issues of national importance. In this sense, Parliament acts a
platform for representatives of political parties to present their views
and debate each other.
Apart from these two functions, the Constitution also bestows
additional functions specifically on the NA in order to enable it to fulfil
its special role as a ‘check’ on the executive authority. This special task is
bestowed on the NA because of the fact that it appoints and can dismiss
the President. It follows, therefore, that the President and his or her
Cabinet need to retain the confidence and hence the support of the NA
to remain in power. Although the tasks of the two Houses, therefore, are
not identical, the two Houses of Parliament can be said to fulfil four
main functions.
They must:
• provide a forum for debate on important issues285
• hold the executive organs of state in the national sphere of
government accountable to Parliament286
• exercise an oversight function over the exercise of national authority
and over other organs of state287
• pass national legislation.288
Apart from the two requirements discussed above, we contend that the
two Houses of Parliament also fulfil their task as a ‘national talk shop’ by
providing a platform for elected political representatives to deliver
speeches and to engage in debates with one another and with the
President about policy questions as well as issues of political
importance. Given that events in Parliament are relatively well reported
by the print, electronic and social media, Parliament provides an
important platform for floating new ideas and for elected politicians to
‘perform’ democracy by illustrating their willingness to debate
important and often emotional issues with members from other
political parties in a relatively rational and calm manner. Parliament, at
its best, therefore, can act as a body that educates citizens about the
importance of participating in a democracy and respecting differences
without having to agree with those who differ from oneself.
The Rules of the NA and the NCOP provide various mechanisms to
achieve these goals.293 The Rules of the NA, for example, provide that a
member of the NA may propose a subject for discussion or a draft
resolution for approval as a resolution of the House, with or without
debate.294 They also provide that an MP may request the Speaker in
writing to schedule without delay an urgent matter of national public
importance for discussion by the House.295 Somewhat similarly, the
Rules of the NCOP provide that a delegate may, in writing, request the
Chairperson of the NCOP to allow a matter of public importance to be
discussed by the Council, but this request will only be granted if the
matter affects the provinces or one or more of them.296
The fact that Parliament in general and the NA more specifically have a
constitutional obligation to hold the President and the rest of the
executive accountable means that the court can order the NA to hold
the President or the executive accountable after making a finding that it
had failed to do so. This is what happened in Economic Freedom Fighters
and Others v Speaker of the National Assembly and Another302 after the
then Public Protector had made adverse findings against the then
President about the use of public funds to renovate the President’s
private home and after the Constitutional Court had held that these
findings were binding on everyone. The Court held that despite these
adverse findings by the Public Protector (including a finding that the
President had violated the Constitution and breached the Executive
Members Ethics Code) the NA had not taken ‘appropriate action’
against the President.303 While minority parties had tabled a motion for
the removal of the President in terms of section 89 of the Constitution
(the so-called impeachment provision), the NA had failed to follow the
required procedure to deal with the motion. This, the court held, meant
that the NA had failed to hold the President to account ‘as was required
by section 89(1)’.304 It appears that if the NA had followed a
constitutionally compliant procedure in terms of section 89(1) and had
nevertheless voted against impeachment of the President, it would have
complied with its duty to hold the President accountable. What is not
clear from the judgment is whether the Court would have held that the
NA had failed in its duty to hold the President accountable if opposition
parties had not tabled a motion for the removal of the President at all. In
other words, it is unclear if it would be overstepping the boundaries of
separation of powers for the Constitutional Court to order the NA to
institute removal proceedings against the President.305
This power of Parliament to hold the executive accountable will only
be effectively exercised where Parliament has the ability to sanction
members of the executive who abuse their power or fail to fulfil their
respective mandates. The power of Parliament to hold the executive
accountable, therefore, entails two distinct but interrelated aspects:
• First, it entails the powers of Parliament to call members of the
executive and the public administration to account for their
activities. This is aimed at enhancing the integrity of public
governance to safeguard government against corruption, nepotism,
abuse of power and other forms of inappropriate behaviour, and to
assist in improving the performance of the Cabinet as well as the
public administration. This kind of accountability also reflects a
culture of transparency, responsiveness and answerability, which is
necessary to ensure public confidence in government, and to bridge
the gap between the governed and the government. If used wisely
and effectively, these accountability mechanisms enable the public
to judge the performance of the government.306
• Second, accountability will arguably not be effective if it does not
include the power of Parliament to take remedial action and even to
dismiss members of the executive who fail to account properly for
their actions. As such, accountability requires the establishment of
institutional arrangements to effect democratic control over the
executive as members of the executive, unlike the MPs, are not
directly democratically elected.
Even if the Committee gave permission for the Bill to proceed, the
majority party in the NA could still decide not to support the initiation
of the Bill which meant that it would not be passed. In practice, this
meant that members of the opposition could never introduce Bills into
the NA unless they were given permission by the majority party to do so.
In Oriani-Ambrosini, MP v Sisulu, MP Speaker of the National
Assembly,352 however, the Constitutional Court invalidated the Rules of
the NA which required a member of the NA to obtain permission from
the NA to initiate and introduce Bills. The Court stated that South
Africa’s constitutional democracy ‘is designed to ensure that the
voiceless are heard’, and is one in which the ‘views of the marginalised
or the powerless minorities’ cannot be suppressed.353 The Court
approvingly quoted a passage from its earlier judgment in Democratic
Alliance and Another v Masondo NO and Another to illustrate the
principle that must apply to the evaluation of NA Rules giving effect to
the constitutional provisions that empower members of the NA to take
certain actions:
[T]he Constitution does not envisage a mathematical form of democracy,
where the winner-takes-all until the next vote-counting exercise occurs.
Rather, it contemplates a pluralistic democracy where continuous respect is
given to the rights of all to be heard and have their views considered … The
open and deliberative nature of the process goes further than providing a
dignified and meaningful role for all participants. It is calculated to produce
better outcomes through subjecting laws and governmental action to the test of
critical debate, rather than basing them on unilateral decision-making.354
This does not mean that the will of the majority party in the NA can
ultimately be overridden. Once a legislative proposal has been initiated
and tabled, the majority party can always vote against a Bill. This can
only happen after the Bill initiated by an ordinary MP has been
discussed and debated by the relevant portfolio committee. Some may
say the right of opposition MPs to introduce their own Bills would
therefore be of little more than ceremonial significance. However, as the
Constitutional Court pointed out, this is not so as it will give opposition
MPS the opportunity to go beyond an obstructionist oppositional role,
allowing them to submit constructive proposals of their own about how
to solve a particular legislative problem and allowing these proposals to
be discussed seriously by the members of the NA.358
Despite the changes brought about by the Oriani-Ambrosini
judgment, most Bills are still initiated and introduced by Cabinet
Ministers who are tasked with leading the legislative agenda of the
elected government of the day. Ordinary members of the NA from the
majority party usually defer to the legislative agenda set by Cabinet.
This means a member of the executive, an individual Cabinet Minister,
usually initiates legislation dealing with issues related to his or her
portfolio before a Bill is introduced and adopted by Parliament. A Bill is
the request submitted to Parliament for the approval of particular
legislation in relation to a particular matter.
Apart from these contextual reasons, there is also a practical reason for
the dominance of the executive in the preparation and introduction of
legislation. Legislation is usually introduced to give legislative effect to
the political programme of action of the majority party (or coalition of
parties) which forms the government. In theory, the voters endorse this
programme in an election. The party then has a democratic mandate to
implement the policies for which it was elected as the governing party.
However, no party can foresee all eventualities and, therefore, does not
place its entire legislative programme before the electorate during an
election. This is why – as we have seen – the Constitution requires
Parliament to facilitate public involvement in the law-making process.
Be that as it may, voters elected a party to lead the government and
expect the leadership of the party to take the initiative and to formulate
policies and eventually legislation to give effect to such policies.
The process of law making through the initiative of the executive, the
normal way in which laws are passed, can be simplified as follows:
• Policy is formulated via various channels, including through the
National Economic Development and Labour Council (Nedlac),
through internal party discussions and Cabinet discussions which
finally results in a draft Bill which is eventually approved by Cabinet.
• After Cabinet has approved the draft Bill, the Cabinet Minister
responsible for the policy in question usually first introduces the Bill
in the NA or, in some cases, the NCOP. This is referred to as the first
reading.
• The Bill is then referred to the appropriate portfolio committee for
review and amendment after facilitation of public involvement as
discussed above. This is referred to as the second reading and the Bill
is considered ready for passing.
• If the NA passes the Bill, it is forwarded to the upper House, the
NCOP, for its assent. If the Bill was introduced in the NCOP and
approved there, it is forwarded to the NA for its assent.368
The Court then decided in this case that it was inconsistent with the
doctrine of separation of powers for Parliament to delegate the power to
amend its laws to the President as head of the executive.425 It argued that
although the need for assignment of subordinate legislative authority
cannot be over-emphasised, the assignment of plenary legislative
powers is a different matter alltogether. This is not allowed under the
new constitutional dispensation as it could give rise to a constitutional
crisis. The Court indicated that the relevant constitutional provision
which deals with legislative authority is not merely directive but is
peremptory. It therefore cannot be said that the power to delegate
primary legislative power is implied in the Constitution. Therefore,
Parliament cannot delegate its original law-making power to the
executive. It can only delegate the making of subordinate legislation
such as presidential proclamations and ministerial regulations. The
position is the same under the 1996 Constitution.426
5.1 Introduction
Summary
5.1 Introduction
Figure 5.1 Separation of powers and the national executive
The President may not serve more than two full terms in office, which
will normally be 10 years. However, if the President is elected to fill a
vacancy which has occurred between elections, the period he or she
serves until the next election will not count as part of one of the two
terms.8 For example, Cyril Ramaphosa was elected as President in 2018
in order to fill the vacancy caused by former President Jacob Zuma’s
resignation. He was elected as President again in 2019 following the
ANC’s victory in the general election. The period he served between his
election as President in 2018 and his re-election as President in 2019
does not count as his first term. Instead, for the legal purpose of
counting terms, his first term began only after he was elected as
President in 2019. This means that a President who takes over the
presidency halfway through the term of the NA, and then serves out that
half term plus two full terms, could serve more than 10 years as
President.
In light of the points set out above, it is clear that the President is not
directly elected by the voters, but is indirectly elected by the members
of the NA. Usually, the leader of the majority party in the NA, who was
elected by representatives of the members of that political party at its
national elective congress or conference, will be elected as President.9 It
follows, therefore, that the President is, in effect, elected by the
delegates who are selected to attend the elective conference of the
political party that wins the next general election and not directly by the
voters. However, voters indirectly confirm the majority party’s choice of
leader, and therefore as President, by voting for that party in the general
election that follows on the election of the party leader.
On paper, the NA – the directly elected body – is more powerful than
the President or his or her Cabinet as the NA has the power not only to
elect the President, but also to remove him or her from office. However,
in practice, the President and the other members of the executive
remain the more powerful arm of government until such time as he or
she loses the support of the majority party in the NA. This is because as
long as the President enjoys the support of the members of the majority
political party of which the President would usually be the leader, his or
her position as party leader will provide him or her with enormous
influence over ordinary members of the party in the NA. In other words,
while technically the President reports to and is accountable to
Parliament, arguably Parliament indirectly reports to the President
because the majority of the members of the NA are ordinary members
of the governing party for which the President is the leader.
The NA can remove the President from office in one of two ways.
First, in terms of section 89(1) of the Constitution, the NA can remove
the President from office if it adopts a resolution to that effect with a
supporting vote of at least a two-thirds majority if they find that one of
the specified grounds for the removal of the President exists. These
grounds are a serious violation of the Constitution or the law, serious
misconduct or inability to perform the functions of office.10 These are
objective grounds and the NA can remove the President in this manner
only after it has found that one or more of these grounds is present. The
removal in terms of section 89(1) is referred to as ‘Impeachment’ –
although that term is not used in the Constitution.11 Impeachment
could only commence if it is established – as a fact – that the President
had committed a serious violation of the Constitution or the law or
serious misconduct, or that he or she is incapacitated. The existence of
one of these factors is a necessary condition for commencing a section
89 process.12 Without accepting that one of the listed grounds exists, the
NA cannot authorise the commencement of the impeachment process,
which could result in the removal of the President from office. This is so
because those grounds constitute conditions for the President’s
removal. As the Constitutional Court explained in EFF II: ‘A removal of
the President where none of those grounds is established would not be
a removal contemplated in section 89(1)’13 and would therefore be
unconstitutional.
Given that the NA can remove the President only after it has found
that one or more of the grounds listed in section 89(1) is present, the
Constitutional Court held in EFF II that the NA’s failure to adopt rules
establishing a specific procedure in terms of which such a finding can
be made was unconstitutional and invalid.14 The NA was thus obliged to
adopt rules specifically tailored for the section 89(1) removal process. In
arriving at this decision, the Court held that the use of an ad hoc
committee in terms of the existing rules of the NA to determine whether
any of the section 89(1) grounds were present was not an appropriate
mechanism for such a momentous task as the removal of a President.
Where one political party has obtained more than 50% of the votes in
the NA, this will in effect mean that the President is at all times required
to retain the support of his or her party both inside and outside the NA.
If the President loses the support of his or her party, a vote of no
confidence can be instituted against the President after which he or she
will have to resign. Following the Constitutional Court’s judgment in
Mazibuko v Sisulu and Another (Mazibuko),20 any member of the NA
can now propose a motion of no confidence in the President and have it
debated in the NA without first having to obtain the consent of the
Programming Committee and thus in effect the majority party. It is,
however, highly unlikely that such a motion will be passed unless the
President has lost the support of his or her party.
South Africa has a closed list proportional representation electoral
system in which political party leaders have influence over who
represents the party in the NA. The practical effect of this system is that
the President must retain the support of the majority party leadership to
ensure that he or she is not ‘recalled’ by that leadership. If members of
the majority party in the NA are instructed by the party leadership to
support a vote of no confidence in the President, they would probably
agree to do so as their failure to obey such an instruction might well
lead to their removal from the NA and their replacement with members
who would obey such an order. This is because the Constitution
provides that a member of the NA ceases to be a member if he or she
‘ceases to be a member of the party that nominated that person as
member of the Assembly’.21 This means if a member of the NA refuses to
follow instructions from party leaders to support a vote of no
confidence in the President, he or she can be removed from the party
for ill-discipline and be replaced with a more docile member. Thus,
‘members’ fate or future in office thus depends largely on the party [or
even the President]’.22 Although the Constitutional Court held in United
Democratic Movement v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others
that MPs, in the event of conflict between upholding constitutional
values and party loyalty, should choose to serve the people who elected
them and not their political parties, in practice, most MPs will follow the
dictates of their parties to protect themselves from party retribution.
This is so unless MPs are allowed to vote in a secret ballot and are thus
protected from consequences of their actions.
It is partly because of this that the Constitutional Court held in the
United Democratic Movement v Speaker of the National Assembly that
the Speaker of the National Assembly has a discretion to decide
whether voting on a motion of no confidence against the President
should take place by open ballot or by secret ballot.23 This discretionary
power should not be exercised arbitrarily or whimsically but should
have a rational basis and have the effect of ensuring effective
enforcement of executive accountability.24 When making his or her
decision, the Speaker must take into account whether the vote is aimed
at holding the President accountable (in which case a secret ballot
would be more appropriate) or for some other party-political reason (in
which case a secret ballot would be less appropriate). The Speaker must
also remain mindful of possible ‘crass dishonesty, in the form of bribe-
taking or other illegitimate methods of gaining undeserved majorities’
when deciding on whether to grant a secret ballot. If a secret ballot
would facilitate such dishonesty a secret ballot should not be granted.25
It is important to note that whether voting should take place through an
open ballot or through a secret ballot is at the discretion of the National
Assembly through the Speaker. In accordance with the principle of
separation of powers26 and in accordance with the National Assembly’s
power to determine and control its internal arrangements, proceedings
and procedures,27 a court of law cannot order the NA to have an open or
secret ballot in conducting a vote of no confidence against the
President.
Given that the President fulfils a vital role in running the country as the
Head of State and head of the executive, the Constitution provides for
the appointment of another office-bearer as an acting President as soon
as a vacancy in the Office of the Presidency arises. A vacancy in the
Office of the President will arise when:
• the President is absent from the Republic
• the President is otherwise unable to fulfil the duties of President, for
example due to illness
• there is a vacancy in the office of President that arises when the
President resigns or dies while in office, a motion of no confidence
in the President is passed or the President is removed from office.
This means that if the President falls ill, passes away or resigns, the
Deputy President will usually act as President until a new President is
elected or until the President can resume his or her duties. However, if
the Deputy President is also unavailable because he or she has resigned
or has also passed away, somebody else, in the order listed above, will
be appointed as acting President to ensure that there is no power
vacuum at the top of the executive.
An acting President has all the responsibilities, powers and
functions of the President.31 Before assuming the responsibilities,
powers and functions of the President, the acting President must swear
or affirm faithfulness to the Republic and obedience to the Constitution
in accordance with the oath of office contained in Schedule 2 of the
Constitution.32 A person who as acting President has sworn or affirmed
faithfulness to the Republic need not repeat the swearing or affirming
procedure for any subsequent term as acting President, during the
period ending when the next elected President assumes office.33
This does not mean that when contemplating the exercise of this kind of
Head of State power, the President should not (or does not have the
right to) consult with and take the advice of Ministers and advisers.
However, the President must take the final decision him or herself.43 The
Constitutional Court can determine whether the Head of State powers
are exercised in accordance with the Constitution and can confirm that
such an exercise of power does not infringe on the Bill of Rights or
breach the principle of legality. We deal with this check on the exercise
of power by the President in more detail in the following section.
One of the ways in which the Head of State powers may be
distinguished from the head of the national executive powers is by
focusing on the nature of the powers themselves. If the President is
required to exercise a political discretion on behalf of the government,
the President is acting as the head of the national executive. If the
President is not required to exercise a political discretion on behalf of
the government, he or she is acting as the Head of State. As Head of
State, the President represents all of the people, and not only the
government formed by the majority party.44 However, as Currie and De
Waal point out, this distinction is difficult to uphold.45
A better distinction can be drawn between the exercise of the Head
of State power and the head of the executive power by focusing on the
historical emergence of the Office of the President. For most of the
twentieth century, the Head of State powers were vested initially in the
Governor-General and, after 1961 when South Africa became a
Republic, in the State President. During this same period, the head of
the national executive powers were vested in the Prime Minister. This
mirrored the roles of the Monarch and the Prime Minister in the United
Kingdom (UK). In terms of this system, the Head of State (the Queen in
the UK and the State President in South Africa) formally exercised the
Head of State power but usually on the advice of the Prime Minister.
Following the enactment of the 1983 tricameral Constitution, these two
offices were combined into a single Office of an executive State
President, and this arrangement was retained in both the 1994 interim
Constitution and 1996 Constitution. Apart from combining the two
offices into one, the former uncodified prerogative powers of the State
President, derived from the British system, were extinguished and
codified initially in section 82(1) of the interim Constitution and
subsequently in section 84(2) of the Constitution.46 In this system,
therefore, the President fulfils the duties of both the Head of State,
which are similar to the ceremonial powers of the Queen, and the head
of the national executive, which are similar to the executive powers of
the Prime Minister.
The Constitution provides some clarity on the distinction between
Head of State and head of the executive powers by listing these powers
in two separate sections. Section 84(2) of the Constitution lists the Head
of State powers exercised by the President alone and states that the
President exercises Head of State powers when he or she:
• assents to and signs Bills
• refers a Bill back to the NA for reconsideration of the Bill’s
constitutionality
• refers a Bill to the Constitutional Court for a decision on the Bill’s
constitutionality
• summons the NA, the NCOP or Parliament to an extraordinary
sitting to conduct special business
• makes any appointments that the Constitution or legislation
requires the President to make, other than as head of the national
executive
• appoints commissions of enquiry47
• calls a national referendum in terms of an Act of Parliament
• receives and recognises foreign diplomatic and consular
representatives
• appoints ambassadors, plenipotentiaries, and diplomatic and
consular representatives
• pardons or reprieves offenders, remits any fines, penalties or
forfeitures and confers honours.48
Although the President has sole authority over the Head of State
powers, in President of the Republic of South Africa v Public Protector,49
the High Court held that the Public Protector’s remedial powers include
the authority, not only to instruct the President to perform his or her
obligations as the Head of State (in this case, to appoint a commission
of inquiry into state capture), 50 but also to determine the manner in
which the President should do so in those cases in which he or she
suffers from a conflict of interest (in this case, to appoint a judge
selected by the Chief Justice as the head of the commission). In that
case, the Public Protector had ordered that the Chief Justice (and not
the President) select the person to chair a Commission of Inquiry into
so-called ‘State Capture’. The Public Protector did this because the then
President was implicated in ‘State Capture’ and may therefore have
been conflicted. Given that the Constitutional Court held (as noted
above) that the President cannot ‘abdicate’ the exercise of powers
explicitly bestowed on him by the Constitution, the judgment of the
High Court in the Public Protector case might not be correct. A better
approach was followed by the High Court in Corruption Watch (RF)
NPC and Another v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others;
Council for the Advancement of the South African Constitution v
President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (Corruption
Watch).51 The case dealt with a situation in which the President was
required to appoint a new National Director of Public Prosecutions, but
where the President was conflicted because the NDPP would be
required to decide whether the President should be prosecuted for
corruption while potentially facing corruption charges himself. The
court relied on section 90(1) of the Constitution which requires the
Deputy President to act as President when the President is ‘unable to
fulfil the duties of President’.52 The High Court explained that:
In a rights-based order it is fundamental that a conflicted person cannot act; to
act despite a conflict is self-evidently to pervert the rights being exercised as
well as the rights of those affected. And s.96(2)(b) makes that clear beyond the
pale. If conflicted, the individual simply cannot act, is “unable” to act, whether
s.90 was there or not. In this light, all s.90 does is to identify the person who
must act whenever the President, by virtue of a conflict, is unable. And it is the
Deputy President, who does not get sworn in; s/he simply performs the act
which the President himself is unable to perform.53
This solution better accords with the settled principle that the President
cannot abdicate his or her power and should not exercise power on the
dictation of any other person. If followed in future, it would mean that
whenever the President is conflicted and is thus unable to exercise a
power, he or she should refrain from exercising that power and should
rather allow the Deputy President to do so.
Section 85(1) of the Constitution states that the executive authority
of the Republic is vested in the President while section 85(2) confirms
that the President exercises the executive authority together with the
other members of the Cabinet. The President has the sole authority to
appoint the Deputy President, Cabinet Ministers and Deputy Ministers
and also has the power to dismiss the Deputy President, Cabinet
Ministers and Deputy Ministers.54 The President also has the sole
authority to appoint the leader of government business in the NA from
among the members of the NA.55 The President exercises executive
authority, together with the other members of the Cabinet, by:
• implementing national legislation except where the Constitution or
an Act of Parliament provides otherwise
• developing and implementing national policy
• co-ordinating the functions of state departments and
administrations
• preparing and initiating legislation
• performing any other executive function provided for in the
Constitution56 or in national legislation, which includes the
appointment of the National Director of Public Prosecutions,57 the
Military Command of the National Defence Force,58 the National
Commissioner of the Police Service, 59 the heads of the intelligence
services,60 and the members of boards of state-owned entities
(SOEs).61
Despite this warning, the courts have consistently asserted the principle
that all decisions by the President are reviewable, if not on the basis that
the decision contravenes the provisions of the Bill of Rights, then on
other grounds that flow from the fact that the Constitution is supreme
and that one of the founding values of the constitutional dispensation is
respect for the rule of law.93 The answer to the question of whether the
exercise of power by the President in a particular case could be tested
against the provisions of the Bill of Rights will be determined with
reference to the nature of the power exercised and the context in which
it is exercised. Where the President exercises a discretion in an
individual case, affecting only one person, and where the power in
terms of which the discretion is exercised is a Head of State power or a
power conferred on the President as part of his or her political duties as
head of the executive, it would be difficult to challenge that decision on
the basis that it infringed one of the rights in the Bill of Rights. However,
where the President exercises a general discretion affecting large
numbers of people, the situation may well be different.
The Constitutional Court found that the power to extend the term of
office is explicitly conferred on Parliament and not on the President.
The Court stated that section 176(1) contains clear textual indicators
that the Constitution does not empower Parliament to delegate the
power to extend the term of service of a judge of the Constitutional
Court as was purportedly done by section 8(a) of the Judges’
Remuneration and Conditions of Employment Act. The Court
confirmed that where the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty
governs, Parliament may delegate as much power as it chooses. In a
constitutional democracy, however, Parliament may not ordinarily
delegate its essential legislative functions. In this case, the power to
extend the term of a Constitutional Court judge goes to the core of the
tenure of the judicial office, judicial independence and the separation
of powers and was therefore deemed to be an essential legislative
function that could not be delegated. As the Court stated:
The term or extension of the office of the highest judicial officer is a matter of
great moment in our constitutional democracy … The 2001 amendment
requires an Act of Parliament to extend the term of office. It requires
Parliament itself to set the term of office … Another important consideration in
deciding whether section 8(a) is constitutionally compliant is the
constitutional imperative of judicial independence. This Court is the highest
court in all constitutional matters. The independence of its judges is given
vigorous protection by means of detailed and specific provisions regulating
their appointment. The Chief Justice is at the pinnacle of the judiciary and thus
the protection of his or her independence is just as important. It is so that
section 176(1) of the Constitution creates an exception to the requirement that
a term of a Constitutional Court judge is fixed. That authority, however, vests in
Parliament and nowhere else. It is notable that section 176(1) does not merely
bestow a legislative power, but by doing so also marks out Parliament’s
significant role in the separation of powers and protection of judicial
independence. The nature of this power cannot be overlooked, and the
Constitution’s delegation to Parliament must be restrictively construed to
realise that protection. Accordingly, section 8(a) violates the principle of
judicial independence. This kind of open-ended discretion may raise a
reasonable apprehension or perception that the independence of the Chief
Justice and by corollary the judiciary may be undermined by external
interference of the Executive. The truth may be different, but it matters not.
What matters is that the judiciary must be seen to be free from external
interference.104
One of the most important ways in which the exercise of power by the
President is controlled is through the requirement that when exercising
any duly authorised power, the President has to act rationally. This
requirement stems from the principle that when the President (or other
members of the executive) exercises power, he or she is constrained by
the principle of legality (an incidence of the Rule of Law) in the sense
that he or she is required to act rationally and in good faith.105 The
requirement that the President must act rationally when exercising his
or her power ‘is a minimum threshold requirement applicable to the
exercise of all public power by members of the executive and other
functionaries’.106 Action that fails to pass this threshold is inconsistent
with the requirements of our Constitution and therefore unlawful.
The rationality test must be distinguished from the test for
reasonableness. The reasonableness standard asks whether the decision
was one ‘that a reasonable decision-maker could not reach’.107
Rationality requires something different. In Albutt v Centre for the
Study of Violence and Reconciliation and Others, the Constitutional
Court explained the rationality standard as follows:
The Executive has a wide discretion in selecting the means to achieve its
constitutionally permissible objectives. Courts may not interfere with the
means selected simply because they do not like them, or because there are
other more appropriate means that could have been selected. But, where the
decision is challenged on the grounds of rationality, courts are obliged to
examine the means selected to determine whether they are rationally related
to the objective sought to be achieved. What must be stressed is that the
purpose of the enquiry is to determine not whether there are other means that
could have been used, but whether the means selected are rationally related to
the objective sought to be achieved. And if objectively speaking they are not,
they fall short of the standard demanded by the Constitution.108
Ministers are not only collectively accountable for the decisions and
actions of the Cabinet as a whole. Section 92(2) of the Constitution also
holds the Cabinet individually accountable to Parliament. Individual
accountability ensures that Parliament can identify the Cabinet
member responsible for a particular issue and can take action to hold
that Cabinet member accountable. As we have seen, the Constitution
bestows wide powers on Parliament to enable it to hold the individual
members of the Cabinet accountable. Moreover, in terms of section
92(3)(b) of the Constitution, Cabinet members are compelled to
provide Parliament with full and regular reports concerning matters
under their control. Collective ministerial accountability means that
Cabinet members ‘act in unison to the outside world and carry joint
responsibility before Parliament for the way in which each member
exercises or performs powers and functions’.150
According to Rautenbach and Malherbe,151 individual responsibility
entails the following:
• a duty to explain to Parliament how the powers and duties under his
or her control have been exercised and performed (the Constitution
provides that members of the Cabinet must act in accordance with
the Constitution and provide Parliament with full and regular
reports concerning matters under their control)
• a duty to acknowledge that a mistake has been made and to promise
to rectify the matter
• a duty to resign if personal responsibility has been accepted.152
SUMMARY
1 A coalition is formed if no party obtains at least 50% of the seats in the NA. Two or more
parties who together have more than 50% of the seats in the NA will then agree to work
together and form a government, based on agreed policies and principles.
2 President of the Republic of South Africa and Others v South African Rugby Football Union
and Others (CCT16/98) [1999] ZACC 9; 1999 (4) SA 147; 1999 (7) BCLR 725 (4 June 1999)
para 138.
3 S 197(1) of the Constitution states: ‘Within public administration there is a public service
for the Republic …’ See also s 1 of the Public Service Act 103 of 1994 read with s 8, and
Currie, I and De Waal, J (eds) (2001) The New Constitutional and Administrative Law, Vol 1
Constitutional Law 229.
4 S 86(1) of the Constitution.
5 S 86(3) of the Constitution.
6 S 87 of the Constitution. This means that the South African President will be elected to the
NA, will take his or her seat, but will only remain a member of the NA for a few hours until
such time as he or she is elected President, after which he or she ceases to be a member of
the NA.
7 Economic Freedom Fighters v Speaker of the National Assembly; Democratic Alliance v
Speaker of the National Assembly (EFF I) [2016] ZAAC 11; 2016 (3) SA 580 (CC); 2016 (5)
BCLR 618 (CC) para 20.
8 See s 88(2) of the Constitution.
9 For example, in terms of Rule 12.3 of the Constitution of the African National Congress
(ANC), its national conference – held every five years – elects the President, the Deputy
President, National Chairperson, the Secretary-General, Deputy Secretary General, the
Treasurer General and the remaining 80 additional members of the National Executive
Committee (NEC) of the party. The NEC, as a whole, must consist of not less than 50%
women. See African National Congress Constitution as amended and adopted at the 54th
National Conference, Nasrec, Johannesburg, 2017, available at
https://www.anc1912.org.za/constitution-anc.
10 S 89(1) of the Constitution.
11 Economic Freedom Fighters and Others v Speaker of the National Assembly and Another
(EFF II) (CCT76/17) [2017] ZACC 47; 2018 (3) BCLR 259 (CC); 2018 (2) SA 571 (CC) (29
December 2017) para 175 where the Court held:
Consistent with the pivotal role played by the President in our democratic order and
bearing in mind the obligation imposed singularly on him or her to uphold, defend
and respect the Constitution as our supreme law, the drafters of the Constitution
sought to limit the power given to the Assembly to impeach and remove a President
from office. Although the Constitution does not use the word “impeach”, it is apparent
that what section 89(1) authorises constitutes impeachment in other jurisdictions.
12 EFF II para 205.
13 EFF III para 179.
14 EFF III para 96.
15 [2017] ZACC 21; 2017 (5) SA 300 (CC); 2017 (8) BCLR 1061 (CC) para 79.
16 S 89(2) of the Constitution.
17 S 89(2); EFF II at para 136.
18 The South African system is not a pure system of parliamentary government as the
President is both Head of State and head of the executive, the President ceases to be a
member of the NA once elected and, as we shall see, two members of Cabinet can be
appointed from outside the NA. Nevertheless, as far as the constitutional structure is
concerned, the South African system is essentially parliamentary in nature and not
presidential in nature, as the President is not directly elected by the people. See also
Murray, C and Stacey, R ‘The President and the national executive’ in Woolman, S and
Bishop, M (2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 18.3.
19 UDM paras 32–4.
20 (CCT 115/12) [2013] ZACC 28; 2013 (6) SA 249 (CC); 2013 (11) BCLR 1297 (CC) (27 August
2013) paras 41 and 45.
21 S 47(3)(c) of the Constitution.
22 UDM para 76.
23 UDM para 85.
24 UDM para 85.
25 UDM para 31.
26 Tlouamma and Others v Mbethe, Speaker of the National Assembly of the Parliament of the
Republic of South Africa and Another (A 3236/15) [2015] ZAWCHC 140; 2016 (1) SA 534
(WCC); [2016] 1 All SA 235 (WCC); 2016 (2) BCLR 242 (WCC) (7 October 2015).
27 S 57(1) of the Constitution.
28 Chikane, F (2012) Eight Days in September: The Removal of Thabo Mbeki 17–8.
29 See the minority judgment of Jafta J in Mazibuko para 90.
30 S 90(1) of the Constitution.
31 S 90(2) of the Constitution.
32 S 90(3) of the Constitution.
33 S 90(4) of the Constitution.
34 These powers are a partial codification of the President’s common law prerogatives. This
partial codification is provided for in s 84(2) of the Constitution and include, among others,
the President’s power to confer honours. According to Mansingh v General Council of the
Bar and Others (Mansingh) (CCT 43/13) [2013] ZACC 40; 2014 (2) SA 26 (CC); 2014 (1)
BCLR 85 (CC) (28 November 2013), the President’s power to confer honours in terms of s
84(2)(k) of the Constitution is wide enough to include the authority to confer Senior
Council status or silk on advocates.
35 See s 83(a) of the Constitution.
36 Mansingh para 25.
37 President of the Republic of South Africa and Another v Hugo (Hugo) (CCT11/96) [1997]
ZACC 4; 1997 (6) BCLR 708; 1997 (4) SA 1 (18 April 1997) para 14.
38 See s 85(2) of the Constitution, which states, ‘The President exercises the executive
authority, together with the other members of the Cabinet, … ’, read with s 101(2): ‘A written
decision by the President must be countersigned by another Cabinet member if that
decision concerns a function assigned to that other Cabinet member’. See also President of
the Republic of South Africa and Others v South African Rugby Football Union and Others
(SARFU III) (CCT16/98) [1999] ZACC 11; 2000 (1) SA 1; 1999 (10) BCLR 1059 (10 September
1999) para 38; and Hugo para 14.
39 See generally Baxter, L (1984) Administrative Law 434–4. See also Hofmeyr v Minister of
Justice and Another 1992 (3) SA 108 (C) at 117 F–G.
40 SARFU III para 40: ‘There can be no doubt that when the Constitution vests the power to
appoint commissions of inquiry in the President, the President may not delegate that
authority to a third party. The President himself must exercise the power. Any delegation to
a third party would be invalid.’
41 SARFU III para 40: ‘cases where a functionary vested with a power does not of his or her
own accord decide to exercise the power, but does so on the instructions of another’.
42 SARFU III para 40: ‘“passing the buck” contemplates a situation in which the functionary
may refer the decision to someone else’.
43 SARFU III para 41.
44 SARFU III para 65.
45 Currie and De Waal (2001) 237.
46 For a discussion on prerogative powers and how these were replaced by enumerated
powers by South Africa’s democratic Constitution, see Hugo paras 5–10.
47 In President of the Republic of South Africa v Office of the Public Protector and Others
(91139/2016) [2017] ZAGPPHC 747; 2018 (2) SA 100 (GP); [2018] 1 All SA 800 (GP); 2018 (5)
BCLR 609 (GP) (13 December 2017) para 71, the court held that ‘even though the
Constitution vests in the President the power to appoint a commission of inquiry, this
power is not an untrammelled one; it must be exercised within the constraints that the
Constitution imposes. The President’s power to appoint a commission of inquiry will
necessarily be curtailed where his ability to conduct himself without constraint brings him
into conflict with his obligations under the Constitution.’
48 According to the decision of the Constitutional Court in Mansingh, the President’s power to
confer honours is wide enough to include his/her authority to confer Senior Council status
or silk on advocates.
49 2018 (2) SA 100 (GP); [2018] 1 All SA 800 (GP); 2018 (5) BCLR 609 (GP) para 62.
50 President of the Republic of South Africa v The Public Protector and Others paras 79–86.
51 (62470/2015) [2017] ZAGPPHC 743; [2018] 1 All SA 471 (GP); 2018 (1) SACR 317 (GP) (8
December 2017).
52 Corruption Watch I para 107.
53 Corruption Watch I paras 112 and 113.
54 S 91(2) of the Constitution.
55 S 91(4) of the Constitution.
56 For instance, in terms of s 231(1) of the Constitution, the negotiation and signing of
international agreements is the responsibility of the national executive, which the President
as head of the executive must undertake together other members of the Cabinet. However,
it is important to note that save for agreements of a technical, administrative or executive
nature and agreements, which do not require ratification, or accession (which merely need
to be tabled in Parliament within a reasonable time), all other international agreements
entered into or withdrawn by the executive on behalf of South Africa requires the approval
of Parliament in the form of a resolution to approve and the passing of relevant legislation.
This limitation of executive power was confirmed by the High Court in Democratic Alliance
v Minister of International Relations and Co-operation and Others (Council for the
Advancement of the South African Constitution as Intervening Party) (83145/2016); [2017]
ZAGPPHC 53; [2017] 2 All SA 123 (GP); 2017 (3) SA 212 (GP); [2017] 2 All SA 123 (GP); 2017
(1) SACR 623 (GP) (22 February 2017) where it was held that the executive’s power to
withdraw from an international agreement must be approved by resolution of Parliament
and after the repeal of the relevant legislation.
57 S 179(1)(a) of the Constitution. In Corruption Watch NPC and Others v President of the
Republic of South Africa and Others; Nxasana v Corruption Watch NPC and Others
(Corruption Watch II) (CCT 333/17; CCT 13/18); [2018] ZACC 23; 2018 (10) BCLR 1179
(CC); 2018 (2) SACR 442 (CC) (13 August 2018) paras 32–5, the Constitutional Court
declared invalid the President’s appointment of the National Director of Public
Prosecutions based on the invalidity of the manner in which the former National Director
of Public Prosecutions vacated his office. The Court held that ‘the appointment of Advocate
Abrahams as NDPP was an act consequential upon the constitutionally invalid vacation of
office by Mr Nxasana [former NDPP]’. According to the Court, ‘now that the manner in
which Mr Nxasana vacated office has been declared constitutionally invalid, it follows that
the appointment of Advocate Abrahams is [consequentially] constitutionally invalid’.
58 S 202(1) of the Constitution.
59 S 207(1) of the Constitution.
60 S 209(2) of the Constitution.
61 For instance, the appointment of the members of the South African Broadcasting
Corporations (SABC) Board in terms of s 13(1) of the Broadcasting Act 4 of 1999, as
amended. In S.O.S. Support Public Broadcasting Coalition and Others v South African
Broadcasting Corporation SOC Limited and Others (81056/14); [2017] ZAGPJHC 289 (17
October 2017), the High Court held that the President’s power to appoint the non-executive
members of the SABC ‘is a purely formal power as the National Assembly is the appointing
authority’ and the President ‘has no discretion’ in the matter. This is sensible as the
National Assembly is made up of multiple political parties representing the entire South
Africa, while the executive usually represents only one party and its interests. The process
followed by the National Assembly to make appointments is also far more transparent than
the process that the President would follow at para 76. The court further held that the SABC
‘must be free from executive control and influence’ (at para 47), because the SABC
performs a watchdog function ‘by investigating and reporting on the maladministration,
abuses of power and corruption as these are matters of public interest’ at para 46.
62 Report of the Presidential Review Commission on the Reform and Transformation of the
Public Service in South Africa, Pretoria (1998) para 1.3, available at
https://www.gov.za/documents/report-presidential-review-commission-reform-and-
transformation-public-service-south. See also Klug, H (2010) The Constitution of South
Africa: A Contextual Analysis 201.
63 Report of the Presidential Review Commission (1998) para 7.2.1.4.
64 Chothia, F and Jacobs, S ‘Remaking the Presidency: The tension between co-ordination
and centralisation’ in Jacobs, S and Calland, R (eds) (2002) Thabo Mbeki’s World: The
Politics and Ideology of the South African President 150.
65 Klug (2010) 203.
66 See generally Calland, R (2013) The Zuma Years: South Africa’s Changing Face of Power for a
discussion of the way in which the Office of the Presidency has operated during President
Jacob Zuma’s tenure.
67 Deputy Chief Justice Dikgang Moseneke ‘Reflections on South Africa’s Constitutional
Democracy – Transition and Transformation’, keynote speech delivered on 12 November
2014 at the Mistra-Tmali-UNISA Conference, accessed on 30 January 2020 at
https://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/dcj-moseneke-reflections-on-south-african-
constitutional-democracy-transition-and-transformation/ [footnotes omitted]
68 S 174(6) of the Constitution which states: ‘The President must appoint the judges of all
other courts on the advice of the Judicial Service Commission.’
69 S 193(4) of the Constitution.
70 Act 32 of 1998 (NPA Act).
71 Corruption Watch II para 31.
72 Corruption Watch II para 35.
73 At para 42. In this regard, s 12(4) of the NPA Act was declared unconstitutional.
74 Corruption Watch at para 48.
75 S 174(3) of the Constitution.
76 S 174(3) of the Constitution.
77 Democratic Alliance v President of South Africa and Others (CCT 122/11) [2012] ZACC 24;
2012 (12) BCLR 1297 (CC); 2013 (1) SA 248 (CC) (5 October 2012) paras 14–26.
78 S 101(1) of the Constitution.
79 S 101(2) of the Constitution.
80 Currie and De Waal (2001) 241.
81 Hugo para 10.
82 SARFU III para 148. Even with regard to the interim Constitution, which did not contain an
explicit provision about the rule of law, the Constitutional Court found in Fedsure Life
Assurance Ltd and Others v Greater Johannesburg Transitional Metropolitan Council and
Others (CCT7/98) [1998] ZACC 17; 1999 (1) SA 374; 1998 (12) BCLR 1458 (14 October 1998)
paras 56–9 that the doctrine of legality, an incidence of the rule of law, was an implied
provision of the interim Constitution. The Court stated at para 58:
‘It seems central to the conception of our constitutional order that the legislature and
executive in every sphere are constrained by the principle that they may exercise no power
and perform no function beyond that conferred upon them by law. At least in this sense,
then, the principle of legality is implied within the terms of the interim Constitution.’
83 Hugo para 10.
84 Hugo para 15. The Court referred to judgments by the Bavarian and Hessen Constitutional
Courts to support this claim. See BayVerfGHE NF 18 140 (1965) at 147; HessStGH NJW
1974, 791 at 793.
85 Hugo para 28.
86 Hugo para 29.
87 S 91(2) of the Constitution.
88 (CCT 01/07) [2007] ZACC 20; 2008 (1) SA 566 (CC); 2008 (1) BCLR 1 (3 October 2007).
89 Masetlha para 77.
90 Masetlha para 77.
91 (CCT10/98) [1998] ZACC 20; 1999 (2) SA 91; 1999 (2) BCLR 151 (2 December 1998) para 41.
92 Masetlha para 77.
93 The actions of the President may also be found to infringe a constitutional right given effect
to in legislation. In President of the Republic of South Africa and Others v M & G Media Ltd
(CCT 03/11) [2011] ZACC 32; 2012 (2) BCLR 181 (CC); 2012 (2) SA 50 (CC) (29 November
2011), for example, the Constitutional Court had to decide whether the refusal by the
President to hand over a Report commissioned by the President to the Mail & Guardian
newspaper contravened the provisions of the Promotion of Access to Information Act 2 of
2000 which gives effect to s 32 of the Constitution.
94 (CCT16/98) [1999] ZACC 11; 2000 (1) SA 1; 1999 (10) BCLR 1059 (10 September 1999).
95 SARFU III paras 146–8.
96 See Albutt v Centre for the Study of Violence and Reconciliation and Others (CCT 54/09)
[2010] ZACC 4; 2010 (3) SA 293 (CC); 2010 (2) SACR 101 (CC); 2010 (5) BCLR 391 (CC) (23
February 2010).
97 Masetlha para 68.
98 Justice Alliance of South Africa v President of Republic of South Africa and Others, Freedom
Under Law v President of Republic of South Africa and Others, Centre for Applied Legal
Studies and Another v President of Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT 53/11, CCT
54/11, CCT 62/11) [2011] ZACC 23; 2011 (5) SA 388 (CC); 2011 (10) BCLR 1017 (CC) (29 July
2011) para 54. See also Executive Council of the Province of the Western Cape v Minister for
Provincial Affairs and Constitutional Development and Another, Executive Council of
KwaZulu-Natal v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others
(CCT15/99,CCT18/99) [1999] ZACC 13; 2000 (1) SA 661; 1999 (12) BCLR 1360 (15 October
1999) para 54.
99 (CCT27/95) [1995] ZACC 8; 1995 (10) BCLR 1289; 1995 (4) SA 877 (22 September 1995) para
62.
100 Executive Council of the Western Cape Legislature para 62.
101 Executive Council of the Western Cape Legislature para 62. In a separate judgment in this
case, Mahommed J confirmed this principle, but for slightly different – more substantive –
reasons. Mahommed said at para 136 that these issues cannot be determined in the
abstract but depend ‘inter-alia on the constitutional instrument in question, the powers of
the legislature in terms of that instrument, the nature and ambit of the purported
delegation, the subject-matter to which it relates, the degree of delegation, the control and
supervision retained or exercisable by the delegator over the delegatee, the circumstances
prevailing at the time when the delegation is made and when it is expected to be exercised,
the identity of the delegatee and practical necessities generally’.
102 (CCT 53/11, CCT 54/11, CCT 62/11) [2011] ZACC 23; 2011 (5) SA 388 (CC); 2011 (10) BCLR
1017 (CC) (29 July 2011).
103 Act 47 of 2001.
104 Justice Alliance paras 65–8.
105 See Hugo para 29. See also SARFU III para 148; Fedsure Life paras 56–8; Masetlha para 23;
Minister for Justice and Constitutional Development v Chonco and Others (CCT 42/09)
[2009] ZACC 25; 2010 (1) SACR 325 (CC); 2010 (2) BCLR 140 (CC); 2010 (4) SA 82 (CC) (30
September 2009) para 30; Albutt para 49; Democratic Alliance para 31.
106 Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of South Africa and Another: In re Ex Parte
President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT31/99) [2000] ZACC 1; 2000 (2) SA
674; 2000 (3) BCLR 241 (25 February 2000) para 90; Kruger v President of the Republic of
South Africa and Others (CCT 57/07) [2008] ZACC 17; 2009 (1) SA 417 (CC); 2009 (3) BCLR
268 (CC) (2 October 2008) para 98.
107 Bato Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v Minister of Environmental Affairs and Tourism and Others
(CCT 27/03) [2004] ZACC 15; 2004 (4) SA 490 (CC); 2004 (7) BCLR 687 (CC) (12 March
2004) para 44.
108 (CCT 54/09) [2010] ZACC 4; 2010 (3) SA 293 (CC); 2010 (2) SACR 101 (CC); 2010 (5) BCLR
391 (CC) (23 February 2010) para 51. See also Democratic Alliance para 30.
109 (CCT 122/11) [2012] ZACC 24; 2012 (12) BCLR 1297 (CC); 2013 (1) SA 248 (CC) (5 October
2012) para 32. See also President of the Republic of South Africa and Others v South African
Dental Association and Another (CCT 201/14) [2015] ZACC 2; 2015 (4) BCLR 388 (CC) (27
January 2015).
110 Democratic Alliance para 90. See also Prinsloo v Van der Linde and Another (CCT4/96)
[1997] ZACC 5; 1997 (6) BCLR 759; 1997 (3) SA 1012 (18 April 1997) para 25; Pharmaceutical
Manufacturers para 90.
111 See Affordable Medicines Trust and Others v Minister of Health and Another (CCT27/04)
[2005] ZACC 3; 2006 (3) SA 247 (CC); 2005 (6) BCLR 529 (CC) (11 March 2005) para 49;
Pharmaceutical Manufacturers para 20; SARFU III para 38; Fedsure Life para 32.
112 Albutt para 49.
113 Albutt para 71.
114 Democratic Alliance para 89.
115 Du Plessis, M and Scott, S (2013) The variable standard of rationality review: Suggestions
for improved legality jurisprudence South African Law Journal 130(3):597–620 at 597
116 Du Plessis and Scott (2013) 598.
117 Du Plessis and Scott (2013) 608–9 (footnotes omitted).
118 Du Plessis and Scott (2013) 617.
119 Du Plessis and Scott (2013) 618.
120 (CCT22/01) [2001] ZACC 3; 2001 (11) BCLR 1168; 2002 (1) SA 33 (CC) (8 October 2001).
121 Liebenberg para 15. See also Von Abo v President of the Republic of South Africa (CCT 67/08)
[2009] ZACC 15; 2009 (10) BCLR 1052 (CC); 2009 (5) SA 345 (CC) (5 June 2009) para 45.
122 (CCT 67/08) [2009] ZACC 15; 2009 (10) BCLR 1052 (CC); 2009 (5) SA 345 (CC) (5 June 2009)
para 45.
123 SARFU III para 240.
124 SARFU III para 242.
125 SARFU III para 243.
126 S 91(1) of the Constitution.
127 S 91(2) of the Constitution.
128 S 91(3)(a) of the Constitution.
129 S 91(3)(b) and (c) of the Constitution.
130 Currie and De Waal (2001) 254.
131 Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (CCT 23/96) [1996]
ZACC 26; 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC) (6 September 1996) para 108.
132 In Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (CCT 23/96) [1996]
ZACC 26; 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC) (6 September 1996) para 109.
133 S 91(2) of the Constitution.
134 S 102 of the Constitution.
135 Masetlha para 228, where Sachs J stated:
This suggests a qualitative distinction based on the fact that the three are not purely
political appointees placed in positions of governmental leadership. Rather, they
are important public officials with one foot in government and one in the public
administration. Members of Cabinet know that they are hired and can be fired at
the will of the President; and if fired, they can mobilise politically, go to the press,
even demonstrate outside Parliament, and hope to muster support for themselves
at the next congress of their party.
136 Masetlha para 228.
137 See also Currie and De Waal (2001) 254 and Mphele v Government of the Republic of South
Africa 1996 (7) BCLR 921 (CK) 954E.
138 See Devenish, GE (1998) A Commentary on the South African Constitution 158. When
President Thabo Mbeki served as Deputy President in the Cabinet of President Nelson
Mandela, he was widely regarded as playing the role of Prime Minister. See generally
Gumede, WM (2008) Thabo Mbeki and the Battle for the Soul of the ANC 33–62.
139 S 90(1).
140 See Corruption Watch (RF) NPC and Another v President of the Republic of South Africa and
Others; Council for the Advancement of the South African Constitution v President of the
Republic of South Africa and Others (62470/2015) [2017] ZAGPPHC 743; [2018] 1 All SA 471
(GP); 2018 (1) SACR 317 (GP) (8 December 2017)
141 S 91(2) of the Constitution.
142 S 92(1) and 92(2) of the Constitution.
143 This is the necessary implication of s 92(2) which states that members of the Cabinet are
collectively responsible to Parliament.
144 See Magidimisi v Premier of the Eastern Cape and Others (2180/04, ECJ031/06) [2006]
ZAECHC 20 (25 April 2006) paras 20–1:
The first respondent is the Premier of the province. The Constitution vests her with the
ultimate executive authority of the province. The Premier and the Members of the
Executive Council are responsible for the implementation of legislation in the province and
for the performance of all other constitutional and statutory executive functions of the
province. The Premier has taken an oath of office to ‘obey, respect and uphold the
Constitution and all other law of the Republic’. This includes the duties to uphold the rule of
law … As the ultimate executive authority in the province the Premier thus bears the
ultimate responsibility to ensure that the provincial government honours and obeys all
judgments of the courts against it. The second respondent, the Member of the Executive
Council for Finance, bears the same general constitutional duties as those of the Premier,
except that he does not bear the ultimate executive authority of the Premier. In addition,
however, he bears responsibility for decisions of the provincial treasury. This would include
decisions relating to the payment of judgments against the province for the payment of
money.
145 S 92(2) of the Constitution.
146 S 96(3) of the Constitution.
147 SARFU II para 41. See also Murray and Stacey (2013) 18.32.
148 S 85(2) of the Constitution states: ‘The President exercises the executive authority, together
with the other members of the Cabinet …’
149 See Murray and Stacey (2013) 18.32. They point out that this aspect requires confidentiality
from members of the Cabinet and Cabinet members are usually not allowed to divulge
information about debates within Cabinet. Although this rule is not encoded in the
Constitution, it has been respected since the advent of the interim Constitution in 1994.
The need for confidentiality has also been accepted by the Constitutional Court in SARFU
III para 243.
150 See Rautenbach, IM and Malherbe, EFJ (2009) Constitutional Law 193.
151 Rautenbach and Malherbe (2009) 193.
152 See also Mafunisa, MJ (2008) The role of codes of conduct in promoting ethical conduct in
the South African public service South African Journal of Labour Relations 32(1):81–92.
153 See also the Code of Conduct for Assembly and Permanent Council Members, available at
https://www.parliament.gov.za/code-conduct-for-na-ncop-members.
154 S 96(2) of the Constitution.
155 Act 82 of 1998.
156 Act 23 of 1994.
157 See s 3 of the Executive Members’ Ethics Act.
158 S 3 of the Executive Members’ Ethics Act.
159 S 91(5) of the Constitution.
Separation of powers and judicial
authority
6.1 The historic legacy of parliamentary sovereignty and apartheid on the judiciary
Summary
The South African judiciary was not left untainted by its role during the
apartheid era.1 There are many reasons why the judiciary cannot be said
to have survived the apartheid era untainted. Before 1994, the doctrine
of parliamentary supremacy was one of the cornerstones of South
African constitutional law. This doctrine obviously limited the
judiciary’s capacity to enforce individual rights and freedoms. As
Mtshaulana points out, because ‘the rule of law was equated to rule by
law, all arbitrary exercise of power, … exercised in terms of a law
enacted by correct constitutional procedures prescribed by Parliament
was considered lawful and in accordance with the rule of law’.2 Although
some judges attempted to interpret and apply the law in such a way as
to limit the harsh effects of apartheid laws, others diligently enforced
apartheid laws. This meant that the apartheid judiciary lacked
legitimacy in the eyes of the majority of people in South Africa.3
Moreover, after anti-apartheid lawyers had won several important
victories in the courts in the 1980s during the States of Emergency,4 the
Appellate Division overturned many of these judgments confirming
that the apartheid state had virtually unlimited power under the
emergency provisions.5 The outcome in these cases further confirmed
the lack of impartiality and independence of the highest court and
eroded whatever legitimacy the judiciary may still have enjoyed.
However, there is some disagreement about whether the timid
approach of many judges during the apartheid years entirely destroyed
the judiciary’s credibility. On the one hand, Madala argues that ‘the
[apartheid] system created a society in which the majority came to
regard the courts, judges, and the administration of justice with
suspicion and anger’.6 On the other hand, Ellmann argues that black
South Africans surprisingly retained a significant degree of confidence
in the legal system and the courts in particular.7 Ellmann argues that
this confidence lent a measure of legitimacy to the legal system. This,
coupled with the history of anti-apartheid lawyering, ‘might have
encouraged South Africans to see virtue in the ideals of fearless
advocacy, independent judging, and the rule of law’, offering the
promise that these same ideals would be honoured in the post-
apartheid South Africa.8
It is nevertheless clear that the institutionalisation of apartheid
through law and legal regulation transformed the legal system and
entrenched the political dominance of the minority over the majority
through the operation of law enforced by the judiciary.9 To this end, the
judiciary ‘was unable to resolve the impasse [of its subjugation] because
it did not have the option to review and reverse unjust laws; rather, the
courts and all the other institutions had to implement and administer
such laws’.10 Because the judiciary operated under the system of
parliamentary supremacy, it meant that ‘by upholding blatantly
discriminatory and unjust legislation, the judiciary functioned as part of
the apartheid legal order and contributed to legitimising and sustaining
it’.11 Judges were regarded as mere mechanical interpreters of the law.
Their function was seen by many – including by most judges and legal
practitioners – merely to ascertain the intention of the apartheid
legislature through the text of the legislation and then to give effect to
that intention, no matter how nefarious the intention might have
been.12 Most judges believed that they could employ only limited
interpretational aids in the event of ambiguity or inconsistency, or if
adherence to the ordinary meaning of the text would result in
absurdity.13 They adhered to the notion that any modifications,
corrections or additions to the text should be left to the legislature as the
government branch responsible for making law. Value judgments of the
content of a statute were irrelevant when interpreting and applying the
legislation passed by the apartheid Parliament.14 Corder draws the
conclusion that:
The overall picture [of judicial attitudes] which emerges is one of a group of
men who saw their dominant roles as the protectors of a stability … The judges
expressed it in terms of a positivistic acceptance of legislative sovereignty,
despite a patently racist political structure, and a desire to preserve the existing
order of legal relations, notwithstanding its basis in manifest social inequalities
…15
These attitudes were amplified by the fact that the power of judges was
constrained under the system of parliamentary supremacy.16
However, despite problems with the formalistic approach to the
interpretation and application of unjust laws, there is widespread
agreement that before the advent of democracy, the judiciary did
exhibit many of the formal attributes of independence. Courtrooms
were open to the general public and judges enjoyed security of tenure
and of salary even though politics played a role in the promotion of
judges to the Appellate Division. Judges served until the age of 70 and
could be removed only by the State President at the request of the
Houses of Parliament on the grounds of misbehaviour or incapacity.
Moreover, the salaries of judges were legally guaranteed and could not
be reduced during their term of office.17
Notwithstanding these features, the judiciary was not entirely free
from indirect political influence through the process of appointment.18
Before 1994, the State President appointed judges in terms of section 10
of the Supreme Court Act.19 However, in practice, it was the Minister of
Justice who made the appointments based on the recommendations of
the Chief Justice or Judge President of the relevant division of the High
Court.20 The State President then merely formalised these
appointments. The process of identifying potential candidates and their
selection was also ‘shrouded in secrecy’ and ‘political factors played a
role in determining who secured appointment and who was
promoted’.21
Furthermore, in the pre-democratic era, the judiciary was
composed almost entirely of white males, drawn from the elitist and
privileged ranks of the ruling minority. Judicial appointees were drawn
primarily from the ranks of senior counsel practising as advocates at the
various bars in South Africa. Before 1990, only one white female had
been appointed as a judge in South Africa while no black judges had
been appointed.22 The selection process was a confidential one which
meant that candidates could be hand-picked based on whether their
beliefs were sympathetic to the government of the day.23 The first black
male judge, Ismael Mahomed, was appointed in 1991.24 When South
Africa became a democracy in 1994, out of 166 judges, 161 were white
men, two were white women, three were black men and there were no
black women judges at all.25
The way in which this tension can best be dealt with is by recognising
that an independent and impartial judiciary is most effective when it
respects the separation of powers doctrine and does not unnecessarily
intrude on the domain of the legislature and the executive. However,
this does not mean the courts must be timid in protecting and enforcing
the Constitution. In International Trade Administration Commission v
SCAW South Africa (Pty) Ltd the Constitutional Court thus said:
In our constitutional democracy, all public power is subject to constitutional
control. Each arm of the state must act within the boundaries set. However, in
the end, courts must determine whether unauthorised trespassing by one arm
of the state into the terrain of another has occurred. In that narrow sense, the
courts are the ultimate guardians of the Constitution. They do not only have the
right to intervene in order to prevent the violation of the Constitution, they also
have the duty to do so. It is in the performance of this role that courts are more
likely to confront the question of whether to venture into the domain of other
branches of government and the extent of such intervention. It is a necessary
component of the doctrine of separation of powers that courts have a
constitutional obligation to ensure that the exercise of power by other branches
of government occurs within constitutional bounds. But even in these
circumstances, courts must observe the limits of their own power.46
‘Judicial overreach’
When should the Constitutional Court (and other
courts) defer to the other branches of government?
What is a court to do when its interpretation of the
Constitution, followed to its logical conclusion, will
require it to intrude into the heartland of the powers
constitutionally earmarked for exercise by the
legislature or the executive? In Economic Freedom
Fighters and Others v Speaker of the National
Assembly and Another48 the Constitutional Court was
confronted with such questions when it was asked to
consider whether the existing mechanisms to impeach
the President in terms of section 89 of the Constitution
(provided for in the rules of the National Assembly)
was constitutionally compliant or not. As the power to
impeach the President is reserved for the
democratically elected National Assembly, the
essential question in the case was whether the courts
should intervene and order the National Assembly to
adopt a procedure for impeachment, and even order
the Assembly to begin the process that would consider
whether to impeach the President or not. The majority
of the court held that the court had a duty to uphold
the Constitution even when this required it to intervene
in the powers exercised by the legislature and ordered
the National Assembly to change its rules to comply
with the courts’ interpretation of section 89. Chief
Justice Mogoeng Mogoeng disgreed with the majority
and in his dissenting opinion bemoaned the majority
decision in the following terms:
The [majority] judgment is a textbook case of judicial overreach –
a constitutionally impermissible intrusion by the Judiciary into the
exclusive domain of Parliament. The extraordinary nature and
gravity of this assertion demands that substance be provided to
undergird it, particularly because the matter is polycentric in
nature and somewhat controversial. It is at odds with the dictates
of separation of powers and context-sensitive realities to
prescribe to the National Assembly to always hold an inquiry, and
to never rely only on readily available documented or recorded
evidential material, to determine the existence of a ground of
impeachment. It is just as insensitive to this doctrine to hold that
impeachment grounds must always be determined by the
Assembly before the debate and voting on a motion of
impeachment could take place.49
The inferior specialist courts include, but are not limited to, the
following:
• The Children’s Court was established to deal with matters related to
children such as custody.71
• The Maintenance Courts were established in terms of the
Maintenance Act 72 to deal with issues around maintenance.
• The Domestic Violence Courts were established in terms of the
Domestic Violence Act.73
The Constitutional Court itself has the power to make the final decision
on whether a matter is within its jurisdiction.95 These amendments
mean that the Constitutional Court is no longer confined to hearing
constitutional matters and matters that are connected with
constitutional matters. The Court can now also consider non-
constitutional matters. However, the Constitutional Court cannot hear
appeals based solely on factual disputes. In cases where an appeal is
lodged with the Constitutional Court that does not deal with a
constitutional matter, the Constitutional Court has a relatively wide
discretion to decide whether it will hear the appeal or not. In doing so, it
will have to take two factors into consideration. To meet the
requirements set in section 167(3)(a) of the Constitution, on must first
ask whether the matter raises an arguable point of law. As the
Constitutional Court cannot entertain a purely factual question the
question in a criminal case of whether evidence is sufficient to justify a
finding of guilt beyond reasonable doubt cannot in itself be a
constitutional matter.96 Moreover, a matter does not raise an arguable
point of law if the argument is ‘totally unmeritorious’, which means the:
notion that a point of law is arguable entails some degree of merit in the
argument. Although the argument need not, of necessity, be convincing at this
stage, it must have a measure of plausibility … in order to be arguable, a point
of law must have some prospects of success.97
Second, one must ask whether this point of law is one of general public
importance. This does not mean the requirement will only be met if the
interests of society as a whole are implicated. It does mean that for a
matter to be of general public importance, it ‘must transcend the
narrow interests of the litigants and implicate the interest of a
significant part of the general public’.98
As pointed out above, matters that turn purely on questions of fact are
not constitutional matters nor do they raise ‘an arguable point of law’.
This means such matters that raise only purely factual disputes cannot
be heard by the Constitutional Court. Similarly, the Constitutional
Court cannot hear matters involving the straightforward application of
law that do not raise constitutional questions, do not require the Court
to interpret or develop legislation, common law or customary law in
line with the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights, and do not
raise an arguable point of law.100
The distinction between factual disputes and
disputes about points of law
The Constitutional Court’s judgment in S v Boesak101
provides a helpful illustration of the distinction
between factual disputes and disputes about points of
law in the context of the pre-seventeenth amendment
regime which still required a constitutional question to
be raised for the Constitutional Court to hear the case.
Boesak was convicted on a charge of fraud and three
charges of theft in the High Court. On appeal, the SCA
set aside the conviction on one of the theft charges but
dismissed the appeal on the other charges. It
nevertheless reduced the sentence to one of three
years’ imprisonment.102
Boesak approached the Constitutional Court to
have the remaining convictions set aside, arguing that
there was not sufficient evidence to support the
findings of the SCA that his guilt had been proven
beyond reasonable doubt. The SCA, Boesak argued,
had interpreted the facts wrongly. This was a violation
of the right to be presumed innocent guaranteed by
section 35(3)(h) of the Bill of Rights.
The Constitutional Court found that, in essence,
Boesak was arguing that the High Court and the SCA
had got the facts wrong. It found that even if this were
true, this would not raise a constitutional issue. The
Court then went on to identify three broad principles
informing the identification of constitutional issues:
(a) A challenge to a decision of the SCA on the basis only that
it is wrong on the facts is not a constitutional matter.
In the context of section 167(3) of the Constitution the
question whether evidence is sufficient to justify a finding
of guilt beyond reasonable doubt cannot in itself be a
constitutional matter. Otherwise, all criminal cases would
be constitutional matters, and the distinction drawn in the
Constitution between the jurisdiction of this Court and that
of the SCA would be illusory. There is a need for finality in
criminal matters. The structure of the Constitution suggests
clearly that finality should be achieved by the SCA unless a
constitutional matter arises. Disagreement with the SCA’s
assessment of the facts is not sufficient to constitute a
breach of the right to a fair trial. An applicant for leave to
appeal against the decision of the SCA must necessarily
have had an appeal or review as contemplated by section
35(3)(o) of the Constitution. Unless there is some separate
constitutional issue raised therefore, no constitutional right
is engaged when an appellant merely disputes the findings
of fact made by the SCA.
(b) The development of, or the failure to develop, a common-
law rule by the SCA may constitute a constitutional
matter.
This may occur if the SCA developed, or failed to develop,
the rule under circumstances inconsistent with its
obligation under section 39(2) of the Constitution or with
some other right or principle of the Constitution.
(c) The application of a legal rule by the SCA may constitute a
constitutional matter.
This may occur if the application of a rule is inconsistent
with some right or principle of the Constitution.103
6.4.1 Introduction
South Africa’s transition to an open and democratic society with a
supreme Constitution relied heavily on the establishment of an
independent and impartial judiciary. In the new system, the role of the
judiciary was dramatically expanded to ensure the protection of
fundamental rights and to ensure that government (as well as private
institutions) remained within the bounds of the law and honoured the
constitutional commitment to openness and democracy. Given the
manner in which the judiciary was tainted during apartheid, it may be
surprising that this institution was entrusted with such a crucial role in
the transition to democracy, especially given the fact that in terms of the
political settlement, it was the only branch that remained largely
unchanged in the new democratic era.143 As we have pointed out, when
the new Constitution came into effect, the judiciary was still largely
dominated by white men and tainted by its role in the interpretation
and implementation of apartheid legislation.144
Despite this history, when South Africa became a democracy, no
judges were relieved of their duties and the courts did not only retain
their powers, but were given extended powers far exceeding those they
had enjoyed under apartheid. The only change came in the form of the
addition of the Constitutional Court to the existing court structure and
changes to the manner in which judges are appointed. While the other
courts and the judges who staffed these courts remained in place, the
interim Constitution provided for the creation of a separate
Constitutional Court to act as the final arbiter of all constitutional
matters.
Against this background, the creation of the Constitutional Court is
a significant development in South Africa’s transition, representing a
first step on the journey of transforming the legal system as a whole. It is
difficult to imagine that the judiciary would have been awarded such an
important role in the transition if a new Constitutional Court had not
been put in place. It is also difficult to imagine that the judiciary would
have been entrusted with the enforcement of a supreme Constitution in
the absence of a newly created Constitutional Court. The decision to
create the Constitutional Court was therefore partly a pragmatic
political move and partly a principled move aimed at increasing the
legitimacy of the judiciary. As the highest Court on constitutional
matters and now also on other matters of legal doctrine, it was
important that the Court be seen to be impartial and independent and
not tainted by South Africa’s apartheid past. Given the fact that the
Court would also act as the ultimate guardian of the impartiality and
independence of all other courts,145 its creation could therefore be said
to be the first step in restoring the independence of the South African
judiciary. It also allowed the retention of the court structure and made it
easier for the drafters of the interim and 1996 Constitutions to safeguard
the tenure of judges appointed by the apartheid government before
1994.
On the one hand, the Court acknowledged the fact that the language of
the Constitution does not necessarily yield one ‘objective’ meaning
which the Court can discover in a mechanistic fashion. It thus
recognised the need to refer to extra-textual factors – such as the South
African context and history and comparable foreign case law 150 – when
interpreting the provisions of the Constitution. On the other hand, the
judgment resisted any move that would implicate the personal views,
political commitments and philosophy of the judges themselves in the
interpretative project in order to safeguard the (symbolic) boundary
between the work done by judges when they interpret and apply the law
and politics.151
In S v Makwanyane and Another,152 several of the justices asserted
the irrelevance of their personal, political or philosophical views when
interpreting the Constitution. Impartiality, they claimed, required
judges to ground their judgments in general human rights principles
that are above controversy and cannot be related to the personal views
of a judge.153 At the same time, many of the justices tentatively
acknowledged the open-ended nature of the language of the
Constitution and the inherent need to refer to ‘extra-legal’ values and
texts, including the South African political context and history, to justify
their decisions.154 The Constitutional Court has since often declared its
commitment to the centrality of the constitutional text in constitutional
interpretation. The judges of this court also acknowledge that any such
interpretation can only be conducted with the assistance of objective or
objectively determinable criteria, or, at the very least, criteria that are
somehow distanced from the personal views, opinions and political
philosophy of the presiding judge.155 However, it is an open question
whether judges can truly empty their minds of all their personal views
and political commitments when they interpret the Constitution and
apply it to a specific set of facts.
Despite these difficulties, the ideal of impartial adjudication
remains a cornerstone of an independent judiciary which has often
been affirmed by the Constitutional Court. Thus, the Constitutional
Court in President of the Republic of South Africa and Others v South
African Rugby Football Union and Others – Judgment on recusal
application (SARFU II) stated that:
It must be assumed that they can disabuse their minds of any irrelevant
personal beliefs or predispositions. They must take into account the fact that
they have a duty to sit in any case in which they are not obliged to recuse
themselves.156
The test for independence
In S and Others v Van Rooyen and Others (General
Council of the Bar of South Africa Intervening),157 the
Constitutional Court affirmed that judicial
independence requires that individual judges must be
able to hear and decide cases that come before them
and that no outsider should be able to interfere with
the way a judge conducts his or her case and makes
his or her decision. This requires judges to act
impartially and, at an institutional level, it requires
structures to protect courts and judicial officers against
external interference.158
At the same time, it is important to note that there
are hierarchical differences between higher courts and
lower courts and that the requirements for
independence could be different for the two types of
courts.159 Just because they are treated differently
does not mean that magistrates’ courts are not
independent. Lower courts are entitled to protection by
higher courts if their independence is threatened so
the greater the protection that is given to higher courts,
the greater the protection is for lower courts. Moreover,
lower courts do not have the power to deal with
constitutional matters and the jurisdiction of the lower
courts set out in the Constitution is much more
restricted than that of the higher courts. This means
that lower courts do not need the same kind of
safeguards as the higher courts.
The test for independence is whether the court or
tribunal ‘from the objective standpoint of a reasonable
and informed person, will be perceived as enjoying the
essential conditions of independence’.160 It is
important that there is public confidence in the
administration of justice. Without that confidence, the
system cannot command the respect and acceptance
that are essential to its effective operation. It is,
therefore, important that a tribunal should be
perceived as independent, as well as impartial, and
that the test for independence should include that
perception. This test is an objective one.161 The
apprehension of bias must be a reasonable one, held
by reasonable and right-minded persons, applying
themselves to the question and obtaining thereon the
required information. We must ask what would an
informed person conclude when viewing the matter
realistically and practically, and having thought the
matter through. The question is whether a reasonable,
objective and informed person would on the correct
facts reasonably apprehend that the judge has not or
will not bring an impartial mind to bear on the
adjudication of the case, that is, a mind open to
persuasion by the evidence and the submissions of
counsel.
It is important to note that this objective test must
be properly contextualised.162 The perception that is
relevant for such purposes is, however, a perception
based on a balanced view of all the material
information. We ask how things appear to the well-
informed, thoughtful and objective observer, rather
than the hypersensitive, cynical and suspicious person.
Bearing in mind the diversity of our society, this
cautionary injunction is of particular importance in
assessing institutional independence. The well-
informed, thoughtful and objective observer must be
sensitive to the country’s complex social realities, in
touch with its evolving patterns of constitutional
development, and guided by the Constitution, its
values and the differentiation it makes between
different levels of courts.
The Van Rooyen judgment provides a general test
to establish whether a judge would be impartial and
independent. We contend that when considering
whether the appointments procedure and other
structural safeguards intended to safeguard the
impartiality and independence of judges are sufficient,
this test must be used.
Judges may not always be able to be impartial (in the sense of being
able to make decisions without taking into account factors that are
legally irrelevant) and may not be able to act without fear or favour if the
conditions under which the judicial function is exercised do not allow
for this and if the judiciary is not created as an independent institution
that functions separately from the other branches of government.
Judges will only be able to rule impartially and to be truly independent
(from pressure of both the state and private actors) if they are able to
operate independently from the other branches of government. They
must be free from potential direct and indirect pressures that could
sway individual judges trying to act in as impartial a manner as is
humanly possible.
Structural safeguards must therefore be put in place to ensure that
judges are protected from the influence of and interference by other
branches of government (as well as from private business interests).163
This requirement for structural safeguards to guarantee the impartiality
and independence of judges places an emphasis on the functional
independence of the judiciary within the larger political system and its
functional relationship with the other branches of government in South
Africa. This second aspect of independence relates to:
the degree to which the judicial institution has a distinct and discrete role –
detached from the interests of the political system, the concerns of powerful
social groups, or the desires of the general public – to regulate the legality of
state acts, enact justice, and determine general and constitutional and legal
values.164
This means that judicial independence is not meaningful if judges
cannot exercise their judicial powers to check the arbitrary or unjust
exercise of power by political and social actors in society. The courts
(and the judges who staff the courts) must not be constrained by fear or
by practical difficulties from carrying out the ideal judicial role. This
implies that structures must be put in place to ensure that judges are
insulated from political and financial pressures and incentives.165 This
fact was endorsed by Chaskalson CJ in Van Rooyen where he argued
that:
the constitutional protection of the core values of judicial independence
accorded to all courts by the South African Constitution means that all courts
are entitled to and have the basic protection that is required … [i]mplicit in this
is recognition of the fact that the courts and their structure, with the
hierarchical differences between higher courts and lower courts which then
existed, are considered by the Constitution to be independent … that involves
an independence in the relationship between the courts and other arms of
government.166
Since courts play a crucial role in our constitutional democracy, without doubt
the JSC’s function of recommending appointments to the senior judiciary is of
singular importance. Bearing in mind the importance of this function, I do not
think it unreasonable to expect that those that bear the responsibility of
nominating, designating or electing individuals for membership of the JSC will
take their responsibility seriously and identify people who are suitably
qualified for the position. Of course, we cannot be blind to some bad
appointments to a variety of senior positions that we have witnessed in
litigation that has come before the courts. But that is not reason enough to
make an assumption that the JSC may well be saddled with bad
appointments.174
When the members of the JSC discuss matters relating to a specific High
Court, the Premier of the province together with the Judge President of
the province also sit on the Commission.175 Matters that affect a specific
High Court include, for example, decisions about the appointment of
judges to that High Court, as well as decisions about the possible
disciplining or even removal of a judge of that High Court from office. If
the Premier of the province is absent when the JSC makes a decision
regarding either the appointment or the disciplining of a judge serving
in that province, the decision of the JSC will be invalid.176
When vacancies occur in a court, the Chief Justice, as Chairperson
of the JSC, calls for nominations after which shortlisted candidates are
publicly interviewed. The JSC then makes recommendations to the
President on whom to appoint. While the JSC conducts its interviews in
public – a welcome departure from the secretive process followed
during the apartheid years – there is little transparency exhibited in the
criteria used for selection. The deliberations of the JSC are normally also
kept confidential. In the past this has led to criticism on the basis that
the JSC’s reasons for preferring one candidate are not always clear.177
The JSC has also been criticised for the manner in which it interviews
candidates. It is said that rarely are questions framed so as to afford a
candidate an opportunity to explain his or her approach to adjudication
and conception of the important constitutional values, and the
candidate’s general judicial philosophy and commitment to legal
transformation.178 However, the Constitutional Court confirmed in
Helen Suzman Foundation v Judicial Service Commission179 that where a
decision about the appointment or non-appointment of a candidate for
a judicial position is challenged in court, the JSC will provide to the
litigant the reasons for the decision by the JSC; the transcripts of the JSC
interviews; each candidate’s application for appointment; comments
on each candidate by various professional bodies and individuals; and
related research, submissions and correspondence.180 The Chief Justice
will distill the reasons for the decision, based on the deliberations of the
JSC. The majority of the court further held that recordings of the
deliberations of the JSC should also be provided to litigants challenging
the lawfulness of the appointment or non-appointment of a candidate
for judicial office.181 The JSC had argued that disclosure of its
deliberations would impede the selection process of judges as secrecy
allowed JSC members to discuss the merits of the candidates with
‘candour’ and in a robust manner. It further argued that if the content of
deliberations and thus the views held by commissioners about
candidates are divulged it might dissuade candidates from putting their
names forward out of fear of embarrassment. The majority of the court
rejected this argument, pointing out that JSC members will only be
worried about disclosure of their deliberations if they make
inappropriate comments, which they should not make.182 Furthermore,
‘the most embarrassing issues that could impugn the dignity or privacy
of candidates are raised during interviews’, which takes place in
public.183 While JSC deliberations remain secret unless an appointments
decision of the JSC is challenged in court, the Helen Suzman
Foundation judgment has the potential to impact on JSC deliberations
as JSC members may be more careful in what they say during such
deliberations, as they will be aware that their statements may be
revealed if their decision is challenged.
The role of the JSC in the appointment of judges differs depending
on the nature of the appointment to be made. The President as head of
the national executive has a relatively wide discretion when he or she
appoints the Chief Justice and the Deputy Chief Justice who both also
serve on the Constitutional Court. When making these appointments,
the President, as head of the national executive, appoints the person of
his or her choice after consulting the JSC and the leaders of parties
represented in the NA.184 The President must therefore consult the JSC,
as well as the leaders of opposition parties in the NA, before deciding on
a candidate for appointment, but the decision remains his or hers
alone. Similarly, when appointing the President and Deputy President
of the SCA, the President, as head of the national executive, appoints
the person of his or her choice after consulting the JSC (but in such
cases the President need not consult the leaders of parties represented
in the NA).185
There has been some controversy around the nature of the
consultation process required although, as stated, it is clear that
consultation has to occur prior to the appointment. Ex post facto
consultation after the President has made a final decision on an
appointment would be unlawful. No matter how rigorous this
consultation might have been, consultation requires more than
informing the parties to be consulted of a decision. Although the
Constitution does not define the notion of consultation, it has been
argued that ‘at least it must entail the good faith exchange of views,
which must be taken seriously’.186 However, it does not mean that the
President must follow the advice of those consulted.
The President, as head of the national executive, appoints the other
judges of the Constitutional Court after consulting the Chief Justice and
the leaders of parties represented in the NA.187 These appointments take
place in accordance with a more complicated procedure in which the
JSC plays a more important, but ultimately not decisive, role.
The JSC must prepare a list of nominees with three names more
than the number of appointments to be made and must then submit the
list to the President.188 The President may make appointments from the
list, but can also initially refuse to appoint someone from the list
provided by the JSC. However, if the President refuses to appoint a
judge from the list of names provided by the JSC, he or she must provide
the JSC with reasons for the decision. If this happens, the JSC is
required to supplement the list with further nominees and the
President must make the remaining appointments from the
supplemented list.189 This means if there is one vacancy in the
Constitutional Court, the JSC must send a list of four nominees to the
President. The President will then appoint one of the four nominees
unless he or she believes one or more of the nominees are not
acceptable or that the list should include a wider selection of names.
For example, if a vacancy occurs on the Constitutional Court and the
JSC sends the names of four white male candidates to the President, the
President may refuse to appoint one of the four nominees, asking for the
list to be augmented with black and female candidates. When making
decisions about the appointment of ordinary judges to the
Constitutional Court, the JSC and the President must keep in mind the
requirement that at least four members of the Constitutional Court
must at any given time be persons who were judges at the time they
were appointed to the Constitutional Court.190
The JSC plays a decisive role in the appointment of all other judges
to the SCA, High Courts and other specialised courts. This includes the
various Judge Presidents who serve as leaders of each of the High
Courts. In the appointment of such ordinary judges, the JSC selects
candidates to fill any vacancies and the President is then required to
appoint the judges ‘of all other courts on the advice of the Judicial
Service Commission’.191 Unlike with the appointment of the
Constitutional Court judges and the leadership of the SCA and the
Constitutional Court, in these cases the President has no discretion and
is required to appoint the candidates selected by the JSC.
As we have seen, the JSC has not always been clear about the criteria
used for the selection of judges for appointment. As noted above, the
Constitutional Court has confirmed that the JSC has a duty to select the
‘best possible candidates to serve as judges’.192 However, this is not an
objective standard and who the ‘best possible candidates’ are will
depend to a large degree on the criteria used for selection of judges. A
starting point for an enquiry into the qualities a candidate should have
for appointment to the bench is the text of the Constitution which spells
out the formal criteria for selection as a judge.193 Two essential criteria
appear in section 174(1) of the Constitution. These criteria are that a
person must be ‘appropriately qualified’ and ‘a fit and proper person’ to
be appointed as a judge. A further criterion for a Constitutional Court
judge is that the appointee must be a South African citizen. These
criteria can be regarded as essential or necessary minimum criteria for
appointment in the sense that a person who is not appropriately
qualified or who is not a fit and proper person may not be appointed as
a judicial officer.
However, the Constitution does not expressly detail the content of
these criteria and we are therefore required to interpret them. The JSC
itself has developed a set of criteria – over and above those mentioned
in the Constitution – that it takes into account when considering
appointments to the judiciary. These are as follows:
1. Is the proposed appointee a person of integrity?
2. Is the proposed appointee a person with the necessary energy and
motivation?
3. Is the proposed appointee a competent person?
a) technically competent
b) capacity to give expression to the values of the Constitution
4. Is the proposed appointee an experienced person?
a) technically experienced
b) experienced in regard to values and needs of the community
5. Does the proposed appointee possess appropriate potential?
6. Symbolism. What message is given to the community at large by a
particular appointment? 194
Apart from the personal values of judicial candidates, the JSC is also
required to take into account another pivotal consideration, namely the
need to transform the judiciary better to reflect the racial and gender
composition of the broader South African community. These
requirements are encapsulated by section 174(2) of the Constitution
which states that:
The need for the judiciary to reflect broadly the racial and gender composition
of South Africa must be considered when judicial officers are appointed.
There are at least two reasons why this section is important. First, as
pointed out above, at the time of the transition to democracy the South
African judiciary was almost exclusively male and white, a situation that
potentially affects the credibility and legitimacy of the judiciary.201
Special measures are therefore required to increase diversity on the
bench to ensure that the judiciary more fairly reflects the composition
of the South African public whom it serves. It would be difficult, if not
impossible, for the judiciary to retain its legitimacy in the eyes of the
public if the overwhelming majority of judges were white and male.
Second, South Africa has an egregious history of 300 years of racial
and gender discrimination – as well as discrimination on many other
grounds like disability, ethnicity and sexual orientation – in society at
large as well as in the legal profession, and there remain ongoing racial
and gender prejudices in society and in the legal profession.202 This
provision is important as it redresses these racial and gender prejudices
and provides a fair opportunity to groups who did not enjoy the same
privileges and opportunities for professional advancement as white
men did to be appointed to the bench. The requirement therefore
addresses possible lingering racial and gender discrimination in the
appointment of judges and is intended to ensure a fair appointment
process. In short, it is necessary to consider the racial and gender
composition of the bench to eradicate patterns of unfair discrimination
in the appointment of judges.203
Finally, it is argued that diversity on the bench can also improve the
quality of justice meted out by the courts. In a diverse society, judges
from different racial backgrounds and different genders and sexual
orientations will often bring different perspectives to bear. This can
improve the quality of jurisprudence and strengthen the intellectual
output of the judiciary.204 As can be seen from Table 6.2 below,205 the JSC
has done relatively well in ensuring the creation of a non-racial
judiciary while gender representation has also improved but still lags
behind. Similarly, the commitment to anti-discrimination on the
grounds of sexual orientation is debatable.206
In this regard, many express the view that being black, or being a
woman, constitutes a valid criterion for judicial selection. This
approach is misleading because the criteria for judicial selection
are that a person be appropriately qualified and a fit and proper
person. If a person is not appropriately qualified and is not a fit
and proper person, it is irrelevant whether they are black or
female. That person does not qualify for judicial office.
This oath requires each judge to decide a case on its legal merits in
accordance with the Constitution and the law and without showing
either favour or disfavour to any of the litigants. The oath therefore
requires judges to promise that they will, as far as it is humanly possible,
always act impartially and uphold the law.216 The requirement
represents a further formal safeguard of the impartiality of judges and
the independence of the judiciary.
Ordinary judges (in other words, judges who do not serve on the
Constitutional Court) hold office until they are discharged from active
service in terms of an Act of Parliament.230 Section 3(2) of the Judges’
Remuneration and Conditions of Employment Act regulates this matter.
This section states that other judges will normally hold office until the
date on which they attain the age of 70 years if they have on that date
completed a period of active service of not less than 10 years. If they
have on that date not yet completed a period of 10 years’ active service,
the term of office will end after serving for 10 years. However, judges
have a further discretion provided by section 4(4) of the Act. This
section allows a judge who on attaining the age of 70 years has not yet
completed 15 years’ active service to continue to perform active service
to the date on which he or she completes a period of 15 years’ active
service or attains the age of 75 years, whichever occurs first.
The requirement that the security of tenure of judges should be
guaranteed has another important consequence: judges should only be
removed from office as a last resort and then only for serious and
objectively determinable reasons. Thus, section 177 of the Constitution
determines that a judge may only be removed from office if the JSC
finds that the judge:
• suffers from an incapacity
• is grossly incompetent
• is guilty of gross misconduct.
Once the JSC has made such a finding, this is not the end of the matter
as the judge in question will only be removed from office if the NA calls
for that judge to be removed by a resolution adopted with a supporting
vote of at least two-thirds of its members. Once the NA has passed such
a resolution, the President must remove the judge from office. The
President has the power, on the advice of the JSC, to suspend a judge
who is the subject of an investigation by the JSC to remove him or her
from office.231 Section 177 of the Constitution ensures that a judge
cannot be arbitrarily removed from the bench for political or other
reasons unrelated to the ability of that judge to perform his or her
functions or the integrity of the judge.
The JSC Act determines the procedure to be followed by the JSC
when dealing with complaints against judges. A Judicial Conduct
Committee (a subcommittee of the JSC) is required to receive, consider
and deal with complaints against judges. The Judicial Conduct
Committee comprises the Chief Justice, who is the Chairperson of the
Committee, the Deputy Chief Justice and four judges, at least two of
whom must be women, designated by the Chief Justice in consultation
with the Minister.232 The Committee can deal with both serious
complaints, which may lead to the dismissal of a judge, or less serious
complaints which will not lead to the dismissal of a judge. However, a
lesser complaint can also be referred to the head of the court in which
the judge complained of serves.233
A complaint must be dismissed if it is not of a serious nature or is
solely related to the merits of a judgment or order, if it is frivolous or
lacking in substance, or if it is hypothetical.234 If the Chairperson of the
Conduct Committee is satisfied that in the event of a valid complaint
being established, it is likely to lead to a finding by the JSC that the
judge being accused suffers from an incapacity, is grossly incompetent
or is guilty of gross misconduct, the Chairperson must refer the
complaint to the Conduct Committee. The Committee must then
consider whether it should recommend to the JSC that the complaint
should be investigated and reported on by a Judicial Conduct Tribunal.
The Committee must also consider whether the complaint, if
established, will prima facie indicate incapacity, gross incompetence or
gross misconduct by the judge. Non-impeachable complaints can be
dealt with by the Committee without referral to the Tribunal which will
only be appointed in the case of impeachable offences.235
Impeachable offences must be referred to a Judicial Conduct
Tribunal, which consists of two judges, one of whom must be
designated by the Chief Justice as the Tribunal President, and one
layperson.236 The Tribunal will then, in effect, try the judge against
whom a serious complaint had been lodged: witnesses will be called
and those making the allegations as well as the judge being accused will
be cross-examined. The Tribunal will then make the appropriate
findings of fact, including the cogency and sufficiency of the evidence
and the demeanour and credibility of any witness, as well as its findings
as to the merits of the allegations in question. It will then submit a
report to the JSC.237 The JSC will decide whether to recommend
impeachment of the judge to the NA. When considering a complaint
against a judge, the JSC is obliged to decide the matter.
This case, read with the other SCA cases dealing with
the procedure to be followed by the JSC when
appointing and disciplining judges, suggests that the
JSC does not only have an obligation to act rationally
when it makes these decisions. It also has a duty to
make some kind of decision and cannot decide not to
make a decision at all in cases where a decision is
required.
The powers of the National Director spelt out in the Act follow very
closely the relatively detailed requirements of section 179 of the
Constitution. Crucial in this respect is the requirement that the National
Director must, with the concurrence of the Minister of Justice and after
consulting the provincial Directors of Public Prosecutions, determine
prosecution policy.295 Because the wording state that there must be
concurrence between the NDPP and the Minister, this means that the
NDPP requires the approval of the Minister before the prosecution
policy can be promulgated, which means that the Minister can veto
policy proposals of the National Director.296 In practice, the requirement
that the Minister must consent to the prosecution policy has not played
a significant role in the debate about the independence of the NPA. This
is because the NPA’s Prosecution Policy297 contains general principles
which are relatively open-ended and thus do not provide very strict
guidelines for prosecutors when deciding when to prosecute and when
not to prosecute.298 As is the case with most prosecution policies
applicable to prosecuting agencies in functioning democracies the
policy includes provisions permitting and regulating prosecutors’
discretion, encompassing an evidential and a public interest test along
similar lines.299
As noted, the NDPP has the power to intervene in any prosecution
where his policy directives have not been followed. This power should
be read with the further power to review a decision to prosecute or not
to prosecute after consulting the relevant Director and ‘after taking
representations … of the accused person, the complainant and any
other person or party whom the National Director considers to be
relevant’.300 This means that the NDPP can intervene in two distinct
situations: first where policy directives are not followed and second,
even where policy directives are complied with. In effect the NDPP
therefore has a broad and sweeping discretion to review a decision by
any prosecutor to prosecute or not to prosecute an accused. This is the
power the acting NDPP exercised when he decided to discontinue the
prosecution of President Jacob Zuma. Although the power is weeping it
is somewhat limited as it is restricted to a review of decisions on
whether to prosecute or not and would not include a direct intervention
in the way a case is presented in court.301 The Constitution and the NPA
Act also impose procedural requirements for the exercise of the power
as it could also not be exercised without the National Director taking
representations from all the prescribed parties. Where such
requirements are not met, a court can review and set aside a decision
not to prosecute, and the effect will normally be ‘that the charges and
the proceedings are automatically reinstated and it is for the executive
authorities to deal with them’. 302
It therefore appears that the NDPP has extraordinary powers. As the
Constitutional Court noted the powers and duties of the NDPP ‘are
extensive and their proper exercise and performance is crucial to the
attainment of criminal justice in our country’.303 The erosion of the
independence of the NPA would therefore pose real risk for the
democracy. As the Constitutional Court stated in Corruption Watch
NPC and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others;
Nxasana v Corruption Watch NPC and Others:
With a malleable, corrupt or dysfunctional prosecuting authority, many
criminals – especially those holding positions of influence – will rarely, if ever,
answer for their criminal deeds. Equally, functionaries within that prosecuting
authority may … be pressured … into pursuing prosecutions to advance a
political agenda. All this is antithetical to the rule of law, a founding value of the
Republic. Also, malleability, corruption and dysfunctionality are at odds with
the constitutional injunction of prosecuting without fear, favour or
prejudice.304
The Act thus envisages (and this has been confirmed by the SCA as an
‘non-contentious’) ‘that the NPA must not be led by political
considerations and that ministerial responsibility over the NPA does not
imply a right to interfere with a decision to prosecute’.313 This view of the
NDPP was confirmed by the Constitutional Court who stated that the
NPA ‘must be non-political and non-partisan and is closely related to
the function of the judiciary broadly to achieve justice and is located at
the core of delivering criminal justice’.314
The President has a wide discretion when he or she appoints the
NDPP and other Directors of Public Prosecution. The only limitation on
the exercise of this power is that the persons appointed must ‘possess
legal qualifications that would entitle him or her to practise in all courts
in the Republic;’ and ‘be a fit and proper person, with due regard to his
or her experience, conscientiousness and integrity, to be entrusted with
the responsibilities of the office concerned’. Furthermore, the National
Director must be a South African citizen and the President must first
consult the Minister of Justice before appointing Deputy National
Directors and Directors. The National Director is appointed for a non-
renewable term of 10 years. The power of the President to appoint the
NDPP was challenged during the certification of the final Constitution
on the grounds that it did not comply with Constitutional Principle VI
which required a separation of powers between the Legislature,
Executive and Judiciary with appropriate checks and balances to ensure
accountability responsiveness and openness.315 In the First Certification
judgment, the Constitutional Court rejected this argument but
confirmed that section 179 establishes the independence of the NPA in
the following terms:
[Section] 179(4) provides that the national legislation must ensure that the
prosecuting authority exercises its functions without fear, favour or prejudice.
There is accordingly a constitutional guarantee of independence, and any
legislation or executive action inconsistent therewith would be subject to
constitutional control by the courts. In the circumstances, the objection to
[section] 179 must be rejected.316
Because the President selects who chairs the inquiry, there is a risk that
the inquiry will not be as impartial and non-political as it should be.
This raises the question of whether the NDPP enjoys sufficient security
of tenure or whether the prescribed process for the removal of the
NDPP from office does not open the door to political interference. This
concern may be heightened by the fact that the President is also
empowered provisionally to suspend the National Director or a Deputy
National Director from his or her office, pending an enquiry into his or
her fitness to hold office.324 This provision could be used to place
pressure on the NDPP to resign or to be persuaded to accept a golden
handshake.
After the inquiry is concluded, the President has a discretion to
remove the NDPP or a Director from office. Once the President has
removed the NDPP or Director from office, Parliament must, within 30
days after being informed of the removal, pass a resolution either
confirming the removal of or reinstating the NDPP.325 The President is
also required to remove the NDPP or any Director from office on the
grounds listed above if requested to do so by both Houses of
Parliament.326 Since the creation of the position of NDPP, six different
individuals have served in a permanent capacity as NDPP and not a
single NDPP has completed his or her 10-year term. Because the NDPP
has such extraordinary power, it is inevitable that politicians and
politically connected businesspeople who wish to protect themselves
from prosecution for corruption and other crimes, would attempt to
ensure that the NDPP remains sympathetic to them. When the NDPP
becomes ‘too independent’ and ‘too fearless’, he or she may well come
under political pressure and runs the risk of either being coaxed out of
office by a golden handshake, or of facing removal through the process
described above. The question therefore arises whether the current
provisions in the NPA Act provide sufficient guarantees to safeguard the
security of tenure of the NDPP.
SUMMARY
The judiciary is the third, but distinct and most independent, branch of
government within the system of separation of powers.
At the pinnacle of the superior courts is the Constitutional Court
which now has the jurisdiction not only to hear any constitutional
matter, but also any other matter that raises an arguable point of law of
general importance which, in the opinion of the Constitutional Court,
ought to be considered by it. The Constitutional Court ordinarily acts as
a court of appeal, considering constitutional and other matters of legal
doctrine on appeal from any of the High Courts or from the Supreme
Court of Appeal (SCA). However, when a High Court declares invalid
provisions of an Act of Parliament, the provisions of a provincial
legislature or an act of the President, the matter automatically goes to
the Constitutional Court which is required to confirm the order of
invalidity before such an order has any force.
In addition, the Constitutional Court has exclusive jurisdiction to
decide:
• on disputes between organs of state in the national or provincial
sphere concerning the constitutional status, powers or functions of
any of those organs of state
• on the constitutionality of any parliamentary or provincial Bill
• on the constitutionality of Bills referred to it by the NA or provincial
legislatures
• on the constitutionality of any amendment to the Constitution
• that Parliament or the President has failed to fulfil a constitutional
obligation or to certify a provincial constitution.
The SCA is an appeal court that can hear appeals from High Courts on
any matter except matters exclusively reserved for the Constitutional
Court. The SCA is the final court on matters relating to findings of fact
and to the application of facts to law. The High Courts can hear
constitutional matters, except those matters exclusively reserved for the
Constitutional Court, and often sit as courts of first instance.
The judiciary (and, in South Africa, most pertinently the superior
courts,) is tasked with interpreting and enforcing the Constitution and
thus as acting as the referee to ensure that members of the other
branches of government act in accordance with the Constitution. It is
therefore important that special safeguards are put in place to secure its
independence. During the apartheid era, the independence of the
judiciary was not adequately guaranteed. With the advent of
democracy, the Constitution created additional mechanisms to
safeguard the independence of the judiciary.
The Judicial Service Commission (JSC), composed of a combination
of lawyers, judges and politicians, now plays an important role in the
appointment of all superior court judges. When the President appoints
the Chief Justice or Deputy Chief Justice and the President and Deputy
President of the SCA, this role of the JSC is only advisory. With all other
High Court judges, the JSC selects the appointees who are then merely
formally appointed by the President. There is much controversy about
the criteria for the appointment of judges, but the need for the judiciary
to reflect broadly the racial and gender composition of South Africa
does play a pivotal role in the consideration of suitable candidates for
appointment.
Apart from the appointment of impartial and independent judicial
officers, the independence of the judiciary is formally guaranteed by
requiring judges to take an oath of office, by safeguarding the security of
tenure of judges, by protecting the financial security of judges and by
limiting the civil liability of judges. Lower courts and traditional courts
are less independent but it is assumed that the superior courts will
protect these courts and will ensure that their decisions comply with the
requisite impartiality and independence.
The National Prosecuting Authority (NPA) is neither part of
government nor of the judiciary but it does play a pivotal role in the
operation of the criminal justice system as it is tasked with making
decisions on the prosecution of criminal suspects. The NPA has a duty
to act without fear, favour or prejudice. This means that it must act
independently from the government of the day although it is legally and
constitutionally required to report to the Minister of Justice on its
activities and decisions. The NPA is headed by the National Director of
Public Prosecutions (NDPP) whose independence is safeguarded by the
NPA Act. The President appoints the NDPP but the appointee must
comply with the objective criteria set out in the NPA Act.
1 For a discussion of the role of the judiciary during apartheid, see Forsyth, CF (1985) In
Danger for Their Talents: A Study of the Appellate Division of the Supreme Court of South
Africa from 1950–1980; Dyzenhaus, D (1991) Hard Cases in Wicked Legal Systems: South
African Law in the Perspective of Legal Philosophy; Ellmann, SJ (1992) In a Time of Trouble:
Law and Liberty in South Africa’s State of Emergency.
2 Mtshaulana, PM ‘The history and role of the Constitutional Court in South Africa’ in
Andrews, P and Ellmann, S (2001) The Post-Apartheid Constitutions: Perspectives on South
Africa’s Basic Law 526.
3 See Klug, H (2010) The Constitution of South Africa: A Contextual Analysis 225–30. See also
Dugard, J (1978) Human Rights and the South African Legal Order.
4 Klug (2010) 226. See generally Haysom, N and Kahanovitz, S ‘Courts and the State of
Emergency’ in Moss, G and Obery, I (eds) (1987) South African Review 4 192.
5 See Basson, D (1987) Judicial activism in a State of Emergency: An examination of recent
decisions of the South African courts South African Journal on Human Rights 3(1):28–43 at
28.
6 See Madala, T (2001) Rule under apartheid and the fledgling democracy in post-apartheid
South Africa: The role of the judiciary North Carolina Journal of International Law and
Commercial Regulation 26(3):743–65 at 748. See also Azanian Peoples Organization
(AZAPO) and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT17/96)
[1996] ZACC 16; 1996 (8) BCLR 1015; 1996 (4) SA 672 (25 July 1996) para 1 where
Mahommed states: ‘The legitimacy of law itself was deeply wounded as the country
haemorrhaged dangerously in the face of this tragic conflict which had begun to traumatise
the entire nation.’
7 Ellmann, S (1995) Law and legitimacy in South Africa Law and Social Inquiry 20(2):407–79
at 425.
8 Ellmann (1995) 409.
9 See Madala (2001) 745.
10 See Madala (2001) 748; Higginbotham, FM (1994) Sins from the past and lessons for the
future: Eliminating apartheid in South African public accommodation and the challenge to
an enlightened judiciary Boston University International Law Journal 12(1):1–56 at 1.
11 See the report by Gordon, A and Bruce, D (2006) Transformation and independence of the
judiciary in South Africa, Centre for Study of Violence and Reconciliation (CSVR) 1–61 at
11.
12 See Dyzenhaus, D (1998) Judging the Judges, Judging Ourselves: Truth, Reconciliation and
the Apartheid Legal Order 16, quoted in Gordon and Bruce (2006), indicating that this
approach means that the ‘judges hold that the judiciary duty when interpreting a statute is
always to look to those parts of public record that make clear what the legislators as a
matter of fact intended [and] in this way, the judges merely determined the law as it is,
without permitting their substantive convictions about justice to interfere’.
13 See Dugard (1978) 369.
14 See Govindjee, A and Olivier, M ‘Finding the boundary: The role of the courts in giving
effect to socio-economic rights in South Africa’ in Osode, PC and Glover, G (eds) (2010)
Law and Transformative Justice in Post-Apartheid South Africa 79.
15 Corder, H (2004) Judicial authority in a changing South Africa Legal Studies 24(2):253–74 at
255.
16 See S v Makwanyane and Another (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3; 1995 (6) BCLR 665; 1995 (3)
SA 391; [1996] 2 CHRLD 164; 1995 (2) SACR 1 (6 June 1995) para 301 where Mokgoro J
stated that:
… due to the sovereignty of parliament, the supremacy of legislation and the
absence of judicial review of parliamentary statutes, courts engaged in simple
statutory interpretation, giving effect to the clear and unambiguous language of the
legislative text – no matter how unjust the legislative provision.
17 See Gordon and Bruce (2006) 11.
18 See Wesson, M and Du Plessis, M (2008) Fifteen years on: Central issues relating to the
transformation of the South African judiciary South African Journal on Human Rights
24(2):187–213 at 190.
19 Act 59 of 1959.
20 Wesson and Du Plessis (2008) 190.
21 Wesson and Du Plessis (2008) 190. See also Cameron, E (1982) Legal chauvinism,
executive-mindedness and justice – LC Steyn’s impact on South African law South African
Law Journal 99(1):38–75 at 40, detailing the ‘meteoric’ rise of LC Steyn to the position of
Chief Justice, largely on the basis of his political affiliation.
22 See Madala (2001) 759.
23 Madala (2001) 759.
24 Mokgoro, Y (2010, December) Judicial appointments Advocate 43–8. See also Davis, DM
(2010, December) Judicial appointments in South Africa Advocate 40–3.
25 Moerane, M (2003) The meaning of transformation of the judiciary in the new South
African context South African Law Journal 120(4):708–18 at 712.
26 Moerane (2003) 712. See also Dugard, J (2007) Judging the judges: Towards an appropriate
role for the judiciary in South Africa’s transformation Leiden Journal of International Law
20(4):965–81 at 968.
27 See, for example, the Income Tax Act 58 of 1962 which created a special court for hearing
income tax appeals.
28 Currie, I and De Waal, J (2001) The New Constitutional and Administrative Law, Vol 1
Constitutional Law 273.
29 See generally the Black Administration Act 38 of 1927 (BAA).
30 Policy Framework on the Traditional Justice System under the Constitution, Department of
Justice and Constitutional Development 10, available at http://www.pmg.org.za/policy-
documents/2009/03/02/policy-framework-traditional-justice-system-under.
31 Vani, MS ‘Customary law and modern governance of natural resources in India: Conflicts,
prospects for accord and strategies’ in Pradham, R (ed) (2002) Legal Pluralism and
Unofficial Law in Social, Economic and Political Development 419.
32 Vani (2002) 419.
33 (CCT 49/03) [2004] ZACC 17; 2005 (1) SA 580 (CC); 2005 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) (15 October 2004).
34 (CCT 03/07) [2008] ZACC 9; 2008 (9) BCLR 914 (CC); 2009 (2) SA 66 (CC) (4 June 2008).
35 Vani (2002) 419.
36 Vani (2002) 419.
37 Vani (2002) 419.
38 Vani (2002) 419.
39 (CCT 40/ 03) [2004] ZACC 14; 2004 (5) SA 331 (CC); 2004 (7) BCLR 735 (CC) (11 March
2004) para 74.
40 See the Traditional Courts Bill B1–2012, available at
http://www.justice.gov.za/legislation/bills/2012-b01tradcourts.pdf. The Bill has been
heavily criticised. See, for example, the submission made to Parliament by the Law, Race
and Gender Research Unit, now the Centre for Law and Society, available at
http://www.cls.uct.ac.za/usr/lrg/docs/TCB/2012/lrg_feb2012_ncopsubmission.pdf.
41 Van Zyl, D (2009) The judiciary as a bastion of the legal order in challenging times
Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal 12(2):1–13 at 2.
42 See Choudhry, S (2009) ‘He had a mandate’: The South African Constitutional Court and
the African National Congress in a dominant party democracy Constitutional Court Review
2:1–86 at 1.
43 S 172(1)(a) of the Constitution.
44 S v Mamabolo (CCT 44/00) [2001] ZACC 17; 2001 (3) SA 409 (CC); 2001 (5) BCLR 449 (CC)
(11 April 2001) para 18:
Therefore courts have over the centuries developed a method of functioning, a self-
discipline and a restraint which, although it differs from jurisdiction to jurisdiction,
has a number of essential characteristics. The most important is that judges speak
in court and only in court. They are not at liberty to defend or even debate their
decisions in public. It requires little imagination to appreciate that the alternative
would be chaotic. Moreover, as a matter of general policy judicial proceedings of
any significance are conducted in open court, to which everybody has free access
and can assess the merits of the dispute and can witness the process of its
resolution. This process of resolution ought as a matter of principle to be analytical,
rational and reasoned. The rules to be applied in resolving the dispute should either
be known beforehand or be debated and determined openly. All decisions of
judicial bodies are as a matter of course announced in public; and, as a matter of
virtually invariable practice, reasons are automatically and publicly given for
judicial decisions in contested matters. All courts of any consequence are obliged to
maintain records of their proceedings and to retain them for subsequent scrutiny.
Ordinarily the decisions of courts are subject to correction by other, higher
tribunals, once again for reasons that are debated and made known publicly.
45 Mahomed, I (1998) The role of the judiciary in a constitutional state South African Law
Journal 115(1):111–15 at 112. See also Mamabolo para 16:
In our constitutional order the judiciary is an independent pillar of state,
constitutionally mandated to exercise the judicial authority of the state fearlessly
and impartially. Under the doctrine of separation of powers it stands on an equal
footing with the executive and the legislative pillars of state; but in terms of
political, financial or military power it cannot hope to compete. It is in these terms
by far the weakest of the three pillars; yet its manifest independence and authority
are essential. Having no constituency, no purse and no sword, the judiciary must
rely on moral authority. Without such authority it cannot perform its vital function
as the interpreter of the Constitution, the arbiter in disputes between organs of state
and, ultimately, as the watchdog over the Constitution and its Bill of Rights – even
against the state.
46 (CCT 59/09) [2010] ZACC 6; 2012 (4) SA 618 (CC); 2010 (5) BCLR 457 (CC) (9 March 2010)
paras 92–3.
47 See generally Roux, T (2009) Principle and pragmatism on the Constitutional Court of
South Africa International Journal of Constitutional Law 7(1):106–38.
48 (CCT76/17) [2017] ZACC 47; 2018 (3) BCLR 259 (CC); 2018 (2) SA 571 (CC) (29 December
2017).
49 EFF para 223-24.
50 EFF para 280-82.
51 S 167(1) read with s 165(6) of the Constitution as well as s 4(1) of the Superior Courts Act 10
of 2013. See also Justice Alliance of South Africa v President of Republic of South Africa and
Others, Freedom Under Law v President of Republic of South Africa and Others, Centre for
Applied Legal Studies and Another v President of Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT
53/11, CCT 54/11, CCT 62/11) [2011] ZACC 23; 2011 (5) SA 388 (CC); 2011 (10) BCLR 1017
(CC) (29 July 2011) para 78.
52 S 167(1) of the Constitution read with s 4(2) of the Superior Courts Act.
53 Justice Alliance para 78.
54 Justice Alliance para 78.
55 Justice Alliance para 78.
56 Justice Alliance para 79.
57 S 4(1)(b) of the Superior Courts Act.
58 S 166(b) of the Constitution. See also Currie and De Waal (2001) 278.
59 S 168(1) of the Constitution.
60 S 4(2)(b) of the Superior Courts Act.
61 S 5(1)(b) of the Superior Courts Act.
62 S 169 of the Constitution.
63 S 169(2) of the Constitution.
64 S 6(2) of the Superior Courts Act.
65 S 8(4)(c) of the Superior Courts Act.
66 S 6 of the Superior Courts Act. Most sections of the Act came into operation in August 2013.
67 See ss 10–16 of the Magistrates Act 90 of 1993.
68 Act 66 of 1995 as amended by Act 127 of 1998.
69 Act 22 of 1994 as amended by Act 48 of 2003.
70 Act 58 of 1962.
71 Children’s Act 38 of 2005.
72 Act 99 of 1998.
73 Act 116 of 1998.
74 Berman G, and Feinblatt, J (2001) Problem-solving courts: A brief primer Law and Policy
23(2):125–40 at 125.
75 See Currie and De Waal (2001) 279–80.
76 See Klug (2010) 237–8.
77 S 168(3) of the Constitution.
78 S 167(3) of the Constitution.
79 However, the Constitution Seventeenth Amendment Act 72 of 2013, available at
https://www.justice.gov.za/legislation/acts/const17th_2013gg36128no72.pdf, changes this
state of affairs.
80 See s 167(3) of the Constitution before it was amended.
81 S 167(3)(b) of the Constitution. See Alexkor Ltd and Another v Richtersveld Community and
Others (CCT19/03) [2003] ZACC 18; 2004 (5) SA 460 (CC); 2003 (12) BCLR 1301 (CC) (14
October 2003) para 24 where the Court had to deal with the interpretation of the
Restitution of Land Rights Act 22 of 1994 in dealing with questions about the Richtersveld
community’s rights to the land, but stated that it would also be necessary to deal with non-
constitutional matters:
A more difficult question is to determine whether this Court has jurisdiction to deal
with all issues bearing on or related to establishing the existence of these matters.
For example, the question might be asked whether the issue concerning the
existence of the Community’s rights in land prior to the colonisation of the Cape, or
the content or incidence of such rights, constitute in themselves ‘constitutional
matters’; the same might be asked concerning the continued existence of such
rights after the British Crown’s annexation of the Cape in 1806, or after the 1847
Proclamation or the subsequent statutory and other acts thereafter.
82 S 167(7) of the Constitution.
83 (CCT31/99) [2000] ZACC 1; 2000 (2) SA 674; 2000 (3) BCLR 241 (25 February 2000) para 44.
84 Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic Offences and Others v Hyundai Motor
Distributors (Pty) Ltd and Others In re: Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd and Others v
Smit NO and Others (CCT1/00) [2000] ZACC 12; 2000 (10) BCLR 1079; 2001 (1) SA 545 (CC)
(25 August 2000) para 24.
85 See Currie, I and De Waal, J (2005) The Bill of Rights Handbook 5th ed 66.
86 Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security (CCT 48/00) [2001] ZACC 22; 2001 (4) SA 938
(CC); 2001 (10) BCLR 995 (CC) (16 August 2001) para 33; see also para 36. See also Thebus
and Another v S (CCT36/02) [2003] ZACC 12; 2003 (6) SA 505 (CC); 2003 (10) BCLR 1100
(CC) (28 August 2003) para 25; K v Minister of Safety and Security (CCT52/04) [2005] ZACC
8; 2005 (6) SA 419 (CC); 2005 (9) BCLR 835 (CC); [2005] 8 BLLR 749 (CC) (13 June 2005)
para 15; Masiya v Director of Public Prosecutions Pretoria (The State) and Another
(CCT54/06) [2007] ZACC 9; 2007 (5) SA 30 (CC); 2007 (8) BCLR 827 (10 May 2007) para 33;
Barkhuizen v Napier (CCT72/05) [2007] ZACC 5; 2007 (5) SA 323 (CC); 2007 (7) BCLR 691
(CC) (4 April 2007) para 35. Some commentators have wrongly taken issue with this
interpretation, arguing that the Constitution accords the spirit, purport and objects of the
Bill of Rights only a secondary role to serve as a tie-breaker when the rights in the Bill of
Rights, justice and the rules of the common law are indeterminate. See Fagan, A (2010) The
secondary role of the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights in the common law’s
development South African Law Journal 127(4):611–27. Fagan has been criticised by Davis,
who argues that the Constitution intended that the common law reflect the normative
value system as found in a holistic reading of the text of the Constitution. This means that
the trigger that propels judges to make the decision to develop the common law is to be
found in a judicial engagement with the constitutional value system. See Davis, DM (2012)
How many positivist legal philosophers can be made to dance on the head of a pin? A reply
to Professor Fagan South African Law Journal 129(1):59–72.
87 See S v Boesak (CCT25/00) [2000] ZACC 25; 2001 (1) BCLR 36; 2001 (1) SA 912 (1 December
2000) para 14.
88 Pharmaceutical Manufacturers para 20.
89 Carmichele para 54.
90 See ss 172(1) and 167(4)(a) of the Constitution. See also Boesak para 14.
91 National Education Health & Allied Workers Union (NEHAWU) v University of Cape Town
and Others (CCT2/02) [2002] ZACC 27; 2003 (2) BCLR 154; 2003 (3) SA 1 (CC) (6 December
2002) para 14; Alexkor para 23; Bato Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v Minister of Environmental
Affairs and Tourism and Others (CCT 27/03) [2004] ZACC 15; 2004 (4) SA 490 (CC); 2004 (7)
BCLR 687 (CC) (12 March 2004) para 25.
92 Act 4 of 2000.
93 MEC for Education: Kwazulu-Natal and Others v Pillay (CCT 51/06) [2007] ZACC 21; 2008
(1) SA 474 (CC); 2008 (2) BCLR 99 (CC) (5 October 2007).
94 S 167(3)(b)(ii) of the Constitution.
95 S 167(3)(c) of the Constitution.
96 S v Boesak (CCT25/00) [2000] ZACC 25; 2001 (1) BCLR 36; 2001 (1) SA 912 (1 December
2000) para 15.
97 Paulsen and Another v Slip Knot Investments 777 (Pty) Limited (CCT 61/14) [2015] ZACC 5;
2015 (3) SA 479 (CC); 2015 (5) BCLR 509 (CC) (24 March 2015) paras 21 and 22.
98 Paulsen para 26. See generally Harms, D Does the Constitutional Court have plenary
(unlimited) appeal jurisdiction? De Rebus in 2017 (April)13.
99 Paulsen para 30.
100 Boesak para 15.
101 (CCT25/00) [2000] ZACC 25; 2001 (1) BCLR 36; 2001 (1) SA 912 (1 December 2000).
102 S v Boesak (105/99) [2000] ZASCA 24 (12 May 2000).
103 Boesak para 15.
104 S 167(5) of the Constitution.
105 (CCT13/09) [2009] ZACC 20; 2009 (6) SA 94 (CC) (22 July 2009) para 15. See also Economic
Freedom Fighters v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others; Democratic Alliance v
Speaker of the National Assembly and Others (CCT 143/15; CCT 171/15) [2016] ZACC 11;
2016 (5) BCLR 618 (CC); 2016 (3) SA 580 (CC) (31 March 2016) para 18 where the
Constitutional Court held: ‘But where the Constitution imposes the primary obligation on
Parliament and leaves it at large to determine what would be required of it to execute its
mandate, then crucial political questions are likely to arise which would entail an intrusion
into sensitive areas of separation of powers. When this is the case, then the demands for
this Court to exercise its exclusive jurisdiction would have been met.’
106 S 167(4)(a) of the Constitution.
107 S 167(4)(b) of the Constitution.
108 S 167(4)(c) of the Constitution.
109 S 80(2)(a) of the Constitution.
110 S 122(2)(a) of the Constitution.
111 Ss 80(2)(b) and 122(2)(b) of the Constitution.
112 S 167(4)(d) of the Constitution.
113 (CCT23/02) [2002] ZACC 21; 2003 (1) SA 495; 2002 (11) BCLR 1179 (4 October 2002) para
12.
114 UDM para 12.
115 (CCT36/95) [1995] ZACC 10; 1995 (12) BCLR 1561; 1996 (1) SA 769 (29 November 1995)
para 47.
116 S 167(4)(e) of the Constitution.
117 President of the Republic of South Africa and Others v South African Rugby Football Union
and Others (SARFU I) (CCT16/98) [1998] ZACC 21; 1999 (2) SA 14; 1999 (2) BCLR 175 (2
December 1998) para 25.
118 Women’s Legal Trust para 11.
119 EFF para 18.
120 Women’s Legal Trust para 12.
121 See generally Doctors for Life International v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others
(CCT12/05) [2006] ZACC 11; 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC); 2006 (6) SA 416 (CC) (17 August
2006).
122 At para 24.
123 See Certification of the Kwazulu-Natal Constitution (CCT15/96) [1996] ZACC 17; 1996 (11)
BCLR 1419; 1996 (4) SA 1098 (6 September 1996); Certification of the Constitution of the
Western Cape, 1997 (CCT6/97) [1997] ZACC 8; 1997 (4) SA 795 (CC); 1997 (9) BCLR 1167
(CC)(2 September 1997); Certification of the Amended Text of the Constitution of the
Western Cape, 1997 (CCT29/97) [1997] ZACC 15; 1997 (12) BCLR 1653; 1998 (1) SA 655 (18
November 1997).
124 Bruce and Another v Fleecytex Johannesburg CC and Others (CCT1/98) [1998] ZACC 3; 1998
(2) SA 1143; 1998 (4) BCLR 415 (24 March 1998) para 9. See also Van der Spuy v General
Council of the Bar of South Africa (CCT48/01) [2002] ZACC 17; 2002 (5) SA 392; 2002 (10)
BCLR 1092 (18 July 2002) para 6; National Gambling Board v Premier of KwaZulu-Natal
and Others (CCT32/01) [2001] ZACC 8; 2002 (2) BCLR 156; 2002 (2) SA 715 (21 December
2001) para 29; Moseneke and Others v Master of the High Court (CCT51/00) [2000] ZACC 27;
2001 (2) BCLR 103; 2001 (2) SA 18 (6 December 2000) paras 18–9; Dormehl v Minister of
Justice and Others (CCT10/00) [2000] ZACC 4; 2000 (2) SA 825; 2000 (5) BCLR 471 (CC) (14
April 2000) para 5; Christian Education South Africa v Minister of Education (CCT13/98)
[1998] ZACC 16; 1999 (2) SA 83; 1998 (12) BCLR 1449 (14 October 1998) paras 3–4; Minister
of Justice v Ntuli (CCT15/97, CCT17/95) [1997] ZACC 7; 1997 (6) BCLR 677; 1997 (3) SA 772
(5 June 1997) para 4; Transvaal Agricultural Union v Minister of Land Affairs and Another
(CCT21/96) [1996] ZACC 22; 1996 (12) BCLR 1573; 1997 (2) SA 621 (18 November 1996)
para 16; Brink v Kitshoff NO (CCT15/95) [1996] ZACC 9; 1996 (4) SA 197; 1996 (6) BCLR 752
(15 May 1996) para 3; Besserglik v Minister of Trade Industry and Tourism and Others
(Minister of Justice intervening) (CCT34/95) [1996] ZACC 8; 1996 (6) BCLR 745; 1996 (4) SA
331 (14 May 1996) paras 4–6; Luitingh v Minister of Defence (CCT29/95) [1996] ZACC 5;
1996 (4) BCLR 581; 1996 (2) SA 909 (4 April 1996) para 15; S v Mbatha, S v Prinsloo
(CCT19/95, CCT35/95) [1996] ZACC 1; 1996 (3) BCLR 293; 1996 (2) SA 464 (9 February
1996) para 29; Executive Council of the Western Cape Legislature and Others v President of
the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT27/95) [1995] ZACC 8; 1995 (10) BCLR 1289;
1995 (4) SA 877 (22 September 1995) paras 15–7; S v Zuma and Others (CCT5/94) [1995]
ZACC 1; 1995 (2) SA 642; 1995 (4) BCLR 401 (SA); 1995 (1) SACR 568; [1996] 2 CHRLD 244
(5 April 1995) para 11.
125 S v Bequinot (CCT24/95) [1996] ZACC 21; 1996 (12) BCLR 1588; 1997 (2) SA 887 (18
November 1996) para 15; See also Carmichele para 50.
126 Bruce para 8.
127 Transvaal Agricultural Union para 20.
128 AParty and Another v The Minister for Home Affairs and Others, Moloko and Others v The
Minister for Home Affairs and Another (CCT 06/09, CCT 10/09) [2009] ZACC 4; 2009 (3) SA
649 (CC); 2009 (6) BCLR 611 (CC) (12 March 2009) para 30.
129 Bruce para 9. See also Van der Spuy para 6; National Gambling Board para 29; Moseneke
paras 18–9; Dormehl para 5; Christian Education paras 3–4; Ntuli para 4; Transvaal
Agricultural Union para 16; Brink para 3; Besserglik paras 4–6; Luitingh para 15; Mbatha,
Prinsloo para 29; Executive Council of the Western Cape Legislature paras 15–7; Zuma para
11.
130 Bruce paras 7–8. See also AParty para 29.
131 S 167(3)(c) of the Constitution.
132 Currie and De Waal (2005) 111.
133 S 168(3)(a) of the Constitution.
134 See Islamic Unity Convention v Independent Broadcasting Authority and Others
(CCT36/01)) [2002] ZACC 3; 2002 (4) SA 294 (CC) 2002 (5) BCLR 433 (11 April 2002) para
17; De Reuck v Director of Public Prosecutions (Witwatersrand Local Division) and Others
(CCT5/03) [2003] ZACC 19; 2004 (1) SA 406 (CC); 2003 (12) BCLR 1333 (CC) (15 October
2003) para 4.
135 See Amod v Multilateral Motor Vehicle Accidents Fund (CCT4/98) [1998] ZACC 11; 1998 (4)
SA 753; 1998 (10) BCLR 1207 (27 August 1998) para 33.
136 (CCT54/06) [2007] ZACC 9; 2007 (5) SA 30 (CC); 2007 (8) BCLR 827 (10 May 2007) para 17.
137 National Gambling Board para 38; Wallach v High Court of South Africa (Witwatersrand
Local Division) and Others (CCT2/03) [2003] ZACC 6; 2003 (5) SA 273 (CC) (4 April 2003)
para 7.
138 (CCT4/98) [1998] ZACC 11; 1998 (4) SA 753; 1998 (10) BCLR 1207 (27 August 1998) para 33.
139 S 169(1)(a) of the Constitution.
140 S 167(5) of the Constitution.
141 See Currie and De Waal (2005) 122.
142 Act 32 of 1944.
143 Wesson and Du Plessis (2008) 191.
144 See also O’Regan, K (2004) Human rights and democracy – a new global debate:
Reflections on the first ten years of South Africa’s Constitutional Court International
Journal of Legal Information 32(2):200–16 at 202.
145 See S and Others v Van Rooyen and Others (General Council of the Bar of South Africa
Intervening) (CCT21/01) [2002] ZACC 8; 2002 (5) SA 246; 2002 (8) BCLR 810 (11 June 2002)
para 27.
146 See Constitution of Kenya (2010) item 23 in Schedule 6, which states:
(1) Within one year after the effective date, Parliament shall enact legislation …
establishing mechanisms and procedures for vetting, within a timeframe to be
determined in the legislation, the suitability of all judges and magistrates who were
in office on the effective date to continue to serve in accordance with the values and
principles set out in [the Constitution] …
(2) A removal, or a process leading to the removal, of a judge, from office by virtue
of the operation of legislation contemplated under subsection (1) shall not be
subject to question in, or review by, any court.
147 De Lange, R and Mevis, PAM (2007) Constitutional guarantees for the independence of the
judiciary Electronic Journal of Comparative Law 11(1):1–17 at 7.
148 See Ntlama, N (2011) The Hlophe saga: the question for the institutional integrity of the
judiciary US-China Law Review 8(8):758–99 at 772.
149 Zuma para 17.
150 See also s 39(1)(b) and (c) of the Constitution which requires the court to take into account
international law and allows the court to take into account foreign case law when
interpreting the provisions of the Bill of Rights.
151 De Vos, P (2001) A bridge too far? History as context in the interpretation of the South
African Constitution South African Journal on Human Rights 17(1):1–33 at 6.
152 (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3; 1995 (6) BCLR 665; 1995 (3) SA 391; [1996] 2 CHRLD 164; 1995
(2) SACR 1 (6 June 1995).
153 Klare, K (1998) Legal culture and transformative constitutionalism South African Journal on
Human Rights 14(1):146–88 at 173. See also Makwanyane para 207, per Kriegler J.
154 Makwanyane para 321, per O’Regan J; para 207, per Kriegler J; para 266, per Mahomed J;
para 382, per Sachs J.
155 See Klare (1998) 172–87 for examples of this kind of reasoning by the judges of the
Constitutional Court.
156 (CCT16/98) [1999] ZACC 9; 1999 (4) SA 147; 1999 (7) BCLR 725 (4 June 1999) para 48.
157 (CCT21/01) [2002] ZACC 8; 2002 (5) SA 246; 2002 (8) BCLR 810 (11 June 2002).
158 Van Rooyen para 19. See also De Lange v Smuts NO and Others (CCT26/97) [1998] ZACC 6;
1998 (3) SA 785 (CC); 1998 (7) BCLR 779 (CC) (28 May 1998) para 71.
159 Van Rooyen para 22.
160 Van Rooyen para 32.
161 Van Rooyen para 33.
162 Van Rooyen para 32.
163 See Lewis, C (2008, 15 October) The troubled state of South Africa’s judiciary, Paper
presented at the South African Institute of Race Relations, available at
http://www.politicsweb.co.za/politicsweb/view/politicsweb/en/page71619?
oid=106544&sn=Detail. See also Currie and De Waal (2001) 300.
164 See Larkins, CM (1996) Judicial independence and democratization: A theoretical and
conceptual analysis American Journal of Comparative Law 44(4):605–25 at 611.
165 Larkins (1996) 611.
166 Van Rooyen paras 22 and 31.
167 For example, after Judge Chris Nicholson found that there was political interference in the
decision to charge Jacob Zuma for corruption in Zuma v National Director of Public
Prosecutions (8652/08) [2008] ZAKZHC 71; [2009] 1 All SA 54 (N); 2009 (1) BCLR 62 (N) (12
September 2008), the NEC of the ANC decided to ‘recall’ then President Thabo Mbeki as
President of South Africa. The judgment therefore had a profound and immediate effect on
who headed up the executive and thus who governed the country.
168 Wesson and Du Plessis (2008) 191.
169 Wesson and Du Plessis (2008) 192.
170 Act 9 of 1994.
171 See Malleson, K (1999) Assessing the performance of the Judicial Service Commission
South African Law Journal 116(1):36–49 at 38.
172 S 178(1)(a)–( j) of the Constitution. See generally Davis (2010, December) 41 and Mgkoro
(2010, December) 43.
173 For an extensive discussion about the political influence on the JSC, see Powell, C and
Franco. J (2004) The meaning of institutional independence in Van Rooyen v S, South
African Law Journal 121(3):562–79 at 562.
174 Helen Suzman Foundation v Judicial Service Commission (CCT289/16) [2018] ZACC 8; 2018
(4) SA 1 (CC); 2018 (7) BCLR 763 (CC) (24 April 2018) paras 34 and 37.
175 S 178(1) of the Constitution.
176 Acting Chairperson: Judicial Service Commission and Others v Premier of the Western Cape
Province (537/10) [2011] ZASCA 53; 2011 (3) SA 538 (SCA); [2011] 3 All SA 459 (SCA) (31
March 2011) para 12 where Harms AJ stated that:
it would be inconsistent and illogical for the Constitution to provide for a Premier to
participate in the appointment of a high court judge – and, as I have said, the JSC
agrees that a Premier is included for this purpose – but not in a decision to remove
such a judge. Both affect the composition of the bench of a particular high court.
177 Davis (2010, December) 41; Wesson and Du Plessis (2008) 193; Kentridge, S (2003) The
highest court: Selecting the judges Cambridge Law Journal 62(1):55–71 at 55.
178 See, for example, McKaiser, E (2009, 6 August) Tragicomedy revealed more about JSC than
about judges Business Day in which the author takes the JSC to task for its inability to probe
any of these key questions when the JSC last year conducted interviews for four vacancies
on the Constitutional Court. See also De Vos, P (2013, 21 January) Judicial appointments:
The JSC’s transformation problem Constitutionally Speaking, available at
http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/judicial-appointments-the-jscs-transformation-
problem/.
179 (CCT289/16) [2018] ZACC 8; 2018 (4) SA 1 (CC); 2018 (7) BCLR 763 (CC) (24 April 2018).
180 Helen Suzman Foundation para 3.
181 Helen Suzman Foundation para 42.
182 Helen Suzman Foundation para 38.
183 Helen Suzman Foundation para 40.
184 S 174(3) of the Constitution.
185 S 174(3) of the Constitution.
186 See Gauntlett, J and Du Plessis, M (2011, 25 August) Ex Parte: Freedom under Law, in re:
The Appointment of the Chief Justice Memorandum 10–11 Constitutionally Speaking,
available at http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/ful-proposes-changes-to-appointment-
of-chief-justice/.
187 S 174(4) of the Constitution.
188 S 174(4)(a) of the Constitution.
189 S 174(4)(b) and (c) of the Constitution.
190 S 174(5) of the Constitution.
191 S 174(6) of the Constitution.
192 Helen Suzman Foundation paras 34.
193 S 174(1) and 174(2) of the Constitution.
194 See Judicial Service Commission, Summary of the Criteria Used by the Judicial Service
Commission when Considering Candidates for Judicial Appointments, available at
http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/criteria-used-by-jsc-when-considering-judicial-
appointments/.
195 Cowen, S (2013) Judicial selection in South Africa, Democratic Governance Rights Unit
(DGRU) Working Paper Series 15, available at
http://www.dgru.uct.ac.za/usr/dgru/downloads/Judicial%20SelectionOct2010.pdf.
196 S 165(2) of the Constitution.
197 In an address to the International Commission of Jurists in Cape Town on 21 July 1998 5.
198 See Mogoeng, M (2014, 29 April) `The role of Constitutional and Supreme Courts in the
protection of the constitutional order’, speech given at the second congress of the
Association of Asian Constitutional Courts and Equivalent Institutions held in Istanbul
Turkey on 29 April 2014.
199 See s 1(a) of the Constitution.
200 Cowen (2013) 57.
201 Forsyth, C (1991) Interpreting a bill of rights: The future task of a reformed judiciary South
African Journal on Human Rights 7(1):1–23 at 15–17.
202 See generally Pruitt, LR (2002) No black names on the letterhead? Efficient discrimination
and the South African legal profession Michigan Journal of International Law 23(3):545–
676.
203 See, for example, Davis, RPB (1914) Women as advocates and attorneys South African Law
Journal 31(4):383–86 at 384 for an example of early discriminatory attitudes towards
women in the legal profession in South Africa:
We cannot but think the common law wise in excluding women from the profession
of law … the law of nature destines and qualifies the female sex for the bearing and
nurture of children and our race and for the custody of the world … all life-long
callings of women, inconsistent with these radical and sacred duties of their sex, as
is the profession of law, are departures from the order of nature and when voluntary
treason against it. The cruel chances of life sometime baffle both sexes and may
leave women free from peculiar duties of their sex … but it is public policy to
provide for the sex not for its superfluous members; and not to tempt women from
the proper duties of their sex by opening to them duties peculiar to ours.
204 See De Vos, P (2013, 11 April) The JSC must redefine merit to advance judicial
transformation Constitutionally Speaking, available at
http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/the-jsc-must-redefine-merit-to-advance-judicial-
transformation/.
205 See Lewis (2008, 14 October) 2.
206 Cowen (2013) 66.
207 Davis (2010, December) 42.
208 For divergent perspectives, see Mkhabela, M (2011, 19 August) Judiciary must be de-
politicised The Sowetan, available at
http://www.sowetanlive.co.za/columnists/2011/08/19/judiciary-must-be-de-politicised;
Hoffman, P (2011, 2 December) To judge the judgments Mail & Guardian, available at
http://mg.co.za/article/2011-12-02-to-judge-the-judgments.
209 Cowen (2013) 69.
210 (818/2011) [2012] ZASCA 115; 2012 (11) BCLR 1239 (SCA); 2013 (1) SA 170 (SCA); [2013] 1
All SA 40 (SCA) (14 September 2012), affirming the decision of the Western Cape High
Court in Cape Bar Council v Judicial Service Commission and Others (11897/2011) [2011]
ZAWCHC 388; 2012 (4) BCLR 406 (WCC); [2012] 2 All SA 143 (WCC) (30 September 2011).
211 Cape Bar Council paras 20–2.
212 Cape Bar Council para 36.
213 Cape Bar Council paras 43–4.
214 Cowen (2013) 71–73.
215 S 174(8) of the Constitution states: ‘Before judicial officers begin to perform their functions,
they must take an oath or affirm, in accordance with Schedule 2, that they will uphold and
protect the Constitution.’
216 Currie and De Waal (2001) 305.
217 See ss 176 and 177.
218 S 176 was amended by the Constitution Sixth Amendment Act 34 of 2001.
219 Act 47 of 2001.
220 The amendment was widely seen as a move to extend the term of office of then Chief
Justice Arthur Chaskalson who was coming to the end of his term of office. See Du Bois, F
(2002) Tenure on the Constitutional Court South African Law Journal 119(1):1–17 who
criticised the amendment of s 176 of the Constitution as well as the provisions of the
Judges’ Remuneration and Conditions of Employment Act and referred to a submission
made to Parliament at the time when it was debating this issue. The article also notes
critical comments made by then Chief Justice Chaskalson about moves to extend his term.
221 (CCT 53/11, CCT 54/11, CCT 62/11) [2011] ZACC 23; 2011 (5) SA 388 (CC); 2011 (10) BCLR
1017 (CC) (29 July 2011).
222 Justice Alliance para 50.
223 Justice Alliance para 51.
224 Justice Alliance para 67.
225 Justice Alliance para 68.
226 Justice Alliance para 73.
227 Justice Alliance para 75.
228 Justice Alliance paras 79–80.
229 Justice Alliance para 91.
230 S 176(2) of the Constitution.
231 S 177(3) of the Constitution.
232 S 8 of the JSC Act.
233 Ss 14 and 15 of the JSC Act.
234 S 15(2) of the JSC Act.
235 S 17 of the JSC Act.
236 S 22 of the JSC Act.
237 S 33 of the JSC Act.
238 (2011 (3) SA 549 (SCA); [2011] 3 All SA 513 (SCA)) [2011] ZASCA 59; 52/2011 (31 March
2011).
239 Freedom Under Law para 7.
240 Freedom Under Law para 63.
241 Freedom Under Law para 42.
242 Freedom Under Law para 45.
243 S 176(3) of the Constitution.
244 Established under s 2 of the Independent Commission for the Remuneration of Public
Office-bearers Act 92 of 1997.
245 Ss 2(6) and 14 of the Judges’ Remuneration and Conditions of Employment Act.
246 See generally Currie and De Waal (2001) 307.
247 1945 AD 6.
248 1981 (1) SA 1 (A).
249 Currie and De Waal (2001) 307.
250 Act 10 of 2013.
251 If it is sought to serve process out of a magistrates’ court, then the litigant must obtain the
prior permission of that division of the Supreme Court which has appeal jurisdiction over
the magistrates’ court in question.
252 Currie and De Waal (2001) 308.
253 S 5 of the Constitutional Court Complementary Act 13 of 1995.
254 S 165(6) of the Constitution states: ‘The Chief Justice is the head of the judiciary and
exercises responsibility over the establishment and monitoring of norms and standards for
the exercise of the judicial functions of all courts.’
255 Act 103 of 1994, Proclamation 44 of 2010, amending Schedule 1.
256 Act 10 of 2013.
257 S 8 of the Superior Courts Act.
258 See ‘Office of the Chief Justice Annual Report 2018/19’, p 18, accessed on 20 October 2019 at
https://www.judiciary.org.za/images/Annual-Reports/OCJ_Annual_Report_2018-19.pdf.
259 See generally Currie and De Waal (2001) 308–10.
260 See s 9(1)(b) of the Magistrates’ Courts Act which sets out the necessary qualifications for
appointment as a magistrate. See generally Van Rooyen.
261 Act 111 of 1984.
262 Currie and De Waal (2001) 308.
263 Hoexter Commission of Inquiry into the Structure and Functioning of the Courts (1983) RP
78/83 Part IV para 4.2.1 (g).
264 Act 90 of 1993.
265 Van Rooyen para 49.
266 Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (CCT 23/96) [1996]
ZACC 26; 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC) (6 September 1996) para 136.
267 See s 3 of the Magistrates Act.
268 Van Rooyen para 57.
269 Van Rooyen para 61.
270 S 3(1)(a) of the Magistrates Act.
271 Van Rooyen para 40.
272 South African Law Commission (2003) Customary Law: Report on Traditional Courts and
the Judicial Function of Traditional Leaders Project 90 1, accessed on 25 January 2013 at
http://www.justice.gov.za/salrc/reports/r_prj90_tradlead_2003jan.pdf.
273 See, for example, the Black Administration Act 38 of 1927, the Bophuthatswana Traditional
Courts Act 29 of 1979, the KwaNdebele Traditional Authorities Act 8 of 1984, the Chiefs
Courts Act 6 of 1993 (Transkei) and the KwaZulu Amakhosi and Iziphakanyiswa Act 9 of
1990.
274 Act 38 of 1927. Most sections of this law have been repealed, but these sections are some of
the few that were retained and continue to be in operation.
275 Section 16 of Schedule 6 of the Constitution reads as follows:
Every court, including courts of traditional leaders, existing when the new
Constitution took effect, continues to function and to exercise jurisdiction in terms
of the legislation applicable to it, and anyone holding office as a judicial officer
continues to hold office in terms of legislation applicable to that office, subject to (a)
any amendment or repeal of that legislation; and (b) consistency with the new
Constitution.
276 S 211(1) of the Constitution states: ‘The institution, status and role of traditional leadership,
according to customary law, are recognised, subject to the Constitution.’
277 S 212(1) of the Constitution.
278 Western Cape Provincial Government and Others In Re: DVB Behuising (Pty) Limited v
North West Provincial Government and Another (CCT22/99) [2000] ZACC 2; 2000 (4) BCLR
347; 2001 (1) SA 500 (2 March 2000) para 1. See also Moseneke paras 20–1 where the
Constitutional Court described the BAA as follows:
The Act systematised and enforced a colonial form of relationship between a
dominant white minority who were to have rights of citizenship and a subordinate
black majority who were to be administered. … It is painful that the Act still survives
at all. The concepts on which it was based, the memories it evokes, the language it
continues to employ, and the division it still enforces, are antithetical to the society
envisaged by the Constitution. It is an affront to all of us that people are still treated
as ‘blacks’ rather than as ordinary persons seeking to wind up a deceased estate,
and it is in conflict with the establishment of a non-racial society where rights and
duties are no longer determined by origin or skin colour.
279 S 12(4) of the BAA provides for appeals from judgments of a chief, headman or chief’s
deputy in a civil matter, while s 20(6) provides for appeals from a chief, headmen or chief’s
deputy in a criminal matter. In each case the appeal goes to the magistrates’ court. See also
Bennett, TW (2004) Customary Law in South Africa 127.
280 SALC (2003) Report on Traditional Courts and the Judicial Function of Traditional Leaders
5.
281 See s 28(1) of the Traditional Leadership and Governance Framework Act 41 of 2003
(TLGFA).
282 Ss 12 and 20 of the BAA.
283 SALC (2003) Report on Traditional Courts and the Judicial Function of Traditional Leaders
6.
284 Mnisi Weeks, S (2011) Beyond the Traditional Courts Bill: Regulating customary courts in
line with living customary law and the Constitution South African Crime Quarterly
35(31):32.
285 S 165(2) of the Constitution. See Bennet (2004) 117. This argument was rejected in
Bangindawo v Head of the Nyanda Regional Authority; Hlantlalala v Head of the Western
Tembuland Regional Authority (1998) 3 BCLR 314 (Tk). However, in Mhlekwa & Feni v Head
of the Western Tembuland Regional Authority 2000 (9) BCLR 979 (Tk) 1017–18, the Court
held that the fact that there is a fusion of judicial and administrative functions does not
necessarily denote an absence of judicial independence. Some of the functions performed
by chiefs are such that they may potentially involve him or her in controversial public
issues and may create a perception of an unduly close relationship with the executive
branch of government. The Court implored the legislature to address this problem.
286 Bennet (2004) 128.
287 See the Attorney-General Act 92 of 1992, which came into operation on 30 December 1992.
288 Zyl Smit, D and Steyn, E (2000) Prosecuting Authority in the New South Africa CIJL YB
8:137–55 at 143.
289 See JA van S d’Oliveira SC (1993) The Office of the Attorney-General Nuntius 70.
290 The salary of an attorney-general could no longer be reduced, except through an act of
Parliament. (Section 3(1)(b) of Act 92 of 1992).
291 S 4 of Act 92 of 1992 provided such security.
292 Van Zyl Smit and Steyn (2000) 145.
293 S 20 of the NPA Act.
294 S 179(5)(c) of the Constitution and s 22(2)(b) of the NPA Act.
295 S 179(5)(a) of the Constitution and s 22(2)(a) of the NPA Act.
296 Van Zyl Smit and Steyn (2000) 146.
297 NPA Prosecution Policy, revised June 2013, accessed on 24 October 2019 at
https://www.npa.gov.za/sites/default/files/Library/Prosecution%20Policy%20%28Final%2
0as%20Revised%20in%20June%202013.%2027%20Nov%202014%29.pdf.
298 See Downer, B ( 2010, 24 September) Address to the Middle Temple South African
Conference on The Rule of Law and Prosecutions: To Prosecute or not to Prosecute: A
South African Perspective.
299 See, for instance, the references to the Ontario Crown Prosecuting manual in McGoey, C
(2004, March) ‘The ‘Good’ Criminal Law Barrister: A Crown Perspective’ Second Colloquia
on the Legal Profession, Canada, March, 2004 4–7.
300 S 179(5)(d) of the Constitution and s 22(1)(c) of the NPA Act.
301 Van Zyl Smit and Steyn (2000) 148.
302 National Director of Public Prosecutions and Others v Freedom Under Law (67/2014) [2014]
ZASCA 58; 2014 (4) SA 298 (SCA); 2014 (2) SACR 107 (SCA); [2014] 4 All SA 147 (SCA) (17
April 2014) para 51.
303 Democratic Alliance v President of South Africa and Others (CCT 122/11) [2012] ZACC 24;
2012 (12) BCLR 1297 (CC); 2013 (1) SA 248 (CC) (5 October 2012) para 13.
304 (CCT 333/17; CCT 13/18) [2018] ZACC 23; 2018 (10) BCLR 1179 (CC); 2018 (2) SACR 442
(CC) (13 August 2018) para 19.
305 National Director of Public Prosecutions v Zuma (573/08) [2009] ZASCA 1; 2009 (2) SA 277
(SCA); 2009 (1) SACR 361 (SCA); 2009 (4) BCLR 393 (SCA); [2009] 2 All SA 243 (SCA) (12
January 2009).
306 Ibid para 32.
307 S 32(1)(a) of the NPA Act. See also National Director of Public Prosecutions v Zuma (573/08)
[2009] ZASCA 1; 2009 (2) SA 277 (SCA); 2009 (1) SACR 361 (SCA); 2009 (4) BCLR 393 (SCA);
[2009] 2 All SA 243 (SCA) (12 January 2009) para 34; and S v Yengeni [2005] ZAGPHC 117;
2006 (1) SACR 405 (T).
308 S 32(1)(b) of the NPA Act.
309 S 41(1) of the NPA Act.
310 S 33(1) of the NPA Act.
311 S 33(2) of the NPA Act.
312 See Woolayer, H and Bishop, M Submission to the Inquiry into the NDPP: South African
Institute for Advanced Constitutional, Public, Human Rights and International 40; See also
Zuma v National Director of Public Prosecutions, Natal Provincial Division (8652/08) [2008]
ZAKZHC 71; [2009] 1 All SA 54 (N); 2009 (1) BCLR 62 (N) (12 September 2008) para 137.
(The ‘Nicholson Judgment’), in agreement, at 90.
313 National Director of Public Prosecutions v Zuma (573/08) [2009] ZASCA 1; 2009 (2) SA 277
(SCA); 2009 (1) SACR 361 (SCA); 2009 (4) BCLR 393 (SCA); [2009] 2 All SA 243 (SCA) (12
January 2009) para 37.
314 Democratic Alliance v President of South Africa and Others (CCT 122/11) [2012] ZACC 24;
2012 (12) BCLR 1297 (CC); 2013 (1) SA 248 (CC) (5 October 2012) para 26.
315 Van Zyl Smit and Steyn (2000) 144; Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South
Africa, 1996 (CCT 23/96) [1996] ZACC 26; 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC)
(6 September 1996) para 141.
316 Certification case para 146.
317 ‘Restoring the Independence of the Prosecutorial Authority in South Africa’ (2019, 19
February), accessed on 21 October 2019 at https://www.lssa.org.za/news-headlines/press-
releases/restoring-the-independence-of-the-prosecutorial-authority-in-south-africa.
318 Certification case para 141.
319 Certification case para 141.
320 (62470/2015) [2017] ZAGPPHC 743; [2018] 1 All SA 471 (GP); 2018 (1) SACR 317 (GP) (8
December 2017).
321 Corruption Watch paras 112 and 114.
322 Corruption Watch para 128.
323 S 12(6)(a) of the NPA Act.
324 S 12(6)(a) of the NPA Act, read with s 12(6)(e).
325 S 12(6)(c) of the NPA Act
326 S 7 of the NPA Act.
327 (CCT 333/17; CCT 13/18) [2018] ZACC 23; 2018 (10) BCLR 1179 (CC); 2018 (2) SACR 442
(CC) (13 August 2018).
328 S 12(8) of the NPA Act.
329 Corruption Watch para 23.
330 Corruption Watch paras 25–8.
Separation of powers and Chapter
9 institutions
7.1 Introduction
Summary
7.1 Introduction
Figure 7.1 Separation of powers and Chapter 9 institutions
The Public Protector also has the additional powers and functions
prescribed by national legislation.62 It is important to note that the
Public Protector Act63 also allows the Public Protector to investigate
matters on his or her own initiative. While the Public Protector mostly
investigates complaints received from the public, he or she need not
wait for a complaint to be lodged before investigating a matter.64 This
was confirmed by the Supreme Court of Appeal, which held that:
The Act makes it clear that while the functions of the Public Protector include
those that are ordinarily associated with an ombudsman they also go much
beyond that. The Public Protector is not a passive adjudicator between citizens
and the state, relying upon evidence that is placed before him or her before
acting. His or her mandate is an investigatory one, requiring pro-action in
appropriate circumstances. Although the Public Protector may act upon
complaints that are made, he or she may also take the initiative to commence
an enquiry, and on no more than ‘information that has come to his or her
knowledge’ of maladministration, malfeasance or impropriety in public life.65
The Court held that the Public Protector’s power to take remedial action
is primarily sourced in the Constitution – not in the Public Protector
Act.91 Whether the remedial action is binding or not was therefore a
constitutional question. The Court interpreted the relevant
constitutional provisions and held that these must be read as allowing
the Public Protector to impose ‘a proper, fitting, suitable and effective
remedy’ so as to ensure that the remedial action would cure ‘the root
cause of the complaint’.92 This requires that the remedial action be
binding in some, but not all, cases. Whether it is binding or not will
depend on the nature of the issue under investigation, the findings
made, and the particular kind of remedial action taken.93 If the remedial
action is phrased as a recommendation, it may not be binding, but
when it is phrased as an instruction it is likely to be binding. When
remedial action is binding, compliance is not optional and the remedial
action taken against those under investigation cannot be ignored
without any legal consequences.94
The fact that the remedial action imposed by the Public Protector
will often be binding does not mean that those affected by the findings
and remedial action are prohibited from inquiring into the correctness
of those aspects of the report they disagree with.95 However, those
affected are not permitted to use the inquiry to justify non-compliance
with the binding remedial action imposed by the Public Protector, as
happened in the Nkandla case. If, the inquiry conducted in this ‘parallel
process’ contradicts the finding and remedial action imposed by the
Public Protector, the only option open to those affected by the report
would be either to comply with it, or to approach a court to review and
set aside the report and the remedial action contained in it.96 As the
Constitutional Court explained when discussing the situation that arose
in the matter of the state-sponsored renovations at the former
President’s house at Nkandla:97
Only after a court of law had set aside the findings and remedial action taken by
the Public Protector would it have been open to the President to disregard the
Public Protector’s report. His difficulty here is that … he did not challenge the
report through a judicial process. He appears to have been content with the
apparent vindication of his position by the Minister’s favourable
recommendations and considered himself to have been lawfully absolved of
liability … Absent a court challenge to the Public Protector’s report, all the
President was required to do was to comply.98
The requirement that the Public Protector must respect the provisions
of the Constitution and must not intrude into the domain of the other
branches of government, may also find application in other contexts.
For example, the Constitution bestows exclusive power on the President
to appoint or remove members of his or her cabinet.122 If the Public
Protector orders the President to remove a member of the cabinet after
making a finding that he or she is guilty of maladministration, such an
order may well violate the separation of powers doctrine.
From the above it must be clear that the Public Protector has wide
powers to investigate maladministration and corruption in state affairs
and to impose effective remedial action to cure the root cause of the
complaint. Courts can review and set aside the findings and remedial
action if these do not comply with the principle of legality, which means
that the courts may play an important role in holding the Public
Protector accountable. Given, however, that the reports, findings and
remedial action of the Public Protector can be reviewed only on the
limited ground of legality, and cannot be appealed so that a court can
consider the correctness of the findings and remedial action, the courts
will not always be in a position to correct mistakes. In this sense the
Public Protector’s position differs markedly from that of the judiciary as
judicial decisions can be appealed and higher courts can overturn the
decisions of lower courts on much broader grounds than mere legality.
This means that the Public Protector is in a unique position in that his
or her findings will often be binding – just like the findings of a court –
but cannot be overturned merely because they are flawed.
SUMMARY
8.2 The division of legislative and executive power between the national and provincial spheres
of governments
8.2.1 Introduction
8.2.2 The objectives and structure of provincial government
8.2.3 Determining legislative competence: the pith and substance test
8.2.4 The resolution of conflicts between the national and provincial spheres
8.2.4.1 Conflicts related to concurrent competences set out in Schedule 4
8.2.4.2 Conflicts related to exclusive provincial competences in Schedule 5
8.2.5 National intervention in provincial administration
8.3 The division of legislative and executive power between the national and provincial and local
spheres of government
8.3.1 Introduction
8.3.2 The objectives of local government
8.3.3 The structure of local government
8.3.4 Municipal powers
8.3.4.1 Original municipal powers
8.3.4.2 Assigned municipal powers
8.3.4.3 Incidental municipal powers
8.3.5 Conflicting national, provincial and municipal laws
8.3.6 Supervision of local government
Summary
8.1.1 Introduction
An important characteristic of the Constitution is that it not only divides
power vertically between the legislative, executive and judicial
branches of government in terms of the separation of powers doctrine.
It also divides power horizontally between the national, provincial and
local spheres of government, thus establishing a quasi-federal system of
government. Section 40(1) of the Constitution provides in this respect
that ‘[i]n the Republic, government is constituted as national, provincial
and local spheres of government which are distinctive, interdependent
and interrelated’. In this chapter we deal with this horizontal division of
power.
What must be emphasised from the outset is that the term ‘sphere’
of government has replaced the previous term ‘level’ of government. An
important consequence of this change in terminology is that all spheres
have an equal constitutional status1 as it derives its authority directly
from the Constitution.2 As the Constitutional Court pointed out in City
of Cape Town and Others v Robertson and Others,3 the Constitution has
moved away from a hierarchical division of governmental power. It has
ushered in a new vision of government in which the sphere of local
government is interdependent, ‘inviolable and possesses the
constitutional latitude within which to define and express its unique
character’ subject to constraints permissible under our Constitution.4
This means, the Constitutional Court pointed out further, that:
A municipality under the Constitution is not a mere creature of statute
otherwise moribund save if imbued with power by provincial or national
legislation. A municipality enjoys ‘original’ and constitutionally entrenched
powers, functions, rights and duties that may be qualified or constrained by law
and only to the extent the Constitution permits. Now the conduct of a
municipality is not always invalid only for the reason that no legislation
authorises it. Its power may derive from the Constitution or from legislation of
a competent authority or from its own laws.5
8.2.1 Introduction
The division of legislative and executive authority between the three
spheres of government is one of the key features of the system of
multisphere government adopted in the Constitution. In this part of the
chapter, we discuss the division of legislative and executive authority
between the national and provincial spheres of government. Although
there is a large overlap between the matters over which each sphere has
legislative and executive authority, provincial executives may have
slightly different powers than provincial legislatures as additional
administrative powers may be delegated to provincial executives by the
national legislature.73 This would empower provincial executives to
exercise administrative powers in terms of such legislation even though
the provincial legislatures may not be empowered to legislate on that
matter. Nevertheless, to a large degree, provincial executives have
authority over the same subject matter as provincial legislatures. Unless
indicated otherwise, we will deal with these matters as if they overlap.
Before discussing this further, however, it will be helpful to discuss
briefly the objectives and structure of provincial government.
The Constitutional Court uses the ‘pith and substance’ test to determine
whether a Bill deals with subject matter contained in schedule 4 or 5 of
the Constitution. The ‘pith and substance’ test requires ‘the
determination of the subject-matter or the substance of the legislation,
its essence, or true purpose and effect, that is, what the [legislation] is
about’124 What complicates matters is that a Bill could have more than
one ‘pith and substance’ – in other words its true purpose could be to
achieve more than one goal. In such a case the pith and substance of
the bill relates to each one of the true purposes of the Bill. However, a
Bill may also contain other provisions dealing with matters not related
to the true purpose of the Bill. Such provisions would be incidental and
in terms of the pith and substance test for legislative competence, such
provisions which fall outside the pith and substance of the legislation
are seen as merely incidental and has no effect on determining the pith
and substance of the Bill.125 The pith and substance test was first applied
by the Constitutional Court in Ex Parte President of the Republic of
South Africa: In re Constitutionality of the Liquor Bill.126 This case
provides a good illustration of the fact that one Bill could have more
than one pith and substance, thus more than one true purpose.
In this case, Parliament passed the Liquor Bill which sought to
regulate the liquor industry comprehensively. The Bill divided the
economic activity of the liquor industry into three categories:
manufacture, distribution and retail sales. The Bill treated manufacture
and distribution as national issues and retail sales as provincial issues to
be dealt with by provincial liquor authorities. However, even in respect
of retail sales, the Bill prescribed detailed mechanisms as to how the
provincial legislatures should establish their retail licensing systems.
The President referred the Bill to the Constitutional Court in terms
of section 84(2)(c) of the Constitution, to consider the constitutionality
of the Bill. The concern was that the Bill exhaustively regulated issues
concerning manufacture and distribution and provided for the national
sphere to control the issuing of liquor licences despite the fact that
liquor licencing was an exclusive provincial competence in terms of
Schedule 5 of the Constitution. Parliament contended that the Bill
primarily dealt with trade, economic and social welfare issues, which
are concurrent competences in terms of Schedule 4. The Western Cape
provincial government argued that the Bill dealt with liquor licences,
which is an exclusive provincial competence in terms of Schedule 5.
The Constitutional Court emphasised that under the post-apartheid
Constitution, governmental power is not located in the national sphere
alone.127 Legislative authority is vested in Parliament for the national
sphere, in the provincial legislature for the provincial sphere and in
municipal councils for the local sphere.128 Any interpretation must
recognise and promote the philosophy of co-operative government at
various levels.129 However, given the breadth of the competencies listed
in the various Schedules, their parameters of operation will, of
necessity, overlap.130
The Constitutional Court pointed out that the Constitution allows
for provincial exclusivity in respect of matters falling within Schedule 5,
subject to an intervention by the national sphere that is justified in
terms of section 44(2) of the Constitution. This, argued the Court, meant
that the functional competencies in Schedule 4 should be interpreted as
being distinct from, and excluding, Schedule 5 competencies.131 The
Court found that the primary purpose of Schedule 4 is to enable the
national government to regulate various issues inter-provincially
(between all the provinces).132 Conversely, the provinces, whose
jurisdiction is confined to their geographical territory, are accorded
exclusive powers in respect of matters that may be regulated intra-
provincially (exclusively within the province).133
The main substance and character of the legislation (its ‘pith and
substance’) determines the field of competence in which it falls. A
single piece of legislation may have various parts and more than one
substantive character.134 According to this reasoning, the Court
concluded that the pith and substance of the bill dealt with the
manufacturing, distribution and sale of liquor. The manufacture and
distribution segments of the legislation affect inter-provincial as
opposed to intra-provincial competencies135 which means that the
competence of liquor licensing in Schedule 5 was not intended to
encompass the manufacturing and distribution of liquor.136 In any
event, the Court was prepared to conclude that even if the provincial
competence in respect of liquor licenses extends to production and
distribution, the national spheres ‘interest in maintaining economic
unity authorises it to intervene in these areas under section 44(2) [of the
Constitution]’.137
However, the Court adopted a much stricter approach to the
national regulation in respect of retail sales. A relatively uniform
approach to liquor licensing in the country may be desirable but this
did not amount to a necessity that justified an intrusion into the
exclusive provincial competence. Thus, the Court deemed those aspects
of the law that regulated the manufacture and distribution of liquor
constitutional and the segment of the national law regulating the retail
industry unconstitutional.138
After setting out these principles, the Constitutional Court applied them
to the facts. In this respect, the Court held that in determining the
substance of the Act it had to be considered as a whole.146 The preamble
of the Act identified the purpose of the legislation as being to eliminate
and prevent the re-emergence of slums in a manner that protects and
promotes the housing construction programmes of provincial and local
governments.147 The Court found that the overall strategy of the Act was
to eliminate slums and to make provision for the progressive realisation
of adequate housing by improving service delivery and by generally
improving the conditions under which people are housed. It was not
simply about eviction with no regard for the consequences of rendering
people homeless.148
The Court concluded that the Act was primarily about improving the
housing conditions of those living in slums in KZN.149 It was therefore
about housing and fell within the legislative competence of the
province.150 However, the majority of the Court found that section 16 of
the Elimination and Prevention of the Re-emergence of Slums Act
obliged owners to institute eviction proceedings when directed to do so
by the MEC even if to do so would not be in accordance with the
Prevention of Illegal Eviction From and Unlawful Occupation of Land
Act (PIE Act).151 The majority found this to be inconsistent with section
25 of the Constitution which seeks to provide greater security of tenure
to communities whose tenure is legally insecure as a result of past
racially discriminatory laws.152
Thus, a full and complete appraisal of the law is required to
determine the substance of the legislation. This, in turn, assists with
assessing whether the law deals with a matter that falls under Schedule
4 or 5 or within the exclusive competence of Parliament. Once this
determination has been made, then clarity can be obtained as to which
legislative body has competence over the matter.
Thus, the first question is whether the legislative body possesses the
constitutional power to legislate over the matter. If the response is that
the provincial legislature, as in the case of the Premier: Limpopo, or
Parliament, as in Executive Council of the Western Cape Legislature and
Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others,154 does not
possess the authority to legislate, then that is the end of the enquiry. The
legislative body lacking the power cannot constitutionally legislate and
there is no need to determine whether national law should prevail over
provincial law or vice versa. It is only if both national and provincial
legislatures have the power to legislate and do so that attempts must be
made to reconcile the laws. If the laws cannot be reconciled, section 146
of the Constitution must then be applied to determine which law
should prevail.
If any one of the criteria listed in section 146 is met, the national law
will prevail.155 The provisions of section 146 can only be resorted to in
respect of conflicting laws dealing with a functional area listed in
Schedule 4.156 Criteria permitting the national override are divided into
two categories. If one of the criteria listed either in section 146(2) or
146(3) is satisfied, then the conflicting provincial law is rendered
inoperative for the period of the conflict.157 If, for some reason, the
conflicting national law is repealed, the provincial law that had been
rendered inoperative as a result of the application of section 146 will
again be operative. All the criteria listed in section 146(2) are subject to
the additional requirement that the national legislation must apply
uniformly to the country as a whole. Thus, a national law that targets a
particular province will not prevail in terms of section 146(2). The
Constitutional Court reaffirmed these principles in Federation of
Governing Bodies for South African Schools (FEDSAS) v Member of the
Executive Council for Education, Gauteng and Another.158 Education is a
Schedule 4 competence over which both the national and provincial
legislatures have concurrent legislative competence. The Court
confirmed that provincial law, without more, is not rendered
inoperative by the existence of a conflicting national law.
In terms of section 146(2), central law will prevail if any one of the
following three conditions is established:
(a) The national legislation deals with a matter that cannot be regulated
effectively by legislation enacted by the respective provinces
individually.159
(b) The national legislation deals with a matter that, to be dealt with
effectively, requires uniformity across the nation, and national
legislation provides that uniformity by establishing norms and
standards, frameworks or national policies.160
(c) The national legislation is necessary for the maintenance of national
security; the maintenance of economic unity; the protection of the
common market in respect of the mobility of goods, services, capital
and labour; the promotion of economic activities across provincial
boundaries; the promotion of equal opportunities or equal access to
government services; or the protection of the environment.161
8.3.1 Introduction
As we have already seen, an important aspect of the Constitution is that
it distributes legislative and executive authority between the national,
provincial and local spheres of government. In the previous part of this
chapter, we discussed the division of legislative and executive authority
between the national sphere of government, on the one hand, and the
provincial spheres of government, on the other. In this part of the
chapter, we discuss the division of legislative and executive authority
between the national and provincial spheres of government, on the one
hand, and the local sphere of government, on the other. Before doing so,
however, it will be helpful to discuss briefly the objectives and structure
of local government.
Despite the fact that these sections impose a wide range of obligations
on local government, the Constitutional Court held in Joseph and
Others v City of Johannesburg and Others that one of the most important
objectives of local government is to meet the basic needs of all of the
inhabitants of South Africa.174 For this reason, ‘the establishment of
wall-to-wall municipalities in the Republic is mandatory’.175
To achieve this objective, the Constitutional Court held further that
sections 152 and 153 of the Constitution, read together with the Local
Government: Municipal Systems Act,176 impose an obligation on every
municipality in the territory to provide basic municipal services to their
inhabitants, such as water and electricity, irrespective of whether or not
they entered in a contract for the supply of these services with the
municipality.177
The Court was obliged to declare the section invalid because not only
was the Appeal Tribunal situated within the provincial sphere of
government, but the MEC was responsible for appointing the members
of the Appeal Tribunal, thus this Tribunal was not independent.251
Likewise, the case of Shoprite Checkers (Pty) Limited v Premier,
Gauteng Province and Others252 unambiguously provides that a
municipality is vested with the exclusive executive authority to consider
and approve applications for the relaxation of height limitations of all
buildings situated within its municipal area.253
An assigning agent may set the parameters for the exercise of the
assigned authority in the legislative act of assignment. The assignment
is intended to be a complete transfer of the function and it entails the
final decision-making power in individual matters. Accordingly, the
assignment must conform to the requirements of section 151(4) of the
Constitution. The assignment of powers and functions to municipalities
by legislation or by an executive act or by agreement is regulated by the
Local Government: Municipal Systems Act.
On the facts of the case, the Provincial Executive did not consider less
drastic means other than to dissolve the Council in order to get the
budget approved. The Court held the principle of legality requires the
holder of public power not to misconstrue that power. The Court
concluded that by misconstruing its power under section 139(4), the
Provincial Executive offended the principle of legality. In addition, the
Court held that by dissolving the Council without considering less
drastic options, the Provincial Executive acted contrary to section 41(1)
of the Constitution which requires all spheres of government to respect
the constitutional powers of other spheres and not to assume any power
or function except those conferred upon them. In the circumstances,
the Court set aside the decision of the Provincial Executive to disband
the Council.
Section 139(5) of the Constitution governs financial crises
interventions. This section provides that if a municipality, as a result of a
crisis in its financial affairs, is in serious or persistent material breach of
its obligations to provide basic services or to meet its financial
commitments, or admits that it is unable to meet its obligations or
financial commitments, the national or relevant provincial executive
must impose a financial recovery plan, dissolve the municipal council,
or assume responsibility for the implementation of a recovery plan.
8.4.1 Introduction
Apart from dividing legislative and executive power between the
national, provincial and local spheres of government, the Constitution
also divides fiscal powers – the power to collect and spend public funds
– between the three spheres of government. Chapter 13 of the
Constitution sets out the constitutional provisions regulating fiscal
powers. Chapter 13 is sometimes referred to as the financial
constitution. Apart from regulating the power to collect and spend
public funds, Chapter 13 of the Constitution also establishes two
important regulatory bodies, namely the central bank and the Fiscal
and Financial Commission (FFC).
While regard must be had for the need of the provinces to be able to
provide basic services and carry out their developmental objectives, the
criteria set out in section 214(2) place a heavy emphasis on the
importance of national objectives and priorities. The listing appears to
suggest that the other criteria will be evaluated through the prism of
national objectives. The process preceding the adoption of the DORA is
set out in the Intergovernmental Fiscal Relations Act.306
At least 10 months before the start of each financial year, the FFC
must submit recommendations for an equitable division of revenue
raised nationally between the three spheres of government as well as
each province’s share of the provincial share of national revenue to the
Minister of Finance, Parliament and the provincial legislatures.307 After
receiving the FFC’s recommendations, the Minister of Finance must
consult with the FFC itself, the provinces, either in the Budget Council
or in some other way, and organised local government, either in the
Budget Forum or in some other way.308 The Budget Council and the
Budget Forum are statutory bodies established by the
Intergovernmental Fiscal Relations Act to facilitate intergovernmental
consultation with respect to fiscal matters.309 Once these consultations
have taken place, the Minister of Finance must introduce the annual
Division of Revenue Bill in the NA at the same time that the annual
budget is introduced. The equitable share allocated to each sphere of
government as well as each province’s share of the provincial share of
national revenue must be set out in this Bill.310
The DORA begins by dividing the revenue raised nationally between
the three spheres of government. It then goes on to divide the provincial
share of revenue raised nationally between the provinces and finally it
divides the municipal share of revenue raised nationally between the
municipalities. The amounts allocated to each province and each
municipality are based on different formulae. These formulae are made
up of a number of different components.311
Finally, it is important to note that although the equitable share of
national revenue is supposed to be an unconditional grant, there are
some restraints on the manner in which the provinces may spend this
money. Section 227 of the Constitution, for example, states that ‘each
province is entitled to an equitable share … to enable it to provide basic
services and perform the functions allocated to it’. Provinces, therefore,
must use the equitable share to provide basic services and perform the
functions allocated to them.
The Reserve Bank thus plays a vital role in the formulation and
implementation of economic policies. Its decisions have a direct impact
on the lives of people. Importantly, the policy decisions of the Reserve
Bank and the government in power may not always coincide and it is for
this reason that the independence of the Bank is entrenched. The
Reserve Bank is meant to act is the best interests of the economy of the
country and to be shielded from having to act in accordance with the
popular will. The importance of the Reserve Bank to the economy of the
country was recognised by the full bench of the High Court in Absa
Bank Limited and Others v Public Protector.322 The Court held that one
of the functions of the Reserve Bank was to act as a lender of last resort
and prevent instability in the banking sector. Powers of this nature are
exercised internationally by central banks. Importantly, the Court noted
that these powers and functions are exercised by experts with specific
skill and competence in financial matters. The Court went on to hold
that other organs of state such as the Public Protector should not lightly
interfere with the exercise of these discretionary powers.
8.4.7 Procurement
8.4.7.1 Introduction
Section 217 of the Constitution makes it imperative for an organ of state
in the national, provincial or local sphere to contract for goods and
services in a manner that is fair, equitable, transparent, competitive and
cost-effective. However, organs of state are not prevented from
implementing a procurement policy providing for categories of
preferences in the allocation of contracts and the protection or
advancement of persons or categories of persons previously
disadvantaged by unfair discrimination.323 The section goes on to
require national legislation to be enacted to prescribe a framework to
implement the policy of preference to previously disadvantaged
persons. The Preferential Procurement Policy Framework Act (PPPFA)324
is the empowering legislation that seeks to achieve this objective.
In Millennium Waste Management (Pty) Ltd v Chairperson of the
Tender Board: Limpopo Province and Others,325 the SCA required
tenders to be evaluated in a manner that advances the five
constitutional values identified in section 217 of the Constitution. In
this case, the appellant had submitted its tender which met all the
specifications of the advertisement. However, the appellant had
inadvertently omitted to sign the declaration of interest, but had
inserted the name of the relevant person and had filled in the relevant
information. A tender committee on behalf of the Limpopo Department
of Health and Social Development disqualified the applicant and finally
awarded the tender to a consortium called TTP. A particularly
concerning aspect was that TTP’s bid for the removal, treatment and
disposal of hospital waste was R3 600 000 per month which was
significantly more than appellant’s tender which would have cost the
Department R400 000 per month.
The Tender Board argued that the signing of the declaration of
interest was peremptory and as the appellant had not signed it, the
Tender Board was obliged to disqualify the appellant.
The SCA held that the decision to award the tender was
administrative action and had to comply with the provisions of the
Promotion of Administrative Justice Act (PAJA),326 with section 217 of
the Constitution and with the PPPFA.327 Interpreting the regulations in
terms of which the Tender Board was acting, the SCA held that the
Tender Board had the power to condone non-compliance with
procedural defects in the application.328 However, the SCA went on to
hold that ‘our law permits condonation of non-compliance with
peremptory requirements in cases where condonation is not
incompatible with public interest and if such condonation is granted by
the body in whose benefit the provision was enacted’.329 The SCA stated
further that the condonation of the failure to sign would have been in
the public interest as it would have facilitated competitiveness.330 A
condonation in this instance would have served the broader
constitutional values of fairness, competiveness and cost-
effectiveness.331
Importantly, the SCA held that whether the appellant’s tender
constituted an acceptable tender in terms of the PPPFA must be
construed in the context of a system that is fair, equitable, transparent,
competitive and cost-effective.332 In other words, the constitutional
values must be the prism through which the enabling legislation must
be interpreted. The SCA held the term ‘tender’ must be given a
relatively narrow meaning and cannot mean that the tender must
comply with conditions which are immaterial, unreasonable or
unconstitutional.333 The SCA concluded that by insisting on
disqualifying the appellant for an innocent omission, the Tender Board
had acted unreasonably.334 The SCA set aside the decision of the Tender
Board and ordered the Tender Board to reconsider and adjudicate on
the bids submitted by the appellant and TTP afresh. The Court thus
assessed the entire tender process against the five values identified in
the Constitution and not just the final evaluation process of the
shortlisted candidates.
Section 217 of the Constitution must be read with section 5 of the PAJA
which requires a functionary to provide adequate reasons for
administrative decisions which materially and adversely affect rights if
requested. Once reasons are provided, the decision can be appraised
against the constitutional criteria in section 217. In the Phoenix Cash &
Carry case, the reasons supplied were woefully inadequate and the
supplementary reasons confirmed that, at best, an unreasonable and
irrational decision had been made. The tenor of the judgment appears
to suggest that the irrationality bordered on improper conduct.
What is apparent from these decisions is that while price may not be
the decisive factor, massive disparities in pricing will weigh with the
court when determining whether a public body has discharged its
ultimate mandate of acting in the public good. It would be advisable
therefore that if the successful tenderer’s contract price is much more
expensive than the unsuccessful tenderer, that the reasons provided
deal with the disparity in price and justify the decision to award the
tender despite the price difference.
The issue of whether inconsequential irregularities can be
disregarded was considered by the Constitutional Court in Allpay
Consolidated Investment Holding (Pty) Ltd and Others v Chief Executive
Officer of the South African Social Security Agency and Others341 in which
Allpay, the unsuccessful bidders, challenged the legality of awarding the
tender to Cash Paymaster Services. The SCA held that ‘a fair process
does not demand perfection and that not every flaw is fatal’. 342 It went
on to state that ‘[i]t would be gravely prejudicial to the public interest if
the law was to invalidate public contracts for inconsequential
irregularities’. Thus, it appeared that the SCA was suggesting that
irregularities that were inconsequential to the final decision or outcome
could be ignored. The Constitutional Court disagreed, and held that the
suggestion ‘that “inconsequential irregularities” are of no moment
conflates the test for irregularities and their import’.343 The
Constitutional Court took the view that process requirements cannot be
conflated with the merits, and went on to hold:
To the extent that the judgment of the Supreme Court of Appeal may be
interpreted as suggesting that the public interest in procurement matters
requires greater caution in finding that grounds for judicial review exist in a
given matter, that misapprehension must be dispelled. So too the notion that
even if proven irregularities exist, the inevitability of a certain outcome is a
factor that should be considered in determining the validity of administrative
action. 344
Previously the body scoring the highest points was allocated the tender.
Thus, the PPPFA and the regulations of 2011 adopted a fairly rigid
system to ensure that price is allocated the overwhelming segment of
the points, but that equity issues are not ignored. However, in terms of
the 2017 regulations to the PPPFA348 (which repealed the 2011
regulations), far more flexibility is conferred on organs of state.
Examples of this flexibility include the fact that as a result of the case of
South African National Road Agency Ltd v The Toll Collect Consortium
and Another,349 as read with Regulation 9(2), it is now compulsory for
organs of state to specify ‘objective criteria’ upfront in the tender
advertisement. These objective criteria encompass such aspects as the
intention to use procurement to promote local industrial development,
the imperative of achieving socio-economic transformation and the
empowerment of small business enterprises, rural and township
enterprises, as well as co-operatives. Furthermore, Regulation 9
authorises an organ of states to insert a condition into the tender
advertisement to the effect that the successful bidder is required to
subcontract a minimum of 30% of the value of its bid to designated
groups as stipulated in Regulation 4. A third example is that Regulation
6(9) and 7(9) provide that ‘If the price offered by a tender scoring the
highest point is not market-related, the organ of state may not award the
contract to that tender’. Therefore, the organ of state is now empowered
to negotiate a market-related price with the bidder that has scored the
highest points. If these negotiations fail, the organ of state may
negotiate with the second highest scoring bidder or even the third
highest scoring bidder. A tender may only be cancelled if no agreement
is able to be reached.
SUMMARY
The Constitution does not only divide power vertically, but also
horizontally between the national, provincial and local spheres of
government. This horizontal division of power establishes a quasi-
federal system of government. Power is divided largely according to an
integrated model of federalism in which the subject matters in respect
of which policies and laws may be made are not strictly divided
between the different levels or spheres of government but are shared
between them. To ensure that this system works optimally, the
Constitution also establishes the principle of co-operative government,
requiring the various spheres of government to work together
regardless of the political party in power nationally, provincially or at
local government level. The National Council of Provinces (NCOP), the
second House of the national legislature, plays an important role in co-
ordinating the legislative activities of the three spheres of government.
The structures of government for the nine provinces largely mirror
that of the national sphere. A Premier elected by the provincial
legislature heads the provincial executive and can also be removed by
the provincial legislature. A province has executive authority in terms of
those functional areas listed in Schedules 4 (concurrent powers shared
with the national executive) and 5 (exclusive powers) of the
Constitution. Provincial legislatures operate largely in the same manner
and according to the same principles as the national legislature.
However, provincial legislatures only have one House and not two
although their interests are represented in the NCOP at national level.
When both the national legislature and the provincial legislature pass
legislation on one of the areas listed in Schedule 4, the provincial
legislation shall prevail except if one of the criteria set out in section 146
of the Constitution is present in which case the national legislation shall
prevail. It will only be permissible in exceptional circumstances for the
national legislature to pass legislation relating to one of the areas
exclusively reserved for provinces in Schedule 5 if this is authorised by
section 44(2) of the Constitution. When determining whether the
subject matter of a Bill falls within Schedule 4 or Schedule 5, we must
apply the pith and substance test. This test must be distinguished from
the substantial measure test used to decide how to tag a national Bill to
decide on the procedure to be used to pass it.
In the constitutional dispensation, local government fulfils an
important role. Municipalities thus enjoy original and constitutionally
entrenched powers, functions, rights and duties that may be qualified
or constrained by law and only to the extent to which these are set out
in section 152(1) of the Constitution. Section 155 of the Constitution
distinguishes between three different categories of municipalities,
namely:
• category A municipalities with exclusive municipal executive and
legislative authority in their area and which are referred to as
metropolitan municipalities
• category B municipalities which share their municipal executive
and legislative authority in their area with a category C municipality
and which are referred to as local municipalities
• category C municipalities with municipal executive and legislative
authority in an area which includes more than one municipality and
which are referred to as district municipalities.
The Constitution determines that a municipality has executive authority
in respect of and has the right to administer the local government
matters listed in Part B of Schedule 4 and Part B of Schedule 5 and any
other matter assigned to it by national or provincial legislation. In
addition, municipalities may make and administer by-laws for the
effective administration of the matters which they have the right to
administer. Conflicts between national and provincial laws and
municipal laws are resolved in terms of section 156(3) of the
Constitution. This section provides simply that, subject to section
151(4), a by-law that conflicts with national or provincial legislation is
invalid. An important consequence of this provision is that a
municipality must exercise its legislative and executive authority within
the parameters set by national or provincial legislation. In the absence
of any national or provincial law regulating a local government matter,
however, a municipality is free to determine the content of its legislative
and executive decisions.
The financial arrangements in the Constitution tilt power decisively
in favour of the national sphere of government as the power to collect
revenue is vested primarily in the national sphere of government. This is
because Chapter 13 of the Constitution restricts the power of the
provincial and local spheres of government to impose taxes. Although
the Constitution restricts the power of the provincial and local spheres
of government to impose taxes and thus to raise revenue, it
compensates them for this loss by granting them a right to an equitable
share of revenue collected nationally. Section 215(1) of the Constitution
provides that the national, provincial and municipal budgetary
processes must promote transparency, accountability and the effective
financial management of the economy, debt and the public sector.
Section 217 of the Constitution also makes it imperative for an organ of
state in the national, provincial or local sphere to contract for goods and
services in a manner that is fair, equitable, transparent, competitive and
cost-effective.
9.1 Introduction
Summary
9.1 Introduction
Like other constitutional democracies, the Constitution of the Republic
of South Africa, 1996 divides public power among the legislative,
executive and judicial branches of government, each of which consists
of a variety of institutions and structures. Apart from the institutions
and structures that make up these three branches, however, the
Constitution also confers public power on another set of institutions
and structures, namely traditional leadership.
These traditional institutions and structures are often overlooked in
conventional discussions of the Constitution. This is a mistake. Not only
does South Africa have a long history of traditional institutions and
structures, but these institutions were also ‘entrenched (albeit in
distorted ways) over many decades of segregationist and apartheid
rule’.1 Millions of South Africans are thus subject to the rule of
traditional leadership, especially in rural areas.
The constitutional framework governing traditional leadership is set
out in Chapter 12 of the Constitution and consists of two brief sections,
namely section 211 and section 212. Section 211 provides that:
(1) The institution, status and role of traditional leadership, according to
customary law, are recognised, subject to the Constitution.
(2) A traditional authority that observes a system of customary law may
function subject to any applicable legislation and customs, which includes
amendments to, or repeal of, that legislation or those customs.
(3) The courts must apply customary law when that law is applicable, subject
to the Constitution and any legislation that specifically deals with
customary law.
9.2.1 Introduction
Traditional leadership is defined in the Framework Act as the
customary institutions or structures or the customary systems or
procedures of governance practised by traditional communities,11 and
traditional communities are defined as those that are subject to a
system of traditional leadership and observe a system of customary
law.12
Customary law, or more precisely ‘living customary law’, consists of
the normative arrangements that regulate the day-to-day life of the
members of a traditional community and that have been willingly
adapted and developed from the (mostly unwritten) customs, practices
and traditions of their predecessors, as well as outside influences. It is a
dynamic rather than a static concept.13
In order to properly understand the institution, status and role of
traditional leadership in a democratic South Africa, however, it is
important to briefly locate traditional leadership in its historical
context, starting with the pre-colonial period (pre-1652), going on to the
colonial and apartheid eras (1652–1990) and ending with the
transitional period (1990–1996).
The key question the Constitutional Court had to answer was whether
the respondent was correct: as the eldest son of the previous Hosi, did
the respondent have a right to succeed to the chieftainship of the Valoyi
Traditional Community in terms of its customary law rules. In order to
answer this question, the Court had to determine what the customary
law rules governing succession to Hosi were. Before engaging in this
task, however, it was important to set out the proper approach that must
be followed when determining customary law rules.51
In so far as the proper approach was concerned, the Constitutional
Court began by pointing out that the status of customary law is
entrenched in terms of section 211 of the Constitution. It follows,
therefore, that customary law is, not only an integral part of the legal
system, but is also an independent source of legal norms:
The import of [section 211], in the words of Langa DCJ in Bhe, is that customary
law ‘is protected by and subject to the Constitution in its own right.’ Customary
law, like any other law, must accord with the Constitution. Like any other law,
customary law has a status that requires respect. As this Court held in Alexkor v
Richtersveld Community, customary law must be recognised as ‘an integral part
of our law’ and ‘an independent source of norms within the legal system.’ It is a
body of law by which millions of South Africans regulate their lives and must be
treated accordingly.52
Given the important role that customary law plays in the legal system,
the Constitutional Court held, several factors must be taken into
account when it comes to determining and developing the content of a
customary law rule.
• First, both the historical and current practices of a community must
be taken into account.53
• Second, a community has the right to develop and change its own
laws and this right must be respected.54
• Third, the development of customary law must be balanced against
legal certainty, vested rights, and constitutional rights, especially of
vulnerable groups.55
9.4.1 Introduction
As noted above, the national legislation referred to in section 212(1) of
the Constitution is the Framework Act. The preamble to this Act states
that it seeks:
• to set out a national framework and norms and standards that will
define the place and role of traditional leadership within the new
system of democratic governance;
• to transform the institution in line with constitutional imperatives;
and
• to restore the integrity and legitimacy of the institution of traditional
leadership in line with customary law and practices.
Regardless of one’s view on this, what is beyond dispute is that first the
Framework Act and now the TKLA have potentially major
consequences for the manner in which large sections of the population
are governed. Roughly 16 to 21 million122 people live in the former
homelands of South Africa or are sequentially migratory between them
and an urban area with which they are connected by labour and
dependence on the cash economy. A large proportion of villages in
these former homelands are remote, deep rural areas which were
systematically disenfranchised and deprived of resources by the
apartheid government and thus left with only poorly funded traditional
structures as their form of local government.123
As some of the other chapters of this textbook have indicated, the
Constitution’s purpose is largely to overcome this entrenched inequality
of citizenship and disproportionate access to resources within South
Africa’s borders and people that is concomitant. How successful this
transformative vision has been is a highly contested question.
9.5.1 Introduction
Section 212(2) of the Constitution provides that national legislation may
establish a house of traditional leaders to deal with matters relating to
traditional leadership, the role of traditional leaders, customary law and
the customs of communities observing a system of customary law.147
The national legislation referred to in this section is the NHTLA.148 The
NHTLA will be repealed and replaced by the TKLA when it is brought
into operation.
At least one third of the members of the national House must consist of
women. However, if this requirement cannot be met, the Minister
responsible for traditional leadership matters must, after consultation
with the Premier of the province in question and the provincial House
concerned, determine a lower threshold.153
Unlike the NHTLA, the TKLA establishes, not only a house of
traditional leaders, but also Khoi-San leaders. This house is known as
the National House of Traditional and Khoi-San Leaders. 154 Once again,
the members of this national House are not democratically elected.
Instead, the TKLA provides that if a provincial House has been
established and there are:
(a) only senior traditional leaders, the provincial House must elect three of
them to serve as members in the national House;155
(b) only senior Khoi-San leaders, the provincial House must elect three of
them to serve in the national House;156
(c) more senior traditional leaders than senior Khoi- San leaders, the
provincial House must elect three senior traditional leaders and one
senior Khoi-San leader to serve in the national House and vice versa;157
and
(d) an equal number of senior traditional and senior Khoi-San leaders, the
provincial House must elect two of each to serve in the national House.158
If a provincial House has not been established, the TKLA provides that
the senior traditional leaders and the senior Khoi-San leaders must, at a
meeting convened by the Premier, elect from themselves
representatives to serve in the national House in accordance with the
representation numbers set out above.159
The national House, therefore, does not have any direct legislative
powers and cannot veto legislation passed by Parliament. It is, in
essence, an advisory body aimed at ensuring that the interests of
traditional leaders and the communities represented by traditional
leaders are considered in the law-making process. Although the
national House must be consulted on issues affecting traditional
communities, including the passing of legislation affecting traditional
communities, the consultation process does not afford traditional
leaders any powers to slow down or thwart the legislative programme of
Parliament.
With one exception, the TKLA largely restates these provisions
(although it also broadens them to include both traditional and Khoi-
San leaders). The exception widens the types of Bills that must or may
be referred to it by the Secretary of Parliament for its comments. Section
39 of the TKLA provides in this respect that:
(a) any Bill that ‘directly affects traditional or Khoi-San communities or that
pertains to customary law or customs of traditional or Khoi-San
communities’ must be referred by the Secretary of Parliament to the
national House for its comments;190 or
(b) any Bill that ‘pertains to any matter referred to in section 154(2) of the
Constitution’ may be referred by the Secretary of Parliament to the
national House for its comments.191
After receiving such a Bill, the national House must within 60 days make
any comments it wishes to make and submit these to the Secretary.192
9.5.8 Conclusion
Considering the history provided to contextualise traditional leadership
within South Africa’s past and present political economy, it may initially
appear doubtful that traditional leadership should be recognised under
the Constitution. However, that is not anyone’s decision to make except
that of the people living under traditional leadership, on a case-by-case
basis as accords with their customary law. Amidst the rhetorical
discussions of how traditional leadership is being undermined and is
not sufficiently respected under the Constitution, it is unfortunate that
public and policy debates should be had outside of the explicit
recognition of the fact that ‘the institutionalisation of traditional
leadership’ that the government is determined to ensure dates right
back to the 19th century when Frederick Lugard articulated the policy
of indirect rule.193 This was social engineering that was devised, as
shown by Chief Justice Ngcobo in his discussion of the Black Authorities
Act,194 for the subjugation of the ‘natives’. It is only in the context of
confronting that truth that the constitutional imperative to:
Recognise the injustices of our past;
Honour those who suffered for justice and freedom in our land;
[…]
Heal the divisions of the past and establish a society based on democratic
values, social justice and fundamental human rights;
Lay the foundations for a democratic and open society in which government is
based on the will of the people and every citizen is equally protected by law;
[and]
Improve the quality of life of all citizens and free the potential of each person
[…]195
SUMMARY
1 See Beall, J, Mkhize, S and Vawda, S (2005) Emergent democracy and ‘resurgent’ tradition:
Institutions, chieftaincy and transition in KwaZulu-Natal Journal of Southern African
Studies 31(4):755–756.
2 Act 22 of 2009.
3 Act 41 of 2003.
4 Act 3 of 2019.
5 Alexkor Ltd and Another v Richtersveld Community and Others (CCT 19/03) [2003] ZACC
18; 2004 (5) SA 460 (CC); 2003 (12) BCLR 1301 (CC) (14 October 2003).
6 Bhe and Others v Khayelitsha Magistrate and Others (CCT 49/03) [2004] ZACC 17; 2005 (1)
SA 580 (CC); 2005 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) (15 October 2004).
7 See Bhe v Magistrate, Khayelitsha (Commission for Gender Equality as Amicus Curiae);
Shibi v Sithole and Others; South African Human Rights Commission and Another v
President of the Republic of South Africa and Another [2004] ZACC 17.
8 Act 3 of 2019.
9 Act 41 of 2003.
10 Act 22 of 2009.
11 S 1 of the Framework Act.
12 S 2(1) of the Framework Act.
13 Himonga, C and Nhlapo, T (eds) (2014) African Customary Law in South Africa: Post-
apartheid and Living Law Perspectives 3rd ed 25.
14 (CCT 67/14) [2014] ZACC 36; 2015 (3) BCLR 268 (CC) (15 December 2014).
15 Bapedi Marota Mamone para 4.
16 Bennett, T and Murray, C ‘Traditional Leadership’ in Woolman, S, Roux, T and Bishop, M
(eds) (2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa 26–5. As Bennett and Murray point out, a
chief was classified by the colonial authorities as a king if he had gained authority over
neighbouring communities, while a chief was classified as a paramount chief if he had not
yet gained such authority or if the community he ruled was not large enough.
17 Bennett and Murray (2013) 26–6.
18 Bennett and Murray (2013) 26–7.
19 Himonga and Nhlapo (2014) 230.
20 Bennett and Murray (2013) 26–8, 26–9. This policy of indirect rule was pioneered in Natal
by Theophilus Shepstone (1817–1893) after he was appointed as the Secretary for Native
Affairs in the first colonial government (see Welsh, D (1971) The Roots of Segregation:
Native Policy in Colonial Natal 1845-1910 2nd ed).
21 Act 38 of 1927. This Act was later renamed the Black Administration Act.
22 S 5(1)(a) of the Native Administration Act.
23 S 2(7) of the Native Administration Act.
24 See Western Cape Provincial Government: In re DVB Behuising (Pty) Limited v North West
Provincial Government (CCT22/99) [2000] ZACC 2; 2001 (1) SA 500 (CC); 2000 (4) BCLR 347
(CC) (2 March 2000) para 41.
25 (CCT100/09) [2010] ZACC 10; 2010 (6) SA 214 (CC); 2010 (8) BCLR 741 (CC) (11 May 2010).
26 Tongoane para 23 [footnotes omitted].
27 Bennett and Murray (2013) 26–10.
28 Himonga and Nhlapo (2014) 232.
29 Bapedi Marota Mamone para 9, quoting from Bennett, TW (2004) Customary Law in South
Africa 109.
30 The apartheid government distinguished black ethnic groups from one another on the
basis of their culture and language. The preamble of the Promotion of Bantu Self-
Government Act 46 of 1959 thus stated that ‘[the Bantu people of the Union of South Africa
do not constitute a homogenous people but form separate national units on the basis of
language and culture’. Acting in terms of this Act, the governing divided black South
Africans into the following ‘national units’: North-Sotho, South-Sotho, Swazi, Tsonga,
Tswana, Venda, Xhosa and Zulu (see Khunou, SF (2009) Traditional leadership and
independent Bantustans of South Africa: Some milestones of transformative
constitutionalism beyond apartheid Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal 12(4):81–87).
31 Native Land Act 27 of 1913 and the Native Trust and Land Act 18 of 1936. The Native Land
Act was later renamed the Black Land Act and the Native Trust and Land Act was renamed
the Development Trust and Land Act.
32 Act 68 of 1951. It was later renamed the Black Authorities Act.
33 Tongoane paras 24 and 25.
34 Act 46 of 1959. It was later renamed the Promotion of Black Self-Governing Act.
35 The 10 homelands were the Bophuthatswana, Ciskei, Gazankulu, KaNgwane, KwaNdebele,
KwaZulu, Lebowa, QwaQwa, Transkei, and Venda.
36 Act 21 of 1971. It was later renamed the Black States Constitution Act and then the National
States Constitution Act.
37 The Transkei was granted independence in 1976, Bophuthatswana in 1977, Venda in 1979
and the Ciskei in 1981. None of these ‘TBVC’ states was recognised as ‘independent’ by any
other state, except South Africa.
38 See Khunou (2009) 81.
39 Himonga and Nhlapo (2014) 17.
40 S 181(1) of the interim Constitution.
41 S 182 of the interim Constitution.
42 S 183 of the interim Constitution.
43 Bennett and Murray (2013) 26–17.
44 (CCT 23/96) [1996] ZACC 26; 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC) (6 September
1996).
45 First Certification Judgment para 189.
46 First Certification Judgment para 197.
47 Chief Albert John Mvumbi Luthuli, available at https://www.sahistory.org.za/people/chief-
albert-john-mvumbi-luthuli.
48 Spitz, R and Chaskalson, M (2000) The politics of transition: A hidden history of South
Africa’s negotiated settlement 46.
49 (CCT 03/07) [2008] ZACC 9; 2009 (2) SA 66 (CC); 2008 (9) BCLR 914 (CC) (4 June 2008).
50 Kaganas, F and Murray, C (1994) The contest between culture and gender equality under
South Africa’s interim Constitution Journal of Law and Society 21(4):409 410.
51 Shilubana para 41.
52 Shilubana para 43.
53 Shilubana para 48.
54 Shilubana paras 45–6.
55 Shilubana para 47.
56 Shilubana para 48.
57 Shilubana para 49.
58 See Bhe v Khayelitsha Magistrate (CCT 49/03) [2004] ZACC 17; 2005 (1) SA 580 (CC); 2005
(1) BCLR 1 (CC) (15 October 2004); and Alexkor Ltd and Another v Richtersveld Community
and Others (CCT 19/03) [2003] ZACC 18; 2004 (5) SA 460 (CC); 2003 (12) BCLR 1301 (CC)
(14 October 2003).
59 (CCT 46/12) [2013] ZACC 3; 2013 (4) BCLR 431 (CC) (28 February 2013).
60 As the Constitutional Court explained in Pilane para 46, a ‘Kgotha Kgothe is a traditional
gathering at which members of a traditional community publicly debate and decide on
matters affecting the community, which may include evaluating and criticising the
performance of their leaders’.
61 Pilane para 39.
62 Act 41 of 2003.
63 Act 2 of 2005.
64 Pilane paras 41–2.
65 Pilane para 44.
66 Pilane para 47.
67 Pilane para 49.
68 Luthuli, A (1962) Let My People Go.
69 Mbeki, G (1964) The Peasants Revolt.
70 Act 41 of 2003.
71 Act 3 of 2019.
72 Act 22 of 2009.
73 S 1 of the Framework Act.
74 S 1 of the Framework Act.
75 S 1 of the TKLA.
76 S 1 of the TKLA. Traditional leadership is defined in s 1 of the TKLA as ‘the institutions or
structures established in terms of customary law or customs, or customary systems or
procedures of governance, recognised, utilised or practiced by traditional communities’.
77 S 1 of the Framework Act.
78 S 8 of the Framework Act.
79 S 1 of the Framework Act.
80 S 9 of the Framework Act.
81 S 1 of the Framework Act.
82 S 10A of the Framework Act.
83 S 1 of the Framework Act.
84 S 11 of the Framework Act.
85 S 1 of the Framework Act.
86 S 11 of the Framework Act.
87 S 1 read together with s 7(1)(a) of the TKLA. Apart from kings, queens, principle traditional
leaders, senior traditional leaders and headmen and headwomen, the TKLA also
recognises regents, acting traditional leaders and deputy traditional leaders.
88 S 7(1)(b) of the TKLA.
89 S 1 read together with s 8 of the TKLA.
90 S 8(2) of the TKLA.
91 S 1 read together with s 10 of the TKLA.
92 S 10(1)(a) of the TKLA.
93 S 10(1)(b) of the TKLA.
94 S 10(1)(c) of the TKLA.
95 (169/14) [2015] ZAECBHC 14; 2015 (6) SA 400 (ECB); [2015] 4 All SA 107 (ECB) (18 August
2015).
96 See, for example, Delius, P ‘Contested Terrain: Land Rights and Chiefly Power in Historical
Perspective’ in Claassens, A and Cousins, B (eds) (2008) Land, Power & Custom:
Controversies generated by South Africa’s Communal Land Rights Act 211–235; Ntsebeza, L
(2005) Democracy compromised: Chiefs and the politics of the land in South Africa 326; and
Peires, J (1981) The House of Phalo: A history of the Xhosa people in the days of their
independence 31–41.
97 S 19 of the Framework Act.
98 S 15 of the TKLA.
99 S 2(1) of the Framework Act.
100 S 2(2) of the Framework Act.
101 S 2(3) of the Framework Act.
102 S 2A of the Framework Act.
103 S 2B of the Framework Act.
104 S 28(3) of the Framework Act.
105 S 3(1) of the TKLA.
106 S 3(4) of the TKLA
107 S 3(7) of the TKLA.
108 S 3(3) of the TKLA.
109 S 5(1) of the TKLA.
110 S 63(1) of the TKLA.
111 S 3(1) of the Framework Act.
112 S 3(2)(a) of the Framework Act.
113 S 3(2)(b) and (d) of the Framework Act.
114 S 3(2)(c) of the Framework Act.
115 S 3A of the Framework Act.
116 S 3B of the Framework Act.
117 S 28(4) of the Framework Act.
118 S 16 and 18 of the TKLA.
119 Land and Accountability Research Centre (LARC) Submission on the Traditional and Khoi-
San Leadership Bill, 2015. 7 September 2018, accessed on 17 August 2020 at
http://www.larc.uct.ac.za/sites/default/files/image_tool/images/347/Submissions/LARC
%20submission%20on%20TKLB_NCOP_20180907.pdf.
120 Land and Accountability Research Centre (2018).
121 Land and Accountability Research Centre (2018).
122 See Debbie Budlender as quoted in Claassens, A and Ngubane, S (2008) ‘Women, land and
power: The impact of the Communal Land Rights Act’ in Claassens, A and Cousins, B (eds)
Land, Power & Custom: Controversies Generated by South Africa’s Communal Land Rights
Act 154–83 at 168 fn 22.
123 Oomen, B (2005) Chiefs in South Africa: Law, power and culture in the post-apartheid era
37–86.
124 S 4(1) of the Framework Act.
125 S 4(1) of the Framework Act.
126 S 4A of the Framework Act.
127 S 4C of the Framework Act.
128 S 20 of the Framework Act.
129 S 19(1) of the TKLA.
130 S 20(1) of the TKLA.
131 S 25(1) of the TKLA.
132 S 2 of the Framework Act, and s 4(1) of the TKLA.
133 Himonga and Nhlapo (2014) 249.
134 Claassens, A (2011) Resurgence of tribal levies: Double taxation for the rural poor South
African Crime Quarterly 35: 11 12.
135 Department of Provincial and Local Government White Paper on Traditional Leadership
and Governance GN 2336 in GG 25438 of 10 September 2000.
136 See ss 228 and 229 of the Constitution.
137 Our emphasis.
138 Act 6 of 2005.
139 Act 4 of 2005. Section 30 prohibits the imposition of levies and section 31 authorises a
decision to raise voluntary contributions.
140 Act 2 of 2005. Section 28 prohibits the imposition of levies and section 29 authorises a
decision to raise voluntary contributions.
141 Act 2 of 2007. Section 24 prohibits the imposition of levies and section 25 authorises a
decision to raise voluntary contributions.
142 Claassens (2011) 11.
143 Act 8 of 2005. Section 8 appears to authorise the receipt of gifts.
144 Act 5 of 2005. Section 8 appears to authorise the receipt of gifts.
145 Act 3 of 2005. Section 9 appears to authorise the receipt of gifts.
146 Our emphasis.
147 S 212(1)(a) of the Constitution.
148 Act 22 of 2009.
149 S 2(1) of the NHTL.
150 A senior traditional leader is defined in s 1 of the NHTLA as a ‘senior traditional leader
defined in section 1 of the [Traditional Leadership and Governance Framework Act 41 of
2003]’. A senior traditional leader is defined in s 1 of this Act as ‘a traditional leader of a
specific traditional community who exercises authority over a number of headmen or
headwomen in accordance with customary law, or within whose area of jurisdiction a
number of headmen or headwomen exercise authority’. A senior traditional leader is
defined in s 1 of the Traditional and Khoi-San Leadership Act 3 of 2019 as ‘a person
recognised as a senior traditional leader in terms of section 8’ of the Act.
151 S 3(1) of the NHTLA. If a provincial House fails to elect one or more of its members to serve
in the national House, the Premier of the province must designate members of the
provincial House to serve in the national house (s 4(7) of the NHTLA).
152 S 3(2) of the NHTLA. The chairpersons of the traditional councils that serve as local houses
must be senior traditional leaders themselves (s 3(3) of the NHTLA).
153 S 3(4) of the NHTLA.
154 S 27(1) of the TKLA.
155 S 28(1)(b)(i) of the TKLA.
156 S 28(1)(b)(ii) of the TKLA.
157 S 28(1)(b)(iii) and (iv) of the TKLA.
158 S 28(1)(b)(v) of the TKLA. If a provincial House has been established and there are two or
less of senior traditional leaders or senior Khoi-San leaders, then these leaders
automatically serve as members of the national House (s 28(1)(b)(vi) of the TKLA).
159 S 28(2)(a) of the TKLA. If a provincial House has not been established and there are two or
less senior traditional leaders of senior Khoi-San leaders, then these leaders automatically
serve as members of the national House (s 28(2)(b) of the TKLA).
160 S 5(a) of the NHTLA.
161 S 5(b) of the NHTLA. Section 30(b) of the TKLA provides that this sentence of
imprisonment must be for more than 12 months without the option of a fine.
162 S 5(c) of the NHTLA.
163 S 5(d) of the NHTLA.
164 S 5(e) of the NHTLA. The NHTLA also provides that this disqualification ends five years
after the sentence has been completed.
165 S 5(f) and (g) of the NHTLA.
166 S 30(f) of the TKLA.
167 S 2(2) of the NHTLA.
168 S 2(3) of the NHTLA.
169 S 21 of the NHTLA.
170 S 27(2) and 47(1) and (2) of the TKLA.
171 S 47(1)(b) of the TKLA.
172 S 9(1) of the NHTLA. Section 34(1) of the TKLA provides that the Chief Justice or another
judge designated by the Chief Justice, and not the President, must preside over the election
of the Chairperson.
173 S 9(2) of the NHTLA.
174 S 9(3) of the NHTLA.
175 S 9(4) of the NHTLA.
176 S 9(9) of the NHTLA.
177 S 9(13) of the NHTLA. Section 34(12) of the TKLA provides that a person may not serve as
Chairperson or Deputy-Chairperson for more than two terms and not simply for more than
two consecutive terms.
178 S 8(4) of the NHTLA.
179 S 8(6) of the NHTLA.
180 S 8(7) of the NHTLA.
181 S 33(6) of the TKLA.
182 S 1(d) of the Constitution.
183 S 11(2)(a) of the NHTLA.
184 S 18(1)(a) of the Framework Act.
185 S 18(1)(b) of the Framework Act.
186 S 11(2)(b) of the NHTLA.
187 S 11(2)(c) of the NHLTA.
188 S 11(2)(e) of the NHTLA.
189 S 11(1)(a) of the NHTLA.
190 S 39(1)(a)(i) of the TKLA.
191 S 39(1)(a)(ii) of the TKLA. S 154(2) of the Constitution provides, inter alia, that draft
national legislation that affects the status, institution, powers or functions of local
government must be published for public comment before it is introduced in Parliament
192 S 39(1)(b) of the TKLA.
193 Lugard, FJD (1922) The Dual Mandate in British Tropical Africa 200–203.
194 Tongoane.
195 Preamble of the Constitution.
PART TWO
10.1 Introduction
10.1 Introduction
The South African Bill of Rights – constructed in a manner to give effect
to the transformative vision of the Constitution – sets out a unique
human rights vision. Its breadth of application – to both the state and, in
many cases, to private parties – and the range of rights protected in it,
establishes the Bill of Rights as a post-liberal text aimed at facilitating
the social and economic transformation of South Africa while
protecting the human dignity of all. Whether the Bill of Rights has
achieved, or is likely to achieve, this ambitious goal is in dispute as
critics point out that 25 years after the advent of democracy, inequality
and the denial of rights remain prevalent. From chapter 13 and onwards
we will look more closely at a selected list of specific rights protected in
the Bill of Rights,1 but before we do, it is necessary to deal with several
important technical issues regarding Bill of Rights adjudication. This is
because the structure of Bill of Rights litigation differs from litigation
dealing with other alleged breaches of the Constitution.
When confronted with the question of whether law or conduct is in
breach of the Bill of Rights, several preliminary questions arise. It is
imperative to consider these questions carefully before engaging in
litigation.
First, a court must ask whether the person or organisation that
claims that their rights have been infringed is entitled to the protection
provided by the Bill of Rights and whether the person or organisation
that wishes to approach the court has standing to bring the case. While
most of the rights in the Bill of Rights are granted to everyone, including
non-citizens, some are restricted to a specific group of persons. There
are also complicated rules to determine whether juristic persons can
claim the protection of the Bill of Rights.
Once a court has established that the person or organisation that
claims that their rights have been infringed is protected by the Bill of
Rights, it must ask whether the person or organisation that is alleged to
have infringed the rights is bound by the Bill of Rights. Apart from the
state, the Bill of Rights also binds private individuals and organisations,
but only when the relevant (and complicated) provisions of the
Constitution have been satisfied.
After a court has established that the rights of a natural or juristic
person have been infringed, it has to determine whether the
infringement is justified in terms of the limitation clause set out in
section 36. If the court finds that the limitation is justified, the
infringement is ‘saved’ and the law or conduct is constitutionally valid.
However, if the court finds that the limitation is not justified, then an
infringement cannot be saved and the law or conduct is
unconstitutional and invalid.
Law or conduct which unjustifiably infringes the Bill of Rights must
be declared invalid. Apart from a declaration of invalidity, however,
there are a number of other constitutional remedies a court may issue.
Among these are declaratory orders, prohibitory interdicts, mandatory
interdicts, structural interdicts, constitutional damages and meaningful
engagement.
This chapter, as well as chapters 11 and 12, deals with the technical
questions relating to Bill of Rights adjudication. While we will discuss
the substantive scope and content of the various fundamental rights
protected by the Bill of Rights in subsequent chapters, it is important
first to answer the relevant preliminary questions about the manner in
which Bill of Rights adjudication should proceed. These questions
include the following:
• Who can claim the rights protected in the Bill of Rights and who is
bound to respect the same rights?
• Can the rights be claimed only by people or also by organisations,
and if so, when?
• Are the rights binding only on the state or are they also binding on
private parties?
• To what extent and how can rights be legally limited and in which
situations?
• If there is an infringement of a right, how can that infringement be
remedied?
10.2 The structure of Bill of Rights litigation
When a person alleges that the state or another person has infringed a
right protected in the Bill of Rights, the process that a court must follow
to determine whether this allegation is valid or not is usually divided
into three stages, namely an application stage, a limitation stage and a
remedies stage.2
The constitutional provisions that regulate these questions are set out in
the operational provisions of the Bill of Rights. Unlike the substantive
provisions dealing with specific rights, the operational provisions do not
regulate the substance of the fundamental rights that are protected by
the Bill of Rights. Instead, they regulate the manner in which the Bill of
Rights operates and the manner in which it can be enforced by the
courts.6
The operational provisions are:
• section 7: the state’s duty to respect, protect, promote and fulfil the
rights in the Bill of Rights
• section 8: who is bound by the rights
• section 36: the limitation of rights
• section 37: the suspension of rights in a state of emergency
• section 38: who has standing to enforce the rights
• section 39: the interpretation of rights.
Apart from these operational provisions, sections 167, 168, 169 and 172
of the Constitution also regulate the enforcement of the Bill of Rights.
These provisions deal with the jurisdiction of the courts, especially in
constitutional matters, and the remedies that the courts may grant
when a right protected by the Bill of Rights has been unjustifiably
infringed. What cannot be forgotten is that South Africa’s system of
government is premised on adherence to the rule of law, as articulated
in section 1(c) of the Constitution. Simultaneously, section 195 of the
Constitution requires ethical, open and accountable conduct by all
organs of State. The presumption, therefore, is that anyone exercising a
public power will not violate any right in the Bill of Rights.
Unfortunately, violations nonetheless occur. Thus, the operational
provisions of the Constitution establish exactly when and how litigation
may be instituted to vindicate a person’s rights.
Classifying rights
As we have already seen, the substantive provisions of
the Bill of Rights are those provisions that regulate the
substance of the fundamental rights that are
entrenched and protected in the Bill of Rights. These
rights may be classified in a number of different ways
and some rights may fall into more than one category.
One of the most widely used methods of
classifying rights is to draw a distinction between civil
and political rights, on the one hand, and social,
economic and cultural rights, on the other hand. This
classification is based on the distinction drawn
between the rights protected in the International
Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR)7 and the
rights protected in the International Covenant on
Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR).8
Civil and political rights are aimed at protecting
people from unlawful interference by the state, private
organisations and individuals and at guaranteeing the
ability of everyone to participate fully in the civil and
political life of the state. Civil and political rights
include the right to equality, the right to freedom of
expression, the right to a fair trial, the right to freedom
of assembly and the right to participate in elections
and to vote.9
Social, economic and cultural rights include the
right to education, the right to housing, the right to
health, the right to food and social security and the
right to freedom of religion. They impose an obligation
on the state not to interfere with the existing enjoyment
of these rights and, where applicable, to take positive
steps to provide people with the resources and the
services they need to live a decent, fulfilling and
minimally good life.10
Another common method of classifying human
rights is to draw a distinction between first generation,
second generation and third generation rights. This
classification is based on the historical development of
human rights and echoes the French revolution’s call
for liberté (freedom), equalité (equality) and fraternité
(solidarity).11
First generation rights are the oldest. They arose in
the eighteenth century and were included in the
American Bill of Rights (1789–1791) and the French
Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen (1789).
First generation rights consist largely of traditional civil
and political rights. Sometimes they are also referred
to as blue rights.12
Second generation rights arose at the end of the
nineteenth century and the beginning of the twentieth
century. They were included in the 1931 Constitution of
Spain and the 1936 Constitution of the Union of
Soviet Socialist Republics. Second generation rights
consist largely of social and economic rights.
Sometimes they are also referred to as red rights.13
Third generation rights are the most recent and
arose towards the end of the twentieth century. Third
generation rights include the right to self-
determination, the right to development and the right
to a healthy environment. Sometimes they are also
referred to as green rights.14
While the classifications set out above provide us
with some insights into the history and nature of the
rights protected in the Bill of Rights, it is important to
note that as international human rights law has
evolved, all rights are viewed as indivisible, interrelated
and interdependent. Therefore, the Bill of Rights itself
does not classify or categorise rights in any of these
ways. Although the Bill of Rights contains examples of
the different categories or generations of rights, it does
not distinguish in any way between the various rights.
Implicit, therefore, in the Bill of Rights is the idea
that our Constitution does not create a hierarchy of
rights.15 Rather than drawing hard and fast distinctions
between the rights, the courts have been mindful to
show that the rights in the Bill of Rights are also
interrelated, interdependent and mutually supporting.
This is best expressed by Nelson Mandela who said:
‘We do not want freedom without bread, nor do we
want bread without freedom’.
10.3.2.1 Introduction
In most cases, ‘everyone’ can claim the rights contained in the Bill of
Rights. This includes every person present in South Africa, irrespective
of whether they are citizens or non-citizens. A limited number of rights
are qualified in that only ‘citizens’,20 ‘children’21 or ‘detained’ persons22
can claim them. When a specific provision states that ‘everyone’ can
claim the right, it usually means that natural persons23 can claim the
right and, in some cases, also juristic persons.24 However, as we shall
see, not all rights can be claimed by juristic persons.
10.3.2.2 Natural persons
Most of the rights in the Bill of Rights are for the benefit of ‘everyone’.
Section 9(1), for example, provides that ‘everyone is equal before the
law and has the right to equal protection and benefit of the law’; section
11 that ‘everyone has the right to life’; and section 13 that ‘no one may
be subjected to slavery, servitude or forced labour’.
The courts have interpreted the term ‘everyone’ to refer not only to
South African citizens, but also to various categories of immigrants, be
they refugees,25 permanent residents26 or persons present in South
Africa on the basis of a temporary permit such as a work permit or a
study permit.27 Even foreigners who have yet to be lawfully admitted
into South Africa have been recognised as beneficiaries of the rights
guaranteed in the Bill of Rights.28 The term ‘everyone’, however, does not
include a foetus.29
While most of the rights in the Bill of Rights are for the benefit of
‘everyone’, some are for the benefit of a narrower category of persons
only. Section 19(1)(a), for example, provides that ‘every citizen is free to
make political choices, which includes the right (a) to form a political
party’; section 23(2)(a) that ‘every worker has the right (a) to form and
join a trade union’; and section 28(1)(a) that ‘every child has the right
(a) to a name and a nationality from birth’. Only those natural persons
who fall into the definition of the category in question may claim these
rights.30
To determine whether a particular person may claim such a right,
the courts will have to interpret the scope of the category in question. In
South African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence,31 for
example, members of the South African National Defence Force
claimed that they were entitled to form and join a trade union in terms
of section 23(2)(a) of the Constitution. To decide whether this claim was
valid, the Constitutional Court had to establish whether the word
‘worker’ was wide enough to include members of the armed forces. In
its judgment, the Court found that the word ‘worker’ was indeed wide
enough to include members of the armed forces. The Court based its
decision on the fact that members of the armed forces receive many of
the same benefits as other employees, for example a salary.32 In
addition, the International Labour Organisation considers members of
the armed forces to be workers for the purposes of the Convention on
the Freedom of Association and Protection of the Right to Organise 87
of 1948 and the Convention on the Right to Organise and Collective
Bargaining 98 of 1949, both of which South Africa has signed and
ratified.33
When a litigant acts solely in his or her own interest, therefore, there is
no broad or unqualified capacity to litigate alleging that a right in the
Bill of Rights has been threatened or infringed. Something more must
be shown.61 How much more, the Court went on to hold, has been set
out in several of its previous judgments. Relying on precedent of
previous cases,62 the Constitutional Court in Giant Concerts, carefully
crafted a set of general principles pertaining to standing. These are as
follows:
• First, to establish own-interest standing under the Constitution a
litigant need not show the same ‘sufficient personal and direct
interest’ that the common law requires, but must still show that a
contested law or decision directly affects his or her rights or
interests, or potential rights or interests.
• Second, this requirement must be broadly and generously
interpreted to accord with constitutional goals. It must, however, be
real and not hypothetical or academic.
• Third, even under the requirements for common law standing, the
interest need not be capable of monetary valuation, but in a
challenge to legislation purely financial self-interest may not be
enough – the interests of justice must also favour affording standing.
• Fourth, standing is not a technical or strictly defined concept, and
there is no magical formula for conferring it. It is a tool a court
employs to determine whether a litigant is entitled to claim its time,
and to put the opposing litigant to trouble.
• Last, each case depends on its own facts. There can be no general
rule covering all cases. In each case, an applicant must show that he
or she has the necessary interest in an infringement or a threatened
infringement.63
10.3.3.1 Introduction
Once a court has determined who can claim rights in terms of the Bill of
Rights, it has to ask a second question, namely against whom can these
rights be enforced. In other words, the court has to ask who is bound to
respect the rights claimed by either a natural or juristic person.
Although ‘everyone’ is entitled to claim the benefit of the rights (or at
least most of the rights) in the Bill of Rights, not everyone is bound by
every right contained in the Bill of Rights. This is because while the Bill
of Rights is always binding on the state, it is not always binding on
private persons.
When it comes to the question of who is bound by the Bill of Rights,
it is important to distinguish between the direct application of the Bill of
Rights and the indirect application of the Bill of Rights:
• When the Bill of Rights applies directly, the purpose is to determine
whether the ordinary rules of law (legislation, common law and
customary law) are consistent with the Bill of Rights. If they are not,
the Bill of Rights overrides the ordinary rules of law. When the Bill of
Rights applies directly, it also generates its own set of special
remedies, for example reading down or reading in.67
• When the Bill of Rights applies indirectly, the purpose is to
determine whether the ordinary rules of law promote the values of
the Bill of Rights. If they do not, the Bill of Rights does not override
the ordinary law or generate its own special remedies. Instead, the
Bill of Rights is used to develop the rules and remedies of the
ordinary law so that the ‘objective normative value system’ that
permeates the Bill of Rights is given effect.68
10.3.3.2.1 Introduction
Section 8(1) of the Constitution governs the direct vertical application
of the Bill of Rights. This section stipulates in unqualified terms that
‘[t]he Bill of Rights applies to all law, and binds the legislature, the
executive, the judiciary and all organs of state’.
Despite the fact that section 8(1) of the Constitution provides that
the Bill of Rights applies directly to ‘all law’, the Constitutional Court has
held that section 8(1) does not regulate the direct application of the Bill
of Rights to disputes between private persons that are governed by the
common law or customary law. This is because section 8(2) of the
Constitution regulates the direct application of the Bill of Rights to these
horizontal disputes as confirmed by the Constitutional Court in its
judgment in Khumalo and Others v Holomisa.73
For the same reasons, section 8(1) does not regulate the direct
application of the Bill of Rights to the judiciary when it is called on to
resolve a dispute between private parties that is governed by the
common law or customary law. This is because section 8(2) of the
Constitution also regulates the direct application of the Bill of Rights to
the judiciary in these horizontal disputes.74
The facts of the case of Khumalo v Holomisa were as follows. The
respondent, who was a prominent politician, sued the appellants, who
were the publishers of a newspaper, for defamation. The appellants,
however, raised an exception to the respondent’s claim. The exception
was that the common law rules of defamation infringed the
constitutional right to freedom of expression guaranteed in section 16 of
the Constitution because they did not impose an obligation on the
plaintiff to prove that the defamatory statements were false. Instead,
they imposed an obligation on the defendant to prove that they were
true.
The Constitutional Court dismissed the exception. In arriving at this
decision, however, the Constitutional Court had to answer a number of
questions. One of these was whether section 16 of the Constitution
applied directly to the dispute even though it was governed by the
common law and neither of the parties was an organ of state. To answer
this question, the Constitutional Court stated it had to deal with two
issues:
• First, whether section 8(1) or section 8(2) of the Constitution
governed the direct horizontal application of the Bill of Rights
• Second, if section 8(2) governed the direct horizontal application of
the Bill of Rights, whether section 16 satisfied the requirements of
section 8(2).75
In so far as the first issue was concerned, the Constitutional Court held
that section 8(2) and not section 8(1) governed the direct horizontal
application of the Bill of Rights. In arriving at its conclusion, the Court
began by noting that sections 8(1) and 8(2) of the Constitution
distinguish between two categories of persons and institutions bound
by the Bill of Rights. Section 8(1) binds the legislature, executive,
judiciary and all organs of state without qualification, while section 8(2)
provides that natural and juristic persons are bound by the provisions of
the Bill of Rights, but only ‘to the extent that, it is applicable, taking into
account the nature of the right and the nature of any duty imposed by
the right’.76
Once a court has determined that a natural person is bound by a
particular provision of the Bill of Rights, the Court noted further, section
8(3) of the Constitution provides that the court must apply and if
necessary develop the common law to the extent that legislation does
not give effect to the right. In addition, it also provides that the rules of
the common law may be developed so as to limit a right as long as the
limitation is consistent with the provisions of section 8(3)(b).77
If section 8(1) of the Constitution governed the direct application of
the Bill of Rights to a horizontal dispute, the Court went on to note, the
Bill of Rights would apply directly to horizontal disputes in all
circumstances and section 8(2) read together with section 8(3) would
have no purpose. To avoid such an absurd result, the direct application
of the Bill of Rights to horizontal disputes had to be governed by section
8(2) and not by section 8(1).78
In so far as the second issue was concerned, the Court noted that the
appellants were members of the media who were expressly identified as
bearers of constitutional rights to freedom of expression and that there
could be no doubt that the law of defamation does affect the right to
freedom of expression. The Court noted further:
Given the intensity of the constitutional right in question, coupled with the
potential invasion of that right which could be occasioned by persons other
than the state or organs of state, it is clear that the right to freedom of
expression is of direct horizontal application in this case as contemplated by
section 8(2) of the Constitution.79
Apart from these exceptions, section 8(1) of the Bill of Rights regulates
the direct application of the Bill of Rights:
• to disputes between the state and private parties that are governed
by legislation, the common law or customary law (‘all law’)
• to disputes between private parties that are governed by legislation,
but not by the common law or customary law.
An interpretation of the Khumalo judgment
Following the Constitutional Court’s judgment in
Khumalo, it seems to be fairly clear that section 8(2)
of the Constitution regulates the direct application of
the Bill of Rights to disputes between private parties
that are governed by the common law or customary
law. It is not entirely clear, however, whether section
8(1) or section 8(2) regulates the direct application of
the Bill of Rights to disputes between private parties
that are governed by legislation.
Although the judgment in Khumalo deals with the
common law of defamation, Woolman argues that the
Constitutional Court held, by implication, that section
8(2) regulates the direct application of the Bill of
Rights to disputes between private parties that are
governed not only by the common law or customary
law, but also by legislation. In other words, section
8(2) regulates the direct application of the Bill of
Rights to all disputes between private persons.80
If this interpretation of the judgment in Khumalo is
correct, he goes on to argue, then certain criticisms
may be levelled against it. Among these are the
following:
• First, it defers – and potentially suppresses – the
direct application of the Bill of Rights to disputes
between private parties, irrespective of whether the
dispute is governed by legislation, the common law
or customary law.81
• Second, less law is subject to the direct
application of the Bill of Rights under the Khumalo
Court’s reading of the Constitution than it was
under the Court’s reading of the interim
Constitution in Du Plessis and Others v De Klerk
and Another.82 This is because it was generally
accepted that the Bill of Rights in the interim
Constitution did apply directly to disputes between
private persons governed by legislation.83
• Third, while the provisions of a statute or regulation
may not necessarily be subject to the direct
application of the Bill of Rights if the dispute was
between two private parties, they would
automatically be subject to the direct application
of the Bill of Rights if the dispute was between a
private party and the state. This distinction is
absurd because it infringes the doctrine of
objective unconstitutionality. This doctrine
provides, inter alia, that constitutional cases, and
thus the constitutionality of laws, cannot be
distinguished on the basis of the parties before the
court.84
Given the important obligations the Bill of Rights imposes on the bodies
and institutions that are bound by it, it is important to determine which
bodies and institutions fall within the scope of the terms ‘legislature’,
‘executive’, ‘judiciary’ and ‘all organs of state’. While the Constitution
itself defines what is meant by the term ‘organ of state’, it does not define
what is meant by the terms ‘legislature’, ‘executive’ and ‘judiciary’. This is
because the meaning of these terms may be discerned from the
provisions of the Constitution. Given that we have already discussed
what is meant by the terms ‘legislature’, ‘executive’ and ‘judiciary’ in
Part I of this book, we are only going to consider what is meant by the
term ‘organ of state’ here.
In terms of this definition, all organs of state may be divided into three
categories:
• First, any department of state or administration in the national,
provincial or local spheres of government
• Second, any functionary or institution exercising a power or
performing a function in terms of the Constitution or a provincial
constitution
• Third, any functionary or institution exercising a public power or
performing a public function in terms of any legislation.85
10.3.3.4.1 Introduction
In some cases the Bill of Rights will not apply directly to law and a court
will not be asked to measure the law against the specific right and then
to declare invalid the provision of the law. Instead, the Bill of Rights will
indirectly influence the way in which the court interprets the law, but
they will not declare the law unconstitutional. While sections 8(1) and
8(2) of the Constitution govern the direct vertical and horizontal
application of the Bill of Rights, section 39(2) of the Constitution
governs the indirect vertical and horizontal application of the Bill of
Rights. Section 39(2) provides that ‘[w]hen interpreting any legislation,
and when developing the common law or customary law, every court,
tribunal or forum must promote the spirit, purport and objects of the
Bill of Rights’.
When the Bill of Rights applies indirectly, the relationship between
the Bill of Rights and the ordinary law is not governed by the principles
and rules set out in the Bill of Rights. Instead, it is governed by the
principles and rules set out in the ordinary law (legislation, common
law and customary law). The manner in which the courts interpret
legislation or develop the common law and customary law, however,
must promote the values in the Bill of Rights.
Unlike the direct application of the Bill of Rights, therefore, the
indirect application of the Bill of Rights is not based on an enquiry as to
whether the law is in direct conflict with an identifiable right. Instead,
the court has to invoke the values that underlie the Bill of Rights and ask
whether it should interpret or develop the law to bring it in line with
these values.
This general obligation, the Court held further, does not mean:
that a court must, in each and every case where the common law is involved,
embark on an independent exercise as to whether the common law is in need
of development and, if so, how it is to be developed under section 39(2). At the
same time there might be circumstances where a court is obliged to raise the
matter on its own and require full argument from the parties.130
The obligation imposed on the courts to develop the common law,
therefore, is an extensive one. It requires the courts to be alert to the
normative framework of the Constitution not only when some startling
new development of the common law is in issue, but in all cases where
the incremental development of the rule is in issue.131
SUMMARY
This chapter deals with some of the technical questions relating to Bill
of Rights litigation. The application of the Bill of Rights gives rise to a
number of difficult questions. The two most important, however, are
who is entitled to claim the right in question and who is bound by the
right in question?
The rights guaranteed in the Bill of Rights may be claimed by both
natural and, in certain circumstances, juristic persons. In so far as
natural persons are concerned, the majority of rights state that they can
be claimed by ‘everyone’. The use of the word ‘everyone’ refers to South
African citizens as well as any other person who is physically present in
the country, irrespective of whether they are here legally or illegally.
Although the majority of rights state that they can be claimed by
‘everyone’, certain rights state that they may be claimed only by a
narrower category of natural persons, for example citizens, children or
detained persons. These rights may be claimed only by those natural
persons who fall into the definition of the relevant category.
In so far as juristic persons are concerned, section 8(4) of the
Constitution provides that ‘[a] juristic person is entitled to the rights in
the Bill of Rights to the extent required by the nature of the rights and
the nature of that juristic person’. To determine whether a juristic
person can claim a particular right, therefore, two factors must be taken
into account: whether the juristic person is capable of exercising the
right in question and whether the juristic person is entitled to exercise
the right in question.
Once a court has determined who can claim rights in terms of the
Bill of Rights, it has to ask a second question, namely, against whom can
these rights be claimed? In other words, the court has to ask who is
bound to respect the rights claimed by either a natural or juristic
person. Although ‘everyone’ is entitled to claim the benefit of the rights
(or at least most of the rights) in the Bill of Rights, not everyone is bound
by every right contained in the Bill of Rights. This is because while the
Bill of Rights is always binding on the state, it is not always binding on
private persons.
When it comes to the question of who is bound by the Bill of Rights,
it is important to distinguish between the direct application of the Bill of
Rights and the indirect application of the Bill of Rights as well as
between the vertical and horizontal application of the Bill of Rights. This
is because in South Africa the Bill of Rights applies not only directly and
indirectly, but also vertically and sometimes horizontally. Section 8(1)
of the Constitution governs the direct vertical application of the Bill of
Rights while section 8(2) governs the direct horizontal application.
Section 39(2) of the Constitution governs the indirect vertical and
horizontal application of the Bill of Rights.
These rights were selected based first, on their general importance and second, on whether
1
these rights are likely to be studied by students in other LLB courses. Provisions dealing
with a fair trial, administrative justice and family law are therefore not discussed in this
book.
2 Currie, I and De Waal, J (2013) The Bill of Rights Handbook 6th ed 24.
3 See ch 6 (Separation of powers and judicial authority) where the courts possessing
constitutional jurisdiction are discussed.
4 Currie and De Waal (2013) 26.
5 Currie and De Waal (2013) 26–7.
6 Freedman, DW ‘Constitutional law: Bill of Rights’ in Joubert, WA (ed) (2012) Law of South
Africa 2nd ed Vol 5 Part 4 para 2.
7 United Nations (1996) International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights available at
http://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/pages/ccpr.aspx.
8 United Nations (1996) International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights
available at
http://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/pages/CESCR.aspx.
9 Dlamini, CRM (1995) Human Rights in Africa: Which way South Africa? 5–6.
10 Dlamini (1995) 5–6.
11 Viljoen, F (2012) International Human Rights Law in Africa 2nd ed 5.
12 Du Plessis, LM (1999) An Introduction to Law 3rd ed 168–9.
13 Du Plessis (1999) 168–9.
14 Du Plessis (1999) 168–9.
15 See Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (CCT 23/96) [1996]
ZACC 26; 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC) (6 September 1996) paras 77–8
(First Certification) where the Court held that socio-economic rights are no less justiciable
than civil and political right, nor would a court adjudicating on them necessarily lead to a
breach of the separation of powers. See also Islamic Unity Convention v Independent
Broadcasting Authority and Others (CCT36/01) [2002] ZACC 3; 2002 (4) SA 294; 2002 (5)
BCLR 433 (11 April 2002); and S v Mamabolo (CCT 44/00) [2001] ZACC 17; 2001 (3) SA 409
(CC); 2001 (5) BCLR 449 (CC) (11 April 2001) para 41 where the Court held that ‘the right to
freedom of expression cannot be said automatically to trump the right to human dignity.
The right to dignity is at least as worthy of protection as is the right to freedom of
expression. How these two rights are to be balanced, in principle and in any particular set
of circumstances, is not a question that can or should be addressed here. What is clear
though and must be stated, is that freedom of expression does not enjoy superior status in
our law.’ [footnote omitted]
16 See Currie and De Waal (2013) 24 and 29.
17 Du Plessis M, Penfold G and Brickhill J (2013) Constitutional Litigation 9 and 19.
18 Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill (2013) 107.
19 Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill (2013) 20.
20 Ss 19, 20 and 22 of the Constitution.
21 S 28 of the Constitution.
22 S 35 of the Constitution.
23 In law, a natural person is a human being as opposed to a juristic person which may be a
private (business entity) or public (government) organisation.
24 A juristic person is an artificial entity through which the law allows a group of natural
persons to act as if it were a single composite individual for certain purposes. This legal
fiction does not mean these entities are human beings, but rather that the law recognises
them as having legal personality and allows them to act as natural persons for some
purposes, most commonly in lawsuits, property ownership and contracts. For example, a
company or a club will act as a juristic person.
25 FNM v The Refugee Appeal Board and Others (71738/2016) [2018] ZAGPPHC 532; [2018] 4
All SA 228 (GP); 2019 (1) SA 468 (GP) (12 July 2018); Minister of Home Affairs and Others v
Watchenuka and Others (010/2003) [2003] ZASCA 142; [2004] 1 All SA 21 (SCA) (28
November 2003); Tantoush v Refugee Appeal Board and Others (13182/06) [2007] ZAGPHC
191; 2008 (1) SA 232 (T) (11 September 2007).
26 Khosa and Others v Minister of Social Development and Others, Mahlaule and Another v
Minister of Social Development (CCT 13/03, CCT 12/03) [2004] ZACC 11; 2004 (6) SA 505
(CC); 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC) (4 March 2004) para 47.
27 Dawood and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others; Shalabi and Another v Minister
of Home Affairs and Others; Thomas and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others
(CCT35/99) [2000] ZACC 8; 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC); 2000 (8) BCLR 837 (CC) (7 June 2000)
para 37.
28 Lawyers for Human Rights and Others v Minister of Home Affairs and Others (CCT 18/03)
[2004] ZACC 12; 2004 (4) SA 125 (CC); 2004 (7) BCLR 775 (CC) (9 March 2004) para 27.
29 Christian Lawyers Association of SA v Minister of Health 1998 (11) BCLR 1434 (T) 1441.
30 Christian Lawyers Association 1441.
31 (CCT27/98) [1999] ZACC 7; 1999 (4) SA 469; 1999 (6) BCLR 615 (26 May 1999).
32 South African National Defence Union para 23.
33 South African National Defence Union para 26.
34 National Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals v Minister of Justice and
Constitutional Development and Another (29677/2013) [2014] ZAGPPHC 763 (8 October
2014) para 20.
35 First Certification paras 57–8.
36 Religious rights and their manifestation in one’s ‘religious and cultural identity’ were in
issue in the case of MEC for Education: KwaZulu-Natal and Others v Pillay (CCT 51/06)
[2007] ZACC 21; 2008 (1) 474 (CC); 2008 (2) BCLR 99 (CC) (5 October 2007). See para 85 in
particular.
37 Strydom v Nederduitse Gereformeerde Gemeente Moreleta Park 2009 (4) SA 510 (T).
38 Strydom para 23.
39 Strydom para 37.
40 (CCT254/16) [2017] ZACC 40; 2018 (2) SA 23 (CC); 2018 (2) BCLR 240 (CC) (14 November
2017).
41 Act 3 of 2000.
42 State Information Technology para 18.
43 State Information Technology para 25.
44 State Information Technology para 26.
45 State Information Technology para 27.
46 State Information Technology para 27.
47 See Chapter 11 (Constitutional Remedies).
48 Child, K (28 November 2018) Listeriosis class-action lawsuit one step closer Times Live
available at https://www.timeslive.co.za/news/south-africa/2018-11-28-listeriosis-class-
action-lawsuit-one-step-closer/.
49 Independent Electoral Commission v Langeberg Municipality (CCT 49/00) [2001] ZACC 23;
2001 (3) SA 925 (CC); 2001 (9) BCLR 883 (CC) (7 June 2001) para 15.
50 See, for example, Ferreira v Levin NO and Others; Vryenhoek and Others v Powell NO and
Others (CCT5/95) [1995] ZACC 13; 1996 (1) SA 984 (CC); 1996 (1) BCLR 1 (6 December
1995); Minister of Home Affairs v Eisenberg & Associates In re: Eisenberg & Associates v
Minister of Home Affairs and Others (CCT15/03) [2003] ZACC 10; 2003 (8) BCLR 838; 2003
(5) SA 281 (CC) (27 June 2003); Kruger v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others
(CCT 57/07) [2008] ZACC 17; 2009 (1) SA 417 (CC); 2009 (3) BCLR 268 (CC) (2 October
2008); Viking Pony Africa Pumps (Pty) Ltd t/a Tricom Africa v Hidro-Tech Systems (Pty) Ltd
and Another (CCT 34/10) [2010] ZACC 21; 2011 (1) SA 327 (CC); 2011 (2) BCLR 207 (CC) (23
November 2010); Tulip Diamonds FZE v Minister for Justice and Constitutional
Development and Others (CCT 93/12) [2013] ZACC 19; 2013 (10) BCLR 1180 (CC); 2013 (2)
SACR 443 (CC) (13 June 2013).
51 Kruger para 21.
52 Kruger para 90.
53 See Currie and De Waal (2013) 77.
54 Currie and De Waal (2013) 77.
55 2004 (4) SA 125 (CC).
56 Lawyers for Human Rights para 24.
57 (CCT 25/12) [2012] ZACC 28; 2013 (3) BCLR 251 (CC) (29 November 2012) para 23.
58 Giant Concerts para 32.
59 Giant Concerts para 33.
60 Giant Concerts para 34.
61 Giant Concerts para 35.
62 See especially Ferreira v Levin NO and Others; Vryenhoek and Others v Powell NO and
Others (CCT5/95) [1995] ZACC 13; 1996 (1) SA 984 (CC); 1996 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) (6 December
1995); Minister of Home Affairs v Eisenberg & Associates In re: Eisenberg & Associates v
Minister of Home Affairs and Others (CCT15/03) [2003] ZACC 10; 2003 (5) SA 281 (CC); 2003
(8) BCLR 838 (CC) (27 June 2003); and Kruger v President of the Republic of South Africa
and Others (CCT 57/07) [2008] ZACC 17; 2009 (1) SA 417 (CC); 2009 (3) BCLR 268 (CC) (2
October 2008).
63 Giant Concerts para 41.
64 See specifically Trustees for the time being of the Children’s Resource Centre Trust and Others
v Pioneer Foods (Pty) Ltd and Others (050/2012) [2012] ZASCA 182; 2013 (2) SA 213 (SCA);
2013 (3) BCLR 279 (SCA); [2013] 1 All SA 648 (SCA) (29 November 2012); and Mukaddam v
Pioneer Foods (Pty) Ltd and Others (CCT 131/12) [2013] ZACC 23; 2013 (5) SA 89 (CC); 2013
(10) BCLR 1135 (CC) (27 June 2013).
65 Mukaddam paras 23–5.
66 The Trustees for the Time Being para 26.
67 Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill (2013) 113. See Chapter 12 on Constitutional Remedies for
an in-depth discussion of these remedies.
68 A particularly relevant case in this regard is Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security
(Centre for Applied Legal Studies Intervening) (CCT 48/00) [2001] ZACC 22; 2001 (4) SA 938
(CC); 2001 (10) BCLR 995 (CC) (16 August 2001) para 54.
69 Currie and De Waal (2013) 41.
70 Currie and De Waal (2013) 41.
71 See Hutchinson, AC (1990) Mice under a chair: Democracy, courts and the administrative
state University of Toronto Law Journal 40(3):374–404 at 379–80.
72 S 8(2).
73 Khumalo and Others v Holomisa (CCT53/01) [2002] ZACC 12; 2002 (5) SA 401 (CC); 2002
(8) BCLR 771 (CC) (14 June 2002) para 31. S 8(2) of the Constitution stipulates that ‘[a]
provision of the Bill of Rights binds a natural or a juristic person if, and to the extent that, it
is applicable, taking into account the nature of the right and the nature of any duty imposed
by the right’. S 8(3) goes on to stipulate that ‘[w]hen applying a provision of the Bill of Rights
to a natural or juristic person in terms of subsection (2), a court: (a) in order to give effect to
a right in the Bill, must apply, or if necessary develop, the common law to the extent that
legislation does not give effect to that right; and (b) may develop rules of the common law
to limit the right, provided that the limitation is in accordance with section 36(1)’.
74 Khumalo para 31.
75 Khumalo paras 30–4.
76 Khumalo para 31.
77 Khumalo para 31.
78 Khumalo para 32.
79 Khumalo para 33.
80 See Woolman, S ‘Application’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2013) Constitutional
Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 31.6.
81 Woolman (2013) 31.7.
82 (CCT8/95) [1996] ZACC 10; 1996 (3) SA 850 (CC); 1996 (5) BCLR 658 (CC) (15 May 1996).
83 Woolman (2013) 31.8.
84 Woolman (2013) 31.8.
85 Freedman (2012) para 7.
86 Du Plessis M, Penfold G and Brickhill J (2013) Constitutional Litigation 3.
87 Du Plessis, Penfold and Brickhill 7.
88 2008 (1) SA 223 (T) 225G–226A.
89 Black Sash Trust v Minister of Social Development and Others (Freedom Under Law NPC
Intervening) (CCT48/17) [2017] ZACC 20; 2017 (9) BCLR 1089 (CC) (15 June 2017) (Black
Sash 2) para 24(1), where Minister Bathabile Dlamini was joined in her personal capacity to
account for the failures to ensure that a new contract was entered into for the payment of
social welfare grants (discussed more fully in ch 11).
90 (410/09) [2010] ZASCA 94; 2010 (5) SA 457 (SCA); [2010] 4 All SA 561 (SCA) (19 July 2010).
91 Act 3 of 2000.
92 Calibre Clinical Consultants para 20.
93 S 239(b)(i) of the Constitution.
94 S 239(b)(ii) of the Constitution; Calibre Clinical Consultants para 19.
95 Calibre Clinical Consultants para 24.
96 Calibre Clinical Consultants para 38.
97 Calibre Clinical Consultants para 40.
98 Act 66 of 1995.
99 Calibre Clinical Consultants para 41.
100 (CCT8/95) [1996] ZACC 10; 1996 (3) SA 850 (CC); 1996 (5) BCLR 568 (CC) (15 May 1996).
101 Du Plessis para 129. Although the Bill of Rights in the interim Constitution did not apply
directly to horizontal disputes, it did apply indirectly. S 35(3) of the interim Constitution
thus provided that ‘[i]n the interpretation of any law and the application and development
of the common law and customary law, a court shall have due regard to the spirit, purport
and objects of [the Bill of Rights]’. The approach adopted by the Constitutional Court in Du
Plessis resulted in much academic debate and criticism. See, for example, Woolman, S and
Davis, D (1996) The last laugh: Du Plessis v De Klerk, classical liberalism, Creole liberalism
and the application of fundamental rights under the interim and final Constitutions South
African Journal on Human Rights 12(3):361–404 at 361 and Sprigman, C and Osborne, M
(1999) Du Plessis is not dead: South Africa’s 1996 Constitution and the application of the
Bill of Rights to private disputes South African Journal on Human Rights 15(1):25–51 at 25.
102 (CCT 29/10) [2011] ZACC 13; 2011 (8) BCLR 761 (CC) (11 April 2011).
103 Juma Musjid para 58.
104 Juma Musjid para 58. See also Khumalo para 33.
105 Juma Musjid para 60.
106 Juma Musjid para 58.
107 Freedman (2012) para 9.
108 S v Mhlungu and Others (CCT25/94) [1995] ZACC 4; 1995 (3) SA 867 (CC); 1995 (7) BCLR
793 (CC) (8 June 1995) para 59; Zantsi v Council of State, Ciskei and Others (CCT24/94)
[1995] ZACC 9; 1995 (4) SA 615 (CC); 1995 (10) BCLR 1424 (CC) (22 September 1995) paras
2–5; Ferreira; Vryenhoek para 199; S v Bequinot (CCT24/95) [1996] ZACC 21; 1996 (12)
BCLR 1588; 1997 (2) SA 887 (18 November 1996) paras 12–13; National Coalition for Gay
and Lesbian Equality and Another v Minister of Justice and Others (CCT11/98) [1998] ZACC
15; 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC); 1998 (12) BCLR 1517 (CC) (9 October 1998) para 21.
109 (CCT283/16, CCT293/16, CCT294/16, CCT283/16) [2017] ZACC 31; 2017 (6) SA 287 (CC);
2017 (11) BCLR 1370 (CC) (29 August 2017).
110 Jordaan para 6
111 Jordaan para 8.
112 See s 39(2) of the Constitution.
113 See Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic Offences and Others v Hyundai Motor
Distributors (Pty) Ltd and Others In re: Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd and Others v
Smit NO and Others (CCT1/00) [2000] ZACC 12; 2001 (1) SA 545 (CC); 2000 (10) BCLR 1079
(CC) (25 August 2000) para 22.
114 Hyundai para 23.
115 See South African Police Service v Police and Prisons Civil Rights Union and Another (CCT
89/10) [2011] ZACC 21; 2011 (6) SA 1 (CC); 2011 (9) BCLR 992 (CC) (9 June 2011) para 29.
116 Daniels v Campbell and Others (CCT 40/03) [2004] ZACC 14; 2004 (5) SA 331 (CC); 2004 (7)
BCLR 735 (CC) (11 March 2004) para 83.
117 Daniels para 24.
118 Hyundai para 22.
119 Daniels para 24.
120 (CCT 77/08) [2009] ZACC 11; 2010 (2) SA 181 (CC); 2009 (10) BCLR 978 (CC) (7 May 2009).
121 Act 56 of 2001.
122 Bertie Van Zyl para 40.
123 Bishop, M and Brickhill, J (2010) Constitutional Law Juta’s Annual Survey of South African
Law 224.
124 Bishop and Brickhill (2010) para 224.
125 Bishop and Brickhill (2010) para 224.
126 Bishop and Brickhill (2010) para 225.
127 The Constitutional text refers to ‘customary law’, which is why we use the term here.
However, scholars have argued that the term ‘customary law’ has its origins in colonialism
and reinforces the marginalisation of what is widely known as customary law and does not
capture the fact that this concept of law includes the interaction of ‘rules’ and ‘processes’ in
non-state normative orders. Sindiso Mnisi-Weeks and Aninka Claassens use the term
‘vernacular law’ and explain the reasons for this as follows: ‘Our preferred word
“vernacular”, when used in relation to law and its underlying values, carries a similar
meaning to that which the term has in relation to language: namely, that it is emic, locally
evolved and not imposed from the outside nor judged in terms of an external logic or
scheme. This is unlike the word “customary”, which has been tainted – especially as it is
often associated with official forms of the law, rather than what is commonly coming to be
known as “living customary law”. The use of the term “living customary law” by the courts
introduces further complexity, however, in that one can no longer be sure whether the
reference is to that form of the living law that is articulated by the courts or that which
continues to develop within the groupings that use vernacular law.’
See Mnisi Weeks, S and Claassens, A (2011) Tensions between vernacular values that
prioritise basic needs and state versions of customary law that contradict them Stellenbosch
Law Review 22(2):823–44.
128 See, for example, Du Plessis; Amod v Multilateral Motor Vehicle Accidents Fund (CCT4/98)
[1998] ZACC 11; 1998 (4) SA 753 (CC); 1998 (10) BCLR 1207 (CC) (27 August 1998).
129 Carmichele para 39.
130 Carmichele para 39.
131 See K v Minister of Safety and Security (CCT52/04) [2005] ZACC 8; 2005 (6) SA 419 (CC);
2005 (9) BCLR 835 (CC); [2005] 8 BLLR 749 (CC) (13 June 2005) para 17.
132 For an interesting and lively debate on this topic, see Fagan, A (2010) The secondary role of
the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights in the common law’s development South
African Law Journal 127(4):611–27; Davis, DM (2012) How many positivist legal
philosophers can be made to dance on the head of a pin? A reply to Professor Fagan South
African Law Journal 129(1):59–72; Fagan, A (2012) A straw man, three red herrings, and a
closet rule-worshipper: A rejoinder to Davis JP South African Law Journal 129(4):788–98;
Davis, DM (2013) The importance of reading: A rebuttal to the jurisprudence of Anton
Fagan South African Law Journal 130(1):52–9.
133 Davis (2012) 67.
134 Davis (2012) 67–8.
135 Jordaan para 8.
136 (CCT36/02) [2003] ZACC 12; 2003 (6) SA 505 (CC); 2003 (10) BCLR 1100 (CC) (28 August
2003) para 27. See also Carmichele para 54; Paulsen and Another v Slip Knot Investments
777 (Pty) Limited (CCT 61/14) [2015] ZACC 5; 2015 (3) SA 479 (CC); 2015 (5) BCLR 509 (CC)
(24 March 2015) para 118; K para 15; and Salem Party Club and Others v Salem Community
and Others (CCT26/17) [2017] ZACC 46; 2018 (3) SA 1 (CC); 2018 (3) BCLR 342 (CC) (11
December 2017) para 68.
137 Thebus para 27.
138 Thebus para 28.
139 Thebus para 32.
140 Thebus para 26.
141 (CCT52/04) [2005] ZACC 8; 2005 (6) SA 419 (CC); 2005 (9) BCLR 835 (CC) (13 June 2005).
142 K para 16.
143 (CCT 57/12) [2013] ZACC 14; 2013 (4) SA 415 (CC); 2013 (8) BCLR 918 (CC) (30 May 2013)
para 24. See also Gumede (born Shange) v President of the Republic of South Africa and
Others (CCT 50/08) [2008] ZACC 23; 2009 (3) SA 152 (CC); 2009 (3) BCLR 243 (CC) (8
December 2008) para 22; Alexkor Ltd and Another v Richtersveld Community and Others
(CCT19/03) [2003] ZACC 18; 2004 (5) SA 460 (CC); 2003 (12) BCLR 1301 (CC) (14 October
2003); Bhe and Others v Khayelitsha Magistrate and Others (CCT 49/03) [2004] ZACC 17;
2005 (1) SA 580 (CC); 2005 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) (15 October 2004) para 41; First Certification
para 197.
144 Dikoko v Mokhatla (CCT62/05) [2006] ZACC 10; 2006 (6) SA 235 (CC); 2007 (1) BCLR 1
(CC) (3 August 2006).
145 Dikoko para 113.
146 Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers (CCT 53/03) [2004] ZACC 7; 2005 (1) SA
217 (CC); 2004 (12) BCLR 1268 (CC) (1 October 2004).
147 Port Elizabeth para 37.
148 Patel, L (2015) Decolonizing Educational Research: From Ownership to Answerability 3.
149 National Development Plan: Vision for 2030 (2011) 290.
Limitation
11.1 Introduction
11.6 Reasonable and justifiable in an open and democratic society based on human dignity,
equality and freedom
11.6.1 Reconsidering the role of proportionality
11.6.2 The purpose of the limitation
11.6.3 The rational connection requirement
11.6.4 Less restrictive, alternative means of achieving the end
11.6.5 Balancing and proportionality proper
11.6.5.1 Introduction
11.6.5.2 Stacking the rights side of the balancing scales
11.6.5.3 Stacking the limiting measure’s side of the balancing scales
11.6.5.4 Balancing and proportionality proper
11.6.5.5 Reasonable accommodation
Summary
11.1 Introduction
Although the rights protected in the Bill of Rights are fundamental and,
therefore, lie at the heart of the Constitution and the democracy it
envisions, they are not absolute. Instead, the Constitution expressly
provides that they may be limited in certain specific circumstances in
order to promote the public interest or to protect other rights. For
example, legislation prohibiting corporal punishment in Christian
schools may well limit the right to freedom of religion, but the
Constitutional Court held that this was a justifiable limitation of this
right.1 Section 7(3) of the Constitution thus provides that ‘[t]he rights in
the Bill of Rights are subject to the limitations contained or referred to
in section 36, or elsewhere in the Bill’. As the provisions of this section
indicate, the Constitution distinguishes between those limitations
authorised by section 36 and those authorised ‘elsewhere’ in the Bill of
Rights.
Apart from the fact that it applies to all of the fundamental rights
protected in the Bill of Rights, section 36 of the Constitution also
provides that the rights in the Bill of Rights must be limited according to
the same criteria. These criteria are set out in section 36(1) itself, which
provides as follows:
The rights in the Bill of Rights may be limited only in terms of law of general
application to the extent that the limitation is reasonable and justifiable in an
open and democratic society based on human dignity, equality and freedom,
taking into account all relevant factors, including:
(a) the nature of the right;
(b) the importance of the purpose of the limitation;
(c) the nature and extent of the limitation;
(d) the relation between the limitation and its purpose; and
(e) less restrictive means to achieve the purpose.
Besides acknowledging that the fundamental rights protected in the Bill
of Rights may be limited, and identifying the criteria according to which
a limitation must be justified, a limitation clause like section 36(1) also
serves a number of other goals.
One of these goals is to address the counter-majoritarian dilemma.
As we discussed in Chapter 2, this dilemma refers to the argument that
judicial review is undemocratic because it confers the power on
unelected and unaccountable judges to substitute their decisions for
those of the democratically elected representatives of the people. When
the courts declare a statutory enactment or executive action to be
unconstitutional, therefore, they are not exercising power on behalf of
the majority, but against it. Although it does not completely resolve the
counter-majoritarian dilemma, section 36(1) ameliorates it by
conceding that democratically elected Parliament may limit the
fundamental rights of individuals, but only within the rigid framework
provided by the limitation clause.2
Section 36(1) also has important implications for the manner in
which the legislative, executive and judicial branches of government
exercise their powers and perform their functions. In so far as the
legislature is concerned, a limitation clause provides an analytical
framework within which legislation must be conceived, drafted, and
debated. A similar point may be made in so far as the executive is
concerned. Executive action must be arranged, developed and
implemented in accordance with the analytical framework established
by the limitation clause. A limitation clause also imposes an obligation
on the courts to consider conflicting public and private interests in an
open, orderly and structured manner.3
Both the first stage and the second stage themselves encompass a
number of enquiries. During the first stage, it must be determined
whether the party who claims that his or her fundamental right has
been limited is a bearer of that right, whether the party who limited the
right (the perpetrator) is bound by it and whether the perpetrator’s
actions (which must take the form of law or conduct) have in fact
limited the right by infringing or violating it.6
During the second stage, it must be determined, in those cases in
which section 36(1) applies, whether the right has been limited by law
of general application and, if so, whether that law is reasonable and
justifiable in an open and democratic society based on human dignity,
equality and freedom; or, where a specific limitation clause applies,
whether the requirements of that specific limitation clause have been
satisfied.
Before turning to discuss each stage in more detail, however, it will
be helpful to set out and discuss the evolution of the general limitation
clause. This is because the nature of the general limitation enquiry has
changed over time. Initially, section 33(1) of the interim Constitution7
appeared to require a structured, sequential enquiry. The
Constitutional Court, however, rejected this approach early in its
jurisprudence and replaced it with a unified, balancing enquiry and this
approach was adopted by the drafters of the Constitution when they
composed section 36.
Although this unified, balancing approach confers a wide discretion
on the Constitutional Court and thus allows it to resolve disputes on a
case-by-case basis in a manner that both promotes the values on which
the Constitution is founded and upholds the separation of powers
between the judiciary, the legislature and the executive, it has also
made it difficult for other courts, other branches of the state, members
of the legal profession and members of the general public to
understand the limitation analysis and predict its outcome in a specific
case.
11.4.1 Introduction
As pointed out above, during the first stage of the two-stage limitation
analysis, it must be determined whether the party who claims that his
or her fundamental right has been limited is a bearer of that right,
whether the party who limited the right (the perpetrator) is bound by it
and whether the perpetrator’s actions (which must take the form of law
or conduct) have limited the right by infringing or violating it. Although
each of these questions is dealt with in separate chapters in this book, it
will be helpful to discuss the third question in a bit more detail.
In Ex parte Minister of Safety and Security: In re S v Walters,35 the
Constitutional Court held that when it comes to determining whether
the perpetrator’s actions – which may take the form of either a law or
conduct – have infringed a right protected by the Bill of Rights, a court
must examine ‘(a) the content and scope of the relevant protected
right(s) and (b) the meaning and effect of the impugned enactment [or
conduct] to see whether there is any limitation of (a) by (b)’.36
Over the past 25 years, the Constitutional Court has adopted two
different approaches to the first stage of the limitation analysis. In some
cases, the Court has set out and discussed the content and scope of the
right in comprehensive detail before going on to consider whether (and
later to what extent) the impugned law or conduct infringes the right. In
other cases, it has not. Instead, the Court has simply accepted
notionally37 or even hypothetically38 that a right has been limited and
then proceeded to the second stage of the limitation analysis without
much analytical rigour.
11.4.2.1 Introduction
In the chapters that follow we will discuss the scope and content of a
selected number of specific rights in detail. However, it is important
here to explain more generally how the courts proceed when deciding
what the scope and content of a specific right is. When it comes to
determining the content and scope of a right, the Constitutional Court
has held that the text of the Constitution must be interpreted
generously, purposively and contextually.40 In S v Makwanyane, for
example, the Court held that while it is important to pay ‘due regard to
the language that has been used’, the interpretation of the Bill of Rights
must be ‘generous’ and ‘purposive’ and ‘[give] expression to the
underlying values of the Constitution’.41
This interpretive approach requires a court to identify the purpose of
a protected right by analysing the history of the right; the language in
which the right has been expressed, the concepts encompassed by the
right; the manner in which the right has been interpreted both in South
Africa and comparable foreign jurisdictions; the other provisions of the
Constitution and the Bill of Rights; and the core values on which the
Constitution is founded.42 International human rights law may also
need to be taken into account.43 Finally, the interpretation should also
be generous, rather than legalistic so as to endow individuals with the
full benefits of the Bill of Rights.44
Although a generous, purposive and contextual approach to the
interpretation of the rights protected by the Bill of Rights will inevitably
narrow the content and scope of a right at the level of its definition, the
Constitutional Court has urged the courts not to unnecessarily restrict
rights by adopting an excessively narrow interpretation that would
result in the premature termination of the limitation analysis at the
expense of the litigant.45 In S v Zuma,46 for example, Kentridge AJ
warned that ‘the two-stage approach may call for a broader
interpretation of the fundamental right, qualified only at the second
stage’.47
An important consequence of Kentridge AJ’s warning is that it may
result in the content and scope of some rights being defined so broadly
that they include conduct that is not worthy of constitutional
protection. In these sorts of cases, however, it will usually be easy to
justify a statutory enactment prohibiting such conduct. This is what
happened in De Reuck v Director of Public Prosecutions.48 In this case,
the applicant, who was a film producer, was found in possession of
child pornography and was charged in the regional magistrates’ court
with contravening section 27(1) of the Film and Publications Act (the
Films Act).49 This section provided that a person committed an offence
if he or she created, produced, imported or possessed any publication
or film which contained child pornography.
After he was charged, the applicant applied to the Johannesburg
High Court for an order declaring section 27(1) of the Films Act to be
unconstitutional and invalid on the ground that it infringed the right to
freedom of expression guaranteed in section 16(1) of the Constitution.
The High Court dismissed his application and the applicant then
appealed directly to the Constitutional Court which also dismissed his
application.
In arriving at this conclusion, the Court followed the two-stage
enquiry. This meant that it had to determine, first, whether section
27(1) of the Films Act infringed section 16(1) of the Constitution and if it
did, second, whether that infringement was a reasonable and justifiable
limitation in an open and democratic society based on human dignity,
equality and freedom.50
In so far as the first stage was concerned, the Director of Public
Prosecutions (DPP) argued that, like in the United States, child
pornography should be excluded from the content and scope of the
right to freedom of expression because it does not serve any of the
values that underlie the right, namely truth seeking, free political
activity and self-fulfilment. It followed, therefore, that the prohibition of
child pornography in section 27(1) of the Films Act did not infringe the
right to freedom of expression and did not have to be justified in terms
of the general limitation clause.51
Although child pornography was classified as unprotected speech in
the United States, the Court held, the same approach could not be
adopted in South Africa. This is because in South Africa all forms of
expression except for those listed in section 16(2) of the Constitution
are protected by section 16(1). Child pornography, therefore, was not
excluded from the content and scope of the right to freedom of
expression and the prohibition in section 27(1) of the Films Act would
be constitutionally valid only if it satisfied the requirements of the
general limitation clause.52
After setting out these principles, the Court turned to consider
whether section 27(1) of the Films Act was a reasonable and justifiable
limitation of the right to freedom of expression in an open and
democratic society based on human dignity, equality and freedom. The
Court found that it was for a wide range of reasons and dismissed the
appeal.53
11.5.1 Introduction
Once a court has determined that an impugned law or conduct limits a
protected right, it must turn its attention to the second stage of the
limitation analysis, where it must consider whether the limitation of the
right is justified. If the court finds that the limitation is justified, the
impugned law or conduct has passed the test of constitutionality. If the
court finds that the limitation is not justified, then the impugned law or
conduct will be unconstitutional and hence invalid. At this stage, there
are two independent requirements that must be met to justify the
limitation of a right: first, the limitation must be ‘in terms of law of
general application’ and, second, the limitation must be ‘reasonable
and justifiable in an open and democratic society based on equality,
freedom and human dignity’.77 Each of these requirements will be
discussed in turn.
11.5.2.1 Introduction
The first hurdle to be cleared at the justification stage of the enquiry is
that the limitation must be ‘sourced’ in a law of general application.78
An important consequence of this requirement is that the limitation of a
protected right by something other than a law of general application
will always be unconstitutional, while the limitation of a protected right
by a law of general application may be saved from unconstitutionality
by the limitation clause.
The rationale for this requirement is based partly on the principle of
democracy and partly on the rule of law. The principle of democracy
provide that the rights in the Bill of Rights should be limited only by
laws passed by a democratically elected legislature as representative of
the people, and the principle of the rule of law provides that limitations
should apply equally to all and should not be arbitrary in their scope
and application.79
What exactly is required by a law of general application is unclear as
the Constitutional Court has not articulated a general set of
requirements that must be met. Instead, it has dealt with this
requirement episodically and without much fervour. What is clear from
the text of section 36(1), however, is that a limitation must take the form
of a ‘law’ and that the content of that law must be ‘generally
applicable’.80
11.6.5.1 Introduction
Once it has been determined that the end is legitimate, that the means
meet the end and that the court has declined to raise alternative, less
restrictive means, then at this point there is something worth balancing.
This stage involves balancing and proportionality which turns
intimately on the facts. In broad terms, this stage involves the balancing
of competing goods: the right and the limiting measure that serves a
constitutionally acceptable purpose. In Walters, the Constitutional
Court described this process as follows:
In essence this requires a weighing-up of the nature and importance of the
right(s) that are limited together with the extent of the limitation as against the
importance and purpose of the limiting enactment. Section 36(1) of the
Constitution spells out these factors that have to be put into the scales in
making a proportional evaluation of all the counterpoised rights and interests
involved.165
Before considering how this balancing process might unfold, there are a
few general comments to be made about how the right and the
limitation influence the proportionality process generally.
At other times, the Constitutional Court has held that certain rights are
not paramount, implying some form of hierarchy.171 Similarly, the
courts have noted that we do not place the same premium on privacy as
other countries.172 If there is some hierarchy of rights, then logically
those rights which arefor example, the limiting measuredirectly based
on the founding constitutional values of dignity, freedom and equality
are likely to receive greater attention than others.
The second and more difficult element of the rights side of the scale
is determining which portion of the right the limiting measure strikes at.
Does it strike at the core of the right or its periphery (or ‘penumbra’)?
Or, to put it another way, what is the ‘extent of the limitation’, which is
one of the factors listed in section 36(1).173 The answer to this question
has as much to do with the nature of the right as it does the limitation
(not every right is capable of part-infringement).
If the first stage of the two-stage enquiry is comprehensive, then the
groundwork for this aspect of the limitation analysis will already have
been covered in that the content and scope of the right in question will
have been examined in some detail. What is left then is to locate the
impact of the limiting measure on the right and assign it a nominal
value to be balanced against the competing value of the limiting
measure. Unfortunately, as part of a more general reluctance to give
content to rights,174 the Constitutional Court has refused to undertake a
detailed analysis of the core and periphery of each right on a number of
occasions.
The impact that the limiting measure has on the right is a
particularly important aspect of the proportionality enquiry. This is
because is sets the bar to be met by the justification.175 In other words,
the point of reference is the right itself. As the Constitutional Court itself
stated in S v Manamela (Director-General of Justice Intervening),176 the
greater the impact is, the more convincing the justification for the
limitation must be:
As a general rule, the more serious the impact of the measure on the right, the
more persuasive or compelling the justification must be. Ultimately, the
question is one of degree to be assessed in the concrete legislative and social
setting of the measure, paying due regard to the means which are realistically
available in our country at this stage, but without losing sight of the ultimate
values to be protected.177
A more recent example can be found in Teddy Bear Clinic for Abused
Children v Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development.219 In this
case, section 15 and 16 of the Criminal Law (Sexual Offences and
Related Matters) Amendment Act220 created the offences of statutory
rape and statutory sexual assault respectively. These offences made it a
crime for children aged 12 to 15 years (adolescents) to engage in
consensual sexual conduct – including hugging, kissing, masturbation
and sexual intercourse – with each other. The applicants applied for an
order declaring sections 15 and 16 of the Sexual Offences Act to be
unconstitutional and invalid on the grounds that the infringed
children’s rights to dignity and privacy, as well as the best interest of the
child principle.
Apart from arguing that sections 15 and 16 of the Sexual Offences
Act did not infringe these rights, the state argued that even if they did,
this limitation was reasonable and justifiable because it was aimed at
deterring adolescents from prematurely engaging in consensual sexual
conduct which could harm their development and increase the risks
associated with sexual conduct, for example unwanted pregnancy and
sexually transmitted disease. In response to this argument, the
applicants presented expert evidence in court that showed that sections
15 and 16 would not deter adolescents from engaging in harmful sexual
conduct. Instead, they did the opposite and increased the likelihood of
adolescents engaging in unsafe sexual conduct. It followed, therefore,
that the offences created by sections 15 and 16 were not rationally
related to their purpose.221
The Constitutional Court accepted the applicant’s argument largely
on the ground that the state had failed to adduce any evidence
supporting its arguments or challenging the applicant’s expert
evidence. The Court, therefore, was left with no choice but to accept the
evidence present by the applicant’s experts.222 In arriving at this
conclusion, the Court noted the following:
where a justification analysis rests on factual or policy considerations, the
party seeking to justify the impugned law – usually the organ of state
responsible for its administration – must put material regarding such
considerations before the court. Furthermore, “[w]here the state fails to
produce data and there are cogent objective factors pointing in the opposite
direction the state will have failed to establish that the limitation is reasonable
and justifiable”.223
SUMMARY
1 Christian Education South Africa v Minister of Education (CCT4/00) [2000] ZACC 11; 2000
(4) SA 757 (CC); 2000 (10) BCLR 1051 (18 August 2000).
2 Cheadle, H ‘Limitation of rights’ in Cheadle, H, Davis, D and Haysom, N (eds) (2002) South
African Constitutional Law: Bill of Rights at 30–2.
3 Cheadle (2002) 30–3.
4 (CCT 36/08) [2009] ZACC 8; 2009 (4) SA 222 (CC); 2009 (7) BCLR 637 (CC) (1 April 2009).
See also Johncom Media Investments Ltd v M (CCT 08/08) [2009] ZACC 5; 2009 (4) SA 7
(CC); 2009 (8) BCLR 751 (CC) (17 March 2009) para 22; Director of Public Prosecutions para
141; Ex parte Minister of Safety and Security: In re S v Williams (CCT20/94) [1995] ZACC 6;
1995 (3) SA 632 (CC); 1995 (7) BCLR 861 (CC) (9 June 1995) para 26; Moise v Greater
Germiston Transitional Local Council: Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development
Intervening (Women’s Legal Centre as Amicus Curiae) (CCT 54/00) [2001] ZACC 21; 2001 (4)
SA 491 (CC); 2001 (8) BCLR 765 (CC) (4 July 2001) para 7; Williams para 54; Coetzee v
Government of the Republic of South Africa; Matiso and Others v Commanding Officer Port
Elizabeth Prison and Others (CCT19/94, CCT22/94) [1995] ZACC 7; 1995 (4) SA 631 (CC);
1995 (10) BCLR 1382 (CC) (22 September 1995) para 9; AB and Another v Minister of Social
Development (CCT155/15) [2016] ZACC 43; 2017 (3) SA 570 (CC); 2017 (3) BCLR 267 (CC)
(29 November 2016); Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development and Others v
Prince (Clarke and Others Intervening); National Director of Public Prosecutions and Others
v Rubin; National Director of Public Prosecutions and Others v Acton (CCT108/17) [2018]
ZACC 30; 2018 (6) SA 393 (CC); 2018 (10) BCLR 1220 (CC) (18 September 2018) paras 59–
82; Centre for Child Law and Others v Media 24 Limited and Others (CCT261/18) [2019]
ZACC 46; 2020 (4) SA 319 (CC); 2020 (3) BCLR 245 (CC) (4 December 2019) paras 52–60.
5 Director of Public Prosecutions, Transvaal para 41.
6 Rautenbach, I (2011) ‘Introduction to the Bill of Rights’ in Bill of Rights Compendium (Issue
29) at 1A–82.
7 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, Act 200 of 1993.
(CCT4/00) [2000] ZACC 11; 2000 (4) SA 757 (CC); 2000 (10) BCLR 1051 (CC) (18 August
8 2000).
9 Act 84 of 1996.
10 Christian Education South Africa para 27.
11 Currie I and De Waal J (2013) The Bill of Rights Handbook 6 ed 153, fn 11.
12 S v Makwanyane (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3; 1995 3 SA 391 (CC), 1995 6 BCLR 665 (CC) (6
June 1995) para 100.
13 Makwanyane para 104.
14 Article 1 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms states:
The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms guarantees the rights and freedoms set out
in it subject only to such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably
justified in a free and democratic society. Part 1 of the Constitution Act (1982).
15 Regarding the evolution of s 33(1), Woolman and Botha note:
The basic form of the interim Constitution’s limitations clause did not change over the
course of the 12 reports generated by the Multi-Party Negotiating Forum’s Technical
Committee on Fundamental Rights. In its second report, the Committee identified
what it believed to be the primary features of a limitations clause: (a) a ‘law of general
application’ threshold test; (b) a reasonableness requirement; (c) a necessity
requirement; (d) a ‘justifiable in a free, open and democratic society’ requirement; (e)
a proportionality or balancing approach; (f ) a ‘non-derogation from the essential
content of the right’ requirement; and (g) an immunisation of select rights from any
limitation at all. With the exception of the last characteristic, all of these attributes
appear in one form or another in the 12th and final version of the Interim
Constitution’s limitations clause.
See Woolman, S & Botha, H ‘Limitations’ in S Woolman, T Roux & M Bishop (eds) (2013)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 34.10–34.11. For a discussion of the
limitations clause under the interim Constitution (s 33) see White, J (1994) Constitutional
Litigation and Interpretation, and Fundamental Rights Annual Survey of South African Law
35–6.
16 These rights were listed as those in ss 10 (human dignity), 11 (freedom and security of the
person), 12 (servitude and forced labour), 14(1) (religion, belief and opinion), 21 (political
rights), 25 (detained, accused and arrested person’s rights) or 30(1)(d) or (e) or (2)
(children’s rights) and ss 15 (freedom of expression), 16 (assembly, demonstration and
petition), 17 (association), 18 (movement), 23 (access to information), or 24 (administrative
justice) in so far as such right relates to free and fair political activity.
17 For a more detailed discussion of the evolution of s 33(1), see Woolman and Botha (2013).
18 The German test was described by the Constitutional Court in S v Makwanyane (CCT3/94)
[1995] ZACC 3; 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC); 1995 (6) BCLR 665 (CC) (6 June 1995) para 108 as
follows:
It has regard to the purpose of the limiting legislation, whether the legislation is suitable for
the achievement of such purpose, is necessary therefor, and whether a proper balance has
been achieved between the purpose enhanced by the limitation, and the fundamental right
that has been limited.
19 132 (1986) 19 CRR 308 (SCC). This judgment was also favourably quoted in Makwanyane
para 105.
20 Oakes para 70.
S v Makwanyane (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3; 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC); 1995 (6) BCLR 665 (CC)
21 (6 June 1995).
22 Makwanyane para 104.
23 Makwanyane para 104 [our emphasis] The reformulation was welcomed by some
commentators at the time. Bronstein and Robinson, for example, argued that ‘[h]ere the
court acknowledges one’s intuitive sense that the effect of the proportionality test used in
analysing rights and their limitations does not depend on the wording of the limitation
clause in an individual case. The best interpretation of the statement quoted above is that
the rights in the Bill of Rights are not weakened by the omission of the word ‘necessary’. The
implication is that it does not make a difference whether the operative words in the
limitation clause are ‘necessary’ or ‘reasonable and justifiable’. This pronouncement should
be interpretively important in the future’ (see V Bronstein and K Robinson ‘Constitutional
jurisprudence and the Bill of Rights’ (1996) Juta’s Annual Survey of South African Law 53).
24 In doing so the Constitutional Court took its lead from the German Constitution Court
which, Chaskalson J remarked in Makwanyane, ‘also has a provision similar to section
33(1)(b) of our Constitution, but the Court apparently avoids making use of this provision,
preferring to deal with extreme limitations of rights through the proportionality test’ (para
108).
25 At the time s 36(1) was drafted, the exact phraseology was contested and confused. As the
Annual Survey of South African Law noted at the time: ‘While the section in the Working
Draft on the limitation of rights was replete with alternative constructions providing that a
right may be limited only to the extent that it is “reasonable/reasonable and
justifiable/reasonable and necessary/ necessary/justifiable” (s 35(1)(a), Working Draft), in
the end the Constitutional Assembly settled for the reasonable and justifiable formulation
(s 36(1), new Constitution) despite some rather puerile debate in which it seemed as if the
constitutional experts did not really seem to have an opinion as to whether there was any
significant point to the different formulations. This particular debate created some
confusion in a public already well rehearsed in the promise that the “draft text has been
written in plain language so that everyone can read and understand it’’.’ See Annual Survey
of South African Law.
26 Under the text of the interim Constitution’s limitation clause courts must first ask if a
limitation is reasonable, and only if it is deemed to be reasonable will they move on the
second question of whether it is justifiable, at which point the court would be required to
balance competing interests.
27 In Makwanyane para 104, Chaskalson P also introduced factors to be considered in the
‘balancing’ process when he said the following: ‘In the balancing process, the relevant
considerations will include the nature of the right that is limited, and its importance to an
open and democratic society based on freedom and equality; the purpose for which the
right is limited and the importance of that purpose to such a society; the extent of the
limitation, its efficacy, and particularly where the limitation has to be necessary, whether
the desired ends could reasonably be achieved through other means less damaging to the
right in question’.
28 While these factors added some substance to an otherwise fairly abstract process, this
value was offset by the exclusion of two features of the interim Constitution’s s 33 that could
potentially have narrowed down the ‘universe of possibility’ presented by the open-ended
nature of the balancing test. The first was the requirement that limitations must not ‘negate
the essential content of the right in question’. The second was the requirement that, in
respect of certain ‘entrenched rights’, the limitation pass the additional test of being
necessary. While these will no doubt have presented their own problems, they would have
brought some clarity to the process of limiting rights. Notably, there was an objection
raised in the Certification judgment regarding the omission of ‘necessary’ but that was
quickly dismissed (see Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996
(CCT 23/96) [1996] ZACC 26; 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC) (6 September
1996) para 90).
29 Roux, T (2014) ‘Assessing the social transformation performance of the South African
Constitutional Court: From totalitarianism to the rule of law’ in Jenkins, C and du Plessis,
M (eds) Law, Nation-Building and Transformation: The South African Experience in
Perspective 223 at 225.
30 Roux (2014) 227.
31 First National Bank of SA Limited t/a Wesbank v Commissioner for the South African
Revenue Services and Another; First National Bank of SA Limited t/a Wesbank v Minister of
Finance (CCT19/01) [2002] ZACC 5; 2002 (4) SA 768 (CC); 2002 (7) BCLR 702 (16 May 2002).
32 Roux (2014) 233.
33 Roux (2014) 234.
34 Roux (2014) 235.
35 (CCT28/01) [2002] ZACC 6; 2002 (4) SA 613 (CC); 2002 (7) BCLR 663 (CC) (21 May 2002).
36 Walters para 26.
37 See Beinash and Ernst & Young (CCT12/98) [1998] ZACC 19; 1999 (2) SA 116 (CC); 1999 (2)
BCLR 125 (CC) (2 December 1998).
38 See Mistry v Interim National Medical and Dental Council (CCT13/97) [1998] ZACC 10;
1998 (4) SA 1127 (CC); 1998 (7) BCLR 880 (CC) (29 May 1998) para 28; S v Jordan (Sex
Workers Education and Advocacy Task Force and Others as Amici Curiae) (CCT31/01)
[2002] ZACC 22; 2002 (6) SA 642 (CC); 2002 (11) BCLR 1117 (CC) (9 October 2002) paras
28–9; and South African Broadcasting Corporation Ltd v National Director of Public
Prosecutions and Others (CCT58/06) [2006] ZACC 15; 2007 (1) SA 523 (CC); 2007 (2) BCLR
167 (CC) (21 September 2006). See also Woolman and Botha (2013) 34.10–34.11.
39 See Woolman and Botha (2013) 34.17–34.18.
40 In Bernstein v Bester NO (CCT23/95) [1996] ZACC 2; 1996 (2) SA 751 (CC); 1996 (4) BCLR
449 (CC) (27 March 1996) para 79, Ackermann J noted in the context of the right to privacy
that ‘[t]he two-stage approach requires, as the first step, a definition of the scope of the
relevant right. At this stage already … it is necessary to recognize that the content of the
right is crystallized by mutual limitation. Its scope is already delimited by the rights of the
community as a whole (including its members)’.
41 Makwanyane para 9.
42 Cheadle (2002) 30–5.
43 South African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence (CCT65/06) [2007] ZACC 10;
2007 (5) SA 400 (CC); 2007 (8) BCLR 863 (CC) (30 May 2007) paras 25–7.
44 R v Big M Drug Mart (1985) 13 CRR 64 103 (SCC).
45 On the other hand, however, too generous (or insufficiently discerning) an interpretation
would render the two-stage approach redundant as all the work will be left to the limitation
enquiry, and the value of the substantive approach to this stage of the enquiry will be
undercut.
46 (CCT5/94) [1995] ZACC 1; 1995 (2) SA 642 (CC); 1995 (4) BCLR 401 (SA) (5 April 1995).
Zuma para 21. In Makwanyane para 100, Chaskalson P held that ‘[o]ur constitution … calls
47
for a ‘two-step’ approach, in which a broad rather than a narrow interpretation is given to
the fundamental rights enshrined in chapter 3 and limitations have to be justified through
the application of section 33’.
48 (CCT5/03) [2003] ZACC 19; 2004 (1) SA 406 (CC); 2003 (12) BCLR 1333 (CC) (15 October
2003).
49 Act 65 of 1996.
50 De Reuck paras 46–7.
51 De Reuck para 48.
52 De Reuck para 48.
53 De Reuck paras 56–83.
54 Ex parte Minister of Safety and Security: In re S v Williams (CCT20/94) [1995] ZACC 6; 1995
(3) SA 632 (CC); 1995 (7) BCLR 861 (CC) (9 June 1995) para 21.
55 Cheadle (2002) 30–2.
56 Cheadle (2002) 30–8.
57 First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Commissioner, South African Revenue Service;
First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Minister of Finance (CCT19/01) [2002] ZACC 5;
2002 (4) SA 768 (CC); 2002 (7) BCLR 702 (CC) (16 May 2002).
58 Act 91 of 1964.
59 First National Bank para 100.
60 First National Bank para 110.
61 First National Bank para 110.
62 First National Bank para 111.
63 Ex parte Minister of Safety and Security: In re S v Walters (CCT20/94) [1995] ZACC 6; 1995
(3) SA 632 (CC); 1995 (7) BCLR 861 (CC) (9 June 1995).
64 Walters paras 26–7.
65 (CCT23/95) [1996] ZACC 2; 1996 (2) SA 751 (CC); 1996 (4) BCLR 449 (CC) (27 March 1996).
66 Bernstein para 75.
67 Bernstein para 77.
68 Jordan.
69 Act 23 of 1957.
70 Jordan paras 82–3.
71 Jordan paras 83–4.
72 2020 (1) SACR 469 (CC); 2020 (3) BCLR 245 (CC).
73 Act 51 of 1977.
74 Centre for Child Law para 46.
75 Centre for Child Law para 48.
76 Centre for Child Law para 49.
77 S 36(1) of the Constitution.
78 Woolman and Botha (2013) 34.48.
79 As above 36-48.
80 See generally Dladla and Another v City of Johannesburg and Others (CCT124/16) [2017]
ZACC 42; 2018 (2) SA 327 (CC); 2018 (2) BCLR 119 (CC) (1 December 2017) para 52; Police
and Prisons Civil Rights Union v South African Correctional Services Workers’ Union and
Others (CCT152/17) [2018] ZACC 24; 2019 (1) SA 73 (CC); 2018 (11) BCLR 1411 (CC) (23
August 2018) para 71; Nandutu and Others v Minister of Home Affairs and Others
(CCT114/18) [2019] ZACC 24; 2019 (5) SA 325 (CC); 2019 (8) BCLR 938 (CC) (28 June 2019)
para 71.
81 The Court has not yet considered the relationship that must exist between the law and the
limiting measure, and more specifically what the phrase ‘in terms of’ means.
82 (CCT8/99) [1999] ZACC 3; 1999 (3) SA 1 (CC); 1999 (4) BCLR 363 (CC) (1 April 1999).
83 August para 23.
84 (CCT124/16) [2017] ZACC 42; 2018 (2) BCLR 119 (CC); 2018 (2) SA 327 (CC) (1 December
2017).
85 Dladla paras 47–51.
86 Dladla para 52.
87 See Currie and De Waal (2013) 156 and Rautenbach, I and Venter, R Rautenbach-Malherbe
Constitutional Law 7 ed (2018) 310.
88 See Currie and De Waal (2013) 156 and Rautenbach and Venter (2018) 310.
89 See Currie and De Waal (2013) 156 and Rautenbach and Venter (2018) 310.
90 Larbi-Odam v Member of the Executive Council for Education (North-West Province)
(CCT2/97) [1997] ZACC 16; 1998 (1) SA 745 (CC); 1997 (12) BCLR 1655 (CC) (26 November
1997) para 27.
91 Du Toit v Minister of Transport (CCT22/04) [2005] ZACC 9; 2006 (1) SA 297 (CC; )2005 (11)
BCLR 1053 (CC) (8 September 2005).
92 Sonderup v Tondelli and Another (CCT53/00) [2000] ZACC 26; 2001 (1) SA 1171 (CC); 2001
(2) BCLR 152 (CC); (4 December 2000).
93 Ingledew v Financial Services Board: In re Financial Services Board v Van der Merwe and
Another (CCT6/02) [2003] ZACC 8; 2003 (4) SA 584 (CC); 2003 (8) BCLR 825 (CC) (13 May
2003) para 19.
94 (CCT11/96) [1997] ZACC 4; 1997 (4) SA 1 (CC); 1997 (6) BCLR 708 (CC) (18 April 1997).
95 Hugo para 96.
96 Hugo para 76 fn 7.
97 Hugo para 98.
98 (1979) 2 EHRR 245.
99 Hugo para 99.
100 (1991) 77 DLR (4th) 385 (SCC).
101 Hugo paras 100–101.
102 Hugo para 102.
103 Dawood v Minister of Home Affairs; Shalabi v Minister of Home Affairs; Thomas v Minister
of Home Affairs (CCT35/99) [2000] ZACC 8; 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC); 2000 (8) BCLR 837 (CC) (7
June 2000).
104 Dawood para 47.
105 Woolman and Botha (2013) 34.61.
106 Woolman and Botha suggest that the movement should be the other way, namely that
content specific questions should be considered under the law of general application
requirement, rather than under the reasonable and justifiable requirement (see Woolman
and Botha (2013) 34.62–34.63).
107 S 33(1) of the interim Constitution provided that ‘[t]he rights entrenched in this Chapter
may be limited by law of general application, provided that such limitation (a) shall be
permissible only to the extent that it is (i) reasonable; and (ii) justifiable in an open and
democratic society based on freedom and equality; and (b) shall not negate the essential
content of the right in question …’. Further, it provided that the limitation of certain
‘entrenched’ rights must also be necessary.
108 These more specific questions are paraphrased by Woolman and Botha as follows: ‘first,
whether the limitation serves a sufficiently important objective; second, whether the
limitation is rationally connected to the said objective; third, whether the limitation
impairs the right as little as possible; and fourth, whether the actual benefits of the
limitation are proportionate to its deleterious consequences for the rights-holder’ (see
Woolman S and Botha H, ‘Limitations: Shared constitutional interpretation, an appropriate
normative framework and hard choices’ Woolman S and Bishop M (eds) (2008)
Constitutional Conversations 155.
109 As discussed further below, the ‘importance of the purpose of the limitation’ factor is made
up of two parts: first, the purpose of the limitation and second, its importance. The first part
is relevant at the threshold stage of the reasonable and justifiable enquiry, while the second
part is relevant at the balancing and proportionality stage.
110 The ‘relation between the limitation and its purpose’ is similarly complex. The relationship
requires at a minimum a rational connection at the threshold stage of the reasonable and
justifiable enquiry and a proportional relationship at the balancing and proportional stage.
Labelling these threshold questions as factors is misleading as it suggests that, like the
other s 36(1) factors, they are optional rather than imperative.
111 Iles, K (2007) A fresh look at limitations: unpacking section 36 South African Journal on
Human Rights 23(1):68.
112 One could consider step one and two – which deal with the internal aspects of limiting
measure – as addressing the question of reasonableness, while the latter two – which
address the relationship between the limiting measure and externalities – address the issue
of justifiability.
113 In Prince para 155, Sachs J noted that ‘[l]imitations analysis under our Constitution is based
not on formal or categorical reasoning but on processes of balancing and proportionality as
required by section 36’.
114 These remaining s 36(1) factors are also, broadly speaking, captured in stages three and
four of the Oakes formulation. The third step in Oakes – whether the limitation impairs the
right as little as possible – is similar to the less restrictive means factor in s 36(1)(e), but is
perhaps more appropriately compared to the phrase ‘to the extent that’. The fourth and
final step under the Oakes formulation – whether the actual benefits of the limitation are
proportionate to its deleterious consequences for the rights-holder – is proportionality in a
limited sense. On this score, s 36(1) is more comprehensive. This is because the remaining s
36(1) factors collectively ask if the legitimate, rationally-based measure constitutes a
proportionate limitation on the right in question, taking into account the degree of
infringement, the nature of the right, the breadth of the measure and the social good it
achieves.
115 See S v Bhulwane, S v Gwadiso (CCT12/95, CCT11/95) [1995] ZACC 11; 1996 (1) SA 388
(CC); 1995 (12) BCLR 1579 (CC) (29 November 1995) para 24. In this case, O’Regan J found
that that the reverse onus provision in s 21(1)(a)(i) of the Drugs and Drug Trafficking Act
140 of 1992 was unconstitutional and invalid because it was not rationally connected to it
purpose, namely suppressing illicit drug trafficking. Despite having come to this
conclusion, O’Regan J went on to state expressly that the provision was unconstitutional,
not only because it failed the threshold rational connection test, but also because it was not
‘justifiable or necessary as contemplated by section 33’.
116 (CCT36/00) [2002] ZACC 1; 2002 (2) SA 794 (CC); 2002 (3) BCLR 231 (CC) (25 January
2002).
117 Prince para 81.
118 (CCT57/06) [2007] ZACC 1; 2007 (6) SA 96 (CC); 2007 (5) BCLR 457 (CC) (6 March 2007).
119 Englebrecht para 41.
120 Makwanyane.
121 Makwanyane paras 145–6.
122 Woolman and Botha (2008) 161.
123 Woolman and Botha (2008) 159.
124 Woolman and Botha (2008) 160.
125 Woolman and Botha (2008) 161.
126 Woolman and Botha (2008) 162.
127 S 36(1)(b) of the Constitution.
128 Jordan para 15.
129 South African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence (CCT27/98) [1999] ZACC 7;
1999 (4) SA 469 (CC) (26 May 1999), where the aim was to comply with s 200(1) of the
Constitution which provides that the South African National Defence Force (SANDF), must
be structured and managed as a disciplined military force.
130 Bhulwane para 20.
131 Larbi-Odam v MEC for Education (North West Province) (CCT2/97) [1997] ZACC 16; 1998
(1) SA 745 (CC); 1997 (12) BCLR 1655 (CC) (26 November 1997) para 30.
132 South African Defence Union para 32.
133 Christian Education South Africa v Minister of Education (CCT13/98) [1998] ZACC 16; 1999
(2) SA 83 (CC); 2000 (10) BCLR 1051 (CC) (14 October 1998) paras 39–41.
134 S v Manamela (CCT25/99) [2000] ZACC 5; 2000 (3) SA 1 (CC); 2000 (5) BCLR 491 (CC) (14
April 2000) para 27.
135 Islamic Unity Convention v Independent Broadcasting Authority (CCT36/01) [2002] ZACC
3; 2002 (4) SA 294 (CC); 2002 (5) BCLR 433 (CC) (11 April 2002) para 45.
136 Jordan para 15.
137 S v Singo (CCT49/01) [2002] ZACC 10; 2002 (4) SA 858; 2002 (8) BCLR 793 (12 June 2002)
para 33.
138 De Reuck.
139 Lawyers for Human Rights v Minister of Home Affairs (CCT 18/03) [2004] ZACC 12; 2004 (4)
SA 125 (CC); 2004 (7) BCLR 775 (CC) (9 March 2004) para 37.
140 Jaftha v Schoeman (CCT74/03) [2004] ZACC 25; 2005 (2) SA 140 (CC); 2005 (1) BCLR 78
(CC) (8 October 2004) para 37.
141 Magajane v Chairperson, North West Gambling Board (CCT49/05) [2006] ZACC 8; 2006 (5)
SA 250 (CC); 2006 (10) BCLR 1133 (CC) (8 June 2006) para 81.
142 Johncom para 29.
143 Moodley v Kenmont School and Others (CCT281/18) [2019] ZACC 37; 2020 (1) SA 410 (CC);
2020 (1) BCLR 74 (CC) (9 October 2019) para 29.
144 Makwanyane para 185.
145 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality para 47.
(CCT108/17) [2018] ZACC 30; 2018 (6) SA 393 (CC); 2018 (10) BCLR 1220 (CC) (18
146
September 2018).
147 Prince para 65.
148 South African National Defence Union.
149 Act 44 of 1957.
150 South African National Defence Union para 35.
151 (CCT12/95, CCT11/95) [1995] ZACC 11; 1996 (1) SA 388 (CC); 1995 (12) BCLR 1579 (CC)
(29 November 1995).
152 Act 140 of 1992.
153 Bhulwana para 24.
154 S v Dodo (CCT 1/01) [2001] ZACC 16; 2001 (3) SA 382 (CC); 2001 (5) BCLR 423 (CC) (5 April
2001) paras 293–294; and Lesapo v North West Agricultural Bank CCT23/99) [1999] ZACC
16; 2000 (1) SA 409 (CC); 1999 (12) BCLR 1420 (CC) (16 November 1999) para 26.
155 Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development and Others v Prince (Clarke and Others
intervening) (CCT 108/17) [2018] ZACC 30; 2018 (6) SA 393 (CC); 2018 (10) BCLR 1220 (CC)
(18 September 2018).
156 Prince para 81. The Court was quoting from Prince v President of the Law Society of the Cape
of Good Hope (CCT 36/00) [2002] ZACC 1; 2002 (2) SA 794 (CC); 2002 (3) BCLR 231 (CC) (25
January 2002) para 61.
157 Although this factor is sequentially last, it makes little sense to consider it after making
proposed means run the gauntlet of the proportionality enquiry, although the
Constitutional Court has done so on occasion.
158 As was noted by O’Regan J in SANDF, ‘the use of the term ‘overbreadth’ can be confusing,
particularly as the phrase has different connotations in different constitutional contexts’,
adding ‘[c]are should therefore be taken when employing the term’. South African National
Defence Union para 18.
159 Although the Constitutional Court has equated this with the less restrictive means
requirement, for the reasons set out about this is better placed under the notion of
proportionality.
160 Williams.
161 Williams para 62.
162 Williams para 75.
163 (CCT 12/13) [2013] ZACC 35; 2014 (2) SA 168 (CC); 2013 (12) BCLR 1429 (CC) (3 October
2013).
164 Teddy Bear Clinic for Abused Children paras 95–100.
165 Walters paras 26–7.
166 Unlike the Constitution, the interim Constitution did create a hierarchy of rights. This is
because s 33 listed a number of ‘entrenched’ rights which were harder to limit. This feature
was dropped from the Constitution.
167 See Johncom para 19; S v Mamabolo (E TV and Others, intervening) [2001] ZACC 17; 2001
(3) SA 409 (CC); 2001 (5) BCLR 449 (CC) (11 April 2001) para 41; and The Citizen 1978 (Pty)
Ltd and Others v McBride (CCT 23/10) [2011] ZACC 11; 2011 (4) SA 191 (CC); 2011 (8) BCLR
816 (CC) (8 April 2011) para 148.
168 Makwanyane para 44.
169 (CCT 49/03) [2004] ZACC 17; 2005 (1) SA 580 (CC); 2005 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) (15 October 2004).
170 Bhe para 71.
171 See Laugh it Off Promotions CC v South African Breweries International (Finance) BV t/a
Sabmark International (CCT42/04) [2005] ZACC 7; 2006 (1) SA 144 (CC); 2005 (8) BCLR 743
(CC) (27 May 2005) para 47 and Mamabolo para 41.
172 See Bernstein para 79.
173 S 36(1)(c) of the Constitution.
174 See Woolman, S (2007) The amazing, vanishing Bill of Rights South African Law Journal
124(4):762.
175 Du Plessis, M and Penfold, G (2008) Bill of Rights Jurisprudence: Operational provisions of
the Bill of Rights Juta’s Annual Survey of South African Law 50.
176 Manamela para 32. The same approach was followed under the interim Constitution. In
Bhulwana para 81, the Constitutional Court held that ‘the court places the purpose, effects
and importance of the infringing legislation on one side of the scales and the nature and
effect of the infringement caused by the legislation on the other. The more substantial the
inroad into fundamental rights, the more persuasive the grounds of justification must be’.
177 Manamela para 32.
178 Christian Education South Africa para 43. In Islamic Unity Convention para 45, the
Constitutional Court considered whether a legislative provision which prohibited the
broadcasting of any material ‘likely to prejudice relations between sections of the
population’ was a justifiable limitation on the right to freedom of expression, among
others. In its defence of the provision, the amicus curiae (Jewish Board of Deputies) raised
a number of arguments that invoked interests that were protected by the provision, namely
that ‘the interests of human dignity and equality, which are founding values of the
Constitution, and national unity, which is an important and legitimate state objective’.
179 See Jordan para 90 where O’Regan and Sachs JJ stated in their minority judgment that
when it comes to the question of proportionality, ‘the Court is obliged to apply the
standards of an open and democratic society’.
180 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality para 57.
181 Prince paras 119–27.
182 This is proportionality with a capital ‘P’.
183 Woolman and Botha (2008) 156.
184 (CCT5/03) [2003] ZACC 19; 2004 (1) SA 406 (CC); 2003 (12) BCLR 1333 (CC) (15 October
2003).
185 De Reuck para 59.
186 De Reuck para 67.
187 De Reuck para 70.
188 Woolman and Botha (2008) 159–60.
189 Islamic Unity Convention.
190 Islamic Unity Convention para 51. The Court also held the provision to be overbroad. See
below.
191 (CCT 26/01) [2001] ZACC 4; 2001 (11) BCLR 1175 (8 October 2001).
192 Act 18 of 1973.
193 Potgieter para 7.
194 Islamic Unity Convention para 49.
195 S 126B(4) of the Defence Act 44 of 1957.
196 South African National Defence Union para 11.
197 Matiso.
198 Coetzee paras 13–4.
199 Christian Education South Africa para 35. In MEC for Education: KwaZulu-Natal v Pillay
(CCT 51/06) [2007] ZACC 21; 2008 (1) SA 474 (CC); 2008 (2) BCLR 99 (CC) (5 October 2007)
para 73, Langa CJ held that at the core of the concept of reasonable accommodation ‘is the
notion that sometimes the community, whether it is the State, an employer or a school,
must take positive measures and possibly incur additional hardships in order to allow all
people to participate and enjoy their rights equally. It ensures that we do not relegate
people to the margins of society because they do not and cannot conform to certain social
norms’.
200 Christian Education South Africa para 32.
201 Prince v President of the Law Society of the Cape of Good Hope para 94.
202 As noted above, although the Constitutional Court has equated this with the less restrictive,
alternative means requirement, for the reasons set out about this is better placed under the
notion of proportionality.
203 Prince v President of the Law Society of the Cape of Good Hope para 139:
The use made of cannabis by Rastafari cannot in the circumstances be sanctioned
without impairing the state’s ability to enforce its legislation in the interests of the
public at large and to honour its international obligation to do so. The failure to make
provision for an exemption in respect of the possession and use of cannabis by
Rastafari is thus reasonable and justifiable under our Constitution.
204 Pillay.
205 Pillay para 79.
206 Pillay para 85.
207 Pillay para 112.
208 It was a hollow victory in light of the fact that the student had matriculated by the time
judgment was handed down.
209 Prince para 156.
210 Makwanyane para 102.
211 In Minister of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime Prevention and the Re-Integration
of Offenders (NICRO) (CCT03/04) [2004] ZACC 10; 2005 (3) SA 280 (CC); 2004 (5) BCLR 445
(CC) para 34, the Constitutional Court held that ‘[i]t is not the conventional onus of proof
as it is understood in civil and criminal trials where disputes of fact have to be resolved. It is
rather a burden to justify a limitation where that becomes an issue in a section 36 analysis’.
212 Moise.
213 Moise para 18.
214 NICRO.
215 NICRO para 36.
216 (CCT19/00) [2000] ZACC 24; 2001 (1) SA 1146 (CC); 2001 (1) BCLR 52 (CC) (29 November
2000).
217 Steyn para 31.
218 Steyn para 32.
219 Teddy Bear Clinic for Abused Children.
220 Act 32 of 2007.
221 Teddy Bear Clinic for Abused Children paras 42–7.
222 Teddy Bear Clinic for Abused Children paras 85–94.
223 Teddy Bear Clinic for Abused Children para 84.
224 Centre for Child Law para 63
225 Centre for Child Law para 63.
226 Rautenbach and Venter (2018) 323.
227 Rautenbach and Venter (2018) 323.
228 Rautenbach and Venter (2018) 325.
229 (CCT 51/06) [2007] ZACC 2008 (1) SA 474 (CC); 2008 (2) BCLR 99 (CC) (5 October 2007).
230 Pillay para 40.
231 Pillay para 40.
232 Act 3 of 2000.
233 S 4 of PAJA.
234 Act 4 of 2000.
235 (CCT 2/02) [2002] ZACC 27; 2003 (3) SA 1 (CC); 2003 (2) BCLR 154 (CC) (6 December
2002).
236 Act 66 of 1995.
237 NEHAWU para 14.
238 (CCT 32/07) [2007] ZACC 25; 2008 (2) SA 319 (CC); 2008 (4) BCLR 417 (CC) (6 December
2007).
239 HTF Developers para 26.
240 (CCT 17/96 [1996] ZACC 16; 1996 (4) SA 672 (CC); 1996 (8) BCLR 1015 (CC) (25 July 1996).
241 Act 34 of 1995.
242 AZAPO para 10.
243 (CCT 58/06) [2006] ZACC 15; 2007 (1) SA 523 (CC); 2007 2 BCLR 167 (CC) (21 September
2006).
244 SABC para 46. The majority concluded that, in the circumstances of the case, the SCA has
struck ‘an appropriate relationship of proportionality between the right to freedom of
expression and the court’s obligation to ensure that the proceedings before it are fair’.
245 SABC para 42.
246 SABC para 92.
247 Independent Newspapers (Pty) Ltd v Minister of Intelligence Services: In re Masetlha v
President of the Republic of South Africa and Another (CCT 38/07) [2008] ZACC 6; 2008 (5)
SA 31 (CC); 2008 8 BCLR 771 (CC) (22 May 2008).
248 Independent Newspapers para 55.
249 Du Plessis and Penfold (2008) 70–1.
250 Independent Newspapers para 83.
CONSTITUTIONAL REMEDIES
12.1 Introduction
12.8 An interdict
12.8.1 Structural Interdicts
Summary
12.1 Introduction
One of the most important characteristics of a judicially enforceable
Constitution is that the courts are empowered to hand down orders that
address infringements of the Constitution (called remedies) in a
manner that assists litigants and those in a similar situation to the
litigants. Therefore, in those cases where a court has found that law or
conduct unjustifiably infringes a fundamental right protected in the Bill
of Rights, it has to decide what the most appropriate remedy would be
to resolve the infringement. When it comes to making this decision,
however, the courts are reluctant to grant remedies that are impractical,
that would not cure the constitutional defect or that would tread too
drastically on the powers of the other branches of the state. It may safely
be stated, therefore, that constitutional litigation aimed at seeking an
appropriate remedy is extremely complex. The issues are usually ‘multi-
faceted, programmatic or involve a variety of public or private role-
players’.1
A remedy may be defined either in a broad or a narrow sense. In its
broad sense a remedy may be defined as ‘a process of legal redress
embracing all the legal procedures that a person has to follow to redress
the violation of their rights’.2 In its narrow sense, a remedy may be
defined as the order made by a court in response to a proven violation
of a person’s rights. As both of these definitions indicate, a remedy is the
mechanism used to repair an infringement of rights once a court has
interpreted the right, applied it to the facts of the case at hand and come
to the conclusion that the law or conduct in question is
unconstitutional. To a significant extent, therefore, the enforcement of
rights through the granting of remedies determines what those rights
mean in practice in the lives of the parties to the dispute.3
Given its function as a mechanism used to repair an infringement of
rights, it is not surprising that an important principle of the law of
constitutional remedies is that successful litigants should obtain the
relief they seek to vindicate their rights. In S v Bhulwana, S v Gwadiso,
for example, the Constitutional Court thus held that ‘[c]entral to a
consideration of the interests of justice in a particular case is that
successful litigants should obtain the relief they seek’.4 When a court
determines what the appropriate remedy in a case will be, it engages in
a profoundly practical exercise that is both legal and political in nature.
It has to consider the consequences of granting or not granting a
particular remedy, both for the litigant who brought the case and for the
state and society at large.
In those cases in which the Bill of Rights applies directly and vertically,
sections 38 and 172(1) of the Constitution govern the kinds of remedies
a court may grant. In those cases in which the Bill of Rights applies
directly and horizontally, sections 8(2) and 8(3) of the Constitution
govern the kinds of remedies a court may grant. And in those cases in
which the Bill of Rights applies indirectly, section 39(2) of the
Constitution regulates the kinds of remedies a court may grant.
This distinction is important because sections 38 and 172(1) of the
Constitution confer on the courts the power to apply and develop
unique constitutional law remedies such as declarations of invalidity,
constitutional damages and structural interdicts. Sections 8(2), 8(3) and
39(2) of the Constitution, however, simply provide that the courts must
use and develop the common law and statutory remedies. For the
purposes of this chapter, therefore, we are going to focus only on the
kinds of remedies a court may grant when the Bill of Rights applies
directly and vertically.
When it comes to identifying the kinds of remedies a court may
grant when the Bill of Rights applies directly and vertically, it is helpful
to start with section 172(1)(a) of the Constitution. This section provides
that ‘[w]hen deciding a constitutional matter … a court must declare
that any law or conduct that is inconsistent with the Constitution is
invalid to the extent of its inconsistency’. The court does not have a
discretion in the matter and cannot, for example, decline to declare law
invalid because Parliament is in the process of amending that law.6
Apart from issuing a declaration of invalidity, section 172(1)(b) of
the Constitution also provides that when deciding a constitutional
matter, a court may make any order that is ‘just and equitable’. The
Constitutional Court has employed this ‘broad and flexible’7 power to
develop a number of appropriate mechanisms aimed at regulating the
impact of a declaration of invalidity. These mechanisms may be divided
into two broad groups. First, those mechanisms aimed at limiting the
substantive impact8 of the declaration of invalidity. These are severance,
notional severance and reading in. Second, those mechanisms aimed at
limiting the temporal impact of the declaration of invalidity.9 These take
the form of controlling the retrospective effect of a declaration of
invalidity, which is expressly provided for in section 172(1)(b)(i) of the
Constitution, or temporarily suspending a declaration of invalidity,
which is expressly provided for in section 172(1)(b)(ii).10
The constitutional remedies referred to in sections 172(1)(a) and (b)
of the Constitution must also be read together with section 38. This
section provides that a court may grant ‘appropriate relief, including a
declaration of rights’ whenever a right in the Bill of Rights has been
violated or threatened. The Constitutional Court has used this power to
develop a number of additional remedies. Among these are interdicts,
constitutional damages and meaningful engagement.
Table 12.1 The remedies available for different breaches of the Constitution
Direct vertical application Sections 38 and • Declaration of invalidity
172(1) and (2) • Declaration of rights
• An interdict (both mandatory and prohibitory)
• Constitutional damages
• Meaningful engagement
• Costs
Direct horizontal application Sections 8(2) and • Remedies contained in legislation that give
8(3) effect to the Bill of Rights
Develop the common law to give effect to the
• Bill of Rights
12.2.1 Introduction
As we have seen, section 172(1)(a) of the Constitution states that when
deciding a constitutional matter within its power, a court ‘must declare
that any law or conduct that is inconsistent with the Constitution is
invalid to the extent of its inconsistency’. Section 172(1)(a) does not
confer a discretion on the courts. Where a law or provision conflicts
with the Constitution, a court is obliged to declare the law or provision
invalid to the extent of the inconsistency.19 The same applies to the
conduct of a person or institution bound by the Constitution.20
The obligation to declare law or conduct that is inconsistent with the
Constitution invalid flows logically from the fact that the Constitution is
supreme. It is not surprising, therefore, that section 2 of the
Constitution expressly provides that ‘[t]his Constitution is the supreme
law of the Republic; law or conduct inconsistent with it is invalid, and
the obligations imposed by it must be fulfilled’.
An important consequence of the supremacy of the Constitution is
that any law or conduct in conflict with the Constitution is invalid from
the moment that the conflict arises. This is called the doctrine of
objective invalidity. Although the invalidity will have legal effect only
once a court has confirmed that there is a conflict between the
Constitution and legislation or the actions of a person, the invalidity
does not arise only at the moment when it is affirmed by the court.21
This means that an order of invalidity usually has retrospective effect as
the court merely confirms that the legislation or the actions of an
individual were invalid from the moment the conflict with the
Constitution arose (or from the date upon which the Constitution
entered into force, whichever is the latter).
The Constitutional Court adopted the doctrine of objective invalidity
in its judgment in Ferreira v Levin NO and Others; Vryenhoek and
Others v Powell NO and Others.22 In this case, the Court held as follows:
The Court’s order does not invalidate the law; it merely declares it to be invalid.
It is very seldom patent, and in most cases is disputed, that pre-constitutional
laws are inconsistent with the provisions of the Constitution. It is one of this
Court’s functions to determine and pronounce on the invalidity of laws,
including Acts of Parliament.23
This does not detract from the reality that pre-existing laws either
remained valid or became invalid when the provisions of the
Constitution came into operation. In this sense, laws are objectively
valid or invalid depending on whether they are consistent with the
Constitution or not. The fact that a dispute concerning inconsistency
may be decided only years afterwards does not affect the objective
nature of the invalidity. The issue of whether a law is invalid or not,
therefore, does not depend on whether – at the moment when the issue
is being considered – a particular person’s rights are threatened or
infringed by the offending law or not.24 The court needs to consider the
matter in an abstract manner, meaning that it must consider the impact
of the legislation on all similarly situated people and not just the
individual litigant in the case at hand.
Sometimes, however, the only way in which the court can cure the
defect in the legislation is to insert a particular word or part of a
sentence, which it does by reading in, discussed next.
12.2.3 Reading in
When the court employs the remedy of reading in, it literally reads
words into an unconstitutional legislative provision to cure that
provision of its unconstitutionality. Reading in is used in cases where a
legislative provision is unconstitutional because of the omission of
certain words and phrases.52 In addition, reading in is also used in cases
where a legislative provision is unconstitutional because it ‘is unduly
invasive of a right’53 (in other words, because it is too broad). In these
cases, the courts read certain words or phrases into the provision to
narrow its scope and thus render it constitutionally valid. It is important
to note, therefore, that reading in occurs only after the court has
established that a legislative provision is in conflict with the
Constitution and has declared the provision invalid.54
Reading in is an invasive remedy and raises separation of powers
concerns.55 In National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v
Minister of Home Affairs, however, the Constitutional Court held that
there is in principle no difference between severance and reading in. In
both cases, legislation enacted by Parliament ‘is being altered by the
order of a court. In the one case by excision and in the other by
addition’.56 The Court has argued that reading in is justified, particularly
if we embrace the view of separation of powers as a structured dialogue
between the three branches of government. Reading in does not give
the judiciary the final word on how legislative provisions should be
formulated:
It should also be borne in mind that whether the remedy a court grants is one
striking down, wholly or in part; or reading into or extending the text, its choice
is not final. Legislatures are able, within constitutional limits, to amend the
remedy, whether by re-enacting equal benefits, further extending benefits,
reducing them, amending them, ‘fine-tuning’ them or abolishing them. Thus
they can exercise final control over the nature and extent of the benefits.57
Before reading words into a statute a court has to ensure, first, that the
provision to which words have been added is consistent with the
Constitution and its fundamental values and, second, that the result
achieved would interfere with the laws adopted by the legislature as
little as possible. As long as there are still many provisions on the statute
books from the pre-constitutional era, ‘the first consideration will in
those cases often weigh more heavily than the second’.58
It must also be borne in mind that it will not always be appropriate
to read words into an impugned provision to cure its
unconstitutionality. As the Constitutional Court stated in National
Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Home Affairs:
it will not be appropriate to read words in, unless in so doing a court can define
with sufficient precision how the statute ought to be extended in order to
comply with the Constitution. Moreover, when reading in (as when severing) a
court should endeavour to be as faithful as possible to the legislative scheme
within the constraints of the Constitution. Even where the remedy of reading in
is otherwise justified, it ought not to be granted where it would result in an
unsupportable budgetary intrusion. In determining the scope of the budgetary
intrusion, it will be necessary to consider the relative size of the group which
the reading in would add to the group already enjoying the benefits. Where
reading in would, by expanding the group of persons protected, sustain a
policy of long standing or one that is constitutionally encouraged, it should be
preferred to one removing the protection completely.59
As this passage indicates, the courts often have to draw a fine balance
between competing interests when deciding whether or not to read in.
Some of the difficulties that this can give rise to are illustrated in the
Constitutional Court’s judgment in Democratic Alliance v Speaker of the
National Assembly.60
In this case, President Zuma delivered the 2015 State of the National
Address to a joint sitting of both Houses of Parliament. During his
address, members of the Economic Freedom Front (EFF) continuously
interrupted President Zuma by asking him when he intended to repay
public money spent on non-security upgrades to his private residence
in Nkandla. As a result of these interruptions, the Speaker asked the
members of the EFF to leave the chamber. They, however, refused to do
so.
After the members of the EFF refused to obey the Speaker’s
instruction, she ordered the police to forcibly remove them in terms of
section 11 of the Powers, Privileges and Immunities of Parliament and
the Provincial Legislatures (PPI Act).61 This section provides that person
who creates a disturbance in the precincts while Parliament or a House
or a committee is meeting may be arrested and removed from the
precincts on the orders of the Speaker or the Chairperson of the
National Council of Provinces.
Following the forced removal of the members of the EFF, the
Democratic Alliance applied to the Western Cape High Court for an
order declaring section 11 of the PPI Act to be unconstitutional and
invalid on the ground that it infringed the parliamentary privilege of
freedom of speech guaranteed in section 58(1)(a) of the Constitution.
After the High Court granted the order, it was referred to the
Constitutional Court for confirmation in terms of section 172(2) of the
Constitution. The Constitutional Court confirmed that section 11 was
unconstitutional and invalid.
In arriving at this decision, the Constitutional Court held that even
though section 11 refers to ‘persons’ and not expressly to members of
the National Assembly, the word ‘person’ is wide enough to include
members of the National Assembly. This means that section 11 does
give the Speaker or the Chairperson the power to order the arrest or
removal of a member of the National Assembly or the NCOP who is
creating a disturbance.62
Given that section 11 of the Act applies only if a member was
creating a disturbance, it was important to define this concept. In this
respect, the Court held that the concept of a disturbance should not be
interpreted broadly. This is because a broad interpretation would
include conduct that is protected by the parliamentary privilege of
freedom of speech, for example conduct that annoys and tests the
patience of the presiding officers or other members of Parliament. If this
sort of conduct was included in the concept of a disturbance, however,
section 11 would clearly infringe the parliamentary privilege and would
be unconstitutional and invalid.63
The concept of a disturbance, therefore, had to be interpreted
narrowly to mean an interference that prevents Parliament from
conducting its business, with little possibility of resumption of business
within a reasonable period of time.64 Despite defining the concept of a
disturbance in this narrow manner, however, the Court went on to find
that section 11 still infringed the parliamentary privilege of freedom of
speech. This is because section 11 had to be read with sections 7 and 27
of the PPI Act which provided that creating or participating in a
disturbance was also a criminal offence and this had a chilling effect on
the parliamentary privilege of freedom of speech.65
Section 11, therefore, was unconstitutional because it not only
prohibited members of the public from creating a disturbance, but also
members of Parliament themselves.66 In other words, it went too far. In
order to remedy this defect, the Court read the words ‘other than a
member’ after the word ‘person’ into section 11 to ensure that it does
not apply toto give Parliament time to correct the constitutional
members of Parliament.67
Despite warning the courts to avoid reading in where this would
result in an unsupportable budgetary intrusion, the Constitutional
Court itself has ignored this warning and read words into a statute that
did have budgetary implications.68
How radical a constitutional remedy is reading
in?
Reading in can appear to be a rather radical remedy.
This is because it implicates the separation of powers
doctrine as the court – and not the legislature – in
effect rewrites a section of the law by reading words
into the statute. It is usually the legislature and not the
judiciary that has to formulate the wording of specific
legal provisions and reading in seems to come close to
breaching this principle. It is for this reason that the
criteria set out above must be adhered to.
However, remember that when a court performs a
reading in, it does not necessarily provide a final and
definitive determination of the rewritten section. The
legislature is free to amend it. When the legislature
does this, it engages in the kind of constitutional
dialogue which we discussed in chapter 2 on the
separation of powers. The legislature, therefore,
potentially has the final say on the exact wording of the
rewritten section.
As long as any amendments to the rewritten
section conform to the Constitution, the court will not
be able to interfere with the determination of the
wording made by the legislature. In this sense, reading
in is perhaps less radical than it may at first appear.
Lawyers must be aware, however, that reading in may
mean that the provisions of a statute as passed by
Parliament do not always accurately reflect its true
meaning as the Constitutional Court may have read
words into that statute.
This point is clearly illustrated by section 4(b) of
the Drugs and Drug Trafficking Act.69 Prior to the
judgment of the Constitutional Court in Minister of
Justice and Constitutional Development and Another v
Prince,70 section 4(b) prohibited, inter alia, the use or
possession of cannabis (dagga) in private by an adult
person for his or her own consumption. In Prince, the
Constitutional Court found that this prohibition was
unconstitutional and invalid because it unjustifiably
infringed the right to privacy guaranteed in section 14
of the Constitution.71 Apart from declaring the
prohibition invalid, however, the Court suspended its
order of invalidity for a period of 24 months to give
Parliament time to correct the constitutional defect. In
order to ensure that no adult could be arrested and
charged for using or possessing cannabis in private
during this period of suspension, the Court also read
words into section 4(b) as an interim measure. The
Court held in this respect that a new sub-paragraph
should be added to section 4(b) (sub-paragraph (vii))
and, that this new sub-paragraph should read as
follows:
(vii) in the case of an adult, the substance is cannabis and he or
she uses it or is in possession thereof in private for his or her
personal consumption in private.72
[…]
12.2.4 Severance
As we have already seen, section 172(1)(a) of the Constitution requires
a court to declare law or conduct invalid to the extent of its
inconsistency with the Constitution. A court, therefore, does not have to
declare an entire legislative provision unconstitutional and invalid if it is
possible to cut out the bad parts of the provision and retain the good
parts. This is called severance. When a court engages in severance it
strikes down a particular section, a particular subsection or the
individual words in a subsection of a law, but leaves the rest of the law
intact.
The test for severance is whether ‘the good is not dependent on the
bad’73 and whether the good can be separated from the bad. The
question that must be asked, therefore, is whether it is possible to give
effect to the good part of the provision that remains after the bad part
has been severed. In other words, after the bad part has been declared
invalid, will the good part still give effect to the main objective of the
statute? ‘The test has two parts: first, is it possible to sever the invalid
provisions [from the valid provisions] and second, if so, is what remains
giving effect to the purpose of the legislative scheme?’74
It is not always possible to sever the good from the bad while still
giving effect to the purpose of an impugned provision. In such a case,
the court has to declare the entire provision invalid.75 When it comes to
exercising this power, the courts are usually circumspect because of
concerns about overstepping the separation of powers. It is usually the
legislature – and not the judiciary – that should draft and amend
legislation. Severance would not be appropriate, for example, where an
offending legislative provision is so overbroad that the blame for the
constitutional invalidity of the section ‘cannot be laid at the door of any
one word, or group of words, but rather permeates the entire text’.76
In Case and Another v Minister of Safety and Security and Others,
Curtis v Minister of Safety and Security and Others,77 for example, the
Constitutional Court had to consider the constitutionality of a
censorship provision enacted during the apartheid era that was so
overbroad that it clearly infringed on the right to freedom of expression.
Given its overbroad nature, the Court could not sever the good from the
bad and had to strike down the provision as a whole. In arriving at this
conclusion, the Court held that if it had to:
apply a blue pencil to each and every noun form and transitive verb that
presents overbreadth problems, we effectively write a new provision that bears
only accidental resemblance to that enacted by Parliament. If, as appears to be
the case, the scheme behind the statute was to impose a comprehensive
scheme of censorship to give effect to a particular moral, cultural and political
world-view, it hardly does justice to the ‘main object’ thereof for this Court to
pare it down to prohibit only that discrete set of sexually-oriented expressions
that this Court believes may constitutionally be restricted. For this Court to
attempt that textual surgery would entail it departing fundamentally from its
assigned role under our Constitution. It is trite but true that our role is to
review, rather than to re-draft, legislation. This Court has already had occasion
to caution against judicial arrogation of an essentially legislative function in
the guise of severance.78
Finally, it is important to note that a court will not always be able to use
notional severance. In National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality
and Others v Minister of Home Affairs and Others, for example, the
Constitutional Court pointed out that where:
the invalidity of a statutory provision results from an omission, it is not
possible, … to achieve notional severance by using words such as ‘invalid to the
extent that’, or other expressions indicating notional severance. An omission
cannot, notionally, be cured by severance … The only logical equivalent to
severance, in the case of invalidity caused by omission, is the device of reading
in.85
A court may also suspend an order of invalidity where the defect in the
impugned legislation is purely procedural, for example, in cases where
Parliament has failed to facilitate adequate public involvement in the
law-making process.102 It would also not be appropriate to invalidate
legislation immediately where such an order would be ‘chaotic and
prejudicial to the interests of justice and good government’.103 A court is
more likely to exercise its powers to suspend the invalidity of pre-
constitutional legislation than post-constitutional legislation.104 When it
declares post-constitutional legislation invalid, it will only suspend the
order ‘where the result of invalidating everything done under such
legislation is disproportional to the harm which would result from
giving the legislation temporary validity’.105
A court looks at the precise circumstances of each case to determine
whether the order of invalidity should be suspended.106 A court does not
normally suspend an order of invalidity if the provisions are so ‘clearly
inconsistent’ with a fundamental right and ‘manifestly indefensible’
under the general limitation clause that there is ‘no warrant for its
retention, not even temporarily’.107 This means that there have to be
persuasive reasons to exercise the power to suspend before a court will
do so.108 In cases where the legislation limits a right of heightened
importance – such as the right not to be unfairly discriminated against
guaranteed in section 9 of the Constitution – the Constitutional Court
has found that:
those subject to the impugned provisions should not be made to wait much
longer to be relieved of the burden of inequality and unfair discrimination …
[as] … that would mean that the benefits of the Constitution would continue to
be withheld from those who have been deprived of them for so long.109
This places a burden on a litigant seeking a suspension of an order of
invalidity (usually the state) to persuade the court to exercise its powers
in terms of section 172(1)(b)(ii) of the Constitution in the interests of
justice and equity.110 It is important that all relevant information is
placed before the court when it is asked to suspend an order of
invalidity. The information must relate to the consequences of an order
of invalidity and the time that will be needed to remedy the defect in the
legislation.111
The time provided to the legislature to correct the defect depends on
the ‘complexity and variety of the statutory and policy alternatives’
available to Parliament.112 Sometimes, proper legislation passed by
Parliament is the only appropriate manner with which to deal with a
constitutional defect in legislation.113
A suspension of an order of invalidity can be seen as a technique
used by the Constitutional Court to manage the separation of powers
tensions that may arise from invalidating legislation. As such, it can be
seen as part of the constitutional dialogue between the three branches
of government mentioned above. A consequence of this is that the
power of the legislature is only partly circumscribed by the suspended
order of invalidity. As long as the legislature amends the law to bring it
into harmony with the Constitution, it has a wide discretion to choose
the means to achieve this goal.
While Parliament (or any other legislature) may choose to correct
the defect in the invalidated law within the period specified, it need not
do so. If it chooses not to correct the defect in the period provided, the
suspension will fall away and the law or provision will become invalid.
The legislature may also take other steps to address the effect of the
declaration of invalidity. In the latter two situations, the declaration of
invalidity will come into effect on the specified date.114
Apart from human dignity and the right to life, the Court also stated that
the duty to engage meaningfully with people who may be rendered
homeless after being evicted is squarely grounded in section 26(2) of
the Constitution. This is because section 26(2) imposes an obligation on
every sphere of government to take reasonable legislative and other
measures, within its available resources, to achieve the progressive
realisation of the right of access to adequate housing.127
The test for reasonableness, the Court went on to state, does not
only impose an obligation on the City to engage meaningfully with
potentially homeless persons, but also to respond to the concerns they
raise during that process in a reasonable manner. This means that in
some cases it may be reasonable to make permanent housing available
and, in others, to provide no housing at all. The possibilities between
these extremes are almost endless. As long as the response of the
municipality in the engagement process is reasonable, however, that
response complies with section 26(2).128
In the same judgment, the Constitutional Court also stated that
engagement is a two-way process in which the City and those about to
become homeless would talk to each other meaningfully in order to
achieve certain objectives. While there is no closed list of objectives, the
sorts of objectives that ought to be achieved when a city wishes to evict
people who may be rendered homeless as a result of the eviction are as
follows:
(a) what the consequences of the eviction might be;
(b) whether the city could help in alleviating those dire consequences;
(c) whether it was possible to render the buildings concerned relatively safe
and conducive to health for an interim period;
(d) whether the city had any obligations to the occupiers in the prevailing
circumstances; and
(e) when and how the city could or would fulfil these obligations.129
In the light of these reasons, the Court concluded that the only
appropriate remedy in the circumstances was to award constitutional
damages to recompense Kate for the breach of her right. In deciding
how to measure that loss in monetary terms, the Court took into
account the following:
It has not been shown that Kate suffered direct financial loss and it is most
unlikely that she did, for the grant was destined to be consumed and not
invested, but the loss was just as real. To be held in poverty is a cursed
condition. Quite apart from the physical discomfort of deprivation it reduces a
human in his or her dignity. The inevitable result of being unlawfully deprived
of a grant that is required for daily sustenance is the unnecessary further
endurance of that condition for so long as the unlawfulness continues. That is
the true nature of the loss that Kate suffered. There is no empirical monetary
standard against which to measure a loss of that kind … in the absence of such
a measure she should be awarded an amount equivalent to the interest that is
recognised in law to be payable when money is unlawfully withheld.142
12.8 An interdict
Interdicts are usually directed at future events and compel a defendant
(or any party to the litigation) to perform a task or to refrain from
undertaking a specific course of action. As such, interdicts usually take
the form of a mandamus (a mandatory interdict) or a prohibitory
interdict.
SUMMARY
13.1 Introduction
Summary
13.1 Introduction
Dignity is a central value underlying the Constitution and we could
even say it is the cornerstone of the Constitution and the rights
protected in it.1 This is made clear by section 1(a) of the Constitution,
which states that the Republic of South Africa is founded on the values
of human dignity, the achievement of equality and the advancement of
human rights and freedoms.2 When considering the scope and content
of the various rights in the Bill of Rights, it is important to understand
that human dignity informs constitutional adjudication and
interpretation and is ‘a value that informs the interpretation of many,
possibly all, other rights’.3 It is a ‘motif which links and unites equality
and privacy’, and which ‘runs right through the protections offered by
the Bill of Rights’.4 The value of dignity permeates the Bill of Rights to
contradict South Africa’s apartheid past ‘in which human dignity for
black South Africans was routinely and cruelly denied’.5
As we shall see, dignity is not only a value that permeates the Bill of
Rights and the Constitution as a whole; it is also a justiciable and
enforceable right. In many cases where the value of human dignity is
offended, the primary constitutional breach occasioned may be of a
more specific right. Arguably, the most important of these rights in the
South African context – given its history of discrimination – is the right
to equality.6 As we shall see, there is a strong link between the value of
dignity and the enforcement of the right to equality and non-
discrimination. The truth is that the value of dignity also undergirds
most, if not all, of the other rights contained in the Bill of Rights.
It is not easy to pin down the content of the value of human dignity.7
The Constitutional Court has recognised that, in the context of Bill of
Rights adjudication, human dignity recognises the inherent worth of all
individuals as members of our society, as well as the value of the
choices that they make. It comprises the ‘deeply personal
understanding we have of ourselves, our worth as individuals and our
worth in our material and social context’.8 The value of dignity asserts
that every human being counts; that every human being has infinite
value, regardless of his or her personal circumstances or actions. Given
that every human being counts, every human being is entitled to be
treated as a human being and to be valued. A more expansive view of
the value of dignity does not only focus on how individuals are treated,
but also focuses on human beings as agents capable of making moral
choices, of shaping their identity, of resisting injustice and of
participating in the shaping of society.9 In the words of Martha
Nussbaum dignity thus understood expresses the notion as follows:
The core idea is that of the human being as a dignified free being who shapes
his or her own life in cooperation and reciprocity with others, rather than being
passively shaped or pushed around by the world in the manner of a ‘flock’ or
‘herd’ animal. A life that is really human is one that is shaped throughout by
these human powers of practical reason and sociability.10
In this view dignity also speaks to the material conditions in which
individuals find themselves. To value the inherent dignity of human
beings as a society is to ensure that people enjoy civil and political
rights and also ‘have effective access to the social and economic means
indispensable to the development of their physical, emotional, creative
and associational capabilities’.11 Adopting a more expansive view of the
value of dignity, may help to reconfigure rights to make them more
responsive to economic and social injustice.
In this chapter we focus on the right to equality, the right to dignity
and the right to privacy, the denial of which can arguably be said to
have resulted in some of the most egregious forms of injustice during
the apartheid era and continue to rob many people of respect and
concern, and the ability to shape their lives in ways that would allow for
human flourishing. Although the denial of these rights has drastic and
personal effects on individuals, it would be a mistake to view them only
in individual terms. Often, the manner in which society is structured,
the cultural assumptions deeply embedded in society and the vast
inequalities between rich and poor have a direct and lasting effect on
the denial of these rights. It is, therefore, impossible not to consider
these rights against the backdrop of the broader social, economic and
political context and to remain mindful of how the broader context
influences our understanding of the operation of these rights.
Accordingly, it would be a mistake to analyse these rights and the
jurisprudence of the Constitutional Court relating to these rights (or any
other rights protected in the Bill of Rights for that matter) in an a-
contextual or overtly formalistic manner. It must always be remembered
that rights are aimed at protecting individual human beings and at
promoting their well-being and ability to make meaningful life choices.
This means that the actual lived reality of individuals and the effects of
impugned actions or omissions by both the state and private parties will
always be centre stage when considering breaches of the rights in the
Bill of Rights.12
The value of ubuntu and the Constitution
Former Constitutional Court justice Yvonne Mokgoro
has argued that the values encapsulated by ubuntu
‘are the very same values that the Constitution in
general and the Bill of Rights in particular aim to
inculcate in our society’.13 This means, she argues
further, that the ‘traditional African values of ubuntu’
could influence the development of South African law
and jurisprudence.14 Noting that the concept ubuntu is
not easily definable, Mokgoro nevertheless proceeds to
describe ubuntu as:
a world-view of African societies and a determining factor in the
formation of perceptions which influence social conduct. It has
also been described as a philosophy of life, which in its most
fundamental sense represents personhood, humanity,
humaneness and morality; a metaphor that describes group
solidarity where such group solidarity is central to the survival of
communities with a scarcity of resources, where the fundamental
belief is that motho ke motho ba batho ba bangwe/umuntu
ngumuntu ngabantu which, literally translated, means a person
can only be a person through others. In other words the
individual’s whole existence is relative to that of the group: this is
manifested in anti-individualistic conduct towards the survival of
the group if the individual is to survive. It is a basically humanistic
orientation towards fellow beings.
But it is not only black people who have suffered and sometimes
continue to suffer from discrimination. Women, gay men and lesbians,
people with disabilities, HIV-positive people, foreigners, religious
minorities and many individuals with distinctive attributes or
characteristics have also suffered marginalisation and exclusion and to
some extent still do. When considering the scope and content of the
right to equality, it is important to have regard to these realities.
No two people in the world are identical in terms of their attributes,
characteristics, intelligence or other talents. Nor do people enjoy
identical benefits and opportunities as they grow up. This is particularly
true in South Africa, a country in which vast discrepancies in wealth,
educational opportunities and access to resources led to an unequal
distribution of opportunities. Race, gender and class differences have
also had an impact and perpetuate the subordination of black people,
women, gay men, lesbians and the poor. A person’s inborn talents,
predisposition and the status accorded to him or her based on
irrelevant considerations such as race, gender or sexual orientation, as
well as other factors such as the quality of education he or she receives,
the access he or she has to financial and other resources, the extent to
which the world is shaped by ideas and assumptions of politically and
economically privileged groups, and the opportunities and support
parents or caregivers are capable of providing, influence the extent to
which a person manages to live a rich and fulfilled life. Through no fault
of their own, different people from different backgrounds have an
unequal chance to reach their goals in life.
To help to address this situation the Bill of Rights contains a specific
right to equality in section 9 of the Bill of Rights. This section reads as
follows:
(1) Everyone is equal before the law and has the right to equal protection and
benefit of the law.
(2) Equality includes the full and equal enjoyment of all rights and freedoms.
To promote the achievement of equality, legislative and other measures
designed to protect or advance persons, or categories of persons,
disadvantaged by unfair discrimination may be taken.
(3) The state may not unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against
anyone on one or more grounds, including race, gender, sex, pregnancy,
marital status, ethnic or social origin, colour, sexual orientation, age,
disability, religion, conscience, belief, culture, language and birth.
(4) No person may unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against anyone
on one or more grounds in terms of subsection (3). National legislation
must be enacted to prevent or prohibit unfair discrimination.
(5) Discrimination on one or more of the grounds listed in subsection (3) is
unfair unless it is established that the discrimination is fair.
It is clear from this approach that the context within which a court must
judge an equality case is of primary importance to determine whether
there is a breach of section 9. This context in which the court must judge
an equality case is formed, first, by the constitutional text in its entirety.
Second, the court must take into account the country’s recent history,
particularly the systematic discrimination suffered by black people
under apartheid26 as well as systematic patterns of discrimination on
grounds other than race that have caused, and may continue to cause,
considerable harm.27 Any consideration of whether a legally relevant
differentiation actually constitutes a breach of section 9, therefore, must
take into account the history of the impugned provision as well as the
history of the group or groups to which the complainant belongs. Taking
this context into account, the court determines whether the legally
relevant differentiation aims to create or perpetuate patterns of group
disadvantage, or whether it aims to break down these structural
inequalities and thus reach for true or substantive equality. If the latter
is the case, the court will be reluctant to declare the measures
unconstitutional.28
Because the court’s approach requires a contextual analysis, it may
take into account the ongoing structural inequality in society when
deciding on the unfairness of the discrimination.29 The court’s
contextual or remedial approach acknowledges that inequality results
from complex power relations in society. It views the law as having an
important role to play in reordering these power relations in ways which
strive to ensure that all individuals are treated as if they have the same
moral worth. Disadvantage here, then, is not equated with different
treatment of individuals who are born free and equal. Disadvantage is
rather equated with some harmful impact, whether direct or indirect,
that the differentiation between groups might have on a set of
complainants within the historical context of South Africa.30
As mentioned above, the focus is on the impact of the treatment
instead of the treatment itself. Substantive equality is remedial in nature
and aims to overcome the effects of past and ongoing prejudice and
discrimination. It requires a retreat from legal formalism and a focus on
the underlying purpose of the right to equality – what harm it seeks to
address – as well as the values underlying equality. The harm to be
addressed rests on at least three pillars:
the culturally constructed ideology of differences based on the belief
• in the superiority of dominant groups and the inferiority of non-
dominant groups
• the economic exploitation and disempowerment of those without
power because of their race, sex, gender, sexual orientation or other
attributes
• in the South African context, the previous political
disenfranchisement of black South Africans.31
The Court accepts that the equality guarantee protects individuals from
differentiation based on one of the specified grounds in section 9(3) or
similar forms of differentiation that have the potential to infringe on a
person’s fundamental human dignity. Conversely, where differentiation
is not based on one of the specified grounds and where it does not have
the potential to infringe on a person’s fundamental human dignity,
there will be no unfair discrimination in terms of section 9(3) of the
Constitution.
The Constitutional Court has adopted quite a broad and expansive
definition of human dignity. It has stated that human dignity will be
impaired whenever a legally relevant differentiation treats people as
‘second-class citizens’, ‘demeans them’, treats them as less capable for
no good reason’, otherwise offends ‘fundamental human dignity’ or
where it violates an individual’s self-esteem and personal integrity.43
This idea of dignity is based on the notion that all human beings have
an equal moral worth – the right to be treated with equal concern and
respect – and derives from the work of Immanuel Kant.44 But the
Constitutional Court has gone beyond this understanding of human
dignity and embraced a more expansive understanding of what it
entails. It has thus held that the value of dignity is also implicated if
individuals do not have the material resources – including access to
food, clothing or shelter – to make meaningful life choices.45 As long as
there are ‘great disparities in wealth’, millions of people continue to live
‘in deplorable conditions and in great poverty’, there is a ‘high level of
unemployment, inadequate social security, and many do not have
access to clean water or to adequate health services’, the value of dignity
will not be honoured.46
This view of equality as inextricably linked to the concept of dignity
has been reiterated in subsequent Constitutional Court judgments47
and has further been elaborated on, most notably in Prinsloo v Van der
Linde and Another.48 In this case, the Court adopted an even more
expansive interpretation of when treatment will be discriminatory. It
held in this respect that treatment will be discriminatory, not only when
it infringes human dignity, but also when it ‘affect persons adversely in
a comparably serious manner’.49 Where legal provisions deny the equal
moral worth of a complainant, the Court will find that there has been an
impairment of human dignity or that the complainant has been
adversely affected in a comparably serious manner. This is a
confirmation of Malherbe’s proposition that ‘equality without dignity is
inhuman’.50
Apart from the value of dignity, the Constitutional Court has also
affirmed that the value of equality is relevant for any understanding of
section 9 of the Constitution especially when dealing with the
restitutionary aspects of equality. In Van Heerden, the Constitutional
Court affirmed the Constitution’s commitment to strive for a society
based on social justice. Equality thus requires more than equal
protection before the law and non-discrimination. In addition, it also
requires ‘a credible and abiding process of reparation for past
exclusion, dispossession, and indignity within the discipline of our
constitutional framework’.57 The Court, per Moseneke DCJ, explained
this point as follows:
What is clear is that our Constitution and in particular section 9 thereof, read as
a whole, embraces for good reason a substantive conception of equality
inclusive of measures to redress existing inequality. Absent a positive
commitment progressively to eradicate socially constructed barriers to
equality and to root out systematic or institutionalised under-privilege, the
constitutional promise of equality before the law and its equal protection and
benefit must, in the context of our country, ring hollow.58
13.2.4.1 Introduction
Different legal tests apply to different situations in which an equality
complaint is lodged. First, where a distinction between different people
stems from a legislative provision and the litigant asks a court to declare
that legislative provision invalid, the court has to rely directly on
sections 9(1), 9(2) or 9(3) of the Constitution. These three sections apply
in different situations and, as we shall see, require the court to apply a
different legal test in each case. It is important to identify whether a set
of facts dealing with a complaint about different treatment between
people or groups of people fits under section 9(1), 9(2) or 9(3). The
court then applies the relevant test applicable to that set of facts. When
attacking the constitutionality of a legislative provision, it is therefore
important, at the outset, to determine whether the attack will be based
on section 9(1), 9(2) or (9(3). A direct reliance on section 9 is required in
such cases because legislation can only be invalidated by invoking the
Constitution itself. This is because the Constitution is supreme and
therefore superior to the legislative provision under attack.
Where a litigant attacks the actions of a public official or private
entity on equality grounds but this attack does not relate to the possible
invalidation of a legislative provision, the litigant will have to rely on the
relevant provisions of the PEPUDA. This is so whether the challenge is
against a redress policy or whether it is against alleged unfair
discrimination.59 This is because the principle of subsidiarity provides
that a litigant who claims that one of his or her constitutional rights has
been infringed must rely on legislation adopted to protect that right
rather than the constitutional right itself. The litigant, therefore, may not
rely on the underlying constitutional provision directly. Unless the
litigant wants to attack the constitutionality of the legislative provision
itself, he or she cannot rely on section 9 as the PEPUDA gives effect to
section 9 and will be the first port of call.60 The Constitutional Court has
advanced three reasons why the principle of subsidiarity is important
and must be adhered to.
First, allowing a litigant to rely directly on a fundamental right contained in the
Constitution, rather than on legislation enacted in terms of the Constitution to
give effect to that right, ‘would defeat the purpose of the Constitution in
requiring the right to be given effect by means of national legislation’. Second,
comity between the arms of government enjoins courts to respect the efforts of
other arms of government in fulfilling constitutional rights. Third, ‘allowing
reliance directly on constitutional rights, in defiance of their statutory
embodiment, would encourage the development of “two parallel systems of
law”’.61
Legislative provision constituting mere A legal provision that requires cigarette Section
differentiation products but not alcohol products to 9(1) of the
carry warning labels Constitution
Legislative provision introducing an affirmative Employment Equity Act (EEA)67 provisions Section
action programme requiring certain employers to institute 9(2) of the
affirmative action policies Constitution
Legislative provision that distinguishes directly or A legislative provision that grants women Section
indirectly between groups based on grounds but not men the right to a certain number 9(3) of the
listed in section 9(3) or analogous grounds of days of pregnancy leave Constitution
An act by a private or public body or person that A holiday resort which allows only Section 14
distinguishes directly or indirectly between groups Christians to visit or an affirmative action of the
of people based on grounds set out in section policy of a small company, and a private PEPUDA
9(3) or analogous grounds and redress measures institution that makes scholarships
imposed by non-legislative means. available only to women to effect redress.
A court, therefore, must look at the effect the remedial measures will
have on the group or groups who may be negatively affected or who
may not be targeted by the measures. In this regard, there appear to be
similarities between this third requirement and the test for unfair
discrimination in terms of section 9(3) discussed below.115 For example,
a programme aimed at addressing the effects of past racial
discrimination may negatively affect white South Africans. Employment
equity legislation or rules designed to accommodate more black
students or women at a university may affect some white applicants for
jobs or university places who may not be appointed or may be denied a
place to study at the university because of the remedial programme.
This in itself will not invalidate the programme. However, where the
measures taken are so extreme that they send a signal that the equal
dignity of white applicants is not respected, the programme may be
invalidated. Thus, where an admissions policy takes race into account
and the effect of that policy is to exclude the vast majority or all of the
white applicants, the programme would probably not pass
constitutional muster.116 In effect, this is a value judgment importing an
internal fairness requirement into the test for a valid remedial
programme.117
The Constitutional Court held that there is an overlap between the
second and the third requirements laid down in Van Heerden as both
are concerned with the desired outcome of redress measures, the
desired outcome being the achievement of equality.118 According to the
Court, what is common to both the second and third requirements is
the reasonable likelihood that the restitutionary measure concerned
would achieve the purpose of equality.119 Despite this overlap, it may be
possible to interpret the two requirements in such a way that they fulfil
different functions. The second requirement focuses on the positive
obligation to work towards the achievement of equality. It speaks to the
obligation that positive steps must be taken by the state and other role
players to effect transformation, and inquires whether the steps that
have been taken are reasonably capable of achieving the goal of
reducing inequality between the economically and socially privileged,
on the one hand, and the economically and socially marginalised on
the other hand. The third requirement focuses on the negative
obligation which requires that measures aimed at achieving equality
should not place an undue burden on those not benefitting from
redress measures. If the two provisions are read in this way, it would
suggest that the third requirement entails some kind of proportionality
test as discussed in the pause for reflection box below. But as the
Constitutional Court has not explicitly addressed this issue, it is not
presently possible to say with certainty that the two requirements
should be distinguished in the manner proposed here.
The Court also held that the policy was irrational. While arbitrariness is
established by the absence of reasons or reasons which do not justify
the action taken, rationality seeks to determine the link between the
purpose and the means chosen to achieve such purpose. It is a standard
lower than arbitrariness. All that is required for rationality to be satisfied
is the connection between the means and the purpose.128 But according
to the majority of the court, the policy did not meet this low bar. The
Court noted that it had already found that the policy was not reasonably
capable of achieving the goal of equality and, therefore, did not meet
the second requirement of the section 9(2) test. ‘[T]he failure to prove
that the policy is reasonably likely to achieve equality’, the Court then
held, ‘must mean that there is no proof of a rational link between the
policy and the purpose sought to be achieved’.129 The Court thus
suggests that the second requirement of the section 9(2) test is similar
to the rationality test. It is unclear, however, whether there will be cases
where a policy meets the second requirement of the section 9(2) test,
but does not meet the rationality standard. What is clear is that this
standard would normally not be difficult to meet.
Analogous grounds will include all the analogous grounds – HIV status,
citizenship, conception infertility – already confirmed by the
Constitutional Court. However, in a potentially radical move, the
Western Cape High Court held in the Social Justice Coalition case that
‘poverty’ also amounted to an analogous ground of discrimination.180
The Court seems to have endorsed the arguments of the applicant that
poverty was a ground of discrimination which caused or perpetuated
systemic disadvantage, undermined human dignity, or adversely
affected the equal enjoyment of the rights and freedoms of the affected
people.181 The Court held that as a result of our history and economic
system, poverty is a systemic problem in South Africa. In addition, the
Court held further, poor people form part of a community that is
vulnerable and marginalised. It follows, therefore, that poverty is
analogous to the other grounds expressly listed in section 9(3) of the
Constitution.182
Once the applicant has made out a prima facie case that
discrimination occurred on either a listed ground or an analogous
ground, the onus shifts to the respondent, who will have to prove that
the discrimination is fair.183 To determine whether the discrimination is
fair or unfair, regard must be had to the factors listed in section 14(2)
and (3) of PEPUDA. Before embarking on a proportionality analysis in
which various interests are weighed up or balanced against each other,
however, a court must first ask:
whether the discrimination reasonably and justifiably differentiates between
persons according to objectively determinable criteria, intrinsic to the activity
concerned.184
What is clear from this list is that PEPUDA allows a court to take into
account a wider range of factors than those set out in the Harksen case
relating to section 9(3) of the Constitution to determine whether
discrimination is fair or unfair. Some of the factors mentioned in section
14 of the PEPUDA mirror those relied on by the Constitutional Court in
section 9(3) cases. Other factors seem to track more closely questions
raised during a section 9(2) enquiry, while yet other factors track the
limitation clause enquiry. The Constitutional Court has not provided an
expansive interpretation of this section so we must assume that its
sections 9(2), 9(3) and 36 analyses are all relevant when applying
section 14 of the PEPUDA.
A contextual enquiry remains at the heart of a section 14 enquiry.
Such a contextual enquiry takes account of the history of the
complainants and their position in society as well as the need for
remedial measures to address the effects of past and ongoing unfair
discrimination. This is in order to advance the value of human dignity
for all. Courts have a discretion to consider all the relevant factors listed
in section 14 and then to decide whether the discrimination is fair or
unfair in the light of these factors. All relevant factors relating to a
specific case must be considered as part of a proportionality analysis to
make an overall assessment of whether the discrimination is fair or
unfair. Not all factors listed in section 14 will be relevant in every case –
it will always depend on the facts of the specific case. When considering
the factors that track closely to the section 36(1) limitation clause
inquiry, one can assume that it would be helpful to borrow from the
Constitutional Court jurisprudence on section 36(1). Similarly, when
dealing with section 9(3) factors one can borrow from the
Constitutional Court jurisprudence on section 9(3).
One aspect of the section 14 enquiry, which has elicited some
discussion by the Constitutional Court, is the requirement that a court
must have regard to ‘whether and to what extent the respondent has
taken such steps as being reasonable in the circumstances to …
accommodate diversity’.187 This factor is generally known as the
requirement for reasonable accommodation.
In MEC for Education: Kwazulu-Natal and Others v Pillay,188 the
Constitutional Court had to decide whether the failure of a school
disciplinary code to take into account the religious or cultural practices
of a Hindu learner unfairly discriminated against her. Ms Pillay wanted
to wear a nose stud to school as this formed part of her religious and
cultural beliefs, but the school’s disciplinary code prohibited this. At the
heart of the case was whether the school had reasonably
accommodated the minority’s religious and cultural practices.
The Court explained that reasonable accommodation required
institutions to ‘take positive measures and possibly incur additional
hardship or expense in order to allow all people to participate and enjoy
all their rights equally’.189 The aim is to ensure that groups are not
relegated to the margins of society because they do not or cannot
conform to certain social norms.190 At the heart of this principle is the
need positively to accommodate diversity. ‘Those steps might be as
simple as granting and regulating an exemption from a general rule or
they may require that the rules or practices be changed or even that
buildings be altered or monetary loss incurred.’191 The extent to which
an institution or community should reasonably accommodate the
cultural and religious beliefs and practices of others is a difficult
question. However, the Constitutional Court has argued that this must
be answered with reference to the specific context. As such, reasonable
accommodation is ‘an exercise in proportionality that will depend
intimately on the facts’ of each case.192
When considering whether discrimination as defined by the
PEPUDA is reasonable or not, ‘reasonable accommodation will always
be an important factor’.193 However, it would be wrong to reduce the test
for fairness to a test for reasonable accommodation. As the
Constitutional Court explained in Pillay:
There may be circumstances where fairness requires a reasonable
accommodation, while in other circumstances it may require more or less, or
something completely different. It will depend on the nature of the case and the
nature of the interests involved. Two factors seem particularly relevant. First,
reasonable accommodation is most appropriate where, as in this case,
discrimination arises from a rule or practice that is neutral on its face and is
designed to serve a valuable purpose, but which nevertheless has a
marginalising effect on certain portions of society. Second, the principle is
particularly appropriate in specific localised contexts, such as an individual
workplace or school, where a reasonable balance between conflicting interests
may more easily be struck. Even where fairness requires a reasonable
accommodation, the other factors listed in section 14 will always remain
relevant.194
13.3.1 Introduction
As we indicated at the beginning of this chapter, dignity is one of the
founding values of the Constitution and permeates many aspects of the
Constitution.200 As we have seen, the value of dignity is used to interpret
the right to equality guaranteed in section 9 of the Constitution. Dignity
also permeates the interpretation of other rights in the Bill of Rights,
including social and economic rights.201
However, dignity is not only one of the founding values of the
Constitution, it is also an independent, self-standing, enforceable right.
Section 10 of the Constitution thus states that ‘[e]veryone has inherent
dignity and the right to have their dignity respected and protected’. The
right, therefore, implies an expectation to be protected from conditions
or treatment which offends a person’s sense of his or her worth in
society. In particular, treatment which is abusive, degrading,
humiliating or demeaning is a violation of this right.202 Moreover,
conduct which treats a person as non-human or less than human or as
an object is intolerable and contrary to section 10 of the Constitution.203
At the heart of the right to dignity is the assumption that each
human being has incalculable human worth, regardless of
circumstances, and should be treated accordingly. This idea or value is
‘at the inner heartland of our rights culture’.204 Dignity can be viewed as
a personal right associated with a person’s identity,205 autonomy and
moral agency.206 In his separate judgment in Walker, Sachs J held that
the right to dignity necessarily entails that everyone has the same moral
worth207 as dignity entails an acknowledgement of ‘the intrinsic worth of
human beings’ and the recognition that ‘human beings are entitled to
be treated as worthy of respect and concern’.208 Moreover, human
dignity demands that people be treated as unique individuals rather
than as representatives of a group.
South African courts have developed a comprehensive meaning of
the right to human dignity. In light of the fact that the Constitution
permits reference to foreign law to interpret the rights in the Bill of
Rights, our courts have invoked the jurisprudence of foreign
jurisdictions to clarify the meaning of the concept of human dignity.
Specifically, former Chief Justice Chaskalson referred to the case of Law
v Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration)209 when he
delivered the Third Bram Fischer lecture in 2000.210 In this case, the
Canadian Supreme Court described human dignity as follows:
Human dignity means that an individual or group feels self-respect and self-
worth. It is concerned with physical and psychological integrity and
empowerment. Human dignity is harmed by unfair treatment premised upon
personal traits or circumstances which do not relate to individual needs,
capacities, or merits. It is enhanced by laws which are sensitive to the needs,
capacities and merits of different individuals, taking into account the context of
their differences. Human dignity is harmed when individuals and groups are
marginalised, ignored, or devalued, and is enhanced when laws recognise the
full place of all individuals and groups within society.211
This fact that the right to dignity includes a right to have one’s agency
respected is a potentially important development as it illustrates that
the right to dignity is not only concerned with the personal feelings of
an individual who has been treated badly. In addition, it allows us to
focus on the negative impact of legislation, rules and policies that
patronise individuals by limiting their ability to make meaningful life
choices. The potentially far-reaching effect of this development is
illustrated by the Constitutional Court judgment in Freedom of Religion
South Africa v Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development and
Others.231 In this case, the Court held that the common law rule which
allowed parents to inflict corporal punishment on their children as long
as this amounted to moderate chastisement, was unconstitutional. The
judgment relied in part on section 12(1)(c) of the Constitution that
guarantees everyone the right to be free from all forms of violence.232
However, the Court also held that this rule infringed on children’s right
to human dignity. This is because ‘children are constitutionally
recognised independent human beings, inherently entitled to the
enjoyment of human rights, regardless of whether they are orphans or
have parents’.233 Quoting from an earlier Constitutional Court
judgment,234 the Court explained that the fact that children enjoy the
right to dignity has far-reaching consequences for how they should be
viewed by the law.
If a child is to be constitutionally imagined as an individual with a distinctive
personality, and not merely as a miniature adult waiting to reach full size, he or
she cannot be treated as a mere extension of his or her parents, umbilically
destined to sink or swim with them … Individually and collectively all children
have a right to express themselves as independent social beings, to have their
own laughter as well as sorrow, to play, imagine and explore in their own way,
to themselves get to understand their bodies, minds and emotions, and above
all to learn as they grow how they should conduct themselves and make
choices in the wide social and moral world of adulthood. And foundational to
the enjoyment of the right to childhood is the promotion of the right as far as
possible to live in a secure and nurturing environment free from violence, fear,
want and avoidable trauma.235
13.4.1 Introduction
In the light of its cruel, discriminatory and oppressive nature, it is not
surprising that there was massive resistance to apartheid both inside
and outside the country. This resistance gave rise to many
organisations, including the African National Congress, the South
African Communist Party and the Pan African Congress. It also took
many forms, including armed resistance, economic and sports boycotts,
pickets and strikes. In order to control and ultimately supress these acts,
the apartheid state relied on both legal and extra-legal mechanisms.
As the Constitutional Court pointed out in De Lange v Smuts NO,247
among the most egregious of these legal mechanisms was the system of
administrative detention without trial for political purposes. Detention
without trial allowed the apartheid security police to arrest activists and
detain them for long periods of time, without having to charge or
prosecute them. Detention was a weapon used by the apartheid regime
to intimidate activists and also provided the opportunity for the security
police to interrogate and torture detained activists. So, although
detention without trial was authorised by law, detainees were
(ostensibly unlawfully) tortured and some died at the hands of the
security police because of this torture. Among the most prominent
detainees to be killed in this way were Ahmed Timol (b.1941, d.1971),
Steven Bantu Biko (b.1946, d.1977) and Neil Aggett (b.1953, d.1982).
Given this history, it is not surprising that section 12 of the
Constitution guarantees a right to freedom and security of the person.
The provisions of this section embody two severable but interrelated
rights. First, a general right to freedom grounded in physical integrity
and, second, a definitive right to bodily and psychological integrity.
Section 12(1) provides in this respect that:
Everyone has the right to freedom and security of the person, which includes
the right:
(a) not to be deprived of freedom arbitrarily or without just cause;
(b) not to be detained without trial;
(c) to be free from all forms of violence from either public or private sources;
(d) not to be tortured in any way; and
(e) not to be treated or punished in a cruel, inhuman or degrading way.
After making these points, the Court turned to discuss each aspect in
more detail.
In so far as the substantive dimension was concerned, the Court
held that it is aimed at ensuring that a deprivation of liberty cannot take
place without a satisfactory or adequate reason for doing so. This
means, first, that there must be a rational connection between the
deprivation and some objectively determinable purpose. If such a
rational connection does not exist, then the deprivation is arbitrary.
However, even if such a rational connection does exist, that by itself is
not enough. The cause, purpose or reason for the deprivation must be a
‘just’ one.276
When it comes to determining what would constitute a ‘just cause’,
the Court held further, it is not possible to give a comprehensive answer.
Instead, the meaning of this concept will have to be developed on a
case-by-case basis. The concept of a just cause, however, must be based
on and consonant with the values set out in section 1 of the
Constitution and gathered from the provisions of the Constitution as a
whole.277 In the case at hand, the Court found that the purpose
underlying section 66(3) of the Insolvency Act was just because it was
aimed at ensuring that a person who was under a legal duty to give
evidence did so.278
In so far as the procedural dimension of the right to freedom was
concerned, the Court held that although section 12(1)(b) refers only to
the ‘right not to be detained without trial’ and not to any other
procedural components of such a trial it is implicit in the section that
the trial must be a ‘fair’ trial.279 This does not mean, however, that the
trial must comply with all of the requirements embodied in section
35(3) of the Constitution. Instead, it simply requires a hearing
conducted by a judicial officer acting in his or her capacity as a judicial
officer.280
The fact that a fair trial requires a hearing conducted by a judicial
officer acting in his or her official capacity, the Court held further, is
based on two important grounds.
First, the decision to commit an uncooperative witness to prison is a
judicial function and only judicial officers may perform this function.
This is because they enjoy complete independence from the other
branches of government and therefore are well placed to curb the abuse
of governmental power.
Second, the decision whether to commit an uncooperative witness
to prison is a dispute envisaged by section 34 of the Constitution which
provides that legal disputes must be decided either by a ‘court or, where
appropriate, another independent and impartial tribunal or forum’.281
While a meeting of the creditors may be classified as a tribunal or
forum, it may only be classified as an independent tribunal or forum if
its presided over by a judicial officer.
13.5.1 Introduction
One of the most notorious legislative provisions in place during the
apartheid era was section 16 of the Immorality Act.341 This section
criminalised all extramarital sexual relations between a white male and
a black (broadly defined) female, and vice versa. (Interracial marriages
were prohibited by the Prohibition of Mixed Marriages Act.342) The
Immorality Act authorised police officers to invade people’s private
homes in order to catch couples in the act of breaking this law, thus
infringing on their privacy. The playwright Athol Fugard wrote a play,
which opened in 1972, entitled Statements After an Arrest Under the
Immorality Act, to dramatise the absurdity, the heartache and the pain
caused by this provision. A short summary of the play illustrates the
effects of section 16:
Set in apartheid South Africa, where relationships across the colour bar were a
criminal offence, two lovers – a black man and white woman meet secretly in
the library where the woman works to make love and share their hopes and
fears. An observant neighbour reports them to the police who secretly
photograph them from the informant’s backyard and eventually break in and
arrest the couple under the then inhuman and universally pilloried Immorality
Act. The play is a compelling and deeply moving love story in which the
physically and emotionally naked lovers expose not only their bodies but also
their deepest longings for personal and emotional freedom.343
The effect of this view regarding privacy is that in the ‘inner sanctum’ of
a person’s life, in his or her ‘truly personal realm’ like his or her home or
bedroom, there would be a far greater likelihood that a person’s
expectation of having his or her privacy respected is reasonable. Privacy
is therefore viewed as a continuum with more intense protection at its
core and less intense protection on the periphery. Privacy becomes
more intense the closer it moves to the intimate personal sphere of life
of human beings and less intense as it moves away from that core.352
Privacy and dignity, therefore, are closely related.353 This is so because
where a person’s privacy is breached, that person will often not be
treated with concern and respect.
There is a range of factors relevant to distinguishing the core of
privacy from its penumbra. One of the considerations is the nature of
the relationship concerned. For example, in Jordan, the minority
judgment of the Constitutional Court found with regard to the
regulation of sex work that:
One of the considerations is the nature of the relationship concerned: an
invasion of the relationship between partners, or parent and child, or other
intimate, meaningful and intensely personal relationships will be a strong
indication of a violation close to the core of privacy.354
Following this reasoning, the minority in the Jordan case concluded
that the commercial nature of the conduct under consideration
removed it from the inner sanctum of privacy. The majority in this case,
controversially, came to the same conclusion, holding that if the right to
privacy is implicated at all in a case where sex work is regulated, ‘it lies
at the periphery and not at its inner core’.355
For the same reason the Constitutional Court found in Investigating
Directorate: Serious Economic Offences and Others v Hyundai Motor
Distributors (Pty) Ltd and Others In re: Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty)
Ltd and Others v Smit NO and Others356 that the privacy rights of a
juristic person would be less intense than those of a human being.
Although juristic persons like big companies also enjoy the protection
of the privacy right, this protection would be weaker than for an
ordinary human being:
As we have seen, privacy is a right which becomes more intense the closer it
moves to the intimate personal sphere of the life of human beings, and less
intense as it moves away from that core. This understanding of the right flows,
as was said in Bernstein, from the value placed on human dignity by the
Constitution. Juristic persons are not the bearers of human dignity. Their
privacy rights, therefore, can never be as intense as those of human beings.
However, this does not mean that juristic persons are not protected by the right
to privacy. Exclusion of juristic persons would lead to the possibility of grave
violations of privacy in our society, with serious implications for the conduct of
affairs. The state might, for instance, have free licence to search and seize
material from any non-profit organisation or corporate entity at will. This
would obviously lead to grave disruptions and would undermine the very fabric
of our democratic state. Juristic persons therefore do enjoy the right to privacy,
although not to the same extent as natural persons. The level of justification for
any particular limitation of the right will have to be judged in the light of the
circumstances of each case. Relevant circumstances would include whether
the subject of the limitation is a natural person or a juristic person as well as
the nature and effect of the invasion of privacy.357
SUMMARY
This chapter deals with the right to equality and the right to dignity.
Section 9 of the Constitution guarantees the right to equality. A litigant
invokes section 9 in cases where he or she wishes to attack the
constitutionality of a legislative provision because the litigant believes
that the provision impermissibly differentiates between people or
groups of people. The courts rely on section 9(1), section 9(2) or section
9(3), depending on the nature of the differentiation complained of, to
decide the case.
The courts rely on section 9(1) where a legislative provision
differentiates between groups of people on grounds other than those
listed in section 9(3) or analogous to those listed in section 9(3). This so-
called mere differentiation includes the many distinctions made in
legislation that are not related to the personal attributes and
characteristics of groups of people. A section 9(1) challenge has to be
based on the question of whether the differentiation (mere
differentiation) was rational or arbitrary.
The courts rely on section 9(2) where the legislative provision being
challenged differentiates between groups of people on one of the
grounds listed in section 9(3) or on grounds analogous to those listed in
this section, for example race, sex or sexual orientation. However, in this
case, the legislation differentiates between groups of people with the
aim of correcting the effects of past unfair discrimination (affirmative
action). When testing an affirmative action provision against section
9(2), the court asks:
• whether the affirmative action scheme devised by the legislature
targets a group who was unfairly discriminated against in the past
• whether the scheme is designed to achieve its redress goal, in other
words, whether it is reasonably capable of doing so
• whether the scheme will achieve the long-term goal of equality,
which would not be the case if the scheme gratuitously and
flagrantly imposes disproportionate burdens on the excluded group.
1 See S v Makwanyane (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3; 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC); 1995 (6) BCLR 665
(CC) (6 June 1995) para 329; Teddy Bear Clinic for Abused Children and Another v Minister
of Justice and Constitutional Development and Another (CCT 12/13) [2013] ZACC 35; 2014
(2) SA 168 (CC); 2013 (12) BCLR 1429 (CC) (3 October 2013) para 52; Freedom of Religion
South Africa v Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development and Others (CCT320/17)
[2019] ZACC 34; 2020 (1) SA 1 (CC); 2019 (11) BCLR 1321 (CC) (18 September 2019) para
45. See also Gelyke Kanse and Others v Chairperson of the Senate of the University of
Stellenbosch and Others (CCT 311/17) [2019] ZACC 38; 2020 (1) SA 368 (CC); 2019 (12)
BCLR 1479 (CC) (10 October 2019) para 63 where the Constitutional Court refers to the
‘dignity-restoring and enhancing aspirational measures’ embodied in the Constitution.
2 See Currie, I and De Waal, J (2013) The Bill of Rights Handbook 6th ed 250.
3 Dawood and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others; Shalabi and Another v Minister
of Home Affairs and Others; Thomas and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others
(CCT35/99) [2000] ZACC 8; 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC); 2000 (8) BCLR 837 (CC) (7 June 2000)
para 35.
4 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality and Another v Minister of Justice and
Others (CCT11/98) [1998] ZACC 15; 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC); 1998 (12) BCLR 1517 (CC) (9
October 1998) para 120.
5 Dawood para 35.
6 Dawood para 35.
7 For an admirable book-length attempt to do so, see Ackermann, L (2012) Human Dignity:
Lodestar for Equality in South Africa.
8 Teddy Bear Clinic para 52. See also Khumalo and Others v Holomisa (CCT53/01) [2002]
ZACC 12; 2002 (5) SA 401 (CC); 2002 (8) BCLR 771 (CC) (14 June 2002) para 27. See also
Cameron, E (2014) ‘Dignity and disgrace: Moral citizenship and constitutional protection’
in Corder, H, Federico, V and Orrù, R (eds) The Quest for Constitutionalism: South Africa
since 1994 101.
9 Liebenberg, S (2005) The value of human dignity in interpreting socio-economic rights
South African Journal on Human Rights 21(1):7.
10 Nussbaum, MC Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach (2000) 72.
11 Liebenberg (2005) 7.
12 See Sanderson v Attorney-General, Eastern Cape (CCT10/97) [1997] ZACC 18; 1998 (2) SA
38 (CC); 1997 (12) BCLR 1675 (CC) (2 December 1997) para 23.
13 Mokgoro, JY (1998) Ubuntu and the law in South Africa Potchefstroom Electronic Law
Journal 1(1):1.
14 Mokgoro (1998) 1.
15 Kunene, M (1995, 16 August) The Essence of being Human: An African Perspective,
inaugural lecture delivered at the University of Natal (as yet unpublished).
16 Kunene (1995) 2.
17 This is starting to change and several scholars have developed arguments in favour of
embedding rights discourse within a social solidarity model. See Douwes, R, Stuttaford, M
and London, L (2018) Social solidarity, human rights, and collective action: Considerations
in the implementation of the national health insurance in South Africa Health and Human
Rights Journal 20(2):185–96.
18 Brink v Kitshoff NO (CCT15/95) [1996] ZACC 9; 1996 (4) SA 197 (CC); 1996 (6) BCLR 752
(CC) (15 May 1996) para 40.
19 Langa, P (2006) Transformative constitutionalism Stellenbosch Law Review 17(3):351–60 at
352–3. See also Albertyn, C and Goldblatt, B ‘Equality’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds)
(2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 35.5.
20 Currie and De Waal (2013) 213.
21 See De Vos, P (2000) Equality for all? A critical analysis of the equality jurisprudence of the
Constitutional Court Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 63(1):62–75 at 65;
Albertyn and Goldblatt (2013) 35.6.
22 De Vos (2000) 65.
23 Albertyn and Goldblatt (2013) 35.6. See also Albertyn, C and Goldblatt, B (1998) Facing the
challenge of transformation: Difficulties in the development of an indigenous
jurisprudence of equality South African Journal on Human Rights 14(2):248–76 at 152–3.
24 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice para 60.
25 (CCT 63/03) [2004] ZACC 3; 2004 (6) SA 121 (CC); 2004 (11) BCLR 1125 (CC); (29 July 2004)
para 27. See also Brink para 40; President of the Republic of South Africa and Another v
Hugo (CCT11/96) [1997] ZACC 4; 1997 (4) SA 1 (CC); 1997 (6) BCLR 708 (CC) (18 April
1997) para 41; Prinsloo v Van der Linde and Another (CCT4/96) [1997] ZACC 5; 1997 (3) SA
1012 (CC); 1997 (6) BCLR 759 (CC) (18 April 1997) para 31; City Council of Pretoria v Walker
(CCT8/97) [1998] ZACC 1; 1998 (2) SA 363 (CC); 1998 (3) BCLR 257 (CC) (17 February 1998)
para 46; Hoffmann v South African Airways (CCT17/00) [2000] ZACC 17; 2001 (1) SA 1 (CC);
2000 (11) BCLR 1211 (CC); (28 September 2000); South African Police Service v Solidarity
obo Barnard (CCT 01/14) [2014] ZACC 23; 2014 (6) SA 123 (CC); 2014 (10) BCLR 1195 (CC);
(2 September 2014) paras 29–35.
26 Brink para 40. See also Walker para 26 where Langa DP stated that the assessment of
discrimination cannot be undertaken in a vacuum, ‘but should be based both on the
wording of the section and in the constitutional and historical context of the developments
in South Africa’.
27 Brink para 41.
28 Brink para 41.
29 See, for example, Harksen v Lane NO and Others (CCT9/97) [1997] ZACC 12; 1998 (1) SA
300 (CC); 1997 (11) BCLR 1489 (CC) (7 October 1997) para 51(b).
30 See De Vos (2000) 66.
31 Botha, H (2009) Equality, plurality and structural power South African Journal on Human
Rights 25(1):1–37 at 7.
32 For a real-life example, see Kassiem, A (2006, 26 June) Guest houses ‘can be for gay men
only’ Independent Online available at http://www.iol.co.za/news/south-africa/guest-
houses-can-be-for-gay-men-only-1.283071.
33 Act 4 of 2000.
34 Prinsloo para 23.
35 Prinsloo para 24.
36 Phaahla v Minister of Justice and Correctional Services and Another (Tlhakanye
Intervening) (CCT44/18) [2019] ZACC 18; 2019 (2) SACR 88 (CC); 2019 (7) BCLR 795 (CC) (3
May 2019) para 46.
37 Brink; Prinsloo; Hugo; Harksen; Larbi-Odam and Others v Member of the Executive Council
for Education (North-West Province) and Another (CCT2/97) [1997] ZACC 16; 1998 (1) SA
745 (CC); 1997 (12) BCLR 1655 (CC) (26 November 1997); Walker; National Coalition for
Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice; Hoffmann; Moseneke and Others v Master of
the High Court (CCT51/00) [2000] ZACC 27; 2001 (2) SA 18 (CC); 2001 (2) BCLR 103 (CC) (6
December 2000); Satchwell v President of Republic of South Africa and Another (CCT45/01)
[2002] ZACC 18; 2002 (6) SA 1 (CC); 2002 (9) BCLR 986 (CC) (25 July 2002); J and Another v
Director General, Department of Home Affairs and Others (CCT46/02) [2003] ZACC 3; 2003
(5) SA 621 (CC); 2003 (5) BCLR 463 (CC) (28 March 2003); Du Toit and Another v Minister of
Welfare and Population Development and Others (CCT40/01) [2002] ZACC 20; 2003 (2) SA
198 (CC); 2002 (10) BCLR 1006 (CC) (10 September 2002); Bhe and Others v Khayelitsha
Magistrate and Others (CCT 49/03) [2004] ZACC 17; 2005 (1) SA 580 (CC); 2005 (1) BCLR 1
(CC) (15 October 2004); Volks NO v Robinson and Others (CCT12/04) [2005] ZACC 2; 2005
(5) BCLR 446 (CC) (21 February 2005); Minister of Home Affairs and Another v Fourie and
Another (CCT 60/04) [2005] ZACC 19; 2006 (1) SA 524 (CC); 2006 (3) BCLR 355 (CC) (1
December 2005); Gory v Kolver NO and Others (CCT28/06) [2006] ZACC 20; 2007 (4) SA 97
(CC); 2007 (3) BCLR 249 (CC) (23 November 2006). See also Pretorius, JL (2010) Fairness in
transformation: A critique of the Constitutional Court’s affirmative action jurisprudence
South African Journal on Human Rights 26(3):536–70.
See generally Fagan, A (1998) Dignity and unfair discrimination: A value misplaced and a
38 right misunderstood South African Journal on Human Rights 14(2):220–47 at 220; and
Westen, P (1982) The empty idea of equality Harvard Law Review 95(3):537–96 at 537.
39 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice para 122.
40 De Vos (2000) 64.
41 (CCT11/96) [1997] ZACC 4; 1997 (4) SA 1 (CC); 1997 (6) BCLR 708 (CC) (18 April 1997).
42 Hugo para 41.
43 Hugo para 41. See also Albertyn and Goldblatt (1998) 257.
44 See Woolman, S ‘Dignity’ in Woolman and Bishop (2013) 36.3.
45 Government of the Republic of South Africa and Others v Grootboom and Others
(CCT11/00) [2000] ZACC 19; 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC); 2000 (11) BCLR 1169 (CC) (4 October
2000) para 23.
46 Grootboom para 25.
47 Hugo para 41; Prinsloo paras 31–3; Harksen para 50.
48 (CCT4/96) [1997] ZACC 5; 1997 (3) SA 1012 (CC); 1997 (6) BCLR 759 (CC) (18 April 1997).
49 Prinsloo para 33. See also Harksen para 50: ‘Whether or not there is discrimination will
depend upon whether, objectively, the ground is based on attributes and characteristics
which have the potential to impair the fundamental human dignity of persons as human
beings or to affect them adversely in a comparably serious manner.’
50 Malherbe, R (2007) Some thoughts on unity, diversity and human dignity in the new South
Africa Tydskrif vir die Suid Afrikaanse Reg/Journal of South African Law 70(1):127–33 at
132.
51 Albertyn and Goldblatt (1998) 256–60.
52 Botha (2009) 8.
53 Botha (2009) 9.
54 Albertyn and Goldblatt (2013) 35.10. See, for example, Grootboom para 23.
55 (CCT 13/03, CCT 12/03) [2004] ZACC 11; 2004 (6) SA 505 (CC); 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC) (4
March 2004).
56 Khosa para 74.
57 Van Heerden para 25.
58 Van Heerden para 31.
59 There is some dispute about this, and the Constitutional Court has not clarified the matter.
See Albertyn, C (2018) Getting it right in equality cases. The evaluation of positive
measures, groups and subsidiarity in Solidariteit v Minister of Basic Education South
African Law Journal 135(3):405 at 416.
60 South African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence and Others (CCT65/06) [2007]
ZACC 10; 2007 (5) SA 400 (CC); 2007 (8) BCLR 863 (CC); (30 May 2007) paras 51–2; MEC for
Education: Kwazulu-Natal and Others v Pillay (CCT 51/06) [2007] ZACC 21; 2008 (1) SA 474
(CC); 2008 (2) BCLR 99 (CC) (5 October 2007) paras 39–40; Walele v City of Cape Town and
Others (CCT 64/07) [2008] ZACC 11; 2008 (6) SA 129 (CC); 2008 (11) BCLR 1067 (CC) (13
June 2008) paras 29–30; Nokotyana and Others v Ekurhuleni Metropolitan Municipality and
Others (CCT 31/09) [2009] ZACC 33; 2010 (4) BCLR 312 (CC) (19 November 2009) paras 47–
9; De Lange v Presiding Bishop of the Methodist Church of Southern Africa for the time being
and Another (CCT223/14) [2015] ZACC 35; 2016 (2) SA 1 (CC); 2016 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) (24
November 2015) para 53; My Vote Counts NPC v Speaker of the National Assembly and
Others (CCT121/14) [2015] ZACC 31 (30 September 2015) para 161. See also Van der Walt,
AJ (2008) Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term Constitutional
Court Review 1:77–128 at 100–03.
61 My Vote Counts para 160 (footnotes omitted).
62 Prinsloo para 25.
63 Prinsloo paras 23–4.
64 Van Heerden para 33.
65 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice para 18.
66 Prinsloo para 22.
67 Act 55 of 1998.
68 Van Der Walt v Metcash Trading Limited (CCT37/01) [2002] ZACC 4; 2002 (4) SA 317 (CC);
2002 (5) BCLR 454 (CC) (11 April 2002) para 24; Phaahla v Minister of Justice and
Correctional Services and Another (Tlhakanye Intervening) (CCT44/18) [2019] ZACC 18;
2019 (2) SACR 88 (CC); 2019 (7) BCLR 795 (CC) (3 May 2019) para 46.
69 Prinsloo para 22, quoting, in part, Didcott in S v Ntuli (CCT17/95) [1995] ZACC 14; 1996 (1)
SA 1207 (CC); 1996 (1) BCLR 141 (CC) (8 December 1995) para 18. See also Walker para 27.
70 Prinsloo para 25 and Walker para 27.
71 Prinsloo para 25.
72 Prinsloo para 25; Herbert N.O. and Others v Senqu Municipality and Others (CCT 308/18)
[2019] ZACC 31; 2019 (6) SA 231 (CC); 2019 (11) BCLR 1343 (CC) (22 August 2019) para 30.
73 (CCT93/14) [2015] ZACC 14; 2015 (4) SA 491 (CC); 2015 (8) BCLR 925 (CC) (4 June 2015)
para 51.
74 See Mendes, E ‘The crucible of the Charter’ in Beaudoin, GA and Mendes, E (eds) (1996)
The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms 3.20; Tribe, LH (1988) American
Constitutional Law 2nd ed 1442–3.
75 Prinsloo para 35.
76 Harksen para 43.
77 Prinsloo paras 24–6.
78 Van der Merwe v Road Accident Fund and Another (CCT48/05) [2006] ZACC 4; 2006 (4) SA
230 (CC); 2006 (6) BCLR 682 (CC) (30 March 2006) para 33. See also Jooste v Score
Supermarket Trading (Pty) Ltd (Minister of Labour intervening) (CCT15/98) [1998] ZACC
18; 1999 (2) SA 1 (CC); 1999 (2) BCLR 139 (CC) (27 November 1998).
79 In Jooste para 16 the Constitutional Court explained this as follows:
It is clear that the only purpose of rationality review is an inquiry into whether the
differentiation is arbitrary or irrational, or manifests naked preference and it is
irrelevant to this inquiry whether the scheme chosen by the legislature could be
improved in one respect or another. Whether an employee ought to have retained
the common law right to claim damages, either over and above or as an alternative
to the advantages conferred by the Compensation Act, represents a highly
debatable, controversial and complex matter of policy. It involves a policy choice
which the legislature and not a court must make. The contention represents an
invitation to this Court to make a policy choice under the guise of rationality review;
an invitation which is firmly declined.
80 (CCT 117/11) [2013] ZACC 4; 2013 (4) BCLR 421 (CC) (7 March 2013). See also Sarrahwitz v
Martiz N.O. and Another (CCT93/14) [2015] ZACC 14; 2015 (4) SA 491 (CC); 2015 (8) BCLR
925 (CC) (4 June 2015).
81 Act 44 of 1958.
82 Ngewu para 17.
83 Brink para 42. See generally Walker.
84 Van Heerden para 27.
85 Van Heerden para 25.
86 Minister of Constitutional Development and Another v South African Restructuring and
Insolvency Practitioners Association and Others (CCT13/17) [2018] ZACC 20; 2018 (5) SA
349 (CC); 2018 (9) BCLR 1099 (CC) (5 July 2018) para 1.
87 See the debate on the nature of these measures in Currie and De Waal (2013) 241–2; Gutto,
S (2001) Equality and Non-Discrimination in South Africa: The Political Economy of Law
and Law Making 204–5. See also Du Plessis, L and Corder, H (1994) Understanding South
Africa’s Transitional Bill of Rights 144–5; Pretorius, JL (2001) Constitutional standards for
affirmative action in South Africa: A comparative overview Heidelberg Journal of
International Law 61(8):403–57 at 403; Van Reenen, TP (1997) Equality, discrimination and
affirmative action: An analysis of section 9 of the Constitution of the Republic of South
Africa SA Publiekreg/Public Law 12(1):151–65 at 151; Dupper, O (2004) In defence of
affirmative action South African Law Journal 121(1):187–215; Dupper, O, MacEwan, M and
Louw, A (2006) Employment equity in the tertiary sector in the Western Cape International
Journal of Discrimination and the Law 8(3):191–212; De Vos, P (2012) The past is
unpredictable: Race, redress and remembrance in the South African Constitution South
African Law Journal 129(1):73–103; Albertyn, CH (2015) Adjudicating affirmative action
within a normative framework of substantive equality and the employment equity act – An
opportunity missed? South African Police Service v Solidarity obo Barnard South African
Law Journal 132(4):711; Gaibie, S (2015) The Constitutional Court decision in Barnard: A
sequel to the Van Heerden judgment Industrial Law Journal 36(1):80.
88 Van Heerden para 73.
89 Van Heerden para 75.
90 Van Heerden para 24.
91 Van Heerden para 31.
92 Van Heerden para 33.
93 Van Heerden paras 34–5.
94 Act 55 of 1998. On the interpretation of this Act, see Solidarity and Others v Department of
Correctional Services and Others (CCT 78/15) [2016] ZACC 18; 2016 (5) SA 594 (CC); 2016
(10) BCLR 1349 (CC) (15 July 2016); Solidarity obo Barnard.
95 S 13 of the Employment Equity Act.
96 Act 53 of 2003.
97 Merten, M (2019, 28 August) Employment Equity – 20 years down the line, a marginal
movement to diversity Daily Maverick available at
https://www.dailymaverick.co.za/article/2019-08-28-employment-equity-20-years-down-
the-line-a-marginal-movement-to-diversity/.
98 Motileng, BB, Wagner, C and Cassimjee, N (2006) Black middle managers’ experience of
affirmative action in a media company SA Journal of Industrial Psychology 32(1):11–6.
99 Motileng, Wagner and Cassimjee (2006) 14.
100 Motileng, Wagner and Cassimjee (2006) 14.
101 Minister of Finance and Other v Van Heerden (CCT 63/03) [2004] ZACC 3; 2004 (6) SA 121
(CC); 2004 (11) BCLR 1125 (CC); (29 July 2004) para 37; Solidarity obo Barnard para 36;
South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association para 38.
102 South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association para 47.
103 Van Heerden para 39.
104 Van Heerden para 40.
105 Albertyn and Goldblatt (2013) 35.35.
106 Van Heerden para 87.
107 Van Heerden para 155.
108 De Vos (2012) 77–8.
109 South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association para 44.
110 Van Heerden para 41.
111 Van Heerden para 43.
112 Van Heerden para 41.
113 Van Heerden para 152.
114 Van Heerden para 44.
115 This view is bolstered by the concurrent decisions of Sachs J in Van Heerden para 146, in
which he emphasises the substantive nature of equality and affirms that s 9(2) of the
Constitution must be applied within this framework.
116 De Vos (2012) 93–4.
117 Pretorius (2010) 564.
118 South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association para 44.
119 South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association para 46.
120 Pretorius (2010) 562.
121 Pretorius (2010) 562–3.
122 Van Heerden para 41. See also Prinsloo paras 24–6 and 36; Jooste para 16.
123 South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association para 47.
124 South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association paras 49–54.
125 South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association paras 55–8.
126 South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association para 54.
127 South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association para 50 and 51.
128 South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association para 55.
129 South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association para 58.
130 In National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice para 18, the
Constitutional Court stressed that the two enquiries need not follow one from the other.
The rational connection enquiry would be clearly unnecessary in a case in which a court
holds that the discrimination is unfair and unjustifiable.
131 Harksen para 44. See also AB and Another v Minister of Social Development (CCT155/15)
[2016] ZACC 43; 2017 (3) SA 570 (CC); 2017 (3) BCLR 267 (CC) (29 November 2016) para
102; Minister of Safety and Security v South African Hunters and Game Conservation
Association (CCT177/17) [2018] ZACC 14; 2018 (2) SACR 164 (CC); 2018 (10) BCLR 1268
(CC) (7 June 2018) para 23.
132 Harksen para 44. This distinction and the concomitant two-stage analysis were not
employed in the cases preceding Harksen. In Prinsloo, for example, the Court combined
the two stages or, at least, did not identify the two stages (paras 30–1). See Currie and De
Waal (2013) 223.
133 Prinsloo para 29.
134 Harksen para 46.
135 Harksen para 50(b).
136 See Albertyn and Goldblatt (2013) 35.43.
137 Harksen para 47.
138 Walker para 43.
139 Walker para 43. Albertyn and Goldblatt (1998) 268 criticise this view and argue that it
‘denudes discrimination of its prejudicial connotations by not requiring that such prejudice
be demonstrated’. They find support for this view from the dissenting opinion of Sachs J in
Walker paras 105–6 who argued that there can only be a finding of discrimination (the first
stage of the analysis) if the claimant can prove that he or she had been prejudiced – that
there had been ‘actual negative impact’ associated with a specified ground – by the
differentiation which was based on one of the specified grounds. He concludes:
The core of my argument at this stage is that the complainant has not made out a
case of having suffered prima facie discrimination at all. In order to invoke the
presumption of unfairness contained in s 8(4) [now s 9(5)] some element of actual
or potential prejudice must be immanent in the differentiation, otherwise there is
no ‘discrimination’ to be evaluated, and the need to establish fairness or
unfairness has no subject matter.
This view was, however, explicitly rejected in the same case by the majority judgment of
Langa DP as contrary to the previous equality decisions of the Court (para 33).
140 Union of Refugee Women and Others v Director, Private Security Industry Regulatory
Authority and Others (CCT 39/06) [2006] ZACC 23; 2007 (4) SA 395 (CC); 2007 (4) BCLR 339
(CC) (12 December 2006) para 45.
141 Harksen para 46.
142 Harksen para 46.
143 Harksen para 47. See also AB para 105.
144 (CCT17/00) [2000] ZACC 17; 2001 (1) SA 1 (CC); 2000 (11) BCLR 1211; (CC) (28 September
2000).
145 Hoffmann para 28.
146 Larbi-Odam para 19.
147 AB paras 106–7, where the Court held that:
Those who are pregnancy infertile, but not conception infertile, can use surrogacy
to ameliorate the psychological harms of infertility. By contrast, those who are both
conception and pregnancy infertile cannot. This raises the differentiation to the
level of discrimination. The harm to psychological integrity that infertility brings,
and which results in discriminatory treatment, is buttressed by our dignity
jurisprudence. The section which follows illustrates in more detail the effect section
294 has on the dignity of those negatively affected by it.
148 Nettle, D (2002) Height and Reproductive Success in a Cohort of British Men Human
Nature 13(4):487.
149 Workplace Rewards Tall People With Money, Respect, UF Study Shows (2003) available at
https://news.ufl.edu/archive/2003/10/workplace-rewards-tall-people-with-money-
respect-uf-study-shows.html.
150 Patzer, GL (1985) The Physical Attractiveness Phenomena 2.
151 See generally De Casanova, EM (2004) “No Ugly Women”: Concepts of Race and Beauty
among Adolescent Women in Ecuador Gender and Society 18(3):287–308. Accessed 19
October 2020 at http://www.jstor.org/stable/4149403.
152 See Fourie.
153 (CCT8/97) [1998] ZACC 1; 1998 (2) SA 363 (CC); 1998 (3) BCLR 257 (CC) (17 February
1998).
154 Walker para 31.
155 (CCT31/01) [2002] ZACC 22; 2002 (6) SA 642 (CC); 2002 (11) BCLR 1117 (CC) (9 October
2002).
156 Jordan para 10.
157 Jordan para 60.
158 See Kassiem, A (2004, 11 February) Gay nightclub admits to discrimination Independent
Online available at http://www.iol.co.za/news/south-africa/gay-nightclub-admits-to-
racial-discrimination-1.122764.
159 Harksen para 44.
160 Harksen para 49.
161 Such an interpretation would mean that human dignity is employed by a court in both step
1 and step 2 in cases where the differentiation is based on one of the unspecified grounds.
This would make the process somewhat strange and at least one of the two steps
completely superfluous.
162 Van Heerden para 27; AB para 126.
163 See National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice para 22 where
Ackermann J further stressed that the harm of discrimination is structural in nature.
164 Harksen para 49: ‘In the final analysis it is the impact of the discrimination on the
complainant that is the determining factor regarding the unfairness of the discrimination.’
AB para 127.
165 Harksen para 50.
166 Brink para 27. See also Albertyn and Goldblatt (2013) 35.76.
167 Khosa para 76.
168 See Hoffmann.
169 Khosa para 71.
170 (CCT10/99) [1999] ZACC 17; 2000 (2) SA 1 (CC); 2000 (1) BCLR 39 (CC) (2 December 1999)
para 54.
171 Act 68 of 1995.
172 Act 4 of 2000.
173 Minister of Health and Another v New Clicks South Africa (Pty) Ltd and Others (CCT
59/2004) [2005] ZACC 14; 2006 (2) SA 311 (CC); 2006 (8) BCLR 872 (CC) (30 September
2005) paras 96 (Chaskalson CJ) and 434–7 (Ngcobo J).
174 Pillay para 40.
175 Pillay para 70.
176 Walker para 32.
177 Jordan para 59.
178 (EC03/2016) [2018] ZAWCHC 181; 2019 (4) SA 82 (WCC) (14 December 2018).
179 Social Justice Coalition para 41.
180 Social Justice Coalition para 65.
181 Social Justice Coalition para 61.
182 Social Justice Coalition para 63.
183 S 13 of PEPUDA, which reads as follows:
1 If the complainant makes out a prima facie case of discrimination (a) the
respondent must prove, on the facts before the court, that the discrimination
did not take place as alleged: or (b) the respondent must prove that the conduct
is not based on one or more of the prohibited grounds.
2 If the discrimination did take place (a) on a ground in paragraph (a) of the
definition of ‘prohibited grounds’. then it is unfair, unless the respondent
proves that the discrimination is fair; (b) on a ground in paragraph (b) of the
definition of ‘prohibited grounds’, then it is unfair (i) if one or more of the
conditions set out in paragraph (b) of the definition of ‘prohibited grounds’ is
established; and (ii) unless the respondent proves that the discrimination is
fair.
184 S 14(2)(b) of PEPUDA.
185 This will constitute indirect discrimination as such a rule will disproportionately exclude
women from employment as security guards because far more men than women are taller
than 1,8 metres.
186 S 14(2)(a) of PEPUDA.
187 Pillay para 69.
188 (CCT 51/06) [2007] ZACC 21; 2008 (1) SA 474 (CC); 2008 (2) BCLR 99 (CC) (5 October 2007).
189 Pillay para 73.
190 Pillay para 73.
191 Pillay para 75.
192 Pillay para 76.
193 Pillay para 77.
194 Pillay para 78.
195 Pillay para 74, quoting from Canadian Supreme Court judgment Eaton v Brant County
Board of Education [1997] 1 SCR 241 para 67.
196 Van Heerden; South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners Association.
197 (58189/2015) [2017] ZAGPPHC 1220 (8 November 2017).
198 Solidariteit Helpende Hand para 75.
199 Albertyn (2018) 414.
200 S 1(a). See also s 36. See also Teddy Bear Clinic para 52.
201 Grootboom para 23.
202 In the case of S v Williams and Others (CCT20/94) [1995] ZACC 6; 1995 (3) SA 632 (CC);
1995 (7) BCLR 861 (CC) (9 June 1995), which concerned corporal punishment, the
Constitutional Court held at para 45 that ‘the fact that the adult is stripped naked [for
purposes of the whipping] merely accentuates the degradation and humiliation. The
whipping of both is, in itself, a severe affront to the dignity as a human being’.
203 Haysom, N ‘Dignity’ in Cheadle, H, Davis, D and Haysom, N (eds) (2002) South African
Constitutional Law: The Bill of Rights 131. For further reading on dignity generally, see
Davis, DM (1999) Equality: The majesty of legoland jurisprudence South African Law
Journal 116:398–414 at 414; Cowen, S (2001) Can dignity guide South Africa’s equality
jurisprudence? South African Journal on Human Rights 17(1):34–58 at 34; Fagan (1998) 220.
204 Masetlha v President of the Republic of South Africa and Another (CCT 01/07) [2007] ZACC
20; 2008 (1) SA 566 (CC); 2008 (1) BCLR 1 (3 October 2007) para 98.
205 See generally the case of Pillay.
206 Woolman, S ‘The widening gyre of dignity’ in Woolman, S and Bishop M (eds) (2008)
Constitutional Conversations 197.
207 Walker para 113.
208 Makwanyane para 28 as per O’Regan J.
209 1 SCR 497 (1999).
210 See Chaskalson, A (2000) The Third Bram Fischer Lecture: Human dignity as a foundational
value of our Constitutional order South African Journal on Human Rights 16(2):193–205.
211 Law v Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration) 1 SCR 497 (1999) para 53.
212 Woolman (2008) 202.
213 See Daniels v Scribante and Another (CCT50/16) [2017] ZACC 13; 2017 (4) SA 341 (CC);
2017 (8) BCLR 949 (CC) (11 May 2017) para 33 where the Constitutional Court explained
how people’s ability to make meaningful choices can be limited indirectly by rules or
policies. The Court explained that denying an occupier on a farm the right to make
improvements to his or her dwelling implicates the right to dignity because —‘[i]f you deny
an occupier the right to make improvements to the dwelling, you take away its habitability.
And if you take away habitability, that may lead to her or his departure. That in turn may
take away the very essence of an occupier’s way of life. Most aspects of people’s lives are
often ordered around where they live.’
214 (CCT5/95) [1995] ZACC 13; 1996 (1) SA 984 (CC); 1996 (1) BCLR 1 (6 December 1995) para
49. See also Cameron, E ‘Dignity and disgrace: Moral citizenship and constitutional
protection’ in McCrudden, C (ed) (2012) Understanding Human Dignity 476.
215 Freedom of Religion South Africa para 45.
216 Dawood para 35.
217 Grootboom para 34.
218 (CCT8/02) [2002] ZACC 15; 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC); 2002 (10) BCLR 1033 (CC) (5 July 2002)
para 28. See also Occupiers of 51 Olivia Road, Berea Township and 197 Main Street
Johannesburg v City of Johannesburg and Others (24/07) [2008] ZACC 1; 2008 (3) SA 208
(CC); 2008 (5) BCLR 475 (CC) (19 February 2008) para 10, where the Constitutional Court
held when discussing the interpretation of social and economic rights:
It is fundamental to an evaluation of the reasonableness of State action that account
be taken of the inherent dignity of human beings. The Constitution will be worth
infinitely less than its paper if the reasonableness of State action concerned with
housing is determined without regard to the fundamental constitutional value of
human dignity. Section 26, read in the context of the Bill of Rights as a whole, must
mean that the respondents have a right to reasonable action by the State in all
circumstances and with particular regard to human dignity. In short, I emphasise
that human beings are required to be treated as human beings. This is the backdrop
against which the conduct of the [State] must be seen.
219 Liebenberg, S (2005) The value of human dignity in interpreting socio-economic rights
South African Journal on Human Rights 21(1):1–31.
220 Liebenberg (2005) 5.
221 Dawood para 35.
222 Dawood para 35.
223 Dawood para 36.
224 Dawood para 28. See also Dladla and Another v City of Johannesburg and Others
(CCT124/16) [2017] ZACC 42; 2018 (2) SA 327 (CC); 2018 (2) BCLR 119 (CC) (1 December
2017) para 49.
225 Dawood para 37.
226 Dladla para 49.
227 (CCT124/16) [2017] ZACC 42; 2018 (2) SA 327 (CC); 2018 (2) BCLR 119 (CC) (1 December
2017).
228 Dladla para 48.
229 Dladla.
230 Dladla paras 48 and 50.
231 Freedom of Religion South Africa.
232 S 12(1)(c) of the Constitution which reads: ‘(1) Everyone has the right to freedom and
security of the person, which includes the right … (c) to be free from all forms of violence
from either public or private sources.’
233 Freedom of Religion South Africa para 46.
234 S v M [2007] ZACC 18; 2008 (3) SA 232 (CC); 2007 (12) BCLR 1312 (CC) (26 September 2007)
paras 18–9.
235 Freedom of Religion South Africa para 46.
236 Freedom of Religion South Africa para 47.
237 (CCT11/98) [1998] ZACC 15; 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC); 1998 (12) BCLR 1517 (CC) (9 October
1998).
238 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality para 28.
239 Fourie para 71.
240 (CCT 12/13) [2013] ZACC 35; 2013 (12) BCLR 1429 (CC) (3 October 2013).
241 Act 32 of 2007.
242 S 56(2)(b) of the Sexual Offences and Related Matters Amendment Act.
243 Teddy Bear Clinic para 55.
244 (CCT35/99) [2000] ZACC 8; 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC); 2000 (8) BCLR 837 (CC) (7 June 2000).
245 See also Freedom of Religion South Africa; Daniels v Scribante and Another (CCT50/16)
[2017] ZACC 13; 2017 (4) SA 341 (CC); 2017 (8) BCLR 949 (CC) (11 May 2017).
246 Khumalo and Others v Holomisa (CCT53/01) [2002] ZACC 12; 2002 (5) SA 401 (CC); 2002
(8) BCLR 771 (CC) para 27; Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development and Others v
Prince (Clarke and Others Intervening); National Director of Public Prosecutions and Others
v Rubin; National Director of Public Prosecutions and Others v Acton (CCT108/17) [2018]
ZACC 30; 2018 (6) SA 393 (CC); 2018 (10) BCLR 1220 (CC) (18 September 2018).
247 (CCT26/97) [1998] ZACC 6; 1998 (3) SA 785 (CC); 1998 (7) BCLR 779 (28 May 1998) paras
26–7. See also Malachi v Cape Dance Academy International (Pty) Ltd (CCT 05/10) [2010]
ZACC 13; 2010 (6) SA 1 (CC); 2010 (11) BCLR 1116 (CC) (24 August 2010) para 33.
248 Act 44 of 1950.
249 Act 37 of 1963.
250 Act 83 of 1967.
251 Act 74 of 1982.
252 The re-opened inquest into the death of Ahmed Essop Timol (IQ01/2017) [2017] ZAGPPHC
652 (12 October 2017) para 39.
253 Ahmed Essop Timol para 39.
254 Ahmed Essop Timol para 39.
255 Ahmed Essop Timol para 43.
256 Ahmed Essop Timol para 45.
257 Ahmed Essop Timol para 46.
258 (CCT5/95) [1995] ZACC 13; 1996 (1) SA 984 (CC); 1996 (1) BCLR 1 (6 December 1995).
259 Act 61 of 1973.
260 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, Act 200 of 1993.
261 Ahmed Essop Timol para 46.
262 Ferreira para 52.
263 Ferreira para 54.
264 Ferreira para 57.
265 Ferreira para 184.
266 Ferreira para 184.
267 (1905) 198 US 4.
268 Ferreira para 182.
269 (CCT23/95) [1996] ZACC 2; 1996 (2) SA 751 (CC); 1996 (4) BCLR 449 (CC) (27 March 1996).
270 Davis, DM ‘Freedom and Security of the Person’ in Cheadle, H and Davis, DM (eds) (2005)
South African Constitutional Law: The Bill of Rights 7–3.
271 Bernstein para 150.
272 See Bernstein para 159; Sibiya and Others v Director of Public Prosecutions: Johannesburg
High Court and Others (CCT45/04) [2005] ZACC 6; 2005 (5) SA 315 (CC); 2005 (8) BCLR 812
(CC); (25 May 2005) para 31; Zealand v Minister for Justice and Constitutional Development
and Another (CCT54/07) [2008] ZACC 3; 2008 (4) SA 458 (CC); 2008 (6) BCLR 601 (CC) (11
March 2008) para 33; Malachi para 25; and De Vos N.O. and Others v Minister of Justice and
Constitutional Development and Others (CCT 150/14) [2015] ZACC 21; 2015 (2) SACR 217
(CC); 2015 (9) BCLR 1026 (CC) (26 June 2015).
273 (CCT26/97) [1998] ZACC 6; 1998 (3) SA 785 (CC); 1998 (7) BCLR 779 (CC) (28 May 1998).
274 Act 24 of 1936.
275 De Lange para 22.
276 De Lange para 23.
277 De Lange para 30.
278 De Lange para 36.
279 De Lange para 24.
280 De Lange para 57.
281 De Lange para 65.
282 See Zealand and Malachi.
283 Ferreira and Bernstein.
284 (CCT 38/10) [2010] ZACC 25; 2011(1) SA 400 (CC); 2011 (2) BCLR 150 (CC) (25 November
2010).
285 Law Society of South Africa para 57.
286 Article 5(b) of the Convention provides that ‘[i]n compliance with the fundamental
obligations laid down in Article 2 of this Convention, States Parties undertake to prohibit
and to eliminate racial discrimination in all its forms and to guarantee the right of
everyone, without distinction as to race, colour, or national or ethnic origin, to equality
before the law, notably in the enjoyment of the following rights: … (b) The right to security
of person and protection by the State against violence or bodily harm, whether inflicted by
government officials or by any individual group or institutions’.
287 Law Society of South Africa para 59.
288 Law Society of South Africa paras 61–3.
289 Law Society of South Africa para 63.
290 S v Baloyi (Minister of Justice Intervening) (CCT29/99) [1999] ZACC 19; 2000 (2) SA 425
(CC); 2000 (1) BCLR 86 (CC) (3 December 1999).
291 Rail Commuters Action Group v Transnet Ltd t/a Metrorail (CCT 56/03) [2004] ZACC 20;
2005 (2) SA 359 (CC); 2005 (4) BCLR 301 (CC) (26 November 2004).
292 Freedom of Religion South Africa v Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development
(CCT320/17) [2019] ZACC 34; 2020 (1) SA 1 (CC); 2019 (11) BCLR 1321 (CC) (18 September
2019).
293 (CCT320/17) [2019] ZACC 34; 2020 (1) SA 1 (CC); 2019 (11) BCLR 1321 (CC) (18 September
2019).
294 Freedom of Religion South Africa para 38.
295 Freedom of Religion South Africa para 40.
296 Freedom of Religion South Africa para 42.
297 Freedom of Religion South Africa para 43.
298 Freedom of Religion South Africa para 44.
299 Freedom of Religion South Africa para 69.
300 (CCT 1/01) [2001] ZACC 16; 2001 (3) SA 382 (CC); 2001 (5) BCLR 423 (CC) (5 April 2001).
See also S v Williams (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3; 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC); 1995 (6) BCLR 665
(CC) (6 June 1995) para 20 and S v Niemand (CCT 28/00) [2001] ZACC 11; 2002 (1) SA 21
(CC); 2002 (3) BCLR 219 (8 October 2001) para 22.
301 Dodo para 35.
302 Dodo.
303 Dodo para 37.
304 Dodo para 38.
305 Dodo para 38.
306 Dodo para 39.
307 S v Niemand (CCT 28/00) [2001] ZACC 11; 2002 (1) SA 21 (CC); 2002 (3) BCLR 219 (CC) (8
October 2001).
308 Act 51 of 1977.
309 Act 8 of 1959.
310 S v Niemand para 25.
311 S v Williams.
312 Some LLB students and young lawyers who discuss Constitutional Court judgments on
Twitter have even jokingly started referring to themselves as ‘S v Makwanyane Twitter’, in
reference to the celebrated case. See @TanveerJeewa available at
https://twitter.com/TanveerJeewa/status/1268436716760817664?s=20 and
@siphosihlembuli available at
https://twitter.com/siphosihlembuli/status/1264461815024664576?s=20.
313 S v Makwanyane para 26.
314 S v Makwanyane para 51.
315 S v Makwanyane para 54.
316 S v Makwanyane para 54.
317 See Murphy, TF (2019) Adolescents and Body Modification for Gender Identity Expression
Medical Law Review 27(4):623–39.
318 See Brandt, AM (1978) Racism and Research: The Case of the Tuskegee Syphilis Study The
Hastings Center Report 8(6):21–9.
319 Jenkins, D, and Johnston, LB (2004) Unethical Treatment of Gay and Lesbian People with
Conversion Therapy Families in Society 85(4):557–61.
320 Patella-Rey, PJ (2018) Beyond privacy: Bodily integrity as an alternative framework for
understanding non-consensual pornography Information Communication & Society
21(5):786–91 at 789.
321 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality para 29. In this case the Constitutional
Court, considering the prohibition on same-sex sodomy, accepted that relying on the right
to privacy alone would be inadequate, but held that it could be invoked along with other
rights such as the right against unfair discrimination.
322 See also Thebus and Another v S (CCT36/02) [2003] ZACC 12; 2003 (6) SA 505 (CC); 2003
(10) BCLR 1100 (CC) (28 August 2003) para 39; De Lange para 22; Nel v Le Roux NO
(CCT30/95) [1996] ZACC 6; 1996 (3) SA 562 (CC); 1996 (4) BCLR 592 (CC) (4 April 1996)
para 12; Bernstein para 145.
323 AB and Another v Minister of Social Development (CCT155/15) [2016] ZACC 43; 2017 (3) SA
570 (CC); 2017 (3) BCLR 267 (CC) (29 November 2016).
324 AB para 66.
325 AB para 67.
326 AB para 310.
327 AB para 69.
328 See Bishop, M and Woolman, S ‘Freedom and Security of the Person’ in Woolman, S and
Bishop, M (eds) (2006) Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed original service chap 40 at
77.
329 Bishop and Woolman (2006) chap 40 at 77.
330 Shirin Heidari (2015) Sexual rights and bodily integrity as human rights Reproductive
Health Matters 23:46, 1–6 at 3
331 Michele O’ Sullivan ‘Reproductive Rights’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2006)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed original service chap chap 37 at 17.
332 S v Baloyi 2000 (2) SA 425 (CC), 2000 (1) BCLR 86 (CC) para 11. See also Sonderup v
Tondelli 2001 (1) SA 1171 (CC), 2001 (12) BCLR 152 (CC) para 34.
333 Albertyn, C (2015) Claiming and defending abortion rights in South Africa Revista Direito
GV 11(2):429–54 at 431.
334 Albertyn (2015) 432.
335 Act 92 of 1996.
336 S 2(1) of the Choice on Termination of Pregnancy Act.
337 Christian Lawyers Association of SA v Minister of Health 1998 (11) BCLR 1434 (T), 1998 (4)
SA 1113 (T) (Christian Lawyers I) and Christian Lawyers Association v Minister of Health
2005 (1) SA 509 (T) (Christian Lawyers II).
338 Christian Lawyers II 526H–7A.
339 AB para 312.
340 AB para 313.
341 Act 23 of 1957, later renamed the Sexual Offences Act.
342 Act 55 of 1949.
343 See http://www.capetownmagazine.com/events/statements-after-an-arrest-under-the-
immorality-act/11_37_54253.
344 Currie and De Waal (2013) 294.
345 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice para 32.
346 Prince para 45.
347 Bernstein para 73; Prince para 44.
348 Bernstein para 75.
349 Bernstein para 75.
350 This is why participants in a reality television show such as Big Brother – in which
contestants are filmed 24 hours a day in a secluded house – would not be able to claim that
their right to privacy had been infringed.
351 Bernstein para 67.
352 Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic Offences and Others v Hyundai Motor
Distributors (Pty) Ltd and Others In re: Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd and Others v
Smit NO and Others (CCT1/00) [2000] ZACC 12; 2001 (1) SA 545 (CC); 2000 (10) BCLR 1079
(CC) (25 August 2000) para 18.
353 Currie and De Waal (2013) 30.
354 Jordan para 80.
355 Jordan para 29.
356 (CCT1/00) [2000] ZACC 12; 2001 (1) SA 545 (CC); 2000 (10) BCLR 1079 (CC). (25 August
2000).
357 Hyundai Motor Distributors para 18.
358 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice para 32.
359 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice para 32.
360 Cameron, E (1993) Sexual orientation and the Constitution: A test case for human rights
South African Law Journal 110(3):450 at 461–2.
361 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice para 30.
362 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice para 32.
363 Teddy Bear Clinic para 60.
364 Teddy Bear Clinic para 60.
365 (CCT108/17) [2018] ZACC 30; 2018 (6) SA 393 (CC); 2018 (10) BCLR 1220 (CC) (18
September 2018).
366 Prince para 58.
367 Prince para 94.
368 Prince paras 78–2.
369 Prince para 100.
370 Prince para 85.
371 Prince para 88.
DIVERSITY RIGHTS
14.1 Introduction
Summary
14.1 Introduction
South Africa is a heterogeneous society in which individuals with
diverse religious affiliations, cultural beliefs and practices, and
languages must co-exist. Given the heterogeneous nature of South
Africa, it is important for the law to respect and protect the beliefs,
practices and languages of the diverse groups that make up South
Africa’s population. This is because in a society in which diversity is not
respected or protected, the law will normally reflect the beliefs,
practices and languages of the majority or dominant group, and will
marginalise the beliefs, practices and languages of minority or
subordinate groups. When the beliefs, practices and languages of
minority or subordinate groups are marginalised, this not only
diminishes the constitutional goal of establishing a diverse society, but
may also cause harm to members of a marginalised group. This is
especially so in those cases where the group in question is
economically, politically or socially vulnerable.
This state of affairs could arise, for example, when the law recognises
and endorses the view that homosexuality is wrong and that gay men
and lesbians do not deserve to be treated with equal concern and
respect. This would be extremely harmful to gay men and lesbians who
would be marginalised and discriminated against and might even face
threats to their physical well-being. Similarly, if the law recognises and
endorses the view that certain cultural practices, such as male
circumcision, were harmful to all boys, the concomitant ban on male
circumcision would limit the rights of those sections of society whose
cultural beliefs demand that all young men should undergo
circumcision. Again, if the law recognises and endorses the view that
English should be the only medium of communication in South Africa,
this would marginalise many South Africans whose mother tongue is
not English.
While it is important to respect the beliefs, practices and languages
of diverse groups, it is also important to recognise that some beliefs,
practices and languages have the potential to marginalise, exclude or
oppress other people and that they should be prohibited from doing so.
When it comes to determining whether the harmful beliefs, practices
and languages of a specific group should be prohibited, the courts must
balance the interests of the harm-causing group with the interests of
others in society. In those cases in which the interests of others in
society outweigh the interests of the harm-causing group, then the
associational rights of the harm-causing group will have to be limited.
Striking the correct balance is not always easy. Sometimes the
interests of some groups have to yield to the interests of other groups. It
is impossible for the law to accommodate all the diverse beliefs,
practices and attitudes of all people living in South Africa in an absolute
manner while also protecting individuals against discrimination,
marginalisation and exclusion.
In this chapter we discuss some of the rights where the problem of
accommodating diversity arises most acutely. These rights include the
right to freedom of association, the right to freedom of religion, the
rights of cultural and religious communities, and language rights. It is
impossible to do so without keeping in mind the scope and content of
the rights to equality, human dignity and privacy discussed in Chapter
13 of this book. This is because the cultural and religious beliefs and
practices of some groups are often in direct or indirect conflict with the
demands not to discriminate unfairly against others and to respect the
human dignity of all. Although we discuss the scope and content of the
various rights in detail, we do so against the background of the broader
question regarding the manner in which the law can respect and protect
cultural and religious diversity without negating the rights of other
groups who do not share the same beliefs and who do not engage in the
same practices.
14.2 Freedom of association
14.2.1 Introduction
Section 18 of the Constitution provides that ‘[e]veryone has the right to
freedom of association’. Freedom of association is often said to be a
foundational right for any vibrant constitutional democracy. A right to
associate freely with others ‘makes participatory politics meaningful
and genuinely representative politics possible’.1 This right also allows
individuals to make choices about how they want to arrange their lives
and about their identities as people in relationships with others in a
given society, thus advancing respect for and protecting diversity.2 The
right to freedom of association guarantees a degree of autonomy that
allows individuals to make both overtly political and more intimate
choices about who to associate with. These are choices that may affect
their lives and their identities by giving them expression in community
with others.
The fact that the right to freedom of association allows individuals to
make both overtly political and more intimate choices about who to
associate with was highlighted by the Constitutional Court in New
Nation Movement NPC and Others v President of the Republic of South
Africa and Others.3 In this case, the Court held that individuals associate
with one another in both large and small groups. Individuals typically
associate in large groups in order to achieve less individualised goals
such as political and religious objectives4 and in small groups in order
to achieve more individualised goals such as ‘succour, solace,
emotional support and sharing joy, pain and confidences’.5 Although
both forms of association are protected by the right to freedom of
association, the Court held further, it will usually be more difficult to
justify state interferences with small and intimate associations between
partners, friends and families than to justify state interferences with
large and non-intimate associations such as political parties.6
At the heart of the right to freedom of association lies the
recognition of the communal nature of people7 and the need for people
to exercise some of their rights as individuals ‘in association with others
of like disposition’.8 It is based on an understanding ‘that generally we
are stronger when we have the support of others’.9 This is because we
can develop our full potential only by relating to other people, either on
an individual or collective basis. In addition, people can often only
engage in meaningful political action in association with others. In
other words, the right to freedom of association ‘protects the rights of
collective self-determination’.10 In MEC for Education: Kwazulu-Natal
and Others v Pillay, the Constitutional Court linked this notion with the
concept of ubuntu, stating:
The notion that ‘we are not islands unto ourselves’ is central to the
understanding of the individual in African thought. It is often expressed in the
phrase umuntu ngumuntu ngabantu which emphasises ‘communality and the
inter-dependence of the members of a community’ and that every individual is
an extension of others. According to Gyekye, ‘an individual human person
cannot develop and achieve the fullness of his/her potential without the
concrete act of relating to other individual persons’. This thinking emphasises
the importance of community to individual identity and hence to human
dignity. Dignity and identity are inseparably linked as one’s sense of self-worth
is defined by one’s identity. Cultural identity is one of the most important parts
of a person’s identity precisely because it flows from belonging to a community
and not from personal choice or achievement. And belonging involves more
than simple association; it includes participation and expression of the
community’s practices and traditions.11
14.2.3.1 Equality
Certain associations may be required to ‘open themselves up to a wider
potential membership because they control access to important social
goods’.48 In the South African context, this requirement features
prominently in the Promotion of Equality and Prevention of Unfair
Discrimination Act (PEPUDA).49 PEPUDA promotes the right to equality
among private bodies and individuals and thus limits the extent to
which private institutions and organisations may determine and
manage their own membership policies and internal affairs. Given that
control over an organisation’s membership policies and internal affairs
are often critical to its identity, PEPUDA could, in effect, force a change
in these policies. It thus represents a severe limitation on the general
right to freedom of association.50
Section 6 of PEPUDA states in this respect that ‘[n]either the State
nor any person may unfairly discriminate against any person’. As we
have seen in chapter 13, when a private individual or organisation
discriminates against an individual by, for example, excluding that
person from membership of the organisation on the basis of his or her
race, gender or sexual orientation, the onus is on the party who
discriminated to prove that the discrimination is not unfair. Sections
14(2) and (3) of PEPUDA set out the factors a court must take into
account when determining whether the respondent has proven the
discrimination to be fair. These factors are:
• the context
• whether the discrimination reasonably and justifiably differentiates
between persons according to objectively determinable criteria
intrinsic to the activity concerned
• whether the discrimination impairs or is likely to impair human
dignity
• the impact or likely impact of the discrimination on the complainant
• the position of the complainant in society and whether he or she
suffers from patterns of disadvantage or belongs to a group that
suffers from such patterns of disadvantage
• the nature and extent of the discrimination
• whether the discrimination is systemic in nature
• whether the discrimination has a legitimate purpose
• whether and to what extent the discrimination achieves its purpose
• whether there are less restrictive and less disadvantageous means to
achieve the purpose
• whether and to what extent the respondent has taken such steps as
are reasonable in the circumstances to address the disadvantage
which arises from or is related to one or more of the prohibited
grounds or to accommodate diversity.
14.2.3.2 Democracy
The state may also interfere in the right to freedom of association in
order to further the goals of democracy. This may require organisations
in certain contexts to structure their internal affairs in a more
democratic and egalitarian fashion.52 In each case the question is to
what extent the state’s interest in the integrity of a democratic process
and in the maintenance and protection of a democratic society justifies
the limitation on the association’s right to order its affairs as it wishes
and to pursue the goals it was set up to pursue. The freedom of political
parties to arrange their internal affairs as they wish and to pursue the
ends they were set up to pursue is acutely affected by the need to
safeguard democracy. This is less evident if we start from the premise
that political parties and other associations are largely private entities
created to pursue private ends.53 However, if we start from the premise
that political parties and other associations are essential for a
functioning representative democracy, a more onerous burden will fall
on political parties to be structured along democratic lines and not to
pursue undemocratic ends.
In Germany, for example, the German Constitutional Court banned
the Socialist Reich Party (SRP) in 1952 and the Communist Party of
Germany (KPD) in 1956. According to article 21(2) of the German Basic
Law, parties which, by reason of their aims or the behaviour of their
members, seek to impair or destroy the free democratic order or to
endanger the existence of the Federal Republic of Germany are
unconstitutional.54 The German Parliament, therefore, may pass
legislation that requires political organisations to structure themselves
in a democratic and egalitarian way.
In the United States, in Buckley v Valeo,55 the US Supreme Court
confirmed the constitutionality of laws requiring compulsory disclosure
of the source of campaign contributions over $10 and of political
contributions over $100 per annum. The applicants in this case argued
that the laws violated the associational rights of minor parties and small
contributors. The Court dismissed this argument. In arriving at its
decision, the Court accepted that the associational rights were
infringed, but went on to find that this infringement was outweighed by
countervailing state interests.56 The societal interests included the need
to help the electorate evaluate the candidates standing for office by
disclosing the identity of their supporters, the need to avoid corruption
and the appearance of corruption, and the need to gather data required
to enforce the contribution limits set down in other laws.57
In Institute for Democracy in South Africa and Others v African
National Congress and Others,58 the Cape Town High Court adopted a
different approach. In this case, the Institute for Democracy in South
Africa (IDASA) brought an application in terms of the Promotion of
Access to Information Act (PAIA)59 against all the major political parties
for access to their donation records regarding the date of donation, the
name of the donor, the amount or value of the donation and the
conditions, if any, on which the donation was made or received. In the
main, the African National Congress (ANC) resisted the application on
the basis that there should be comprehensive legislation on this issue as
opposed to having to disclose information on an ad hoc basis.
The Court was of the opinion that the political parties for the
purposes of this application were to be regarded as private bodies. In
terms of the PAIA, an applicant had to demonstrate that they required
the information from the private body for the exercise or protection of
any rights.60 One of the arguments made by the applicants was that they
required the records to assist citizens to make more accurate political
choices and to choose between the various parties. Disclosure of
financial benefactors would place citizens in a better position to make
these decisions. The Court was of the view that this did not adequately
demonstrate ‘how the donation records would assist them in exercising
or protecting any of the rights on which they rely or why, in the absence
of these donation records, they are unable to exercise those rights’.61 It
went on to hold:
On the face of it, s 19(1) prevents any restrictions being imposed on a citizen’s
right of making political choices, such as forming a political party,
participating in the activities of and recruiting members for a party, and
campaigning for a political cause. Similarly, the right to ‘free, fair and regular
elections’ enshrined in s 19(2) does not impose a duty on political parties to
disclose funding sources, nor does it afford citizens a right to gain access to
such records. The emphasis in s 19(2) lies upon the elections and the nature of
the electoral process and not so much upon the persons or parties
participating in those elections.62
Not admitting white journalists on the basis of their race to the Imbizo and
excluding them from membership of the FBJ on the same basis is clearly
invasive of their right to dignity. The issue is whether the benefits that accrue to
the organisation justifies [sic] this intrusion …
… , the Supreme Court of Appeal in Midi Television (Pty) Limited t/a e-tv v
Director of Public Prosecutions83 had to reconcile and balance the freedom of
expression and the right to a fair trial. The following was stated:
Thus the submission by the appellant that it can adopt a racially exclusive
membership policy provided that it demonstrates a rational connection
between its discriminatory policy and the association’s ends is inconsistent
with comments made in the VA report and with the dicta from Midi Television
quoted above. The FBJ has the right to form an association to uplift black
journalists and exclude persons whose objectives are inimical to its founding
values. FBJ used race as the criterion and formed the view that all white
journalists should be excluded from their organisation. No argument has been
made as to why the less intrusive admission policy which required a full
commitment to the values and goals of the organisation would not have been
sufficient to protect its distinct ‘voice’ and identity. The imprecise and blunt
instrument of racial exclusivity was relied upon notwithstanding the egregious
impact of exclusions upon people who may have supported the broader
objectives of the organisation. There is nothing before us which leads us to
conclude that the racially exclusive membership policies and practices bring a
legitimate benefit to the FBJ which justifies the infringement of the right to
dignity of the persons excluded on the basis of race. In the circumstances, we
find that the exclusion of the white journalists both from the Imbizo and from
membership of the FBJ is not justified in terms of section 36 of the
Constitution.85
The Appeal Committee of the SAHRC thus found against the FBJ. As the
extracts set out above illustrate, it is necessary to determine what
benefit accrues as a consequence of the exclusion. The benefit must
then be weighed against the cost occasioned by such exclusion. The
courts will sanction the exclusion if the benefit outweighs the cost of the
exclusion and is a reasonable and proportionate response.
When can the right to freedom of association
be used to justifiably exclude others from
associating with the organisation?
This question is a source of great jurisprudential and
moral anxiety, partly because the ability to associate
holds potential financial and social benefits. Excluding
some from these benefits on the basis of personal
attributes or characteristics may therefore harm those
who are excluded.
White suggests certain rules to deal with this
difficult question.86 The first rule or guideline White
suggests is that an exclusionary rule is presumptively
legitimate if it is purpose-protecting. In other words, if an
exclusionary rule is aimed at protecting the very
purpose for which the association was created, it will
be presumed to be legitimate.87
However, White suggests a second rule, namely
that if an exclusionary rule is opportunity-depriving, the
rule must presumptively be viewed as not being
legitimate. In other words, if by excluding individuals
from the association they are potentially deprived of
opportunities, it will be difficult to justify the
exclusion.88
A third rule is that the presumption of legitimate
exclusion is especially strong if the rule is integrity-
protecting. In other words, where the formation of an
association is particularly important to allow an
individual to exercise his or her liberties of conscience
or expression, then there will be a strong assumption
that the exclusionary rule that safeguards this
associational space should be held as being
legitimate.89
Of course, it will be clear that these three rules
could easily be in tension with one another. An
exclusionary rule that is purpose-protecting as well as
integrity-protecting can be so drastically opportunity-
depriving that it would not be held to be valid. For
example, a rule that allows a religious school to
exclude female learners on the grounds that male and
female learners must be taught separately may be
both purpose-protecting and integrity-protecting. But
where that school offers a high-quality education and
provides its graduates with opportunities in life that are
not easily provided to others in the same community,
the rule may also be opportunity-depriving. This is
because female learners will be deprived in a drastic
manner of some of the opportunities that are available
to male learners. Consequently, it is far from clear
whether such a rule conforms with the right to freedom
of association.
14.3.1 Introduction
Freedom of religion and conscience – the freedom to hold views about
religious and other moral issues and the freedom to practise those
beliefs – goes to the heart of what it means to be human in a modern
democracy. In the open and democratic society contemplated by the
Constitution, both the religious beliefs held by the great majority of
South Africans as well as the beliefs of non-believers and minority faiths
must be fully respected.90 As the Constitutional Court pointed out in
Minister of Home Affairs and Another v Fourie and Another:
For many believers, their relationship with God or creation is central to all their
activities. It concerns their capacity to relate in an intensely meaningful
fashion to their sense of themselves, their community and their universe. For
millions in all walks of life, religion provides support and nurture and a
framework for individual and social stability and growth. Religious belief has
the capacity to awaken concepts of self-worth and human dignity which form
the cornerstone of human rights. Such belief affects the believer’s view of
society and founds a distinction between right and wrong. It expresses itself in
the affirmation and continuity of powerful traditions that frequently have an
ancient character transcending historical epochs and national boundaries. For
believers, then, what is at stake is not merely a question of convenience or
comfort, but an intensely held sense about what constitutes the good and
proper life and their place in creation.91
In short, all the justices of the Constitutional Court agreed that the right
to freedom of religion is protected if there is an ‘absence of coercion or
constraint’ on a particular religious belief or practice.123 Freedom of
religion will ‘be impaired by measures that force people to act or refrain
from acting in a manner contrary to their religious [and, we assume,
other non-religious] beliefs’.124 Subsequent Constitutional Court
judgments essentially endorsed this view of the scope of the right to
freedom of religion.125 The Court also noted that the right to freedom of
religion would not only be infringed by acts of direct coercion. Actions
by the state could also run the risk of indirectly coercing individuals into
certain religious beliefs and practices. This was a particular danger
when the power, prestige and financial support of government were
placed behind a particular religious belief as it would place indirect
coercive pressure on religious minorities to conform to the prevailing
officially approved religion.126
A far more difficult question that arose in the Lawrence case was
whether the state was required to treat all religions in a fair and
equitable manner. It is on this issue that the judges of the
Constitutional Court differed. Chaskalson P, writing for four justices of
the Constitutional Court, rejected the notion that the right to freedom of
religion required the state to act in an even-handed or equitable
manner towards all religions.127 O’Regan J, writing for three justices of
the Constitutional Court, however, argued that the right to freedom of
religion required more than the absence of direct or indirect coercion to
be fully and effectively protected.128 This additional requirement of
fairness or equity, argued O’Regan J, reflected ‘an important component
of the conception of freedom of religion contained in our
Constitution’.129 She stated:
Our society possesses a rich and diverse range of religions. Although the state
is permitted to allow religious observances, it is not permitted to act
inequitably. In determining what is meant by inequity in this context, it must
be remembered that the question of voluntary participation is a consideration
separately identified in section 14(2) [now section 15(2)]. The requirement of
equity must therefore be something in addition to the requirement of
voluntariness. It seems to me that, at the least, the requirement of equity
demands the state act even-handedly in relation to different religions.130
This did not mean complete neutrality but did require that observances
should not favour one religion over another.131 This judgment went on to
state that the purpose of the right was a rejection of past practices when
Christianity was deemed to be the favoured religion.132 Endorsement by
the state of any one religion would not be permitted as it would result in
indirect coercion and would amount to a threat to those wishing to
exercise other religious beliefs.133 O’Regan J concluded by holding that it
is not sufficient that there is no direct coercion of religious beliefs. In
addition, there had to be no inequitable or unfair preference of one
religion over others.134
In a separate judgment, Sachs J appeared to agree with the approach
adopted by O’Regan J when he held that the right to religious freedom
does not only prohibit the state from forcing people to act or refrain
from acting in a manner contrary to their religious beliefs, but also from
endorsing or favouring one particular faith, for example Christianity,
over all others:
By endorsing a particular faith as a direct and sectarian source of values for
legislation binding on the whole nation, [the State] exceeds the competence
granted to it by the Constitution. Even if there is no compulsory requirement to
observe or not to observe a particular religious practice, the effect is to divide
the nation into insiders who belong, and outsiders who are tolerated. This is
impermissible in the multi-faith, heterodox society contemplated by our
Constitution.135
Apart from the points set out above, it is also important to note that
religious activities often take place in a communal context. In
recognition of this fact, section 31 of the Constitution adds to the scope
and content of the right to freedom of religion. Section 31 of the
Constitution deals with the right of religious communities to practise
their religion together with other members of their community. The
right can be optimally exercised only if people of similar beliefs or faiths
can assemble, jointly express their beliefs, advance their religion and
regulate their affairs. The right to religious freedom, therefore, also
includes the right to interact with fellow believers. This means an
individual religious denomination must have the right – to the extent
that this does not infringe other rights – to decide for itself on the rules
for membership as well as the rules about the behaviour of the
members of the religious denomination. A fuller discussion of the
association rights contained in section 31 follows later in the chapter.
In the context of section 15, it is unnecessary to focus on whether a
specific belief is religious in nature or not as the section protects not
only the right to freedom of religion but also the right to freedom of
conscience, thought, belief and opinion. Nevertheless, it has been
suggested that to qualify as a ‘religious belief system’ a religion should
have some of the following features: ‘belief in a supreme being, belief in
transcendent reality, a moral code, a world view accounting for people’s
role in the universe, sacred rituals, worship and prayers, a sacred text,
and membership in a social organisation’.146
In the US context, it was held that the test should not be whether the
belief is objectively reasonable, but rather whether it forms part of the
practices and beliefs of that religion and whether persons belonging to
that religion genuinely and sincerely embrace the practice. Religious
beliefs are by their very nature subjective and courts will not easily
conclude that a specific belief is not religious in nature or is not
sincerely held. In addition, the courts are generally reluctant to make
determinations as to whether the practice being restricted is central or
foundational to the religious beliefs. It is not the function of the court to
interpret religious texts or dogma. As O’Connor J, a former justice of the
US Supreme Court, put it:
The dissent offers us the prospect of this court holding that some sincerely held
religious beliefs and practices are not ‘central’ to certain religions, despite the
protestations to the contrary from religious observers who brought the lawsuit.
In other words, the dissent’s approach would require us to rule that some
religious adherents misunderstand their own religious beliefs. We think that
such an approach cannot be squared with the Constitution or with our
precedents, and that it would cast the judiciary in a role that we never intended
to play.147
‘We had to apply three times,’ said Gustav Nipe, chairman of the
organisation.
The church, which holds CTRL+C and CTRL+V (shortcuts for copy
and paste) as sacred symbols, does not directly promote illegal
file sharing, focusing instead on the open distribution of
knowledge to all.
Given the fact that the LGBT+ community suffered discrimination in the
pre-constitutional South Africa and still suffers discrimination today,
they are a particularly vulnerable group which would make it more
difficult for a religious organisation to justify discriminating against
them. In this particular case, there were two specific reasons why the
church could not claim that its interest in religious liberty trumped the
interest of LGBT+ people not to be unfairly discriminated against. First,
it was unclear what the doctrine of the church was on this topic as ‘the
Church was split on its interpretation of the Bible pertaining to same-
sex marriages and leadership in the Church based on sexual
orientation’.166 Second, the Church presented no plausible argument
why it was necessary for it to discriminate and had not placed facts
before the Court to do so.167 If the principles applied in the Gaum case
are adopted by other courts, it will become ever more difficult for
religious institutions to justify discriminating against LGBT+ people or
women by invoking their right to freedom of religion.
The minority were of the view that the statute was overbroad and not
carefully tailored to ‘constitute a minimal intrusion upon the right to
freedom of religion’.186 The law, according to the minority, was
unconstitutional as it did not allow for the religious use of cannabis that
was not necessarily harmful and which could be controlled more
effectively.187
The inherent flexibility of the limitation clause allows the courts to
assess whether the law that infringes the right to freedom of religion is
proportionate. As the split decision in Prince demonstrates, even the
judges of the highest court may differ in their determination of what is
reasonable in the circumstances. In essence, the state must identify a
societal objective which the governmental action advances, the
attainment of which justifies the right being infringed. The courts then
ask the additional question of whether the societal objective could
reasonably be achieved by a less intrusive limitation of the right. The
governmental conduct limiting the right will only pass constitutional
muster if the courts are satisfied that the importance of the societal
objective sought to be achieved outweighs the adverse effects of the
limitation on the right to freedom of religion. Ultimately, both the
prohibition on corporal punishment and the prohibition on the use of
dagga except for medicinal reasons were upheld even though both
measures infringed aspects of the right to freedom of religion.
An example of reasonable accommodation
The requirement that various religious beliefs and
practices have to be accommodated in a reasonable
manner can be illustrated with reference to a specific
example. Imagine that Claremont High School in Cape
Town has been besieged by ill-discipline and in some
instances learners have attacked educators. Imagine
further that in a specific incident a grade 12 learner
stabbed an educator who had reprimanded the learner
for being drunk at a sports event hosted by the school.
Now, it would not be surprising if the school, in an
effort to improve the teaching and learning
environment, adopted a code of conduct after
consulting the learners, the parents and the educators.
Such a code could, among others, expressly forbid
learners from bringing to school knives, daggers or
other weapons or instruments that could cause harm
to the learner, other learners or staff at the school.
On the face of it, such a rule would seem to be
eminently reasonable. However, the rule would have a
disproportionate impact on Sikh learners. This is
because according to the Reht Maryada, the official
Sikh Code of Conduct, a Sikh must at all times carry
five items, including a kirpan, on his person. According
to the Reht Maryada, a kirpan is a dagger that
represents the power of truth to cut through untruth. A
Sikh learner, therefore, would be able to argue that the
seemingly neutral code of conduct infringed on his
right to freedom of religion, read with his right not to
be discriminated against on the basis of his religion,
because it would prohibit him from wearing the kirpan
to school. In deciding whether the code should make
an exception for Sikh learners, the court would have to
employ the principle of reasonable accommodation.188
14.3.4 The right not to believe in any God or higher being
As we noted above, section 15 of the Constitution protects both the right
to freedom of religion and the right to freedom of other beliefs and
conscience. As such, it also protects a person’s right not to believe in a
God and not to have to participate in any religious practices such as
prayers and the singing of hymns. In Torcaso v Watkins,189 the US
Supreme Court invalidated a state law which required all public office
holders to declare that they believed in God prior to assuming public
office. In arriving at this decision, the Supreme Court pointed out that
the apart from stating that the government may not establish a religion,
the First Amendment to the US Constitution also states that it may not
prohibit the free exercise of religion. The free exercise clause, the Court
held, prevents the government from either awarding benefits or
imposing burdens based on a person’s religious beliefs or lack of
religious belief.190 Our courts have held that the free exercise clause is
similar to the right to freedom of religion and conscience protected by
section 15 of the South African Constitution. Similar sentiments were
expressed by Sachs J in Lawrence when he held:
South Africa is an open and democratic society with a non-sectarian state that
guarantees freedom of worship; is respectful of and accommodatory towards,
rather than hostile to or walled-off from, religion; acknowledges the multi-faith
and multi-belief nature of the country; does not favour one religious creed or
doctrinal truth above another; accepts the intensely personal nature of
individual conscience and affirms the intrinsically voluntary and non-coerced
character of belief; respects the rights of non-believers; and does not impose
orthodoxies of thought or require conformity of conduct in terms of any
particular world-view.191
The breadth of section 15 signifies that our society must not act
punitively towards non-believers by withholding benefits or imposing
burdens on them because of their non-belief. However, it is probable
that if a non-believer is discriminated against, he or she will rely on the
right not to be unfairly discriminated against on the basis of conscience
and belief rather than the right to freedom of religion, belief and
conscience.
14.3.5 Conducting religious observances at state institutions:
section 15(2) of the Constitution
As we noted above, the South African Constitution – unlike its US
counterpart – does not require a complete separation between the state
and religion. The South African Constitution does allow some
entanglement between the state and religion. Section 15(2) of the
Constitution makes this clear when it states that religious observances
may be conducted at state or state-aided institutions on condition that:
• these observances follow rules made by appropriate public
authorities
• they are conducted on an equitable basis
• attendance at these observances is free and voluntary.
Despite the provisos in sections 30 and 31, these associational rights are
not presumptively inferior and of less weight than the rights to equality,
dignity and other rights.
A ‘constitutionally offensive group practice’ in this context means
any exclusionary policies, rules or forms of conduct adopted or applied
by a cultural, religious or linguistic community and which are not
permitted by the Constitution. The key issue is whether the policies,
rules or conduct of the community are consistent with the Constitution.
In deciding whether these policies, rules or forms of conduct are
permitted, regard must be had to whether the policy, rule or conduct is
reasonable and justifiable. The rights of the individual who is denied
access must be balanced against the purpose that the policy, rule or
conduct seeks to achieve. The policy, rule or conduct must also be
proportionate. In other words, the infringement of the individual right
must be weighed and balanced against the rights of the community.
The impact on the complainant is usually the most important factor
in this exercise. The more egregious the violation is, the less likely it is
that it will be deemed fair. In Lovelace v Canada,242 for example, the
applicant challenged a Canadian federal statute, the Indian Act 1970.
This Act provided that a Canadian Indian woman who married a non-
Indian could not be registered as an Indian. Ms Lovelace married a
non-Indian. As a consequence of the law, she was denied the right to
return to her native home in the Tobique Reservation in Canada. She
argued that the law excluded her from living her life as an Indian. In
addition, it specifically resulted in her losing the cultural benefits of
living in an Indian community and of having emotional ties to her
home, family, friends and neighbours. The United Nations Human
Rights Committee upheld the complaint as the exclusion of Lovelace
from the tribe meant that she was not able to enjoy her cultural rights as
an Indian. This drastic intrusion was not reasonable and necessary to
preserve the identity of the tribe.
Ms Lovelace simply had no other forum or association, other than
the tribal area, within which to exercise and enjoy her cultural rights.
Her exclusion thus meant an eradication of her right to enjoy her
culture. This was impermissible given the fact that article 27 of the
ICCPR protects the right to cultural associations. The cost that she had
to bear was disproportionate and excessive when compared to the
potential benefit that would accrue to the tribe as a consequence of the
law. Section 31 of the Constitution is materially similar and it is likely
that a similar outcome would have been reached through an
application of the limitation clause.
The manner in which the rights of the organisation or community
must be weighed and balanced against the infraction of the individual
rights is also illustrated in the case of Taylor v Kurtstag NO and Others.243
The applicant and his wife had voluntarily submitted to the jurisdiction
of the ad hoc Beth Din (Jewish Ecclesiastical Tribunal) and requested
that it arbitrate on the custody of their children and on the maintenance
to be paid. The applicant did not comply with the findings and was
effectively excommunicated. The applicant sought to set aside the edict
of the Beth Din that effectively excommunicated him from Jewish
society for failing to comply with its decision. He argued that the edict 244
conflicted with his individual rights to religion and to cultural
association. The edict, according to the community, was the only means
available to it to ensure compliance with the rulings of the Beth Din.
The High Court enquired into whether the limitation of the
applicant’s rights could be justified by reference to the associational
rights of the community. The Court concluded that the limitation on the
applicant’s rights was reasonable and justifiable as a failure to enforce
the Beth Din’s rulings would result in the Jewish faith not being able to
protect the integrity of Jewish law.245 The associational rights of the
organisation took precedence over the personal rights of the
individual.246 In reaching its conclusion, the Court assessed the full
extent of the limitation on the rights of the applicant and weighed this
against the associational rights of the organisation.247 Malan J
concluded:
At the core of this dispute is a matter of religious doctrine: in all religions there
are rules entailing consequences if the rules are broken. It does not follow that
a contravention of the rules will invariably lead to the conclusion that, because
the member’s rights of dignity have been infringed, the infringement is
unconstitutional. Were this the position, it would be impossible for voluntary
organisations, particularly religious communities, to require conformity with
particular values and to impose sanctions for the contraventions.248
The Court went on to hold that the purpose of the edict was to punish,
to maintain standards and to encourage the dissenter to return by
complying with the ruling.249 In the circumstances, the Court held that
the community had not acted in a constitutionally offensive manner
and upheld the edict.250
As stated earlier, the courts have to balance the rights of the
individual who has been shut out of the community and the rights of
the community to protect its identity. Where an individual asserts that
his or her constitutional right has been infringed by another private
person or entity and that the other entity seeks to justify the limitation
by reference to his or her own rights, then sections 8(2) and (3) of the
Constitution have application. Section 8(2) provides:
A provision of the Bill of Rights binds a natural or a juristic person if, and to the
extent that, it is applicable, taking into account the nature of the right and the
nature of any duty imposed by the right.
14.5.1 Introduction
One of the factors that triggered the Soweto student uprisings in 1976
was the insistence by the education authorities that Afrikaans and
English be the dual mediums of instruction in black schools in the area.
Prior to this decree, English was the sole medium of instruction. At the
time, English and Afrikaans were the only official languages. The
apartheid government perceived the implementation of Afrikaans as a
medium of instruction in schools as a method of entrenching and
extending its dominance. The perception that the language of the
oppressor was being imposed on black children fuelled the revolt
against the apartheid government.
The uprising occurred against the backdrop of the mistreatment of
indigenous languages under apartheid. Such indigenous languages,
even though spoken by millions of people, were not afforded official
recognition in South Africa in the pre-democratic era. The message
conveyed by this non-recognition was that these languages were less
important than English and Afrikaans and had a lower status than the
two languages officially recognised by the apartheid state.
To affirm the dignity of communities using the various languages
and to signal a decisive break with past thinking in this regard, section 6
of the Constitution recognises Sepedi, Sesotho, Setswana, siSwati,
Tshivenda, Xitsonga, Afrikaans, English, isiNdebele, isiXhosa and
isiZulu as official languages of the Republic. Section 6(4) requires all
official languages to be treated equitably and to enjoy parity of esteem.
Recognising that some indigenous languages had been systematically
disadvantaged, the Constitution imposes an obligation on the state to
take positive measures to advance the status of these languages.271 The
establishment of the Pan South African Language Board is one of the
initiatives that aims to foster respect for all languages. The challenge
facing those seeking to foster parity of esteem is to deal with the
dominance of English as the international language of commerce,
science, the law and technology.
SUMMARY
Summary
15.1.1 Introduction
In the pre-democratic era, the apartheid state enforced severe forms of
censorship to limit the range of political speech as well as the range of
artistic expression allowed in the country. If, for example, a person was
banned in terms of the Internal Security Act,1 not only was he or she
prohibited from speaking in public and publishing any written
materials, but the media were also prohibited from broadcasting,
publishing or reporting his or her words. Many prominent South
Africans were served with banning orders during the apartheid era,
including Chief Albert Luthuli, Steven Bantu Biko and Winnie
Madikizela Mandela. Apart from banning individuals, the apartheid
state also regularly banned books, films and plays because of their
political or sexual content. Banning made it a criminal offence to
possess, read or watch these products of artistic expression. During the
various states of emergency which were declared for long periods in the
1980s, the ability of newspapers to report on the actions of the police
and the military were severely limited by law. Thus, in this pre-Internet
era, the dark pall of censorship hung over South Africa. These
restrictions did not only constitute a denial of democracy. They also
exacerbated the impact of the systemic violations of other fundamental
human rights in South Africa.2
Black Wednesday
On 12 September 1977, Steve Bantu Biko – who
espoused the idea of black consciousness – died at
the hands of the apartheid police while in detention.
Biko’s funeral was attended by about 20 000 people.
Partly in response to these events, on the morning of
19 October 1977, scores of Black Consciousness
activists were arrested and detained under section 10
of the Internal Security Act.3
In addition to the large number of activists
detained, about 18 organisations were banned, as well
as three newspapers, namely The World, Weekend
World and Pro Veritate. Journalists who worked for
these and other newspapers were also detained,
including Mr Percy Qoboza, the editor of The World,
and Mr Aggrey Klaaste, the former editor of the
Sowetan.
This day came to be known as Black Wednesday. In
South Africa today, 19 October is still commemorated
with the aim of celebrating media freedom and to raise
awareness about real or perceived threats to the
freedom of the media.
Censorship is incompatible with South Africa’s present commitment to
a society based on a ‘constitutionally protected culture of openness and
democracy and universal human rights for South Africans of all ages,
classes and colours’.4 To prevent a recurrence of censorship, section 16
of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 explicitly
guarantees the right to freedom of expression for everyone. Section
16(1) states that this right includes:
• freedom of the press and other media
• freedom to receive or impart information or ideas
• freedom of artistic creativity
• academic freedom and freedom of scientific research.
15.1.3.1 Introduction
Apart from the general right to freedom of expression, section 16(1) of
the Constitution lists certain specific forms of protected expression.
These are:
(a) freedom of the press and other media;
(b) freedom to receive or impart information or ideas;
(c) freedom of artistic creativity; and
(d) academic freedom and freedom of scientific research.
Courts play a vital role to solve conflicts in all spheres of life. This
is what the Constitution promises us. The aesthetics of the court
building are a daily gentle reminder of this promise. The
overarching theme of the Constitutional Court building is justice
under a tree. For instance, the Constitutional Court logo depicts
people sheltering under a baobab tree. As former justice Sachs
described it, “[t]he tree protects the people, and they look after
the tree”. This is symbolic of the synergy between the law and the
people. It gives the court “an organic ambience” a space where
you feel welcome to see justice in motion.
But what did happen recently, in 1994, was that time stopped,
and our country was divided. Not by people, though, but by time.
When the new constitution came into force, a new South Africa
was born. The old South Africa, tyrannical and unjust, was now
impotent in its reign, while the new South Africa was full of hope
and unconstrained potential. The Constitution of the new South
Africa has been applauded by Justice Ginsburg of the United
States Supreme Court as “a deliberate attempt to have a
fundamental instrument of government that embrace[s] human
rights [and ensures] an independent judiciary”. For open justice
alone, the Constitution guarantees the freedom of the press, the
freedom of the media, and the right of the public to receive and
discuss information and ideas. It provides for all criminal accused
the right of a fair and public trial. And for all others, a fair and
public hearing. Even the Constitutional Court itself is
architecturally designed to both ensure, and represent, open
justice. For example, the courtroom includes a dedicated media
box, windows on all sides, and artwork of clouds on the walls to
give one the impression of being outside. Further, the logo of the
Court is intended to symbolise justice under a tree. Consider this
in comparison to the past, the old South Africa, with rampant
practices of incommunicado detention, without any prospect of a
proper trial. The old Terrorism Act permitted a senior police officer
to decide that a person should be detained without trial for up to
sixty days, without any right to communicate with the outside
world. While the Act had the appearance of being “designed to
combat terrorism [it in fact] itself become an instrument of
terror”.
[…]
The principle of open justice is, after all, a core part of the notion
of participatory democracy, particularly one whose Constitution
begins with the very words “democracy and open society”. It is
not a principle that should be defined in haste. The public is
entitled to have access to courts, and to obtain information about
them. Besides the obvious space limitation of there not being
enough room in a courtroom to always fit everyone, and the
distance limitation of court proceedings taking place in all four
corners of our country, there is also the realistic point that not
everyone wants to come to court to find out what is happening.
Instead, they rely on the media to tell them. And we do not want a
system in which the judicial system is “shrouded in mystique and
protected at all times from the prying eye of the camera or the
invasive ear of the microphone”. We want a system in which the
public trusts that the judiciary is acting according to the “time-
honoured standards of independence, integrity, impartiality and
fairness”. For that to happen, we must, as far as reasonably
practicable, create means for the media to access, observe and
report on the administration of justice. This has generally involved
the media having the ability to enter the courtroom, and to access
papers and written arguments.
In light of these points, the SCA then turned to consider whether the
approach it adopted in the SABC case, namely that ‘live or recorded
sound broadcasting should not be allowed unless the court is satisfied
that justice will not be inhibited’68 was still valid. The Court held that it
was not and, accordingly, that its judgment in SABC should be
overruled for the following reasons:
• First, at the time the SABC case was decided, live broadcasting of
court proceedings was virtually unknown in South Africa. Since then
the position had changed fundamentally and live broadcasts had
become the default position in the Constitutional Court, the SCA
and some divisions of the High Court.69
• Second, there had also been an important shift in the manner in
which South Africans, and especially younger South Africans, kept
up to date with news and current affairs. Instead of relying on
newspapers, magazines and other forms of print media, more and
more South Africans rely on television, social media and the internet
as their main source of information.70
• Third, following the example set by the International Military
Tribunal at Nuremberg in 1945, most international and regional
courts, including the European Court of Human Rights, the Inter-
American Court of Human Rights, the International Criminal
Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia and the International Criminal
Court, have opened their proceedings to cameras, not as an
exception, but as a general rule.71
Although all the arguments in favour of allowing cameras in the
courtroom are compelling, the SCA held further that it was also
important to note that allowing cameras in the courtroom was merely
the starting point. As a part of its inherent power to manage its own
process, a trial court was still entitled to direct that some or all of the
proceedings before it could not be broadcast at all or could be
broadcast only, for example, in audio form.72
The correct legal position, therefore, the SCA went on to conclude, is:
that there can be no objection in principle to the media recording and
broadcasting counsel’s address and all rulings and judgments (in respect of
both conviction and sentence) delivered in open court. When a witness objects
to coverage of his or her testimony, such witness should be required to assert
such objection before the trial judge, specifying the grounds therefor and the
effects he or she asserts such coverage would have upon his or her testimony.
This approach entails a witness-by-witness determination and recognises as
well that a distinction may have to be drawn between expert, professional
(such as police officers) and lay witnesses. Such an individualised enquiry is
more finely attuned to reconciling the competing rights at play than is a
blanket ban on the presence of cameras from the whole proceeding when only
one participant objects. Under this approach cameras are permitted to film or
televise all non-objecting witnesses. Spurious objections can also be dealt with
…73
If the judge determines that the witness has a valid objection to cameras,
alternatives to regular photographic or television coverage could be explored
that might assuage the witness’ fears. For example, television journalists are
often able to disguise the identity of a person being interviewed by means of
special lighting techniques and electronic voice alteration, or merely by
shielding the witness from the camera. In other instances, broadcast of
testimony of an objecting witness could be delayed until after the trial is over. If
such techniques were used in covering trials, the public would have more
complete access to the testimony via television, and yet the witness could
maintain some degree of privacy and security.74
After finding that section 12 of the Divorce Act was unconstitutional and
invalid, the Court turned to consider what would be the most
appropriate remedy. In this respect, the Court held that apart from
declaring section 12 to be invalid, it would be appropriate to issue an
order prohibiting the publication of the identities of divorcing parties
and their children and any information that could reveal their
identities.93
From the right to open justice flows the media’s right to gain access to, observe
and report on, the administration of justice and the right to have access to
papers and written arguments which are an integral part of court proceedings
subject to such limitations as may be warranted on a case-by-case basis in
order to ensure a fair trial.95
15.1.4.1 Introduction
The Constitution is founded on the values of dignity, equal worth and
freedom, values that are given effect to in the text of the Constitution. It
is therefore not surprising that section 16 of the Constitution makes it
clear that certain forms of expression do not deserve constitutional
protection since they have the potential to impugn the dignity of others
and cause harm.109 As we pointed out above, section 16(2) of the
Constitution deals with expression that is specifically excluded from the
protection of the right to freedom of expression in section 16(1). While
section 16(2)(a) and (b) are concerned with ‘propaganda for war’ and
‘incitement of imminent violence’, section 16(2)(c) is concerned with
what is commonly referred to as ‘hate speech’. Out of these three forms
of excluded expression, hate speech has received the most attention
from the courts and commentators. For the purposes of this book,
therefore, we are going to focus on this form of excluded expression
only.
Hate speech at a social level is said to be prohibited for one or more
of the following four reasons:
1. To prevent disruption to public order and social peace stemming
from retaliation by victims.
2. To prevent psychological harm to targeted groups that would
effectively impair their ability to positively participate in the
community and contribute to society.
3. To prevent both visible exclusion of minority groups that would
deny them equal opportunities and benefits of … society and
invisibly exclude their acceptance as equals.
4. To prevent social conflagration and political disintegration.110
The Equality Court formulated the reasons for the prohibition on hate
speech slightly differently in South African Human Rights Commission v
Qwelane and Another,111 when it held as follows:
The power of words is limitless. Although words can be used to inspire people
and promote good, they also can be used to destroy. In the form of hate speech,
words can be ‘used as weapons to ambush, terrorize, wound, humiliate and
degrade’ … On an individual basis, hate speech inflicts ‘emotional pain and
distress, intimidation, and fear’ on its targets …112
South African courts have had difficulty with the interpretation and
application of section 10 due to the way in which the provision is
formulated. The SCA has complained that section 10 is ‘exceptionally
difficult to understand’ and endorsed the view that ‘it is doubtful that
the average person “will be able to use the Act to guide his or her
conduct clearly”’.115 The Court nevertheless concluded the prohibition
on hate speech in the PEPUDA is more far-reaching than the description
of hate speech in section 16(2)(c) of the Constitution.116 This is because
it is not based simply on the grounds listed in section 16(2)(c), namely
race, ethnicity, gender and religion. Instead, it is based on all of the
prohibited grounds listed in the PEPUDA. These grounds include race,
gender, sex, pregnancy, marital status, ethnic or social origin, colour,
sexual orientation, age, disability, religion, conscience, belief, culture,
language and birth, or any other similar ground such as HIV status. It is
also important to note that speech will not constitute hate speech
merely because it is offensive or because it offends a certain section of
the population. The threshold test is that the speech must be aimed at
one of the defined groups. Offending speech targeting all lawyers or all
journalists would therefore never constitute hate speech because it
does not target a person on the basis of one of the listed or associated
grounds.
Once it is determined that the speech targets a person based on one
of the listed or similar grounds, the question will be asked whether it
could reasonably be construed to demonstrate a clear intention to be
hurtful, harmful or to propagate hatred. An Equality Court need not find
that the speaker actually had the intention to be hurtful, to incite harm
or to propagate hate. The question is whether the words of the speaker
could reasonably be construed in this way. The subjective question (the
intention of the speaker) must be determined by using an objective test
(what a reasonable person would have thought).117 To decide this
question, we would need to look at who the speaker is, in what context
the words were uttered and, given this context, how a reasonable
person would have interpreted the words. We assume that a reasonable
person is someone who is imbued with the values of the Constitution
and who understands the importance of freedom of speech and robust
debate in a democracy. He or she is not hypersensitive and will not
assume that the speaker had the intention to be hurtful or to incite
harm merely because the words may have offended the person
targeted. It will not be sufficient to show that members of the targeted
group were hurt by the speech or believed that the speech incited harm
against them. What is required is to determine whether a reasonable
person would have believed that the speaker had the intention to hurt
the targeted group or to incite harm against that group. As summarised
by the SCA in Qwelane v South African Human Rights Commission and
Another,118 one need not ask whether:
a reasonable person would interpret the conduct in such a way, only that it is
possible that he might construe it in this way … The result is to depart
significantly from the objective constitutional test and replace it with the
subjective opinion of a reasonable person hearing the words. This is an
extensive infringement on the right of freedom of expression.119
At the time of writing the Qwelane judgment was being appealed to the
Constitutional Court, but remains binding law. The SCA’s endorsement
of the disjunctive reading of section 10(1) in this case, confirms the
broad scope of the hate speech provision. But it is exactly because of the
wide reach of the provision when interpreted disjunctively, that led the
SCA in Qwelane to declare parts of section 10(1) unconstitutional. The
SCA pointed out that, read disjunctively, all that would be needed to be
guilty of hate speech was for a complainant to show that the disputed
words could reasonably be construed as having the intention to be
hurtful on the grounds such as race, sex, sexual orientation, religion and
the like. This, held the SCA, was problematic because the term ‘hurtful’
was both vague and broad. Hurtful words would include any words that
attacked another person’s feelings or subjective emotions.125
The SCA then proceeded to consider whether section 10(1) of the
PEPUDA infringed on the guarantee of freedom of expression
contained in section 16(1) of the Constitution. As section 16(1)
guarantees all forms of expression not explicitly excluded from
protection by section 16(2), any regulation of hate speech that went
beyond the exclusions contained in section 16(2) would impose a limit
on freedom of expression. In the words of the SCA: ‘Where the State
extends the scope of regulation beyond expression envisaged in s 16(2),
it encroaches on the terrain of protected expression and can do so only
if such regulation meets the justification criteria in s 36(1) of the
Constitution.’126 The question was whether the legislature had extended
the scope of section 10(1) of the PEPUDA beyond expression envisaged
by section 16(2)(c) of the Constitution. The latter section states that the
right in section 16(1) ‘does not extend to advocacy of hatred that is
based on race, ethnicity, gender or religion, and that constitutes
incitement to cause harm’. The SCA held that section 10(1) regulated
expression far broader than that described in section 16(2)(c) of the
Constitution. This was so, first, because section 10 regulated speech
based on grounds not listed in section 16(2)(c). While the latter
provision only excludes hate speech based on ‘race, ethnicity, gender or
religion’ from constitutional protection, section 10(1) of the PEPUDA
prohibits hate speech on many other grounds as well – including on the
ground of sexual orientation. Second, section 10(1) was far too broad
and regulated speech that was protected, specifically because it
extended hate speech to types of speech that were merely ‘hurtful’. The
SCA noted that the PEPUDA did not define what types of hurt would be
sufficient to warrant a hate speech finding and that the provision was
therefore far too vague. According to the SCA:
daily human interaction produces a multitude of instances where hurtful
words are uttered and thus, to prohibit words that have that effect, is going too
far. So, too, a host of jokes might be hurtful to those who bear the brunt of
them. Are we to entertain complaints that extend to jokes that are not within
the limitations of s 16(2)(c) of the Constitution?127
As a result, the SCA held that section 10(1) of the PEPUDA went much
further than the exclusion in section 16(2)(c) of the Constitution and
therefore constituted a limitation on the right to freedom of expression
contained in section 16(1) of the Constitution. The SCA further held that
this limitation was not justifiable in terms of the limitation clause.128 The
SCA suggested that what was needed was a provision that tracked far
more closely to the wording of section 16(2)(c) of the Constitution. The
Court gave Parliament 18 months to correct the defect in section 10(1),
but crafted an interim order, which put in place a redrafted version of
section 10(1), which reads as follows:
No person may advocate hatred that is based on race, ethnicity, gender,
religion or sexual orientation and that constitutes incitement to cause harm.
15.2.1 Introduction
One of the most powerful ways in which individuals can express their
views on political and social issues is by coming together and protesting
peacefully. The freedom to assemble, demonstrate, picket and petition,
therefore, forms an integral part of the democratic rights of citizens in a
democracy. When a large crowd of people assemble in the street to
express their views on issues of the day, this can be viewed as a form of
participatory democracy.
In the apartheid era, rallies and demonstrations protesting against
the policies of the apartheid regime or popularising the ideas of anti-
apartheid organisations, such as the African National Congress (ANC),
the Azanian People’s Organisation (AZAPO), the Pan Africanist
Congress (PAC) or the United Democratic Front (UDF), were often
banned by the government. In one of the most famous incidents,
peaceful protesters in Cape Town, bearing placards proclaiming ‘the
people shall govern’, were sprayed with purple dye by the police. A
spirited activist seized the initiative and grabbed the nozzle from the
police. He then proceeded to paint the surrounding area purple. An
inspired graffitist subsequently wrote on a wall ‘The purple shall
govern!’136
In post-apartheid South Africa, the right to assemble and
demonstrate cannot legally be curtailed in the same manner. This is
because section 17 of the Constitution guarantees the right to freedom
of assembly, demonstration, picket and petition. This section provides
simply that ‘[e]veryone has the right, peacefully and unarmed, to
assemble, to demonstrate, to picket and to present petitions’.
Democracy entails more than the right to vote in regular free and
fair elections. As we have seen in the first part of this book, democracy
also requires citizens actively to participate in public affairs. For this
reason, the right to freedom of assembly plays an important role in a
democratic society. Assemblies, demonstrations, pickets and petitions
allow groups, whose influence on political parties or the political
process would otherwise be minimal, to raise issues that are important
to them, to draw attention to these issues and to engage with their
fellow citizens and representatives about these issues.
Citizens also use such events to enforce their rights outside the
formal legal process by placing pressure on the legislature and the
executive not to infringe on the rights of individuals. Such events also
help civil society groups build support for their causes and mobilise
voters in order to ensure more responsive and accountable government
from those who were elected to serve the people. Often, such activities
precede or go hand-in-hand with court action.137
A further reason why South African courts take an expansive view of the
right to freedom of assembly is that it forms part of a web of mutually
supporting rights which are closely linked to the proper functioning of
the democracy. In this regard, the Constitutional Court noted in South
African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence and Another145
that there was an interrelationship between the various freedom rights:
[Freedom of speech] is closely related to freedom of religion, belief and
opinion (s 15), the right to dignity (s 10), as well as the right to freedom of
association (s 18), the right to vote and to stand for public office (s 19) and the
right to assembly (s 17). These rights taken together protect the rights of
individuals not only individually to form and express opinions, of whatever
nature, but to establish associations and groups of like-minded people to foster
and propagate such opinions.146
Peaceful assemblies
Like section 17 of the Constitution, Article 8(1) of the
German Constitution provides that ‘all Germans’ …
‘have the right to assemble peacefully and unarmed
without prior notification or permission’.
In the Brokdorf Demonstration case,148 a number
of non-governmental organisations announced that
they were planning to hold a large demonstration
against plans to build a nuclear power plant in
Brokdorf. Following this announcement, the relevant
authorities banned any demonstrations against the
nuclear power plant in an area covering 210 km2
around the site. The relevant authorities based their
decision on the grounds that they believed that 50
000 people would attend the demonstration and that
some of the demonstrators intended to engage in acts
of violence.
In dealing with this case, the Federal Constitutional
Court discussed the scope and ambit of the right to
assemble and, in particular, the requirements that the
right applies only to those assemblies that are
peaceful. The Court held that an assembly will be
classified as non-peaceful only if acts of physical
violence against persons or property are committed or
threatened.149 In addition, the Court also held that
where the organisers and participants in a
demonstration do not plan to engage in acts of
physical violence, that demonstration may not be
prohibited or broken up if a small minority of
demonstrators or counter-demonstrators plan to
engage in acts of violence. In these sorts of cases, the
Court went on to hold, the authorities must act against
the violent minority and not against the demonstration
as a whole. The demonstration as a whole remains
protected by Article 8.150
15.2.3 Distinguishing between assemblies, demonstrations,
pickets and petitions
15.2.3.2 Pickets
Like the word ‘assembly’, the Constitution does not define the word
‘picket’. It appears, however, to apply to those situations where people
come together to carry placards in a public place at or near a business
premise.157
Picketing is a common feature in labour disputes. The Labour
Relations Act (LRA)158 protects the right of trade unions and their
members to picket. Section 69(1) of the LRA thus provides that ‘[a]
registered trade union may authorise a picket by its members and
supporters for the purposes of peacefully demonstrating (a) in support
of any protected strike; or (b) in opposition to any lock-out’.
Section 69(2) of the LRA goes on to provide that ‘[d]espite any law
regulating the right of assembly, a picket authorised in terms of
subsection (1), may be held (a) in any place to which the public has
access but outside the premises of an employer; or (b) with the
permission of the employer, inside the employer’s premises’. The
permission referred to in this section may not be unreasonably
withheld.159 The sorts of places referred to in section 69(2) include
shopping malls and waterfronts.
15.2.3.3 Petitions
The right to petition protects the right to make direct submissions to the
relevant person or institution.168 The right to petition in terms of section
17 should be read together with sections 56(d) and 115 of the
Constitution which provide that the National Assembly (NA) and the
provincial legislatures are obliged to ‘receive petitions, representations
or submissions from any interested persons or institutions’.
To give effect to these rights and obligations, all the provincial
legislatures, with the exception of the Eastern Cape Provincial
Legislature, have enacted Petitions Acts.169 Section 1 of the KwaZulu-
Natal Petitions Act defines a petition as:
a complaint, request, representation or submission addressed by a petitioner
to the Committee, and may take the form of:
(a) a single petition, which is an individual submission from a single
petitioner concerning a particular complaint or request;
(b) a collective petition, which is a collection of signatures from a number of
petitioners concerning a particular complaint or request;
(c) a group petition, made up of individual or group submissions from a
number of petitioners concerning the same or substantially similar
complaints or requests;
(d) an association petition, which is an individual submission from an
association, or an individual mandated by an association, concerning a
particular complaint or request.
After making these points, the Court then turned to examine section
11(2). In this respect, the Court began by noting that the purpose of the
section was:
• to provide for the statutory liability of organisations
• to afford the organiser a tighter defence by allowing it to rely on the
absence of reasonable foreseeability and the taking of reasonable
steps
• to place the onus on the organiser to prove this defence instead of
requiring the plaintiff to prove the organiser’s unlawfulness and
negligence.193
15.3.1 Introduction
Before 1994, the majority of South Africans were prohibited from voting
in elections based solely on their race. The oppressive and
undemocratic state curtailed much of extra-parliamentary political
activity. Liberation movements such as the ANC, AZAPO, the PAC and
the SACP were prohibited from operating in the country. Police
harassed and at times detained, tortured and even killed activists who
belonged to organisations such as the UDF – which was established in
1983 to spearhead resistance against apartheid – and the End
Conscription Campaign (ECC). In short, the majority of South Africans
who opposed the apartheid regime enjoyed little or no political rights.
The drafters of the Constitution, therefore, included a wide range of
political rights in the Constitution. Section 19(1) of the Constitution
thus states that ‘[e]very citizen is free to make political choices’. This
includes the right:
(a) to form a political party;
(b) to participate in the activities of, or recruit members for, a political party;
and
(c) to campaign for a political party or cause.
Section 19(2) states that ‘[e]every citizen has the right to free, fair and
regular elections for any legislative body established in terms of this
Constitution’ while section 19(3) confirms that ‘[e]very adult citizen’
has the right:
(a) to vote in elections for any legislative body established in terms of this
Constitution and to do so in secret; and
(b) to stand for public office and, if elected, to hold office.
A second reason why these rights are important is that they aim to give
effect to a system of representative democracy. In Ramakatsa,
Moseneke DCJ explained this by affirming that section 19 has to be
interpreted against the background of the Constitution as a whole,
especially the role afforded in the Constitution to political parties:
In our system of [constitutional] democracy political parties occupy the centre
stage and play a vital part in facilitating the exercise of political rights. This fact
is affirmed by section 1 of the Constitution which proclaims that ‘[u]niversal
adult suffrage, a national common voters roll, regular elections and a multi-
party system of democratic government, to ensure accountability,
responsiveness and openness’ are some of the values on which our State is
founded.200
In contrast to most of the rights set out in the Bill of Rights that attach to
‘every person’, the rights contained in section 19 of the Constitution are
available only to citizens.201 It can therefore be observed that the
Constitution distinguishes between citizens who are the bearers of
political rights and ‘everyone’ else, including, for example, foreign
nationals, who are not entitled to participate in the exercise of political
rights. While foreign nationals enjoy almost all the other rights
contained in the Bill of Rights, only citizens can invoke the political
rights set out in section 19.
15.3.2.1 Introduction
Political parties lie at the heart of South Africa’s constitutional
democracy. The Constitution does not regulate the internal affairs of
political parties. Nor does it contain extensive provisions on the
appropriate constitutional relationship between political parties and
constitutional structures such as legislatures and executives. Note too
that the right to make political choices goes beyond the involvement of
citizens in party politics: the involvement of some citizens in social
movements, citizen activism and other civil society organs is also
pivotal for the proper functioning of a democracy. The rights to freedom
of expression, assembly and association ensure that these political
activities not associated directly with political parties are adequately
protected by the Constitution.
However, section 19(1) of the Constitution, which guarantees for all
citizens the right to form, participate in the activities of and campaign
for political parties, affirms that such participation lies at the heart of
the right to make political choices. Section 19(1) thus primarily
guarantees the freedom to make a choice with regard to a political party
and once that choice has been made, it safeguards a member’s free and
fair participation in the activities of the party concerned.203
These provisions have a number of important consequences.
Among these are the following:
• First, members of a political party have a constitutional right to
participate in the activities of their party.
• Second, this constitutional right can be enforced not only against
external interference, but against interference arising from within
the party itself.204 The constitutions and rules of political parties
must, therefore, be consistent with the Constitution.205
Prohibited donations
The Political Party Funding Act regulates both the
public and private funding of political parties. In so far
as the private funding of political parties is concerned,
the Act prohibits certain donations made directly to
political parties. As De Vos points out, the prohibitions
are not without criticism:
Section 8(1) of the Act prohibits political parties from accepting a
donation from foreign governments or foreign government
agencies. It also prohibits, with some exceptions, foreign persons
or entities to donate. Importantly organs of state or state-owned
enterprise are also prohibited from donating to political parties.
Section 8(2) further prohibits a political party from accepting a
donation from a person or entity in excess of R15 million per
financial year.
15.3.5.1 Introduction
Section 19(3) of the Constitution provides that ‘[e]very adult citizen has
the right – (a) to vote in elections for any legislative body established in
terms of the Constitution and to do so in secret; and (b) to stand for
public office and, if elected, to hold office’.
The Constitutional Court highlighted the significance of the right to
vote (and its intimate relationship with the value of human dignity that
permeates the Bill of Rights) in August. The Court held that ‘[t]he vote of
each and every citizen is a badge of dignity and of personhood. Quite
literally, it says that everybody counts’.255 The right to vote, therefore, is
symbolic of our citizenship and represents a practical manifestation of
how the Constitution recognises and protects the dignity of every
citizen. Given South Africa’s history in which the dignity of black South
Africans was systematically denied by the state – in part by denying
black South Africans the right to vote – this right and its protection is of
profound importance for every citizen. As O’Regan J stated in the New
National Party judgment:
The obligation to afford citizens the right to vote in regular, free and fair
elections is important not only because of the relative youth of our
constitutional democracy but also because of the emphatic denial of
democracy in the past. Many of the injustices of the past flowed directly from
the denial of the right to vote on the basis of race to the majority of South
Africans. The denial of the right to vote entrenched political power in the hands
of white South Africans.256
Apart from its symbolic role of affirming the dignity of all, the
Constitutional Court held in Richter v The Minister for Home Affairs and
Others that the right to vote is also a crucial working part of our
democracy:
Without voters who want to vote, who will take the trouble to register, and to
stand in queues, as millions patiently and unforgettably did in April 1994,
democracy itself will be imperilled. Each vote strengthens and invigorates our
democracy. In marking their ballots, citizens remind those elected that their
position is based on the will of the people and will remain subject to that will.
The moment of voting reminds us that both electors and the elected bear civic
responsibilities arising out of our democratic Constitution and its values.257
Second, the measures must not unjustifiably infringe the right to vote
guaranteed in section 19(3) of the Constitution.267 In this regard, the
Court held that the method Parliament adopts for voters to identify
themselves will infringe the right to vote if, at the time the method was
adopted by Parliament, an eligible voter who wanted to vote would not
be able to do so even though he or she took reasonable steps in pursuit
of his or her right to vote. This is because any method which was not
sufficiently flexible to be reasonably capable of achieving the goal of
ensuring that people who wanted to vote would be able to do so if they
acted reasonably in pursuit of the right, had the potential to infringe the
right.268 Given this test, the majority found that the bar-coded ID
requirement did not infringe the right to vote. This is because even
though the Electoral Act had been promulgated only nine months
before the general election, there was no evidence to show that at the
time Parliament passed the Electoral Act the Department of Home
Affairs would be unable to issue a bar-coded ID to any eligible voter
who applied for one before the voter registration process closed. Any
eligible voter who took reasonable steps to obtain a bar-coded ID and to
register as a voter, therefore, would be able to vote.269
15.3.5.3.2 Prisoners
Apart from August, which is discussed above, the Constitutional Court
considered the exclusion of prisoners from the right to vote in Minister
of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime Prevention and the Re-
integration of Offenders (NICRO) and Others.273 Unlike in August, this
case dealt with a legislative provision purporting to limit the rights of
prisoners to vote.274 The provisions effectively disenfranchised
convicted prisoners serving sentences of imprisonment without the
option of a fine by prohibiting them from registering as voters and from
voting while in prison.275 Unsentenced prisoners and prisoners
incarcerated because of their failure to pay their fines retained the right
to register and vote.
After the provisions of the Electoral Laws Amendment Act276 came
into operation, the respondents applied for an order declaring them to
be unconstitutional and invalid on the grounds that they unjustifiably
infringed the right to vote. A majority of the Constitutional Court agreed
with the respondents and granted the order.
The Court accepted (and this was conceded by all parties) that these
provisions, which prevented most prisoners from voting, infringed on
their right to vote which is guaranteed in section 19(3)(a) of the
Constitution. The only question was whether such a limitation of the
right was justifiable in terms of the limitation clause or not. The majority
of the court held that the limitation was not justifiable and hence was
unconstitutional.277
The Court rejected the argument that special arrangements would
have to be made for the prisoners in question to vote and that these
special arrangements could put the integrity of the voting process at
risk. Special measures, therefore, would have to be put in place and this
would put a strain on the Electoral Commission’s financial and
logistical resources. The factual basis for this justification had not been
established. The Electoral Commission had made arrangements for
registering unsentenced prisoners and prisoners incarcerated because
of their failure to pay their fines. There was nothing to suggest that
extending these arrangements to include convicted prisoners serving
sentences of imprisonment without the option of a fine would place an
undue burden on the Electoral Commission’s financial and logistical
resources. Apart from saying that it would be costly to do so, the
Minister provided no information about the logistical problems or
estimates of the costs involved.278
The Court also grappled with the argument advanced by the
government that it was important for the government to denounce
crime and to communicate to the public that the rights that citizens
have, such as the right to vote, are related to fulfilling their duties and
obligations as citizens. The Court pointed out that a majority of the
Canadian Supreme Court had rejected a similar argument in Sauve v
Canada (Chief Electoral Officer) 279 despite the fact that the Canadian
government had presented a great deal of evidence to justify the law in
question.280 Unlike the Canadian government, the Court held further,
the Minister had presented almost no evidence to justify the Electoral
Laws Amendment Act other than simply saying that the ‘government
did not want to be seen to be soft on crime and that it would be unfair to
others who cannot vote to allow prisoners to vote’.281 These statements,
the Court went on to conclude, could not hope to justify the Electoral
Laws Amendment Act which applied to both serious and relatively
minor crimes and even to prisoners whose convictions and sentences
were still under appeal.282
SUMMARY
Given that the majority of South Africa’s citizens were denied political
rights prior to 1994, it is not surprising that section 19 of the
Constitution protects a wide range of political rights. Among these are
the right to make political choices; the right to free, fair and regular
elections and the right to vote in secret and to stand for public office.
These rights are important not only because they are aimed at
preventing the wholesale denial of political rights from ever taking place
again, but also because they are aimed at giving effect to the system of
representative democracy enshrined in the Constitution.
In so far as the rights guaranteed in section 19 of the Constitution
are concerned, however, it is important to note that, unlike most of the
other rights set out in the Bill of Rights, these rights are available only to
citizens. The Constitution, therefore, distinguishes between citizens
who are the bearers of political rights and ‘everyone’ else, including, for
example, foreign nationals, who are not entitled to participate in the
exercise of political rights. While foreign nationals enjoy almost all of
the other rights contained in the Bill of Rights, only citizens can invoke
the political rights set out in section 19.
The political rights protected in section 19 of the Constitution must
be read together with the right to freedom of expression guaranteed in
section 16 and the right to freedom of assembly, demonstration, picket
and petition guaranteed in section 18. This is because democracy
entails more than simply being able to vote. It must also give people an
opportunity to form their own views and to express them by coming
together and protesting peacefully. This allows people whose influence
on political parties would otherwise be minimal to raise issues that are
important to them, to draw attention to these issues and to engage with
their fellow citizens and representatives about these issues.
Apart from participation in the political process, the rights to
freedom of expression and assembly, demonstration, picket and
petition also promote a number of other goals. The right to freedom of
expression, for example, recognises and protects the moral agency of
individuals in our society and facilitates the search for truth. The right to
freedom of assembly, demonstration, picket and petition promotes the
development of each individual’s unique personality. This is because
our personalities do not develop in isolation, but rather in the context of
groups. Cultural, education and religious assemblies may, therefore, be
as important as political assemblies.
Finally, it is important to note that both of these rights have internal
modifiers. The right to freedom of expression, therefore, does not
include the right to promote war, incite imminent violence or advocate
hatred that is based on race, ethnicity, gender or religion, and that
constitutes incitement to cause harm. The right to freedom of assembly,
demonstration, picket and petition does not include the right to
assemble, demonstrate, picket or petition in a violent or armed manner.
Although these sorts of activities are not prohibited by the Constitution,
they are also not protected by the Constitution. This means that they
may be prohibited by legislation. PEPUDA thus prohibits hate speech
and the Regulation of Gatherings Act prohibits armed and violent
assemblies, demonstrations and pickets.
1 Act 74 of 1982.
2 See S v Mamabolo (CCT 44/00) [2001] ZACC 17; 2001 (3) SA 409 (CC); 2001 (5) BCLR 449
(CC) (11 April 2001) para 28; Islamic Unity Convention v Independent Broadcasting
Authority and Others (CCT36/01) [2002] ZACC 3; 2002 (4) SA 294; 2002 (5) (CC); BCLR 433
(CC) (11 April 2002) para 25.
3 Act 74 of 1982.
4 Shabalala and Others v Attorney-General of the Transvaal and Another (CCT23/94) [1995]
ZACC 12; 1996 (1) SA 725 (CC); 1995 (12) BCLR 1593 (CC) (29 November 1995) para 26.
5 Islamic Unity Convention para 30.
6 Islamic Unity Convention para 30.
South African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence (CCT27/98) [1999] ZACC 7;
7 1999 (4) SA 469 (CC); 1999 (6) BCLR 615 (CC) (26 May 1999) para 8.
8 See Shabalala; South African National Defence Union; Islamic Unity Convention;
Mamabolo.
9 South African National Defence Union para 8.
10 (CCT27/98) [1999] ZACC 7; 1999 (4) SA 469 (CC); 1999 (6) BCLR 615 (CC) (26 May 1999)
para 7.
11 (CCT 44/00) [2001] ZACC 17; 2001 (3) SA 409 (CC); 2001 (5) BCLR 449 (CC) (11 April 2001)
para 37.
12 Mamabolo para 37.
13 Case and Another v Minister of Safety and Security and Others, Curtis v Minister of Safety
and Security and Others (CCT20/95, CCT21/95) [1996] ZACC 7; 1996 (3) SA 617 (CC); 1996
(5) BCLR 608 (CC) (9 May 1996) para 26.
14 Herman, ES and Chomsky, N (1988) Manufacturing Consent: The Political Economy of the
Mass Media 306.
15 Herman and Chomsky (1988) 306.
16 De Vos, P (2017) Rejecting the free marketplace of ideas: a value-based conception of the
limits of free speech South African Journal on Human Rights 33(3):359–79 at 368.
17 Case para 26.
18 (CCT53/01) [2002] ZACC 12; 2002 (5) SA 401 (CC); 2002 (8) BCLR 771 (CC) (14 June 2002)
para 18.
19 (CCT 90/07, CCT 92/07) [2008] ZACC 14; 2009 (1) SA 141 (CC); 2009 (3) BCLR 309 (CC) (31
July 2008) para 52. See also Mthembi-Mahanyele v Mail & Guardian Ltd and Another
(054/2003) [2004] ZASCA 67; [2004] 3 All SA 511 (SCA) (2 August 2004) para 41.
20 The First Amendment reads as follows: ‘Congress shall make no law respecting an
establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom
of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition
the Government for a redress of grievances.’
21 Nelson Mandela Foundation Trust and Another v Afriforum NPC and Others (EQ02/2018)
[2019] ZAEQC 2; [2019] 4 All SA 237 (EqC); 2019 (10) BCLR 1245 (EqC); 2019 (6) SA 327 (GJ)
(21 August 2019).
22 (CCT20/02) [2003] ZACC 1; 2003 (3) SA 345 (CC); 2003 (4) BCLR 357 (CC) (11 March 2003).
23 Phillips para 15.
24 Islamic United Convention paras 28–9.
25 Hamata and Another v Chairman, Peninsula Technikon Internal Disciplinary Committee
and Others 2000 (4) SA 621 (C) para 32.
26 Islamic Unity Convention para 27.
27 Islamic Unity Convention para 28.
28 Islamic Unity Convention para 31.
29 (CCT42/04) [2005] ZACC 7; 2006 (1) SA 144 (CC); 2005 (8) BCLR 743 (CC) (27 May 2005)
para 47.
30 See De Reuck v Director of Public Prosecutions (Witwatersrand Local Division) and Others
(CCT5/03) [2003] ZACC 19; 2004 (1) SA 406 (CC); 2003 (12) BCLR 1333 (CC) (15 October
2003) para 48.
31 (CCT5/03) [2003] ZACC 19; 2004 (1) SA 406 (CC); 2003 (12) BCLR 1333 (CC) (15 October
2003).
32 Act 65 of 1996.
33 De Reuck paras 46–7.
34 De Reuck para 48.
35 De Reuck para 48.
36 De Reuck para 59.
37 De Reuck para 64–5.
38 De Reuck paras 71–9.
39 Lucas, M (2006) On gay porn Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 18(1):299–302 at 299.
40 Lucas (2006) 299. See also Sherman, JG (1995) Love speech: The social utility of
pornography Stanford Law Review 47(4):661–706 at 702–3, where he argues that ‘gay male
pornography is a necessary tool in gay men’s struggle to attain sexual integrity’, and asserts
that ‘[t]he relative importance of pornography in the gay male imagination results from the
suppression of other forms of gay expression: not only artistic expression but lived
interpersonal expression’.
41 Khumalo paras 22–4; South African Broadcasting Corporation Limited v National Director
of Public Prosecutions and Others (CCT58/06) [2006] ZACC 15; 2007 (1) SA 523 (CC); 2007
(2) BCLR 167 (CC); (21 September 2006) para 24; Print Media South Africa and Another v
Minister of Home Affairs and Another (CCT 113/11) [2012] ZACC 22; 2012 (6) SA 443 (CC);
2012 (12) BCLR 1346 (CC) (28 September 2012) para 54.
42 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Sunday Times Newspaper and Another 1995
(2) SA 221 (T) 227H–228A.
43 (CCT53/01) [2002] ZACC 12; 2002 (5) SA 401 (CC); 2002 (8) BCLR 771 (CC) (14 June 2002).
44 Khumalo para 24.
45 ‘Sanef calls for action over reporters being prevented from doing job in Cape Town’ (2020, 3
March) IOL, accessed on 6 April 2020 at https://www.iol.co.za/capetimes/news/sanef-
calls-for-action-over-reporters-being-prevented-from-doing-job-in-cape-town-43995492.
46 See Holomisa v Argus Newspaper 1996 (2) SA 588 (W) 855–56; Midi Television (Pty) Ltd v
Director of Public Prosecutions (Western Cape) (100/06) [2007] ZASCA 56; [2007] 3 All SA
318 (SCA); 2007 (9) BCLR 958 (SCA) (18 May 2007) para 6; South African Broadcasting
Corporation para 42; Johncom Media Investments Limited v M and Others (CCT 08/08)
[2009] ZACC 5; 2009 (4) SA 7 (CC); 2009 (8) BCLR 751 (CC) (17 March 2009) para 28.
47 Moseneke, D (2015, May 15) The Media, Courts and Technology: Remarks on the Media
Coverage of the Oscar Pistorius Trial and Open Justice Constitutionally Speaking available
at https://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/dcj-dikgang-moseneke-the-media-courts-and-
technology-remarks-on-the-media-coverage-of-the-oscar-pistorius-trial-and-open-
justice/.
48 Moseneke (2015).
49 (435/06) [2006] ZASCA 90; [2006] SCA 89 (RSA); [2007] 1 All SA 384 (SCA) (24 August 2006).
50 SABC paras 14 and 15.
51 SABC para 20
52 SABC para 25.
53 SABC para 27.
54 SABC para 28.
55 South African Broadcasting Corporation Ltd v National Director of Public Prosecutions and
Others (CCT58/06) [2006] ZACC 15; 2007 (1) SA 523 (CC); 2007 (2) BCLR 167 (CC); (21
September 2006).
56 SABC para 41.
57 SABC para 55.
58 (10193/2014) [2014] ZAGPPHC 37; [2014] 2 All SA 446 (GP); 2014 (1) SACR 589 (GP) (25
February 2014).
59 Pistorius para 18.
60 Pistorius para 19.
61 Pistorius paras 19 and 20.
62 Pistorius para 21.
63 Pistorius paras 25–26 and 30.
64 Van Breda para 58.
65 Van Breda para 59.
66 Van Breda para 60.
67 Van Breda para 61.
68 SABC para 20.
69 Van Breda para 63.
70 Van Breda para 64.
71 Van Breda paras 65–8.
72 Van Breda para 70.
73 Van Breda para 72.
74 Van Breda para 73.
75 Van Breda para 74.
76 (CCT261/18); [2019] ZACC 46; 2020 (3) BCLR 245 (CC); 2020 (1) SACR 469 (CC) (4
December 2019).
77 Act 51 of 1977.
78 Centre for Child Law paras 29–35.
79 Centre for Child Law paras 37–43.
80 Centre for Child Law paras 44–50.
81 Centre for Child Law para 54.
82 Centre for Child Law paras 55–8.
83 Centre for Child Law para 68.
84 Centre for Child Law para 69.
85 Centre for Child Law para 70.
86 Centre for Child Law paras 91–113.
87 Centre for Child Law paras 96–100.
88 (CCT 08/08) [2009] ZACC 5; 2009 (4) SA 7 (CC); 2009 (8) BCLR 751 (CC) (17 March 2009).
89 Act 70 of 1979.
90 Johncom Media Investments para 23.
91 Johncom Media Investments para 29.
92 Johncom Media Investments para 30.
93 Johncom Media Investments para 42.
94 (CCT38/07) [2008] ZACC 6; 2008 (5) SA 31 (CC); 2008 (8) BCLR 771 (CC) (22 May 2008)
para 39.
95 Independent Newspapers paras 40–1.
96 Independent Newspapers para 43.
97 Independent Newspapers para 44.
98 Independent Newspapers para 45.
99 (CCT 113/11) [2012] ZACC 22; 2012 (6) SA 443 (CC); 2012 (12) BCLR 1346 (CC) (28
September 2012).
100 Print Media South Africa para 20.
101 Print Media South Africa para 27.
102 Print Media South Africa para 17.
103 Print Media South Africa para 60.
104 Print Media South Africa para 98.
105 Print Media South Africa para 55.
106 Print Media South Africa para 56.
107 ICASA was created by the Independent Communications Authority of South Africa Act 13
of 2000. For a discussion on the role of the regulation of the public broadcaster, see
Tomaselli, KG (2008) Exogenous and endogenous democracy: South African politics and
media International Journal of Press/Politics 13(2):171–80 at 171.
108 There are therefore similarities between the regulation of electronic broadcasters and that
of the print media although different bodies deal with complaints relating to these
categories of the media in terms of different Codes.
109 Islamic United Convention para 10.
110 Afri-Forum and Another v Malema and Others (20968/2010) [2011] ZAEQC 2; 2011 (6) SA
240 (EqC); [2011] 4 All SA 293 (EqC); 2011 (12) BCLR 1289 (EqC) (12 September 2011) para
29, citing Braun, S (2004) Democracy Off Balance: Freedom of Expression and Hate
Propaganda Law in Canada 62.
111 South African Human Rights Commission v Qwelane and Another (EQ44/2009; EQ13/2012)
[2017] ZAGPJHC 218; [2017] 4 All SA 234 (GJ); 2018 (2) SA 149 (GJ) (18 August 2017).
112 Webb, TJ (2010) Verbal poison-criminalizing hate speech: A comparative analysis and a
proposal for the American system Washburn LJ 50:445 at 445.
113 Act 4 of 2000.
114 The SCA got this wrong in the case of Masuku and Another v South African Human Rights
Commission obo South African Jewish Board of Deputies (1062/2017) [2018] ZASCA 180;
2019 (2) SA 194 (SCA); [2019] 1 All SA 608 (SCA) (4 December 2018) para 13. The Court
ignored the applicable law contained in the PEPUDA and wrongly dealt with the case as if s
16(2) is the applicable provision that prohibits speech. The SCA explained its approach by
claiming that the respondents had disavowed reliance on the PEPUDA and had accepted
‘that the statements, as any other form of speech, would be excluded from protection (as
hate speech) under s 16(1) of the Constitution only if they fell afoul of s 16(2) thereof’.
115 Qwelane para 68.
116 Qwelane para 67.
117 See De Vos, P (2010) On ‘Shoot the Boer’, hate speech and the banning of struggle songs 11.
118 (686/2018) [2019] ZASCA 167; [2020] 1 All SA 325 (SCA); 2020 (2) SA 124 (SCA); 2020 (3)
BCLR 334 (SCA) (29 November 2019) para 66 (Qwelane SCA).
119 Qwelane SCA para 66.
120 Qwelane SCA para 75.
121 South African Human Rights Commission v Velaphi Khumalo (EQ6-2016; EQ1-2018) [2018]
ZAGPJHC 528; 2019 (1) SA 289 (GJ); [2019] 1 All SA 254 (GJ) (5 October 2018) para 82.
122 Khumalo para 88.
123 (686/2018) [2019] ZASCA 167; [2020] 1 All SA 325 (SCA); 2020 (2) SA 124 (SCA); 2020 (3)
BCLR 334 (SCA) (29 November 2019).
124 Qwelane SCA para 64.
125 Qwelane SCA para 68.
126 Qwelane SCA para 45.
127 Qwelane SCA para 69.
128 Qwelane SCA para 88.
129 Qwelane SCA para 70.
130 (EQ02/2018) [2019] ZAEQC 2; [2019] 4 All SA 237 (EqC); 2019 (10) BCLR 1245 (EqC); 2019
(6) SA 327 (GJ) (21 August 2019).
131 Nelson Mandela Foundation Trust para 45.
132 Nelson Mandela Foundation Trust para 77–8.
133 Nelson Mandela Foundation Trust para 163.
134 Nelson Mandela Foundation Trust para 176.
135 Qwelane para 96.
136 Smuts, D and Westcott, S (eds) (1999) The Purple Shall Govern: A South African A to Z of
Nonviolent Action.
137 See Berger, JM (2001) Litigation strategies to gain access to treatment for HIV/AIDS: The
case of South Africa’s Treatment Action Campaign Wisconsin International Law Journal
20:595–614 at 596; Berger, JM and Kapczynski, A ‘The story of the TAC case: The potential
and limits of socio-economic rights litigation in South Africa’ in Hurwitz, DR and
Satterthwaite, ML (eds) (2009) Human Rights Advocacy Stories.
138 Berger and Kapczynski (2009) 4.
139 (CCT 112/11) [2012] ZACC 13; 2013 (1) SA 83 (CC); 2012 (8) BCLR 840 (CC) (13 June 2012)
para 61.
140 Woolman, S ‘Assembly, demonstration and petition’ in Currie, I and De Waal, J (2013) The
Bill of Rights Handbook 6th ed 377.
141 South African Transport and Allied Workers Union and Another v Garvas and Others (CCT
112/11) [2012] ZACC 13; 2013 (1) SA 83 (CC); 2012 (8) BCLR 840 (CC) (13 June 2012) para
61.
142 De Vos, P (2018) The constitutional limits of disruptive protest: the case of student protest
in South Africa Journal for Human Rights/Zeitschrift für Menschenrechte 51(4):64–86
143 Garvas para 52.
144 Garvas para 52.
145 (CCT27/98) [1999] ZACC 7; 1999 (4) SA 469 (CC); 1999 (6) BCLR 615 (CC) (26 May 1999).
146 South African National Defence Union para 8.
147 See for example Garvas para 63; Print Media South Africa and Another v Minister of Home
Affairs and Another (CCT 113/11); [2012] ZACC 22; 2012 (6) SA 443 (CC); 2012 (12) BCLR
1346 (CC) para 54; Khumalo and Others v Holomisa [2002] ZACC 12; 2002 (5) SA 401 (CC);
2002 (8) BCLR 771 (CC) para 24; and South African National Defence Union para 8.
148 BVerfGE 73, 206.
149 BVerfGE 73, 206 at 360.
150 BVerfGE 73, 206 at 361.
151 Rautenbach, IM and Malherbe, EFJ (2012) Constitutional Law 6th ed 376.
152 Rautenbach and Malherbe (2012) 376.
153 Act 205 of 1993.
154 S 1(v) of the Regulation of Gatherings Act.
155 S 1(vi) of the Regulation of Gatherings Act.
156 Woolman (2013) 386.
157 Growthpoint Properties Ltd v South African Commercial, Catering and Allied Workers
Union (SACAWU) and Others (6467/2010) [2010] ZAKZDHC 38; 2011 (1) BCLR 81 (KZD);
[2011] 1 All SA 537 (KZD); (2010) 31 ILJ 2539 (KZD) (3 September 2010).
158 Act 66 of 1995.
159 S 69(3) of the LRA.
160 (6467/2010) [2010] ZAKZDHC 38; 2011 (1) BCLR 81 (KZD); [2011] 1 All SA 537 (KZD);
(2010) 31 ILJ 2539 (KZD) (3 September 2010).
161 Growthpoint Properties para 46.
162 Growthpoint Properties paras 47–8.
163 Growthpoint Properties para 57.
164 Growthpoint Properties para 58.
165 Growthpoint Properties para 59.
166 Growthpoint Properties para 60.
167 Growthpoint Properties para 61.
168 Rautenbach and Malherbe (2012) 377.
169 See Free State Petitions Act 2 of 2008; Gauteng Petitions Act 5 of 2002; KwaZulu-Natal
Petitions Act 4 of 2003; Limpopo Petitions Act 4 of 2003; Mpumalanga Petitions Act 6 of
2000; Northern Cape Petitions Act 8 of 2009; North West Petitions Act 2 of 2010.
170 Act 17 of 1956.
171 Act 74 of 1982.
172 For a comprehensive discussion of the operation of the Regulation of Gatherings Act, see
Currie and De Waal (2013) 381–3.
173 S 9(2)(e) of the Gatherings Act. See also Memeza, M (2006) A critical review of the
implementation of the Regulation of Gatherings Act 205 of 1993: A local government and
civil society perspective available at http://www.fxi.org.za.
174 De Vos, P (2009) Freedom of assembly and its limits Constitutional Court: Without
Prejudice 9(8):4–5.
175 S 3(5)(c) of the Gatherings Act.
176 S 4(1) of the Gatherings Act.
177 S 4(4)(b) of the Gatherings Act.
178 S 4(4)(c) of the Gatherings Act.
179 (CCT32/18) [2018] ZACC 45; 2019 (1) BCLR 88 (CC); 2019 (1) SACR 429 (CC) (19 November
2018).
180 Mlungwana para 43.
181 Mlungwana para 47.
182 (CCT 112/11) [2012] ZACC 13; 2013 (1) SA 83 (CC); 2012 (8) BCLR 840 (CC) (13 June 2012).
183 Mhlungwana paras 62 and 63.
184 Mhlungwana para 80.
185 Mhlungwana para 93.
186 Mhlungwana para 101.
187 Duncan, J & Royeppen, A (2013) Inside Rustenberg’s banned protests, accessed 26 May
2020 at https://www.dailymaverick.co.za/article/2013-03-07-inside-rustenbergs-banned-
protests/.
188 Duncan & Royeppen (2013).
189 S 11(1).
190 (CCT 112/11) [2012] ZACC 13; 2013 (1) SA 83 (CC); 2012 (8) BCLR 840 (CC) (13 June 2012).
191 SATAWU para 37.
192 SATAWU para 38.
193 SATAWU para 39.
194 SATAWU para 43.
195 SATAWU paras 4–5.
196 SATAWU paras 51–9.
197 SATAWU paras 34 and 94.
198 New National Party v Government of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT9/99)
[1999] ZACC 5; 1999 (3) SA 191 (CC); 1999 (5) BCLR 489 (CC) (13 April 1999) para 10;
Minister of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime Prevention and the Re-Integration of
Offenders (NICRO) and Others (CCT 03/04) [2004] ZACC 10; 2005 (3) SA 280 (CC); 2004 (5)
BCLR 445 (CC) (3 March 2004) para 47; Ramakatsa and Others v Magashule and Others
(CCT 109/12) [2012] ZACC 31; 2013 (2) BCLR 202 (CC) (18 December 2012) para 64; New
Nation Movement NPC and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others
(CCT 110/19) [2020] ZACC 11; 2020 (8) BCLR 950 (CC) (11 June 2020) paras 106–108.
199 (CCT 109/12) [2012] ZACC 31; 2013 (2) BCLR 202 (CC) (18 December 2012) para 64.
200 Ramakatsa para 65.
201 In Richter v The Minister for Home Affairs and Others (CCT03/09, CCT 09/09) [2009] ZACC
3; 2009 (3) SA 615 (CC); 2009 (5) BCLR 448 (CC) (12 March 2009) and AParty and Another v
The Minister for Home Affairs and Others, Moloko and Others v The Minister for Home
Affairs and Another (CCT 06/09, CCT 10/09) [2009] ZACC 4; 2009 (3) SA 649 (CC); 2009 (6)
BCLR 611 (CC) (12 March 2009), the Constitutional Court was called on to determine the
voting rights of non-resident citizens.
202 Rautenbach and Malherbe (2012) 382.
203 Ramakatsa para 71. S 197(3) of the Constitution provides that no employee of the public
service may be favoured or prejudiced because he or she supports a particular political
party or cause.
204 Ramakatsa para 71.
205 Ramakatsa para 72.
206 New Nation Movement NPC and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and
Others (CCT 110/19) [2020] ZACC 11; 2020 (8) BCLR 950 (CC) (11 June 2020).
207 New Nation Movement para 17.
208 Ramakatsa para 73.
209 ANC National Disciplinary Committee (2012, 29 February) Luthuli House, Johannesburg:
Public Announcement on the Disciplinary Hearing of Floyd Shivambu, Sindiso Magaqa
and Julius Malema available at https://www.sahistory.org.za/archive/anc-national-
disciplinary-committee-29-february-2012-luthuli-house-johannesburg.
210 There are several references to political parties in the Constitution. For example, s 47(3)(c)
states that a member of the NA who ‘ceases to be a member of the party that nominated
that person as a member of the Assembly’ will lose his or her membership of the Assembly.
S 57(2)(b) similarly allows minority parties to participate in the proceedings of the NA in a
manner consistent with democracy.
211 Dube and Others v Zikalala and Others (7904/2016P) [2017] ZAKZPHC 36; [2017] 4 All SA
365 (KZP) (12 September 2017).
212 Dube para 34.
213 Dube para 129.
214 Act 73 of 1998.
215 Act 51 of 1996.
216 Ss 15, 16 and 17 of the Electoral Commission Act as well as ss 26–31 of the Electoral Act.
217 Ss 26(b) and 27 of the Electoral Act.
218 S 99 of the Electoral Act.
219 Liberal Party v The Electoral Commission and Others (CCT 10/04) [2004] ZACC 1; 2004 (8)
BCLR 810 (CC) (5 April 2004).
220 (CCT 10/06) [2006] ZACC 1; 2006(3) SA 305 (CC); 2006(5) BCLR 579 (CC) (24 February
2006) para 31.
221 Act 27 of 2000.
222 African Christian Democratic Party para 27.
223 African Christian Democratic Party para 21.
224 African Christian Democratic Party para 33.
225 Act 103 of 1997.
226 Lowry, MP (2008) Legitimizing elections through the regulation of campaign financing: A
comparative constitutional analysis and hope for South Africa Boston College International
and Comparative Law Review 31(2):185–212 at 185.
227 Steytler, N ‘The legislative framework governing party funding in South Africa’ in Matlosa, K
(2004) The Politics of State Resources: Party Funding in South Africa 59 and 64. For a
discussion regarding the funding of political parties, see generally Tshitereke, C (2002)
Securing democracy: Party finance and party donations – the South African challenge
Institute for Security Studies 63:1–12.
228 My Vote Counts NPC v Minister of Justice and Correctional Services and Others (CCT249/17)
[2018] ZACC 17; 2018 (5) SA 380 (CC); 2018 (8) BCLR 803 (CC) (21 June 2018).
229 424 U.S. 1 (1976) para 66.
230 My Vote Counts para 33.
231 My Vote Counts para 36.
232 My Vote Counts para 48.
233 My Vote Counts para 68.
234 My Vote Counts para 72.
235 My Vote Counts para 95.
236 Act 6 of 2018.
237 S 3 of the Political Party Funding Act.
238 S 8 of the Political Party Funding Act.
239 De Vos, P (2019, 12 February) Political Party Funding Act should be brought into operation
forthwith Constitutionally Speaking, available at
https://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/political-party-funding-act-should-be-brought-
into-operation-forthwith/.
240 (CCT9/99) [1999] ZACC 5; 1999 (3) SA 191 (CC); 1999 (5) BCLR 489 (CC) (13 April 1999).
New National Party para 12. In the same case the Constitutional Court also held that unlike
241
the right to vote, all South African citizens irrespective of their age have a right to free, fair
and regular elections (para 12).
242 New National Party para 118 where O’Regan stated: ‘Unlike some of the other rights in
chapter 2 of the Constitution, the primary obligation which s 19(2) and (3) impose upon
government is not a negative one, requiring government to refrain from conduct which
could cause an infringement of the right, but a positive one, requiring government to take
positive steps to ensure that the right is fulfilled.’
243 See New National Party paras 13–14; August and Another v Electoral Commission and
Others (CCT8/99) [1999] ZACC 3; 1999 (3) SA 1 (CC); 1999 (4) BCLR 363 (CC) (1 April 1999)
para 16; NICRO para 28; Richter para 54.
244 New National Party para 16.
245 S 181(3) provides that ‘[o]ther organs of state, through legislative and other measures, must
assist and protect [the Chapter Nine Institutions] to ensure the independence, impartiality,
dignity and effectiveness of these institutions’ and s 181(4) provides that ‘[n]o person or
organ of state may interfere with the functioning of [the Chapter Nine Institutions]’. The
Electoral Commission is also accountable to the NA, and must report on its activities and
the performance of its functions at least once a year (s 181(5)).
246 New National Party para 98.
247 New National Party para 99.
248 New National Party para 12.
249 (CCT8/99) [1999] ZACC 3; 1999 (3) SA 1 (CC); 1999 (4) BCLR 363 (CC) (1 April 1999).
250 S 5(1)(e) of the Electoral Commission Act.
251 August para 33.
252 Kham and Others v Electoral Commission and Another (CCT64/15) [2015] ZACC 37; 2016
(2) BCLR 157 (CC); 2016 (2) SA 338 (CC) (30 November 2015).
253 (CCT55/16) [2016] ZACC 15; 2016 (5) SA 1 (CC); 2016 (8) BCLR 987 (CC) (14 June 2016).
254 Mhlope para 109.
255 August para 17.
256 New National Party para 120.
257 (CCT03/09, CCT 09/09) [2009] ZACC 3; 2009 (3) SA 615 (CC); 2009 (5) BCLR 448 (CC) (12
March 2009) para 53.
258 In New National Party para 6, the Constitutional Court held that these three requirements
are derived from s 19(3) of the Constitution read together with s 46(1)(b) and 46(1)(c).
Section 46(1)(b) provides that ‘[t]he National Assembly consists of no fewer than 350 and
no more than 400 women and men elected as members in terms of an electoral system that
is based on the national common voters roll’ and s 46(1)(c) provides that ‘the National
Assembly consists of no fewer than 350 and no more than 400 women and men elected as
members in terms of an electoral system that provides for a minimum voting age of 18
years’.
259 New National Party para 15.
260 Rautenbach and Malherbe (2012) 89 fn 56.
261 The fact that prisoners who were serving life sentences without the option of a fine were
excluded from voting was declared unconstitutional by the Constitutional Court in NICRO.
262 The rendering of assistance by electoral officials at the request of a voter is also subject to
the secrecy of the vote. S 39 of the Electoral Act provides that assistance may be given to
voters who are unable to read, are blind or visually impaired. For a discussion of the plight
of the visually impaired, see generally Maseko, TW (2009) The right of blind and visually
impaired citizens to vote in secret: Is there a duty to do more? SA Public Law 24(2):623–39.
263 S 6(1) of the Electoral Act provides that ‘[a]ny South African citizen in possession of an
identity document may apply for registration as a voter’ and s 1 of the Act defines an
identity document as a bar-coded identity card issued in terms of the Identification Act 68
of 1997 or a temporary identification certificate issued in terms of the Identification Act.
264 New National Party para 19.
265 New National Party para 24.
266 New National Party para 26.
267 New National Party para 20.
268 New National Party para 23.
269 New National Party para 43.
270 New National Party para 122.
271 New National Party para 122.
272 See August; NICRO; Richter; AParty.
273 (CCT 03/04) [2004] ZACC 10; 2005 (3) SA 280 (CC); 2004 (5) BCLR 445 (CC) (3 March 2004).
274 The amendments to the Electoral Act effecting these limitations were made shortly before
the 2004 general election when Parliament passed the Electoral Laws Amendment Act 34 of
2003.
275 S 8(2)(f ) of the Electoral Act prohibited convicted prisoners who were ‘serving a sentence of
imprisonment without the option of a fine’ from registering as voters and s 24B(2)
prohibited convicted prisoners who were ‘serving a sentence of imprisonment without the
option of a fine’ and who were already on the voters’ roll from voting if they were in prison
on the day of the election.
276 Act 34 of 2003.
277 NICRO para 16.
278 NICRO para 49.
279 2002 SCC 68.
280 NICRO para 58.
281 NICRO para 66.
282 NICRO para 67.
283 Richter para 56.
284 Richter para 57.
285 Richter para 68.
286 Richter para 69.
287 Richter para 76.
288 Richter para 77.
289 Richter para 78.
290 New Nation Movement para 5.
291 New Nation Movement para 100.
292 New Nation Movement para 120.
293 New Nation Movement paras 16–19.
294 New Nation Movement paras 20–24.
295 New Nation Movement para 17.
296 New Nation Movement para 18.
297 New Nation Movement para 19.
298 New Nation Movement para 22.
299 New Nation Movement paras 30–46.
300 New Nation Movement paras 48–9.
301 New Nation Movement para 52.
302 New Nation Movement para 60.
303 New Nation Movement para 63.
304 New Nation Movement para 89.
305 New Nation Movement paras 96–9.
306 New Nation Movement paras 113–20.
307 New Nation Movement para 125.
Constitutional property law
16.1 Introduction
Summary
16.1 Introduction
The modern history of South Africa is dominated by the conquest and
dispossession of black South Africans of their land by the colonial and
apartheid states. This process had a devastating effect on their lives. It
deprived black people, not only of their land, but also of their
communities, their homes, their livelihoods, their way of life and
ultimately their dignity and sense of belonging. A pivotal moment in the
history of land dispossession came shortly after the formation of the
Union of South Africa, with the passing of the Natives Land Act1 in 1913.
The Act allocated only approximately 8% of arable land to black South
Africans and left the remaining 82% of usually more fertile arable land
for whites. It also created reserves for black South Africans and
prohibited the sale of territory in white areas to blacks and vice versa.
Sol Plaatje eloquently summed up the effect of this Act when he stated –
after it came into operation – that ‘Awakening on Friday morning, June
20, 1913, the South African native found himself, not actually a slave,
but a pariah in the land of his birth’.2 A further pivotal development
occurred when the apartheid regime decided in the 1950s to move all
black people from areas partly occupied by white people or situated
close to areas where white people lived. These forced removals were
coupled with the policy of keeping black people out of ‘white’ urban
areas, unless they were employed there. Many people were
dispossessed of their land during these forced removals, including
people who lived in Sophiatown in Johannesburg and District Six in
Cape Town.
[15] The effects of this Act are well known to many South
Africans:
[16] The purpose of it all was, first, the obvious one of making
more land available to white farmers. The second “was to
impoverish black people through dispossession and prohibition of
forms of farming arrangements that permitted some self-
sufficiency. This meant they depended on employment for survival,
thus creating a pool of cheap labour for the white farms and the
mines. White farmers had repeatedly complained that African
people refused to work for them as servants and labourers”. The
third was the enforcement of the policy of racial segregation,
which assumed heightened proportions during the apartheid era.
“The baas exacted from him the services of himself, his wife
and his oxen, for wages of 30 shilling a month, whereas
Kgobadi had been making £100 a year, besides retaining the
services of his wife and of his cattle for himself. When he
refused the extortionate terms, the baas retaliated [by
requiring] him to betake himself from the farm … by sunset of
the same day, failing which his stock would be seized and
impounded, and himself handed over to the authorities for
trespassing on the farm.”
It is in this context that Mostert points out that ‘the South African
property clause is characterised by inherent tension between its
dichotomously protective and reformative aspects’.5 In an attempt to
provide a legal analysis of the property clause, one simply must be
mindful of the fact that you are constantly required to consider this
tension between the needs of the ‘haves’ and the ‘have-nots’.
With this in mind, this chapter will provide an overview of the
constitutional framework governing land and land matters in South
Africa. The legal framework governing section 25 will be analysed with
the view to understanding the constitutional property clause in context.
Furthermore, the chapter will examine key aspects of constitutional
property law, such as:
1. the fact that private property is negatively protected in terms of
section 25 and the implications of that point of departure for
property protection under the property clause;
2. the distinction between deprivation and expropriation of property,
which distinction is not always articulated clearly by South African
courts and remains a notoriously contentious issue;
3. the requirement of compensation for expropriation, which is
perhaps one of the most contested issues in modern South African
property law; and, finally,
4. the importance of land reform as a tool to ensure a more equitable
distribution of land in South Africa.
This latter section will focus on framing the historical context within
which any discussion of land should be understood in South Africa. In
this regard, it is crucial to understand dispossession of African land by
the colonial and apartheid states in order to understand why land
reform is an integral part of the South African property clause. These are
some of the pertinent issues that are applicable in the context of
constitutional property law currently and will be elaborated on in this
chapter.
As Roux points out, instead of resolving the conflict between the right to
property in section 25 and the right to housing in section 26 by
privileging ownership over the right not to be dispossessed of a home,
the Constitutional Court in Port Elizabeth Municipality sought to
reconcile the two rights by adopting a ‘context-sensitive balancing’
approach.24 This context-sensitive balancing approach, he points out
further, is not aimed at providing a thorough theory on the
Constitution’s property rights morality, but rather at installing an ethic
of compassion in the courts and other organs of state that are
responsible for mediating competing property interests. This means
that ‘s[ection] 26(3) may be said to have created a new form of property
right, one that does not provide an absolute barrier against eviction, but
which rather requires the courts to treat common-law ownership rights
and the right not to arbitrarily be evicted from one’s home in a non-
hierarchical way.’25 This is an important insight into the contextual
nature of the property clause and the particular understanding of the
negative phraseology of the provision. In resolving property disputes in
the constitutional dispensation, a context-sensitive approach may
require giving due cognisance to other, non-property rights, if these
rights are implicated.
The context-sensitive balancing approach was also applied by the
Constitutional Court in Daniels v Scribante and Another.26 In this case,
the applicant, Mrs Daniels, worked and lived on a farm together with
her family. She wanted to make basic improvements to her dwelling in
order to bring it up to a habitable standard, at her own cost. These
improvements included levelling the floors, paving part of the outside
area, and installing an indoor water supply, a wash basin, a second
window and a ceiling.
After she started making these improvements, Mrs Daniels received
a letter from the respondent, Mr Scribante, who was the farm manager,
ordering her to stop the work. Despite conceding that the living
quarters were not fit for human habitation, Mr Scribante and the farm
owners claimed that the improvements Mrs Daniels was making were
unlawful because she did not first obtain their permission.
In response to this letter, Mrs Daniels argued that the Extension of
Security of Tenure Act27 (ESTA) granted her both the right to reside on
the farm28 as well as the right to dignity29 and that, read together, these
provisions gave her the right to make improvements without first
obtaining permission. In their reply, Mr Scribante and the farm owners
argued that ESTA does not explicitly provide occupiers with a right to
improve the property in which they live and, consequently, that no such
right existed.
The Constitutional Court found in favour of Mrs Daniels. In arriving
at this decision, it held that Mr Scribante and the farm owner’s
argument was ‘unduly narrow’. ESTA, the Court held, is aimed, not only
at giving effect to section 25(6) of the Constitution, but also at
addressing the egregious history of African land dispossession in South
Africa. It must, therefore, be interpreted as providing an occupier of
land with the right to make improvements to the dwelling in which he
or she lives.30
To hold otherwise, could strip the rights conferred on occupiers of
their substance. Specifically, while the right enjoyed by an occupier
could – on paper – be viewed as no more than a right to reside on and
use the land in issue, the section must be interpreted purposively to
give it a broader meaning. As Madlanga J explained:
An occupier who lives on property under the most deplorable conditions does
‘reside’ on that property. But is that the right conferred by ESTA? Definitely not.
The occupier’s right to reside must be consonant with the fundamental rights
contained in section 5 [of ESTA], in particular – for present purposes – the right
to human dignity. Put differently, the occupation is not simply about a roof
over the occupier’s head. Yes, it is about that. But it is about more than just that.
It is about occupation that conduces to human dignity and … other
fundamental rights.31
In any event, if occupiers were not allowed to upgrade their dwellings, this
could lead to eviction by stealth by property owners. ‘This would be a direct
result of the intolerability of conditions on the dwelling. And these “evictions”
might happen beneath the radar of the carefully crafted eviction process. That
would make nonsense of the very idea of security of tenure [guaranteed by the
Constitution]’.32
After all, like the notion of ‘reside’, security of tenure must mean that the
dwelling has to be habitable. That in turn connotes making whatever
improvements that are reasonably necessary to achieve this. Of what use is a
dwelling if it is uninhabitable? None.33
Apart from the fact that ESTA does not explicitly provide occupiers with
a right to improve the property in which they live, Mr Scribante and the
farm owners advanced a second argument. In this respect, they argued
that the right to reside on the farm should not be interpreted as
including the right to make improvements, because such an
interpretation would indirectly place a positive obligation on a farm
owner to give effect to section 25(6) of the Constitution.34
The reason why such an interpretation would indirectly place a
positive obligation on a farm owner to give effect to section 25(6) is
because section 13 of ESTA provides that a court may order a farm
owner to pay compensation for improvements made by an occupier
when that occupier is evicted. A farm owner, therefore, could
potentially be forced to pay for improvements even though he or she
had refused to give permission for those improvements to be made.35
The Constitutional Court rejected this argument. It held that the
provisions of the Bill of Rights – including section 25(6) – could, in
certain circumstances, bind private land owners and thus place a
financial obligation on a farm owner to reimburse an occupier who had
made improvements on his or her dwelling.
By its very nature, the duty imposed by the right to security of tenure, in both
the negative and positive form, does rest on private persons. People requiring
protection under ESTA more often than not live on land owned by private
persons. Unsurprisingly, that is the premise from which this matter is being
litigated. And I dare say the obligation resting, in particular, on an owner is a
positive one. A private person is enjoined by section 25(6) of the Constitution
through ESTA to accommodate another on her or his land. It is so that the
obligation is also negative in the sense that the occupier’s right should not be
‘improperly invaded’.36
(a) where the land is not being used and the owner’s main purpose is not to
develop the land or use it to generate income, but to benefit from
appreciation of its market value;
(b) where an organ of state holds land that it is not using for its core functions
and is not reasonably likely to require the land for its future activities in
that regard, and the organ of state acquired the land for no consideration;
(c) notwithstanding registration of ownership in terms of the Deeds Registries
Act, 1937 …, where an owner has abandoned the land by failing to exercise
control over it;
(d) where the market value of the land is equivalent to, or less than, the
present value of direct state investment or subsidy in the acquisition and
beneficial capital improvement of the land; and
(e) when the nature or condition of the property poses a health, safety or
physical risk to persons or other property.
SUMMARY
Apart from being the longest right in the Bill of Rights, section 25 of the
Constitution is also the most complex and controversial. This is because
it has been allocated the unenviable task of reconciling two conflicting
goals. On the one hand, section 25 is aimed at protecting existing
private property rights and thus has the potential to entrench the
unequal distribution of property in South Africa and, consequently, to
preserve white privilege. On the other hand, section 25 is aimed at
remedying the dispossession of African land during the colonial and
apartheid eras and thus has the potential to perpetrate new injustices,
to promote conflict and to undermine confidence in the legal and
economic system.
As this chapter demonstrates, the Constitutional Court has sought to
reconcile these two goals in a number of different ways. Among the
most important of these are the following:
• First, the Court has redefined the common law concept of
ownership in a manner that emphasises the obligations the right of
ownership imposes on an owner and not only the entitlements or
powers. An important consequence of this approach is that property
rights may no longer be viewed as absolute or unrestricted. Instead,
they must now be understood as inherently limited or restricted
rights. In its judgment in Daniels, the Court took this approach a
step further when it found that property clause imposes both
negative and positive obligations on an owner.
• Second, the Court has adopted a variable test for determining
whether a deprivation of property is arbitrary or not and thus
reserved for itself a wide discretion to decide each constitutional
property dispute on a case-by-case basis. The variable test adopted
by the Court in FNB provides that in some cases a deprivation
simply has to be rational, while in others it has to be proportional or
at least close to proportional. When it comes to determining which
standard must be applied, however, a multiplicity of relations and a
number of factors must be taken into account, including the nature
of the right, the nature of the property and the extent of the
deprivation.
• Third, the Court has adopted a narrow definition of expropriation as
the compulsory acquisition of property by the state. An important
consequence of this approach is that the circumstances in which the
state is required to pay compensation for expropriating property are
narrow. It is not required to pay compensation when it takes away
property, but only when it takes away and also acquires that
property. Despite reducing the compensatory burden that section
25 imposes on the state, this obligation has proved to be very
controversial. This is because it is not entirely clear in which
circumstances the state is entitled to pay less than market value
compensation or even nil compensation. In order to address this
uncertainty, the National Assembly has resolved to amend section
25 to expressly provide for the payment in nil compensation in those
circumstances identified in national legislation. These amendments
and their likely consequences are also explored in this chapter.
1 Act 27 of 1913.
2 Plaatje, ST (2007) Native Life in South Africa: Past and Present 21.
3 (CCT50/16) [2017] ZACC 13; 2017 (4) SA 341 (CC); 2017 (8) BCLR 949 (CC) (11 May 2017).
4 See Van der Walt, AJ (2011) Constitutional Property Law 3rd ed 1–2.
5 Mostert, H (2010) Engaged citizenship and the enabling state as factors determining the
interference parameter of property: A comparison of German and South African law South
African Law Journal 127(2):238–73 at 239.
6 Section 28 of the interim Constitution provided that ‘(1) every person shall have the right to
acquire and hold rights in property and, to the extent that the nature of the rights permits,
to dispose of such rights. (2) No deprivation of any rights in property shall be permitted
otherwise than in accordance with a law. (3) Where any rights in property are expropriated
pursuant to a law referred to in subsection (2), such expropriation shall be permissible for
public purposes only and shall be subject to the payment of agreed compensation or,
failing agreement, to the payment of such compensation and within such period as may be
determined by a court of law as just and equitable, taking into account all relevant factors,
including, in the case of the determination of compensation, the use to which the property
is being put, the history of its acquisition, its market value, the value of the investments in it
by those affected and the interests of those affected’. See further Van der Walt (2011) 17.
7 Van der Walt (2011) 34–42; Currie, I and De Waal, J (2013) The Bill of Rights handbook 6th
ed 534.
8 This idea that ownership of property is absolute has been contested for many years. Many
property theorists have contributed substantially to the debates around a changed idea of
ownership in modern times. For some of these contributions, see Visser, DP (1985) The
“absoluteness” of ownership: The South African common law in perspective Acta Juridica
39–52; Birks, P (1985) The Roman law concept of dominium and the idea of absolute
ownership Acta Juridica 1–38; Van der Walt, AJ and Kleyn, DG ‘Duplex dominium: The
history and significance of the concept of divided ownership’ in Visser, DP (ed) (1989)
Essays on the History of Law 213–14; Van der Walt, AJ and Dhliwayo, P (2017) The notion of
absolute and exclusive ownership: A doctrinal analysis South African Law Journal
134(1):34–52; Dhliwayo, P (2015) A constitutional analysis of access rights that limit
landowners’ right to exclude (unpublished LLD dissertation Stellenbosch University 2015);
Van der Walt, AJ (2015) Sharing servitudes European Property LJ 4(3):162–222. However, it
should be noted that the constitutional notion of ‘property’ is in any event wider than the
private law concept of ownership. See Reflect-All 1025 CC and Others v MEC for Public
Transport, Roads and Works, Gauteng Provincial Government and Another (CCT 110/08)
[2009] ZACC 24; 2009 (6) SA 391 (CC); 2010 (1) BCLR 61 (CC) (27 August 2009) para 32;
Shoprite Checkers (Pty) Ltd v MEC for Economic Development, Eastern Cape and Others
(CCT 216/14) [2015] ZACC 23; 2015 (6) SA 125 (CC); 2015 (9) BCLR 1052 (CC) (30 June
2015) para 104. See also Rautenbach, IM (2015) Dealing with the social dimensions of
property Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 825–29; Van der Walt, AJ (2016) Section 25
vortices (part 1) Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 3:412–27 at 416–19; Van der, AJ Walt
(2016) Section 25 vortices (part 2) Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 4:597–621 at 599–
605; Marais, EJ (2016) Expanding the contours of the constitutional property concept
Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 576–92; Swanepoel, J (2016) Constitutional property
law in Central Eastern European jurisdictions: A comparative analysis (unpublished LLD
dissertation Stellenbosch University 2016) 211–20; Badenhorst, P and Young, C (2017) The
notion of constitutional property in South Africa: An analysis of the Constitutional Court’s
approach in Shoprite Checkers (Pty) Ltd v MEC for Economic Development, Eastern Cape
2015 (6) SA 125 (CC) Stellenbosch Law Review 28(1):26–46 at 40–5; Du Plessis, M and
Palmer, T (2018) Property rights and their continued open-endedness – A critical
discussion of Shoprite and the Constitutional Court’s property clause jurisprudence
Stellenbosch Law Review 29(1):73–89 at 86–7.
9 Singer, J (2000) The edges of the field: Lessons on the Obligations of Ownership 76.
10 Van der Walt, AJ ‘The future of common law landownership’ in Van der Walt, AJ (ed) Land
reform and the future of landownership in South Africa (1991) 21–35 at 31; Van der Walt, AJ
(1992) Roman-Dutch and environmental land-use control South African Public Law
1(11):4; Van der Walt, AJ (1992) The South African law of ownership: A historical and
philosophical perspective De Jure 25:446–457 at 447.
11 Johannesburg Municipal Council v Rand Townships Registrar and Others 1910 TS 1314
1319; Chetty v Naidoo 1974 (3) SA 13 (A) 20; Gien v Gien 1979 (2) SA 1113 (T) 1120.
12 Rand Townships Registrar 1319.
13 Dhliwayo, P (2015) A constitutional analysis of access rights that limit landowners’ right to
exclude (LLB, Stellenbosch University 2015) 95.
14 Van der Walt, AJ and Dhliwayo, P (2017) The notion of absolute and exclusive ownership: A
doctrinal analysis South African Law Journal 134(1):49.
15 Van der Walt, AJ (1999) Property rights and hierarchies of power: a critical evaluation of
land-reform policy in South Africa Koers: Bulletin for Christian Scholarship 64(2/3):259–94
at 261–3.
16 Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers (CCT 53/03) [2004] ZACC 7; 2005 (1) SA
217 (CC); 2004 (12) BCLR 1268 (CC) (1 October 2004).
17 Act 19 of 1998.
18 S 6(1) of PIE.
19 S 6(3)(a) of PIE.
20 S 6(3)(b) of PIE.
21 S 6(3)(c) of PIE.
22 Port Elizabeth Municipality para 59.
23 Port Elizabeth Municipality para 23.
24 Roux, T (2013) The politics of principle: The first South African Constitutional Court, 1995–
2005 327. Roux mentions that other judgments in the context of property rights also show
the same trend, for example First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Commissioner,
South African Revenue Service; First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Minister of
Finance (CCT19/01) [2002] ZACC 5; 2002 (4) SA 768 (CC); 2002 (7) BCLR 702 (CC) (16 May
2002) and Government of the Republic of South Africa and Others v Grootboom and Others
(CCT11/00) [2000] ZACC 19; 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC); 2000 (11) BCLR 1169 (CC) (4 October
2000).
25 Roux (2013) 326.
26 (CCT50/16) [2017] ZACC 13; 2017 (4) SA 341 (CC); 2017 (8) BCLR 949 (CC) (11 May 2017).
27 Act 62 of 1997.
28 S 6 of ESTA.
29 S 5 of ESTA.
30 Daniels para 23.
31 Daniels para 31.
32 Daniels para 32.
33 Daniels para 32.
34 Daniels para 37.
35 Daniels para 37.
36 Daniels para 49.
37 Daniels para 136.
38 Daniels para 137.
39 Singer (2000) 10.
40 Singer (2000) 10–11.
41 Singer (2000) 36–7.
42 Singer (2000) 27.
43 Singer (2000) 17.
44 Singer (2000) 36.
45 Singer (2000) 32.
46 Underkuffler, LS (2003) The idea of property: Its Meaning and Power 3.
47 Daniels para 36.
48 First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Commissioner, South African Revenue Service
and Another; First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Minister of Finance (CCT 19/01)
[2002] ZACC 5; 2002 (4) SA 768 (CC); 2002 (7) BCLR 702 (CC) para 46.
49 First National Bank para 57.
50 First National Bank para 60.
51 First National Bank para 58.
52 First National Bank para 59.
53 For an exposition of the distinction between deprivations and expropriations, see Harksen
v Lane NO (CCT 9/97) [1997] ZACC 12; 1998 (1) SA 300 (CC); 1997 ( 11) BCLR 1489 (CC)
para 33; First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Commissioner, South African Revenue
Service and Another; First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Minister of Finance (CCT
19/01) [2002] ZACC 5; 2002 (4) SA 768 (CC); 2002 (7) BCLR 702 (CC) para 46. See further
Van der Walt, AJ (2004) Striving for a better interpretation – A critical reflection on the
Constitutional Court’s Harksen and FNB decisions on the property clause South African
Law Journal 121:854–878 873; Van der Walt, AJ (2005) Retreating from the FNB arbitrariness
test already? Mkontwana v Nelson Mandela Metropolitan Municipality; Bissett v Buffalo
City Municipality; Transfer Rights Action Campaign v MEC for Local Government and
Housing, Gauteng South African Law Journal 123:75–89 77; Van der Walt, AJ (2011)
Constitutional property law 3rd ed 339–341; Marais, EJ (2015) When does state interference
with property (now) amount to expropriation? An analysis of the Agri SA court’s state
acquisition requirement (Part I) Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal 18(29):2982–3031
2985.
54 Van der Walt (2011) 347. See also Slade, BV (2016) Compensation for what? An analysis of
the outcome in Arun Property Development (Pty) Ltd v Cape Town City PELJ 19:1–25 20;
Marais, EJ and Maree, PJH (2016) At the intersection between expropriation law and
administrative law: Two critical views on the Constitutional Court’s Arun judgment PELJ
19:1–54 (especially footnote 76); Van Wyk, J (2016) Planning and Arun’s (not so straight and
narrow) roads PELJ 19:1–29 17.
55 Van der Walt (2011) 351.
56 Slade (2016) 1–25 20.
57 2002 (4) SA 786 (CC).
58 If the FNB methodology is followed strictly, the consequence will be that the arbitrary
deprivation (or deprivation that has excessive effects) will be declared invalid. See Van der
Walt (2011) 272; Bezuidenhout, K (2014) Compensation for excessive but otherwise lawful
regulatory state action (unpublished LLD dissertation) Stellenbosch University 44.
59 Bezuidenhout (2014) 251
60 Dugard, J and Seme, N (2018) Property rights in court: an examination of judicial attempts
to settle section 25’s balancing act re restitution and expropriation South African Journal on
Human Rights 34:1, 33–56.
61 Dugard and Seme (2018) 43–44.
62 Dugard and Seme 44.
63 First National Bank.
64 First National Bank para 57.
65 First National Bank para 57.
66 (CCT 57/03) [2004] ZACC 9; 2005 (1) SA 530 (CC); 2005 (2) BCLR 150 (CC) (6 October 2004).
67 Mkontwana v Nelson Mandela Metropolitan Municipality and Another; Bissett and Others v
Buffalo city Municipality and others; Transfer Rights Action Campaign v Member of the
Executive Council for Local Government and Housing and Others (CCT 57/03) [2004] ZACC
9; 2005 (1) SA 530 (CC); 2005 (2) BCLR 150 (CC) (6 October 2004) para 32.
68 2011 (1) SA 293 (CC) paras 38–46.
69 Offit Enterprises (Pty) Ltd and Another v Coega Development Corporation (Pty) Ltd and
Others (CCT 15/10) [2010] ZACC 20; 2011 (1) SA 293 (CC); 2011 (2) BCLR 189 (CC) (18
November 2010) para 44.
70 See Van der Walt (2011) 203–209.
71 Van der Walt (2011) 209–13.
72 Roux, T ‘Property’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) Constitutional law of South Africa
2nd ed rev service 5 (2003) chap 46 at 46-2 – 46-5, 46-18, 46-23 – 46-25.
73 (CCT234/16) [2017] ZACC 26; 2017 (6) SA 331 (CC); 2017 (10) BCLR 1303 (CC) (24 July
2017).
74 Act 56 of 1986.
75 South African Diamond Producers Organisation v Minister of Minerals and Energy NO and
Others (CCT234/16) [2017] ZACC 26; 2017 (6) SA 331 (CC); 2017 (10) BCLR 1303 (CC) (24
July 2017) para 42 relying on Mkontwana para 32.
76 South African Diamond Producers para 43.
77 Offit Enterprises para 41.
78 (CCT184/14) [2015] ZACC 29; 2015 (6) SA 440 (CC); 2015 (11) BCLR 1265 (CC) (23
September 2015).
79 City of Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality v Link Africa (Pty) Ltd and Others (CCT184/14)
[2015] ZACC 29; 2015 (6) SA 440 (CC); 2015 (11) BCLR 1265 (CC) (23 September 2015) para
167.
80 Link Africa paras 163–73.
81 South African Diamond Producers para 47.
82 Van der Walt (2011) 209.
83 1999 (2) BCLR 204 (T) 221.
84 Act 71 of 1988.
85 2000 (2) BCLR 151 (C) para 82.
86 Act 76 of 1996.
87 (CCT 110/08) [2009] ZACC 24; 2009 (6) SA 391 (CC); 2010 (1) BCLR 61 (CC) (27 August
2009).
88 S 118(1) of the Act limits the owner’s power to transfer his immovable property in so far as
the registrar of deeds is prohibited from effecting the transfer without a certificate from the
municipality. The certificate will be issued once all consumption charges due for a period
of two years before the date of issue of the certificate have been paid.
89 Mkontwana para 65.
90 Mkontwana para 66.
91 Mkontwana paras 66–7.
92 Act 8 of 2001.
93 Reflect-All para 40 relying on Mkontwana para 65.
94 Reflect-All paras 46–7.
95 Van der Walt (2011) 264–70.
96 Act 3 of 2000.
97 Van der Walt (2011) 264–70; Van der Walt, AJ (2012) Procedurally arbitrary deprivation of
property Stellenbosch Law Review 23(1):88–94; Van der Sijde, E Reconsidering the
relationship between property and regulation: A systemic approach (unpublished LLD
dissertation Stellenbosch University 2015) 121–27.
98 Van der Walt (2011) 267.
99 Van der Sijde (2015) 124.
100 Act 91 of 1964.
101 See Mkontwana para 51. See also Van der Walt (2011) 250.
102 See FNB para 65. See also Van der Walt (2011) 244.
103 FNB para 100.
104 (74195/2013; 13039/2014; 13040/2014; 19552/2015; 23826/2014) [2016] ZAGPPHC 941;
[2017] 1 All SA 585 (GP); 2017 (2) SA 295 (GP) (7 November 2016).
105 Act 32 of 2000.
106 Jordaan and Another v City of Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality and Others; New
Ventures Consulting and Services (Pty) Ltd and Others v City of Tshwane Metropolitan
Municipality and Another; Livanos and Others v Ekurhuleni Metropolitan Municipality and
Another; Oak Plant Rentals (Pty) Ltd and Others v Ekurhuleni Metropolitan Municipality
(74195/2013; 13039/2014; 13040/2014; 19552/2015; 23826/2014) [2016] ZAGPPHC 941;
[2017] 1 All SA 585 (GP); 2017 (2) SA 295 (GP) (7 November 2016) para 24. It should be
noted that the North Gauteng High Court, Pretoria, held that in so far as section 118(3) of
the Municipal Systems Act is a charge on the land that can be enforced against subsequent
(or new) owners for debts incurred by previous owners, the provision was unconstitutional.
The High Court assumed that s 118(3) can be interpreted in such a way that it is enforceable
against new owners, and, on that basis, it was declared unconstitutional. The
Constitutional Court was required, in line with s 167(5) of the Constitution, to confirm or
deny a High Court decision. See Jordaan and Others v City of Tshwane Metropolitan
Municipality and Others; City of Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality v New Ventures
Consulting and Services (Pty) Limited and Others; Ekurhuleni Metropolitan Municipality v
Livanos and Others (CCT283/16, CCT293/16, CCT294/16, CCT283/16) [2017] ZACC 31;
2017 (6) SA 287 (CC); 2017 (11) BCLR 1370 (CC) (29 August 2017). The discussion in this
chapter refers mostly to the High Court decision, which was essentially confirmed by the
Constitutional Court, because the analysis of the deprivation issue is more elaborate in the
High Court judgment.
107 Jordaan para 30.
108 Jordaan paras 31–2.
109 Jordaan para 32. Therefore, although ownership entails certain responsibilities, even in
relation to debts incurred by tenants, the same responsibility that rests on current owners
for debts incurred by tenants in relation to property, cannot easily be placed upon future
owners (or subsequent owners) who purchase property that has historical debts.
Interestingly, the Court shifted the responsibility for the recovery of historical debts onto
the municipality and held that ‘it is not only possible but also desirable for a municipality
to prevent the accumulation of historical debts by taking responsible action before the
property is transferred into the name of a subsequent or new owner’. This is the case
because the new owners have no way of ensuring that the previous owners or tenants acted
in a responsible manner, or ensuring appropriate tenants were chosen, or that proper
agreements were concluded between the previous owners and tenants. They also have no
way of managing or controlling the indebtedness of their predecessors in title. The
municipality would have been in a much better position to manage the situation. In fact,
the Court stressed that such an obligation rests on the municipality by virtue of s 96 of the
Municipal Systems Act, which requires the municipality to recover all outstanding debts
payable to it. See Jordaan para 34. See also Brits, R (2014) The statutory security right in
section 118(3) of the Local Government: Municipal Systems Act 32 of 2000 – does it survive
transfer of the land? [Discussion of City of Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality v
Mathabathe 2013 4 SA 319 (SCA)] Stellenbosch Law Review 25(3):536–46.
110 Jordaan para 38.
111 First National Bank para 108.
112 Jordaan para 38.
113 Jordaan para 39.
114 Siphuma, S The lessor’s tacit hypothec: A constitutional analysis (unpublished LLM thesis
Stellenbosch University 2013) chapter 4; Viljoen, S The law of landlord and tenant (2016)
320–34.
115 Act 91 of 1964.
116 Siphuma (2013) 81.
117 Van der Walt, AJ (2017) Property law in the constitutional democracy Stellenbosch Law
Review 28(1):8–25. See also Kiewitz, L Relocation of a specified servitude of right of way
(unpublished LLM thesis Stellenbosch University 2010); Van der Walt, AJ and Marais, EJ
(2012) The constitutionality of acquisitive prescription: A section 25 analysis Tydskrif vir die
Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 714–36; Boggenpoel, ZT (2013) The decision to order transfer of
encroached-upon land: A constitutional analysis Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-
Hollandse Reg 76:1–15; Van der Walt, AJ and Raphulu, TN (2014) The right of way of
necessity: A constitutional analysis Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg
77:468–84.
118 First National Bank para 57. See also Currie and De Waal (2013) 534.
119 First National Bank paras 60, 100. See also Van der Walt (2011) 219–20, 247.
120 First National Bank para 60. See also Van der Walt, AJ (2011) Constitutional Property Law
Juta’s Quarterly Review 3:2.2.1, where Van der Walt indicates that the Court failed to
recognise the academic argument of Roux in terms of which an expropriation that has
passed the non-arbitrariness test of s 25(1) cannot seriously still be questioned for non-
compliance with s 25(2) or (3). It may have been interesting and crucial in this regard to see
whether the expropriation would have passed the scrutiny of s 25(1) in terms of the non-
arbitrariness test if the Court had been more thorough in its s 25(1) analysis. Perhaps it
would not have made a difference, but even then the fact that it would not have made a
difference influences the academic argument surrounding Roux’s contention substantially.
Therefore, the fact that the Court did not give any recognition to the arbitrariness vortex
argument when interpreting s 25 (and purportedly following the FNB methodology) casts
doubt on the court’s interpretation of s 25(1).
121 [B23–2020].
122 See clause 1 of the draft Expropriation Bill [B23–2020].
123 (CCT 51/12) [2013] ZACC 9; 2013 (4) SA 1 (CC); 2013 (7) BCLR 727 (CC) (18 April 2013).
124 Agri SA para 48.
125 Agri SA para 59.
126 Agri SA para 58 (our emphasis added).
127 Act 28 of 2002. Agri SA para 68.
128 Agri SA para 68.
129 For a comprehensive discussion of compensation for expropriation, see Du Plessis, WJ
Compensation for Expropriation under the Constitution (unpublished LLD dissertation
Stellenbosch University 2009); Van der Walt (2011) 503–20. See also Iyer, D (2012) Is the
determination of compensation a pre-requisite for the constitutional validity of
expropriation? Haffejee NO and Others v Ethekwini Municipality and Others Speculum Juris
2:66–74; Du Plessis, WJ ‘The public purpose requirement in the calculation of just and
equitable compensation’ in Hoops B et al (eds) Rethinking Expropriation Law I: Public
Interest in Expropriation (2016) 369–87; Van Wyk, J (2017) Compensation for land reform
expropriation Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 21–35.
130 In Nhlabathi and Others v Fick 2003 (7) BCLR 806 (LCC) the Land Claims Court mentioned
that in instances where ‘[n]o provision is made for any compensation to the landowner’
(para 26) there may be several repercussions, namely: ‘It could be that the provision
contains an implied right to compensation, or that the court might have to read such a right
into the provision, or that sections 25(2) and (3) of the Constitution provide a right to
compensation. Where an obligation to pay compensation is incompatible with the essence
of the permitted expropriation, it could be that the authorizing statutory provision is
invalid. It could also be that the absence of a right to compensation is justifiable under
section 36 of the Constitution’ (para 32).
131 Van der Walt (2011) 509; T Roux ‘Property’ in S Woolman, T Roux and M Bishop (eds)
(2003) Constitutional law of South Africa vol 3 2nd ed OS ch 46 34–6.
132 Van der Walt (2011) 509.
133 Act 63 of 1975.
134 See s 12 of the Expropriation Act 63 of 1975. See also Van der Walt (2011) 513.
135 Du Plessis (2015) 369–87; Van Wyk (2017) 21–35 at 35.
136 2016 (5) SA 513 (LCC). For a discussion of the judgment, see Slade, BV (2016)
Constitutional property law JQR 3:para 2.1.
137 Msiza v Director-General, Department of Rural Development and Land Reform 2016 (5) SA
513 (LCC) para 47.
138 S 25(2)(a) of the Constitution. For an extensive doctrinal analysis of the meaning of the
public purpose/public interest requirement for expropriation, see Slade, BV The
justification of expropriation for economic development (unpublished LLD dissertation
Stellenbosch University 2012) 57–131. See also Slade, BV (2013) The less invasive means
argument in expropriation law Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 199–216; Slade, BV
(2014) “Public purpose or public interest” and third party transfers Potchefstroom
Electronic Law Journal 17:166–206; Slade, BV ‘Less invasive means: The relationship
between sections 25 and 36 of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996’ in
Hoops, B et al (eds) (2015) Rethinking Expropriation Law I: Public Interest in Expropriation
331–48.
139 Harvey v Umhlatuze Municipality and Others (4387/08) [2010] ZAKZPHC 86; 2011 (1) SA
601 (KZP); 2011 (4) BCLR 379 (KZP) (3 December 2010) para 82; Slade (2012) 3.
140 (458/2011) [2012] ZASCA 93; 2012 (5) SA 1 (SCA); [2012] 3 All SA 266 (SCA); 2012 (9) BCLR
958 (SCA) (31 May 2012) (our emphasis added).
141 Minister of Minerals and Energy v Agri South Africa (458/2011) [2012] ZASCA 93; 2012 (5)
SA 1 (SCA); [2012] 3 All SA 266 (SCA); 2012 (9) BCLR 958 (SCA) (31 May 2012) para 18.
142 Gildenhuys, A (2001) Onteieningsreg 2nd ed 151.
143 Gildenhuys (2001) 151.
144 Gildenhuys (2001) 151.
145 2016 (5) SA 513 (LCC) (for a discussion of the judgment, see Slade (2016) 2.1).
146 (1222/2016) [2017] ZASCA 130; 2018 (3) SA 440 (SCA) (29 September 2017).
147 Msiza v Director-General, Department of Rural Development and Land Reform 2016 (5) SA
513 (LCC).
148 Act 3 of 1996.
149 See specifically Mokgoro J’s comments in Du Toit v Minister of Transport (CCT22/04) [2005]
ZACC 9; 2006 (1) SA 297 (CC); 2005 (11) BCLR 1053 (CC) (8 September 2005) para 36.
150 See Du Plessis (2009) 267.
151 Du Plessis (2009) 271.
152 Du Plessis (2009) 299–300.
153 Van der Walt (2011) 509.
154 Van der Walt (2011) 509.
155 Du Toit para 51.
156 Van der Walt (2011) 514.
157 Van der Walt (2011) 518.
158 See Du Plessis (2015) 369–87.
159 (LCC 156/2009) [2012] ZALCC 7 (19 April 2012).
160 Du Plessis (2015) 379.
161 Du Plessis (2015) 380.
162 Du Plessis (2015) 387.
163 Van der Walt (2011) 509.
164 Du Plessis (2009) 299–300.
165 Van der Walt (2011) 509.
166 Marais, EJ Is onteiening sonder vergoeding werklik die antwoord? Litnet Akademies
available at https://www.litnet.co.za/onteiening-sonder-vergoeding-werklik-die-
antwoord/.
167 Act 126 of 1993.
168 Act 22 of 1994.
169 Act 2 of 1996.
170 Act 31 of 1996.
171 Act 28 of 1996.
172 Act 62 of 1997.
173 Act 11 of 2004. This Act was declared unconstitutional by the Constitutional Court in 2010
(see Tongoane and Others v National Minister for Agriculture and Land Affairs and Others
(CCT100/09) [2010] ZACC 10; 2010 (6) SA 214 (CC); 2010 (8) BCLR 741 (CC) (11 May
2010)).
174 Presidential Advisory Committee on Land Reform and Agriculture Final Report May 2019
at 12.
175 Presidential Advisory Committee on Land Reform and Agriculture Final Report May 2019
at 11. See also the High Level Panel on the Assessment of Key Legislation and the
Acceleration of Fundamental Change Final Report November 2017 at 202.
176 See, for example, Black First Land First Written Submission to Parliament on Review of the
Land Clause of the Constitution (June 2018) and Foundation for Human Rights Submission
to the Constitutional Review Committee (November 2018). See also African National
Congress Report on the Possible Review of Section 25 of the Constitution (November 2018)
and Economic Freedman Fighters Report on the Review and Amendment of Section 25 of
the Constitution (November 2018).
177 Minutes of Proceedings of the National Assembly on Tuesday 27 February [No 3 – 2018:
Fifth session, Fifth Parliament] page 8.
178 Joint Constitutional Review Committee (2018) Report on the possible review of section 25 of
the Constitution (November 2018) at para 7.
179 Draft Constitution Eighteenth Amendment Bill.
180 [B23–2020].
181 Ngcukaitobi, T (2019, 13 December) What section 25 means for land reform Mail &
Guardian available at https://mg.co.za/article/2019-12-13-00-what-section-25-means-for-
land-reform/.
182 See s 25(5)–(9) of the Constitution.
183 Pienaar, JM (2014) Land Reform 12; Pienaar, JM (2014) Reflections on the South African
land reform programme: Characteristics, dichotomies and tensions (part 1) Tydskrif vir die
Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 425–46 at 426.
184 See Kloppers, HJ and Pienaar, GJ (2014) The historical context of land reform in South
Africa and early policies Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal 17:677–706. This article
provides an overview of the most prominent legislation which provided the framework for
the policy of racially based territorial segregation that applied for the most part of the
twentieth century. It further discusses the legislative measures and policies which were
instituted during the period from 1991 to 1997, aimed at abolishing racially based laws and
practices related to land and which eventually provided the basis to the current land
reform programme in South Africa. Interestingly, Beinart and Delius survey the historical
background and realities of the Natives Land Act and argue that despite how racist and
segregationist the Act was, its immediate purpose was not to dislodge Africans from land
but to maintain and solidify the status quo of land possession and ownership until
government commissions could find more lasting solutions entailing segregation and land
distribution. They make this argument to point out that land dispossession is an injustice
that started long before 1913. See Beinart, W and Delius, P ‘The Natives Land Act of 1913: A
template but not a turning point’ in Cousins, B and Walker, C (eds) (2015) Land Divided
Land Restored: Land Reform in South Africa for the 21st Century 24–39 at 25.
185 Van der Walt, AJ and Pienaar, GJ (2016) Introduction to the Law of Property 7th ed 360.
186 Van Wyk, J (2010) Feasibility of restoration as a factor in land restitution claims South
African Public Law 25:590–601 at 591.
187 Pienaar (2014) Land reform 9, 11.
188 This section does not purport to provide a complete or overall picture of the history of land
dispossession in South Africa. The point of the section is to highlight key aspects of land
dispossession in order to show the important context within which the need for s 25
developed.
189 To view some of the accounts, see Cousins, B and Walker, C (eds) (2015) Land Divided
Land Restored: Land Reform in South Africa for the 21st Century; Ngcukaitobi (2019);
Pienaar (2014) chap 3.
190 Cousins, B and Walker, C (eds) ‘Land divided, land restored: Introduction’ in Cousins, B
and Walker, C (eds) (2015) Land Divided Land Restored: Land Reform in South Africa for
the 21st Century 1–23 at 17–21.
191 Hendricks, FT, Ntsebeza, L and Helliker, K ‘Land questions in South Africa’ in Hendricks,
FT, Ntsebeza, L and Helliker, K (eds) (2013) The Promise of Land: Undoing a Century of
Dispossession in South Africa 1–26 at 3–4.
192 Hendricks, Ntsebeza and Helliker (2013) 1–26 at 9.
193 Claassens, A ‘Law, land and custom, 1913-2014: What is at stake today?’ in Cousins, B and
Walker, C (eds) (2015) Land Divided Land Restored: Land Reform in South Africa for the
21st Century 68–84 at 70–2.
194 Pienaar (2014) 6.
195 See Kloppers and Pienaar (2014) 677–706.
196 Pienaar (2014) 6.
197 Pienaar (2014) 7.
198 Pienaar (2014) Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 425–46 at 430 [footnotes omitted].
Van der Walt and Pienaar explain that ‘[p]roperty relationships were disturbed and skewed
199 fundamentally during the apartheid era. To rectify the situation and to establish a measure
of normality and fairness as far as property is concerned will take time, and in the
meantime a measure of political interference is unavoidable. An important aspect of the
processes through which greater normality and fairness regarding property distribution are
promoted is land reform’. See Van der Walt and Pienaar (2016) 359–60.
200 Pienaar (2014) 14.
201 Hall, R ‘Who, what, where how why? The many disagreements about land redistribution in
South Africa’ in Cousins, B and Walker, C (eds) (2015) Land Divided Land Restored: Land
Reform in South Africa for the 21st Century 127–44 at 140.
202 Pienaar (2014) 15. See also Hall (2015) 127–44 at 140–41.
203 Pienaar (2014) Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 425–46 at 439–40.
204 Pienaar (2014) 425–46, 439–40; Hall (2015) 127–44. See also Pienaar (2014) 193, 203.
Pienaar analyses the South African land reform policy framework, starting with the
Department of Land Affairs White Paper on South Africa Land Policy (1997) available at
http://www.ruraldevelopment.gov.za/phocadownload/White-
Papers/whitepaperlandreform.pdf, and includes both the Department of Rural
Development and Land Reform Green Paper on Land Reform (2011) and Department of
Rural Development and Land Reform (DRDLR) Policy Framework for Land Acquisition and
Land Valuation in a Land Reform Context (2012).
205 Pienaar (2014) Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 425–46 at 439–40.
206 Hall (2015) 127–44, 128. See also Hall, R ‘Two cycles of land policy in South Africa: Tracing
the contours’ in Anseeuw, W and Alden, C (eds) (2010) The Struggle Over Land in Africa:
Conflicts, Politics and Change 175–92.
207 Hall (2015) 127–44 at 141.
208 See Hall (2015) 127–44 at 143–44, where Hall makes a number of suggestions of ways in
which the policies of land redistribution should be approached.
209 See s 25(7) of the Constitution. See also Van Wyk (2010) 590–601 at 591.
210 S 25(7) of the Constitution.
211 This is in line with the s 25(7) of the Constitution. The preamble of the Restitution of Land
Rights Act 22 of 1994 states that the aim of the Act is ‘[t]o provide for the restitution of rights
in land in respect of which persons or communities were dispossessed under or for the
purpose of furthering the objects of any racially based discriminatory law; to establish a
Commission on Restitution of Land Rights and a Land Claims Court; and to provide for
matters connected therewith’.
212 Hall, R (2004) Land restitution in South Africa: Rights, development, and the restrained
state Canadian Journal of African Studies 38(3):654–71 at 656.
213 Hall (2004) 654–71 at 656.
214 Pienaar (2014) 425–46 at 429; Hall (2010) 175–92 at 190.
215 Hall (2004) 654–71 at 659.
216 Hall (2004) 654–71 at 659.
217 Hall (2004) 654–71 at 660.
218 Act 15 of 2014.
219 Hall (2004) 654–71 at 660. Hall also argues that the Growth Employment and Redistribution
(GEAR) policies of the state impact directly on the fact that it is restrained it the context of
land redistribution. See specifically Hall (2004) 654–71 at 660–64.
220 Pienaar (2014) Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 425–46 at 428.
221 Pienaar (2014) Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 425–46 at 433.
Education and socio-economic
rights
17.1 Introduction
Summary
17.1 Introduction
The turn of the millennium has seen an increasing interest in the
promotion and protection of socio-economic rights.1 It is often argued
that one of the transformative features of the Constitution of the
Republic of South Africa, 19962 is the inclusion of a wide range of
justiciable social, economic and cultural rights (socio-economic
rights).3 Socio-economic rights have been defined as entitlements to
those conditions and resources necessary for the material well-being of
people.4 They include rights to goods and services such as food, water,
sanitation, housing, healthcare, social assistance, education, and a
healthy environment, among others. The Constitution is one of the first
to enshrine a comprehensive suite of socio-economic rights as fully
justiciable and has, as a result, attracted widespread attention both at
the regional and international level.5 The fact that they are justiciable
means that these rights can be enforced through judicial mechanisms.6
This development is predicated on the realisation that socio-economic
rights are important in eradicating poverty,7 particularly in a country
like South Africa with huge socio-economic discrepancies emanating
from the legacy of apartheid. It is noteworthy that the Constitution was
adopted within a particular historical and social context where the
black majority had been subjected to systemic discrimination in
accessing basic services due to the apartheid policies of the National
Party government.8
17.2.1 Introduction
One of the notable features of the Constitution, as alluded to above, is
the inclusion of a range of socio-economic rights as justiciable rights, a
position that distinguishes it from constitutions in comparative
jurisdictions.30 Despite the debates31 surrounding the inclusion of
justiciable socio-economic rights in the Constitution, there are cogent
reasons why such rights were included, particularly in the South African
context.32 Perhaps the most of important of these is the fact that racial
oppression in South Africa manifested itself not only on political but
also on economic, social and cultural grounds. This left the country with
an entrenched legacy of political, social and economic inequality.33 The
constitutionalisation of socio-economic rights also indicates an
understanding of the scale and scope of the problem that faced the
South African society at the dawn of democracy. The Constitutional
Court in Soobramoney v Minister of Health (KwaZulu-Natal)
highlighted the prevailing conditions as follows:
We live in a society in which there are great disparities in wealth. Millions of
people are living in deplorable conditions and in great poverty. There is a high
level of unemployment, inadequate social security, and many do not have
access to clean water or to adequate health services. These conditions already
existed when the Constitution was adopted and a commitment to address
them, and to transform our society into one in which there will be human
dignity, freedom and equality, lies at the heart of our new constitutional
order.34
17.5.1 Introduction
As is the case with the interpretation of all rights, the starting point is
the specific wording of the right concerned. In the case of socio-
economic rights, it will be of particular importance to establish whether
the specific right contains internal modifiers relating, for example, to
‘available resources’ and ‘reasonableness’. However, section 7(2) of the
Constitution will also loom large when a court is called upon to
interpret the socio-economic rights contained in the Bill of Rights.
Section 7(2) – which applies to both civil and political rights and socio-
economic rights105 – imposes both negative and positive obligations on
the state regarding the realisation of rights. This means that it will be
important to interpret the text of a right with reference to the nature of
the negative and positive obligations imposed on the state in terms of
section 7(2). As socio-economic rights arguably impose a wider array of
positive obligations on the state, it is of particular assistance to keep the
array of positive obligations imposed by section 7(2) in mind when
interpreting these rights. A closer look at section 7(2) is therefore
warranted.
Section 7(2) of the Constitution provides that the ‘state must respect,
protect, promote and fulfil the rights in the Bill of Rights’.106 As was noted
by the Court in Glenister v President of the Republic of South Africa and
Others:
This obligation goes beyond a mere negative obligation not to act in a manner
that would infringe or restrict a right. Rather, it entails positive duties on the
state to take deliberate, reasonable measures to give effect to all of the
fundamental rights contained in the Bill of Rights.107
Elaborating state obligations in this way highlights the fact that states
have an active role to play in the implementation of human rights,
rather than a mere obligation of non-interference with the enjoyment of
human rights.108 In addition, the respect, protect, promote and fulfil
analytic model has unpacked the nature of the duties that human rights
impose on states.109 The following section analyses the nature of the
duties that the socio-economic rights contained in the Bill of Rights
impose on the state.
17.7.1 Introduction
A noteworthy feature of the Constitutional Court’s socio-economic
jurisprudence is that it has drawn a distinction between the model of
review applied to negative duties imposed by socio-economic rights,
positive duties imposed by immediately realisable socio-economic
rights and positive duties imposed by progressively realisable socio-
economic rights.
Where the state deprives people of their existing access to socio-
economic rights, this constitutes a breach of the negative duty to respect
the relevant rights.147 This happens, for example, where the state closes a
clinic already providing basic health care to people in a district, making
it more difficult or impossible for them to access health care. However,
the breach may be justified by the state if it satisfies the purpose and
proportionality requirements of the general limitations clause
contained in section 36(1).148 Such an approach is in line with the
traditional two-stage approach to constitutional review applied in
respect of most rights in the Bill of Rights.149 Similarly, where the state
fails to fulfil an immediately realisable socio-economic right, essentially
the same model of review is applied. This happens, for example, where
the state fails to provide textbooks to primary schools despite the
constitutional obligation to provide basic education to all.
The failure constitutes a breach of the positive duty to immediately
fulfil the relevant right, but the infringement may be justified by the
state if it satisfies the requirements of the general limitation clause.
Where, however the state fails to fulfil a progressively realisable socio-
economic right (in other words, where it fails to take positive steps to
realise the right), a different model of review is applied. In so far as this
model of review is concerned, two different approaches have been
developed. The one was developed by the United Nations Committee
on Economic Social and Cultural Rights (CESCR) and is commonly
referred to as the ‘minimum core’ approach. The other was developed
by the Constitutional Court and is commonly referred to as the
‘reasonableness’ approach. These approaches are fully discussed below.
The Court pointed out that the first subsection (section 26(1)) confers a
general right of access to adequate housing and the second subsection
(section 26(2)) establishes and delimits the scope of the positive
obligations imposed on the state to realise that right. It follows that
subsections (1) and (2) are related and must be read together, and not
in isolation from each other. Accordingly, the constitutional right of
access to housing guaranteed in section 26 does not impose a duty on
the state that is not achievable within its available resources.178 As far as
the actual obligations imposed by the right are concerned, several
interrelated but distinct sets of qualifiers must be considered.
The state therefore has a duty to ‘create the conditions for access to
adequate housing for people at all economic levels of our society’, if
necessary also relying on ‘other agents within our society, including on
individuals themselves’.180 State policy dealing with housing must
therefore take account of different economic levels in our society.181 As
there is a difference between the position of those who can afford to pay
for housing, and those who cannot, the state will have to treat the needs
of such differently situated people differently.
For those who can afford to pay for adequate housing, the state’s primary
obligation lies in unlocking the system, providing access to housing stock and a
legislative framework to facilitate self-built houses through planning laws and
access to finance. Issues of development and social welfare are raised in
respect of those who cannot afford to provide themselves with housing. State
policy needs to address both these groups. The poor are particularly vulnerable
and their needs require special attention.182
These passages suggest that for those who have the means to access
housing (for example by financing the purchase of a house through
taking a bond from a bank), the state would be required to do no more
than to create and maintain the requisite infrastructure and ensure that
it is possible for such individuals to borrow money from a bank under
fair conditions. But for the many people who cannot afford this, the
state’s obligations would be more onerous, including, ultimately
requiring it to build houses to provide an ever-increasing number of
people with better access to housing. While this obligation is not linked
to an individual person and while an individual can therefore not
obtain a court order to force the state to build him or her a house,
anyone can approach a court to challenge its programme for not
increasing access to housing over time.
17.7.3.1.3.2 Reasonableness
The second set of modifiers is, as we have seen, contained in section
26(2) and 27(2) of the Bill of Rights, which determines that as far as its
positive obligations are concerned the state only needs to do what is
reasonable, within its available resources, progressively to realise the
right. The reasonableness of the measures adopted by the state will be
pivotal, which means it is important to establish exactly what criteria a
court will use to determine whether the challenged policy as well as its
implementation are reasonable.
The starting point is to ask is whether the means chosen are
reasonably capable of facilitating the realisation of the socio-economic
rights in question.183 In Grootboom, the Constitutional Court held that
the state’s positive obligation under section 26 of the Constitution was
primarily to adopt and implement a reasonable policy, within its
available resources, which would ensure access to adequate housing
over time.184 This approach, it was held, was designed to allow
government a margin of discretion relating to the specific policy choices
adopted to give effect to socio-economic rights. According to the Court:
[A] court considering reasonableness will not enquire whether other more
desirable or favourable measures could have been adopted, or whether public
money could have been better spent. The question would be whether the
measures that have been adopted are reasonable. It is necessary to recognise
that a wide range of possible measures could be adopted by the State to meet its
obligations. Many of these would meet the requirement of reasonableness.
Once it is shown that the measures do so, this requirement is met.185
The Court held that, to qualify as reasonable, the state’s housing policy
must:
• be comprehensive, coherent and effective186
• have sufficient regard for the social, economic and historical context
of widespread deprivation187
• have sufficient regard for the availability of the state’s resources188
• make short-, medium- and long-term provision for housing needs189
• give special attention to the needs of the poorest and most
vulnerable190
• be aimed at lowering administrative, operational and financial
barriers over time191
• allocate responsibilities and tasks clearly to all three spheres of
government192
• be implemented reasonably, adequately resourced and free of
bureaucratic inefficiency or onerous regulations193
• respond with care and concern to the needs of the most desperate194
• achieve more than a mere statistical advance in the numbers of
people accessing housing, by demonstrating that the needs of the
most vulnerable are catered for.195
The CESCR further held that beyond the minimum core entitlements,
the state is obliged to adopt legislative measures to progressively
achieve the full spectrum of the socio-economic rights guaranteed in
the ICESCR.219 In Grootboom, TAC220 and Mazibuko,221 the
Constitutional Court declined to adopt the minimum core approach as
a model of assessing state compliance with the positive obligations
imposed by sections 26 and 27 of Constitution. The Court’s reasoning
included textual, institutional and feasibility considerations.222
In Grootboom, for instance, the Constitutional Court pointed out
that the determination of the minimum core in the context of the right
to have access to adequate housing presents considerable difficulties.
This is because there are some people who need land, others who need
both land and houses and yet others who need financial assistance.223
Furthermore, the Court said that, unlike the CESCR which developed
the notion of the minimum core obligations based on its extensive
experience in reviewing state reports under the ICESCR, it lacked
adequate information on which the content of the minimum core
obligations could be based.224
In TAC, the Constitutional Court followed the same approach as in
Grootboom when it rejected the argument that section 27 of the
Constitution should be interpreted to contain a minimum core content,
stating that:
Although … evidence in a particular case may show that there is a minimum
core of a particular service that should be taken into account in determining
whether measures adopted by the State are reasonable, the socio-economic
rights of the Constitution should not be construed as entitling everyone to
demand that the minimum core be provided to them. Minimum core was thus
treated as possibly being relevant to reasonableness under section 26(2), and
not as a self-standing right conferred on everyone under section 26(1).225
17.7.5.1 Introduction
Not all socio-economic rights are qualified in the manner that sections
26 and 27 – discussed above – are qualified. Some rights are
immediately realisable, which means they impose an obligation on the
state to ensure everyone has access to the right. The right to basic
education, including adult basic education, which is guaranteed by
section 29(1)(a) of the Constitution, is such a right. Other aspects of the
right to education protected by section 29 – including the right to
further education – are qualified, but not in exactly the same manner
that section 26 and 27 are qualified. In this sense, the right to education
is a hybrid right, containing both immediately realisable aspects, and
aspects that only need to be implemented progressively.
The right to education is a pivotal right as its realisation will
contribute to the realisation of many other rights – including the right to
equality. Educational inequality was deliberately built into the South
African education system, and this was exacerbated by the introduction
of ‘Bantu Education’ after 1948. These overt racist policies were aimed
at creating two separate education systems, one for white people and
one for black people, with the latter designed to limit the ability of black
people to access quality education. While formal legal discrimination in
education was abolished after 1994, the current education system does
not provide equal quality education for all. According to Vally, this
overtly racist system has been replaced by a covertly racist and class-
dominated system. As a result, ‘new’ educational injustices are
preventing poor and marginalised groups from getting universal access
to high-quality education in the ‘new’ South Africa.
The long shadow of apartheid ideology … continues to cast its Stygian gloom,
no longer through racially explicit policies, but by proxy: high school fees,
exclusionary language and admission policies, and other transparent
maneuvers such as ‘crowding out’ black learners by bussing-in white learners
from outside the feeder area.290
17.7.5.2.1 Introduction
The right to education is widely protected in international human rights
instruments, most notably in the founding document of international
human rights, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR).
Article 26(2) of the UDHR this provides that:
Education shall be directed to the full development of the human personality
and to the strengthening of respect for human rights and fundamental
freedoms. It shall promote understanding, tolerance and friendship among all
nations, racial or religious groups, and shall further the activities of the United
Nations for the maintenance of peace.291
Bantu Education
Prior to the enactment of the Bantu Education,295 the
majority of black schools in South Africa were state-
aided mission schools. Apart from phasing out mission
schools and placing black schools under the central
control of the Department of Bantu Education, this Act
was aimed at entrenching racial segregation, ensuring
that black schools were inferior to white schools and
that black children were educated only for semi-skilled
or unskilled work. At the time the Bantu Education Act
was passed, the then Minister of Native Affairs,
Hendrik Verwoerd, who was also the ‘architect of
apartheid’, stated that:
There is no place for [the Bantu] in the European community
above the level of certain forms of labour … What is the use of
teaching the Bantu child maths when it cannot use it in practice.
That is quite absurd. Education must train people in accordance
with their opportunities in life, according to the sphere in which
they live.
As Woolman and Fleish have pointed out, the fact that the right to a
basic education is immediately realisable has a number of important
consequence.
First, unlike the progressively realisable socio-economic rights,
section 29(1)(a) provides that everyone has a right to basic education
itself and not a right of ‘access’ to basic education. Instead of imposing
an obligation on the state to simply enable people to fulfil this right
themselves, section 29(1)(a) imposes an obligation on the state itself to
fulfil the right.309
Second, again unlike the progressively realisable socio-economic
rights, section 29(1)(a) provides that the right to a basic education is not
subject to ‘reasonable legislative and other measures’. This means that
the reasonableness standard adopted in Grootboom does not apply to
this right. A failure to fulfil this right, therefore, will amount to
infringement even if the state has taken reasonable steps to do so.310
Third, the state’s obligation to fulfil section 29(1)(a) is not subject to
progressive realisation and does not depend on the availability of
resources. This means that the state may not fulfil the right to a basic
education gradually over time. Instead, it must fulfil the right
immediately and a failure to do so will amount to an infringement even
if the state is suffering from a lack of resources.311
Apart from the fact that is immediately realisable, the right to a basic
education – like all other rights – imposes both a negative and a positive
obligation on the state (and, in some instances, private parties). This
point was emphasised by the Constitutional Court in Gauteng
Provincial Legislature: In re Gauteng School Education Bill of 1995,316
where the Court held that:
[The right to basic education] creates a positive right that basic education be
provided for every person and not merely a negative right that such person
should not be obstructed in pursuing his or her basic education.317
The negative dimension means that the state is prohibited from acting
in ways that take away or diminish the existing enjoyment of the right
and from denying or preventing people from taking steps to access
basic education themselves. For example, where the state closes a rural
school, and this makes it more difficult for children to attend school, it
may infringe the state’s negative obligation to respect the right to basic
education. The positive dimension means that the state itself must take
steps to provide a basic education to everyone. For example, where the
state fails to deliver textbooks or fails to build classrooms, this may
infringe on its positive obligation to protect, promote and fulfil the right
to education. As pointed out above, the positive dimension of the right
to a basic education is immediately realisable, which means that it is
not subject to the reasonableness standard, it is not dependent on the
availability of resources and it is the source of a direct and immediate
entitlement.
17.7.5.3.1 Introduction
The (limited) right to be educated in the official language of one’s
choice has become controversial, especially in the context of
educational institutions that traditionally conducted education
exclusively in Afrikaans. Much of the contestation about this right has
centred on the impact that the use of Afrikaans at educational
institutions might have on the ability of some black South Africans to
access such educational institutions. This right must therefore be
considered with reference to the prohibition on unfair discrimination
protected by section 9(3) of the Constitution. The right to receive
education in the language of one’s choice is guaranteed in section 29(2)
which provides that:
Everyone has the right to receive education in the official language or
languages of their choice in public educational institutions where that
education is reasonably practicable. In order to ensure the effective access to,
and implementation of, this right, the state must consider all reasonable
educational alternatives, including single medium institutions, taking into
account: (a) equity; (b) practicability; and (c) the need to redress the results of
past racially discriminatory laws and practices.
The convoluted nature of this right and especially the reference to single
medium institutions reflects the compromise struck during the
constitutional negotiations between the National Party’s desire to
constitutionally protect Afrikaans-only schools and the African National
Congress’s determination to prevent Afrikaans-only schools being used
to perpetuate racial discrimination. This compromise not only allowed
both parties to move forward and vote in favour of the draft text but also
to claim victory in so far as language rights were concerned.
Before turning to consider the provisions of this right in more detail,
however, it will be helpful to briefly set out the contentious role that
language and particularly Afrikaans has played as a medium of
instruction in South Africa. This is because section 29(2) must be
interpreted in light of this historical context.
The history of Afrikaans medium education
The issue of single medium schools, and especially
single medium Afrikaans schools, has a long and
contentious history in South Africa. Giliomee traces it
back to the years immediately following the South
African war (1899-1902), when the British introduced
English as the sole official language in the former Boer
Republics of the Transvaal and the Orange Free
State.335 This decision was opposed by the defeated
Boers and eventually overturned in 1910 when both
English and Dutch were recognised as official
languages in section 137 of the Union Constitution.336
Following the establishment of the Union, the
campaign to recognise Dutch as an official language
was replaced with a new movement to replace Dutch
with Afrikaans.337 This movement formed a part of the
rise of Afrikaner nationalism in the 1920s and 1930s
and was accompanied by a drive to replace Dutch with
Afrikaans as a medium of instruction and to establish
single medium Afrikaans schools. This was organised
by the Dutch Reformed Church and was based on the
belief that single medium schools would act as a
mechanism for binding the white Afrikaans community
together.338
This movement achieved success following the
National Party’s victory in the 1948 general election
and the introduction of apartheid. One of the National
Party’s goals was to place Afrikaans on an equal
footing with English by developing and promoting the
academic, cultural, political and scientific use of
Afrikaans, through the use of a variety of state
mechanisms, including single medium Afrikaans public
schools and universities.339 As Mogoeng CJ stated in
Afriforum and Another v University of the Free State,
Afrikaans Universities ‘were exceedingly well-resourced
for the exclusive or primary benefit of white Afrikaner
students. And their inseparable and almost destiny-
defining mandate was to develop the Afrikaans
language very well. As a result, it now effortlessly and
admirably fits President Mandela’s poetic description
of it as a language of ‘scholarship and science’.340
Besides placing Afrikaans and English on an equal
footing, the promotion of single medium schools also
fitted in with the National Party’s policy of separate
development in terms of which each ethnic group
would be educated in its own language. Bantu
Education thus provided that black children would be
educated in their mother tongue in primary school and
then switch to English in high school.341 The apartheid
government’s decision in 1976 to replace English with
Afrikaans in key subjects in black high schools,
however, angered black students and lead to the mass
struggles of the 1970s and 1980s and, ultimately, to
the end of apartheid.342 As Froneman J stated in
Gelyke Kanse and Others v Chairman of the Senate of
the University of Stellenbosch, ‘[t]he apartheid system
“used promotion of the mother-tongue principle,
specifically the advancement of the indigenous
languages as subject and medium of instruction, as a
central instrument of the policy of divide and rule”.
And the 1976 Soweto school uprisings still resonate
deeply in our national psyche’.343
The requirement that a court must take into account all the relevant
circumstances of the case means that it would be more difficult for a
higher education institution to invoke section 29(2) in order to provide
education in the language of a specific group. First, there are only a
limited number of higher education institutions in South Africa and
places in these institutions are limited, making it more difficult to justify
a language policy that would deny access to some. Second, the question
of racial exclusion and racial segregation is likely to rear its head. For
example, in Afriforum the Constitutional Court considered the
constitutionality of a decision by the University of the Free State to
change its language policy from an existing Afrikaans-English parallel-
medium system to a new English single-medium system. The focus in
Afriforum, therefore, was not on the positive dimension of section 29(2)
of the Constitution, but rather on the negative dimension of the right.
The Court noted that the parallel-medium language policy adopted by
the University resulted in separate lectures for black and white students.
Black students overwhelmingly attended lectures conducted in English,
while white students attended those conducted in Afrikaans. In light of
this fact, the University commissioned an investigation into its language
policy which found that the language policy was frustrating the
University’s goal of integrating black and white students. The University,
therefore, decided to adopt a new single-medium language policy in
terms of which English would be the primary medium of instruction.
Afriforum challenged this decision on the ground that it infringed
section 29(2). The Court dismissed this claim because it was not
reasonably practicable for the University to continue offering lectures in
both Afrikaans and English. In arriving at this decision, the Court held
that the phrase ‘reasonably practicable’ must be interpreted, not only in
light of the circumstances listed in Hoërskool Ermelo, but also in light of
the second part of section 29(2) and especially the factors listed in
paragraphs (a), (b) and (c) of section 29(2), namely what is fair, feasible
and satisfies the need to remedy the results of past racially
discriminatory laws and practices. This is because these factors are
related to some of the values on which the Constitution is based,
specifically equity, responsiveness and non-racialism.352
Given that these factors are related to equity, responsiveness and
non-racialism, the Court held further, they must be applied even when
‘a learner already enjoys the benefit of being taught in an official
language of choice’. Inequity, unresponsiveness and racial
discrimination, therefore, are an ‘appropriate justification’ for
diminishing or taking away an existing right to be educated in one’s
mother tongue.353 If an existing right to be educated in the language of
one’s choice threatens access, integration and racial harmony then it is
no longer reasonably practicable.354 Reasonable practicability, the Court
concluded, therefore, ‘requires not only that the practicability test be
met, but also that considerations of reasonableness that extend to
equity and the need to cure the ills of our shameful past, be
appropriately accommodated. And that is achievable only if the
exercise of the right to be taught in a language of choice does not pose a
threat to racial harmony or inadvertently nurture racial supremacy’.355
After setting out these principles, the Court turned to apply them to the
facts of the case and came to the conclusion that while the existing
dual-medium Afrikaans-English language policy followed by the
University might be practical, it was not reasonable because it
unwittingly perpetuated segregation and racism. It thus offended
constitutional norms.356
The question of racial exclusion also arose in Gelyke Kanse, but in a
slightly different manner. The Constitutional Court had to consider
whether a decision by the University of Stellenbosch to move from an
existing predominantly Afrikaans parallel-medium system to a new
predominantly English parallel-medium system infringed section 29(2)
of the Constitution. In this case, however, the reason for the changing
the policy was not to combat the problem of racially segregated
lectures, but rather to promote integration, equitable access and non-
racialism in a cost effect manner. The focus in Gelyke Kanse, therefore,
was partly on the role that cost plays in deciding whether a language
policy is reasonably practicable.
Like the University of the Free State, the University of Stellenbosch
was historically an Afrikaans single-medium institution. In 2014,
however, it adopted a predominantly Afrikaans parallel-medium
language policy in order to comply with the Ministerial Language Policy
for Higher Education. In terms of this policy, all courses were offered in
Afrikaans and many, but not all, in Afrikaans and English. In order to
accommodate English speakers, Afrikaans instruction was also
accompanied by real-time translations. Following the Fees Must Fall
and Open Stellenbosch student protests in 2015, however, the
University decided to adopt a new language policy. This new policy
provided that where it was reasonably practicable courses would
continue to be offered in both Afrikaans and English. Where it was not,
courses would be offered in English only, with a subsequent Afrikaans
translation. In other words, all courses would now be offered in English,
but not in Afrikaans. Afrikaans courses would be offered only if there
was sufficient demand and resources.
After the University took this decision, Gelyke Kanse, which was a
voluntary organisation committed to equal chances for all indigenous
languages, applied to the Western Cape High Court in Cape Town for an
order declaring the new language policy to be unconstitutional and
invalid on the ground that it infringed section 29(2) of the Constitution.
The High Court rejected this application and Gelyke Kanse then
appealed to the Constitutional Court. The Constitutional Court also
dismissed the appeal. In the Constitutional Court, Gelyke Kanse
accepted that even though the predominantly Afrikaans parallel-
medium policy did not result in racially separate lectures, it
nevertheless did alienate black students who did not speak Afrikaans
from the academic, residential and social life of the University.357 This
problem could be resolved, however, Gelyke Kanse argued, not by
adopting a predominantly English parallel-medium system, but rather
by adopting a full parallel-medium system in terms of which every
course was offered in both Afrikaans and English.358
In response, the University conceded that this suggestion was
feasible, but went on to argue that it was not reasonably practicable
because it was too expensive.359 The key issue the Court had to decide,
therefore, was whether a student’s existing right to be educated in the
official language of his or her choice can be diminished (although not
extinguished) when this is a more cost-effective means of achieving the
goals of racial equity, access and inclusion.360 The Court held that it
could. Although the predominance of Afrikaans was sacrificed in terms
of the new language policy, when this sacrifice was weighed against the
fact that Afrikaans would still be used as a medium of instruction, that
black students who could not speak Afrikaans would be less
marginalised and stigmatised and that the new language policy was
more cost-effective than the alternative suggested by Gelyke Kanse,
then it was clear that the new language policy was constitutionally
justifiable.361
17.7.5.4.1 Introduction
As noted earlier in this chapter, the right to education guaranteed in
section 29(1) of the Constitution is a hybrid right. While section 29(1)(a)
discussed above imposes an immediately enforceable right to basic
education, section 29(1)(b) imposes a programmatic right which is not
immediately enforceable in the same manner. At the same time section
29(1)(b) places internal modifiers on the right that differ from the
internal modifiers imposed on section 26(1) and section 27(1). It is
therefore necessary to discuss this subsection of the right to education
separately, specifically because its scope and content is of immediate
concern in relation to the struggle for free tertiary education.367
Every year hundreds of thousands of learners pass matric with the
dream of studying further. Many of those who qualify to attend tertiary
institutions simply cannot afford to enrol. Black youth in particular are
denied the equal opportunity of accessing further education because of
continuing higher levels of poverty among the black population.
Students at tertiary institutions are also at risk of dropping out because
they cannot afford to continue their studies. Students are
understandably desperate to gain entry to further education institutions
and to complete their studies once there. A tertiary qualification
represents a means for students to achieve their career ambitions. It
also represents for most the opportunity to lift themselves and their
families out of desperate poverty. A lack of government funding towards
higher education over the years has, however, caused a rise in student
fees.
Over the last decade, student fees have grown faster than inflation
levels.368 The inadequacy of government funding has placed universities
and other tertiary institutions under financial strain. Escalating student
fees led to the extraordinary student protests that began at the end of
2015 and spread quickly throughout South African universities. These
student protests sparked the rise of the Fees Must Fall movement. The
movement’s original demand was that student fees not be increased.
This transformed into a demand for free tertiary education for all. The
Fees Must Fall protests eventually led to then President Jacob Zuma
appointing a Commission of Inquiry into Higher Education and
Training in 2016. The Commission was required to investigate whether
free tertiary education for all is achievable in South Africa. At the end of
2017, President Jacob Zuma also seemingly raised the expectations of
many students when he promised that higher education would be made
free for all.
One lens though which to look at this question, is to ask what
obligations section 29(1)(b) of the Constitution impose on the state to
ensure free further education for all. Specifically, we ask what the
guarantee in section 29(1)(b) – which states that everyone has the right
to further education, which the state, through reasonable measures,
must make progressively available and accessible – in fact entails.
SUMMARY
1 The increasing recognition of such rights in national constitutions has been on the rise.
Importantly, South Africa, on 12 January 2015, ratified the International Covenant on
Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR) UN Doc A/6316, the pre-eminent
international human rights instrument on economic, social and cultural rights (socio-
economic rights), among a suite of international instruments that provide for socio-
economic rights.
2 Moyo, K ‘The advocate, peacemaker, judge and activist: A chronicle on the contributions of
Justice Johann Kriegler to South African constitutional jurisprudence’ in Bohler-Muller, N,
Cosser, M and Pienaar, G (eds) (2018) Making the Road by Walking: The Evolution of the
South African Constitution 78–9.
3 Bilchitz, D (2018) ‘The performance of socio-economic rights in the South African
Constitution’ in Dixon, R and Roux, T (eds) Constitutional Triumphs, Constitutional
Disappointments: A Critical Assessment of the 1996 South African Constitution’s Local and
International Influence 45–87 at 45.
4 See De Vos, P and Freeman, W (2014) South African Constitutional Law in Context 667.
5 Bilchitz (2018) 45.
6 De Vos and Freedman (2014) 684. In the process of adjudicating disputes on the basis of
constitutionally entrenched socio-economic rights, courts interpret these rights and give
concrete and authoritative expression to the duties they impose.
7 See Chenwi, L ‘An appraisal of international law mechanisms for litigating socio-economic
rights, with a particular focus on the Optional Protocol to the International Covenant on
Economic, Social and Cultural Rights and the African Commission and Court’ in
Liebenberg, S and Quinot, G (eds) (2012) Law and Poverty: Perspectives from South Africa
and Beyond 241.
8 Moyo (2018) 78.
9 McLean, K (2009) Constitutional Deference, Courts and Socio-Economic Rights in South
Africa vii.
10 McLean (2009) vii.
11 McLean (2009) vii.
12 McLean (2009) vii.
13 Government of the Republic of South Africa (2011) National Development Plan 2.
14 See Education and Training Unit (2016) How Government Works 13.
15 Liebenberg, S (2010) Socio-Economic Rights: Adjudication under a Transformative
Constitution 2.
16 See Langford, M ‘The justiciability of social rights: From practice to theory’ in Langford, M
(ed) (2008) Social Rights Jurisprudence: Emerging Trends in International and Comparative
Law 33.
17 See Langford (2008) 98.
18 Statistics South Africa estimates for the amount an individual needs to buy basic foods and
services. See Education and Training Unit (2016) 13.
19 See Education and Training Unit (2016) 13.
20 See Education and Training Unit (2016) 13–14.
21 See Government of the Republic of South Africa (2011) 4.
22 See Preamble to the Constitution.
23 Klare, KE (1998) Legal culture and transformative constitutionalism South African Journal
on Human Rights 14(1):146–88.
24 Moyo (2018) 78.
25 See Preamble to and s 1 of the Constitution.
26 See Madlingozi, T (2007) Post-Apartheid Social Movements and the Quest for the Elusive
`New’ South Africa Journal of Law and Society 34(1):77–98; Wesson, M (2018) The Limits of
Constitutional Justice Public Law Review 29(1):63 and Shai, I (2019) Radical transformation
and the limits of law Acta Academica 51(1):144–62.
27 Madlingozi, T (2017) Social justice in a time of neo-apartheid constitutionalism: critiquing
the anti-black economy of recognition, incorporation and distribution Stellenbosch Law
Review 8(1):123–47.
28 Davis, DM (2006) Adjudicating the Socio-Economic Rights in the South African
Constitution: Towards Deference Lite South African Journal on Human Rights 22(2):301–27
at 315.
29 Davis (2006) 315.
30 The Constitutions of Kenya (2010) and Zimbabwe (2013) have followed suit in
constitutionalising judicially enforceable socio-economic rights.
31 For a summary of the debates surrounding the inclusion of justiciable socio-economic
rights in the Constitution, see Keightley, R (2011) The challenges of litigating socio-
economic rights in South Africa New Zealand Law Review 2011(2): 296–99.
32 Bilchitz (2018) 49.
33 Keightley (2011) 296.
34 Soobramoney v Minister of Health (KwaZulu-Natal) (CCT32/97) [1997] ZACC 17; 1998 (1)
SA 765 (CC); 1997 (12) BCLR 1696 (27 November 1997) para 8.
35 Bilchitz (2018) 49, citing Mbazira, C (2009) Litigating socio-economic rights in South Africa:
A choice between corrective and distributive justice 103–11.
36 Keightley (2011) 296.
37 Bilchitz (2018) 49.
38 Keightley (2011) 297.
39 Keightley (2011) 297.
40 Keightley (2011) 297.
41 See Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (CCT 23/96) [1996]
ZACC 26; 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC) (6 September 1996) paras 77–8.
This judgment is commonly referred to as the First Certification Judgment.
42 First Certification Judgment para 77.
43 First Certification Judgment para 78.
44 First Certification Judgment para 77.
45 First Certification Judgment para 78.
46 Mazibuko and Others v City of Johannesburg and Others (CCT 39/09) [2009] ZACC 28; 2010
4 SA 1 (CC) ; 2010 (3) BCLR 239 (CC) (8 October 2009) para 61.
47 Biegon, J ‘The inclusion of socio-economic rights in the 2010 constitution: Conceptual and
practical issues’ in Biegon, J and Musila, GM (eds) (2011) Judicial Enforcement of Socio-
Economic Rights under the new Constitution: Challenges and Opportunities for Kenya 13, 14.
48 Biegon (2011) 18.
49 Sunstein, CR Against positive rights: Why social and economic rights don’t belong in the
new constitutions of post-communist Europe East European Constitutional Review 2:35–8.
50 Ray, B (2016) Engaging with social rights: Procedure, participation and democracy in South
Africa’s second wave 11.
51 Chirwa, DM and Chenwi, L ‘The protection of economic, social and cultural rights in Africa’
in Chirwa, DM and Chenwi, L (2016) The Protection of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights
in Africa: International, Regional and National Perspectives 17.
52 Chirwa and Chenwi (2016) 15.
53 See s 26 of the Constitution.
54 S 27 of the Constitution.
55 S 29 of the Constitution.
56 S 28(1)(c) of the Constitution.
57 S 35(2)(e) of the Constitution.
58 Soobramoney and Minister of Health and Others v Treatment Action Campaign and Others
(No 2) (CCT8/02) [2002] ZACC 15; 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC); 2002 (10) BCLR 1033 (CC) (5 July
2002).
59 Government of the Republic of South Africa and Others v Grootboom and Others
(CCT11/00) [2000] ZACC 19; 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC); 2000 (11) BCLR 1169 (CC) (4 October
2000).
60 Khosa and Others v Minister of Social Development and Others (CCT 13/03, CCT 12/03)
[2004] ZACC 11; 2004 (6) SA 505 (CC); 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC) (4 March 2004).
61 Mazibuko and Others v City of Johannesburg and Others (CCT 39/09) [2009] ZACC 28; 2010
(4) SA 1 (CC); 2010 (3) BCLR 239 (CC) (8 October 2009).
62 Joseph and Others v City of Johannesburg and Others (CCT 43/09) [2009] ZACC 30; 2010 (4)
SA 55 (CC); 2010 (3) BCLR 212 (CC) (9 October 2009).
63 Nokotyana and Others v Ekurhuleni Municipality and Others CCT 31/09) [2009] ZACC 33;
2010 (4) BCLR 312 (CC) (19 November 2009).
64 See Head of Department: Mpumalanga Department of Education v Hoërskool Ermelo and
Others 2010 (2) SA 415 (CC); AfriForum and Another v University of the Free State
(CCT101/17) [2017] ZACC 48; 2018 (2) SA 185 (CC); 2018 (4) BCLR 387 (CC) (29 December
2017) and Gelyke Kanse and Others v Chairman of the Senate of the University of
Stellenbosch and Others (CCT 311/17) [2019] ZACC 38; 2020 (1) SA 368 (CC); 2019 (12)
BCLR 1479 (CC) (10 October 2019).
65 See ss 26(2) (housing) and 27(2) (health care, food, water and social security).
66 Minister of Health and Others v Treatment Action Campaign and Others (CCT 08/02) [2002]
ZACC 15; 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC); 2002 (10) BCLR 1033 (CC) (5 July 2002) para 39.
67 Mazibuko para 50.
68 Grootboom para 38.
69 TAC para 31. See also Mazibuko paras 49–50.
70 Grootboom para 95.
71 See ss 26(3) and 27(3) of the Constitution.
72 Bilchitz (2018) 51.
73 Liebenberg, S (2014) Judicially enforceable socio-economic rights in South Africa: Between
light and shadow Dublin University Law Journal 37:137–72 at 145.
74 In this regard, the Constitutional Court has upheld a two-stage approach to constitutional
interpretation. The first phase consists of interpreting the scope of the right and whether
the applicant’s claim falls within this scope. The second stage consists of assessing whether
or not any limitation the state relies on is reasonable and justifiable in terms of the
requirements of the general limitations clause contained in s 36 of the Constitution.
75 S 10.
76 S 32. This right has been given effect under the Promotion of Access to Information Act 32
of 2000.
77 S 32.
78 S 33.
Liebenberg, S (2010) Socio-Economic Rights Adjudication under a Transformative
79 Constitution 93.
80 Keightley (2011) 303.
81 Mazibuko para 166.
82 Groomboom paras 71–8.
83 Sachs, A The judicial enforcement of socio-economic rights: The Grootboom case in Jones,
P and Stokke, K (eds) (2005) Democratising Development: The Politics of Socio-Economic
Rights in South Africa 133.
84 Biowatch Trust v Registrar, Genetic Resources and Others (CCT 80/08) [2009] ZACC 14; 2009
(6) SA 232 (CC); 2009 (10) BCLR 1014 (CC) (3 June 2009).
85 In Biowatch, the Court expressly recognised the importance of the involvement of public
interest organisations in constitutional cases.
86 First Certification Judgment para 111.
87 South African Association of Personal Injury Lawyers v Heath and Others (CCT27/00) [2000]
ZACC 22; 2001 (1) SA 883 (CC); 2001 (1) BCLR 77 (CC) (28 November 2000) paras 18–22.
88 Liebenberg (2010) 66.
89 See Soobramoney and Mazibuko.
90 Fuller, L and Winston, KI (1978–1979) The forms and limits of adjudication Harvard Law
Review 92(2):353–409.
91 Liebenberg (2010) 72.
92 Fuller (1978–1979) 353–409.
93 See First Certification Judgment para 77.
94 Langford (2008) 31.
95 Ray (2016) 16. See also Pieterse, M (2004) Possibilities and pitfalls in the domestic
enforcement of social rights: Contemplating the South African experience Human Rights
Quarterly 26(4):882–905.
96 Keightley (2011) 307.
97 Mazibuko para 161.
98 Mazibuko para 61.
99 TAC para 38.
100 TAC para 38.
101 Mazibuko para 70.
102 Mazibuko para 71.
103 Langford (2008) 32.
104 First Certification Judgment para 111.
105 The Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (CESCR) has adopted the quartet
of state obligations in elucidating the obligations imposed by the various provisions of the
ICESCR though the obligation to promote tends to be encapsulated under the obligation to
fulfil.
106 See TAC para 39 and Grootboom para 84.
107 Glenister v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT 48/10) [2011] ZACC 6;
2011 (3) SA 347 (CC); 2011 (7) BCLR 651 (CC) (17 March 2011) para 105.
108 Leckie, S (1998) Another step towards indivisibility: identifying the key features of
violations of economic, social and cultural rights Human Rights Quarterly 20(1):81–124 at
91.
Sepulveda, MM (2003) The Nature of Obligations under the International Covenant on
109
Economic, Social and Cultural Rights 12 and 172.
110 Craven, M (1993) The domestic application of the International Covenant on Economic,
Social and Cultural Rights Netherlands International Law Review 40(3):367–404 at 110.
111 Biegon (2011) 13, 22.
112 Moyo, K ‘Taming the leviathan: An analysis of the extraterritorial application of the right to
water under the African system for the protection of human rights’ in Chenwi, L and Bulto,
T (eds) (2018) Justice Beyond Borders: The Extraterritorial Reach of African Human Rights
Instruments Intersentia 170.
113 City of Johannesburg Metropolitan Municipality v Blue Moonlight Properties 39 (Pty) Ltd
and Another [2011] ZACC 33; 2012 (2) BCLR 150 (CC); 2012 (2) SA 104 (CC) (1 December
2011).
114 See Gross, AM ‘The right to health in an era of privatisation and globalisation: National and
international perspectives’ in Barak-Erez, D and Gross, AM (2007) Exploring Social Rights:
Between Theory and Practice 303.
115 Craven (1993) 112.
116 Moyo (2018) 171.
117 Craven (1993) 112.
118 Such third parties include individuals, groups, corporations and any other entities as well
as other agents acting under state authority.
119 See De Schutter, O (2010) International Human Rights: Cases, Materials, Commentary 461.
120 Moyo (2018) 172–74. See also Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (2002)
General Comment No 15 The Right to Water UN Doc E/C.12/2002/11 para 12(c)(ii).
121 Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (2002) General Comment No 15 The
Right to Water UN Doc E/C.12/2002/11 para 12(c)(ii) where the it is stated that’ [t]he duty
to fulfil should also be interpreted to require the state to accord the minimum amount of
socio-economic provisions to those who lack the resources to pay for their basic needs.’
122 Moyo (2018) 172–74.
123 Moyo (2018) 172–74.
124 Grootboom para 99.
125 See Grootboom, TAC, Soobramoney and Mazibuko cases.
126 Pejan, R (2004) The right to water: the road to justiciability The George Washington
International Law Review 36:1181–210 at 1186.
127 Pejan (2004) 1186.
128 Kok, A ‘Privatisation and the right to access to water’ in De Feyter, K and Isa, FG (eds)
(2005) Privatisation and Human Rights in the Age of Globalisation 281.
129 See Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights Human Rights Education and
Public Information Activities Relating to the ICESCR (1996) UN Doc E/1996/22, Chapter IV
para 324.
130 The right to access information is constitutionally entrenched in s 32 of the Constitution.
131 Liebenberg, S ‘Adjudicating socio-economic rights under a transformative constitution’ in
Langford, M (ed) (2008) Socio-Economic Rights: Emerging Trends in International and
Comparative Law 78.
132 Liebenberg (2008) 78 has defined ‘horizontal application of the Bill of Rights’ as referring to
the applicability of the Bill of Rights in relations between private parties.
133 For a discussion on the horizontal application of South Africa’s Bill of Rights, see
Liebenberg (2008) 78–9.
134 Daniels v Scribante and Another (CCT50/16) [2017] ZACC 13; 2017 (4) SA 341 (CC); 2017 (8)
BCLR 949 (CC) (11 May 2017) para 48.
135 (CCT 29/10) [2011] ZACC 13; 2011 (8) BCLR 761 (CC) (11 April 2011).
136 Juma Musjid para 58.
137 Juma Musjid para 57.
138 Juma Musjid para 58.
139 Juma Musjid para 59.
140 (CCT50/16) [2017] ZACC 13; 2017 (4) SA 341 (CC); 2017 (8) BCLR 949 (CC) (11 May 2017).
141 Daniels para 37.
142 Daniels para 40.
143 Daniels para 39.
144 Daniels para 54.
145 Liebenberg Socio-Economic Rights (2010) 61.
146 Liebenberg Socio-Economic Rights (2010) 63.
147 Grootboom para 34.
148 S 36 of the Constitution.
149 Quinot, G and Liebenberg, S ‘Narrowing the Band: reasonableness review in administrative
justice and socio-economic rights jurisprudence in South Africa’ in Liebenberg, S and
Quinot, G (eds) (2012) Law and Poverty: Perspectives from South Africa and Beyond 63.
150 Quinot and Liebenberg (2012) 309.
151 Jaftha v Schoeman and Others; Van Rooyen v Stoltz and Others (CCT74/03) [2004] ZACC 25;
2005 (2) SA 140 (CC); 2005 (1) BCLR 78 (CC) (8 October 2004).
152 Jaftha paras 31–4.
153 Act 32 of 1944
154 Jaftha para 12.
155 Jaftha paras 31–4.
156 Gundwana v Steko Development CC and Others (CCT 44/10) [2011] ZACC 14; 2011 (3) SA
608 (CC); 2011 (8) BCLR 792 (CC) (11 April 2011).
157 Liebenberg (2014) 155.
158 Grootboom para 34.
159 Liebenberg (2014) 155.
160 Liebenberg (2014) 155.
161 Grootboom para 34.
162 S 36 of the Constitution.
163 Quinot and Liebenberg (2012) 63.
164 Soobramoney para 12.
165 Soobramoney para 13.
166 Soobramoney para 20.
167 Soobramoney para 19.
168 Soobramoney para 23.
169 Soobramoney para 27.
170 Soobramoney para 31.
171 Soobramoney para 29.
172 Grootboom para 3.
173 Grootboom paras 9–11.
174 Grootboom paras 34–46.
175 Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1991) General Comment No. 3 on the
Nature of States Parties’ Obligations (Fifth Session, 1991), U.N. Doc E/1991/23. The Court
considered and rejected the approach again in TAC at paras 26–39.
176 Grootboom para 22.
177 Grootboom para 37.
178 Grootboom para 20.
179 Grootboom para 35.
180 Grootboom para 35.
181 Grootboom para 35.
182 Grootboom para 36.
183 Grootboom para 41.
184 Grootboom para 41.
185 Grootboom para 41.
186 Grootboom para 40.
187 Grootboom para 43.
188 Grootboom para 46.
189 Grootboom para 43.
190 Grootboom para 42.
191 Grootboom para 45.
192 Grootboom para 39.
193 Grootboom para 42.
194 Grootboom para 44.
195 Grootboom para 44.
196 TAC para 39.
197 Mazibuko para 50.
198 Mazibuko para 71.
199 Mazibuko para 71.
200 See Grootboom para 43.
201 The ICESCR is the primary human rights instrument on economic, social and cultural
rights at the international level.
202 CESCR General Comment No. 3 para. 2.
203 See Occupiers of 51 Olivia Road, Berea Township and 197 Main Street Johannesburg v City
of Johannesburg and Others (24/07) [2008] ZACC 1; 2008 (3) SA 208 (CC); 2008 (5) BCLR 475
(CC) (19 February 2008) paras 10, 16–18.
204 Mbazira, C (2008) Enforcement of Socio-Economic Rights in South Africa: Strengthening
the Reasonableness Approach Nordisk Tidsskrift for Menneskerettigheter 26:131, 136.
205 See, for example, Khosa v Minister of Social Development; Mahlaule v Minister of Social
Development 2004 6 SA 505 (CC) paras 74, 76–77, 79–81.
206 Quinot and Liebenberg (2012) 657.
207 Bilchitz, D (2003) Towards a reasonable approach to the minimum core: Laying the
foundations for future socio- economic rights jurisprudence South African Journal on
Human Rights 19 (1):1–26 at 9–10.
208 Quinot and Liebenberg (2012) 648.
209 Bilchitz (2003) 9–10.
210 Quinot and Liebenberg (2012) 649.
211 Quinot and Liebenberg (2012) 649.
212 Liebenberg (2008) 89.
213 Grootboom para 44.
214 See Grootboom para 79.
215 Bilchitz (2003) 11.
216 Bilchitz (2003) 11.
217 See CESCR General Comment No. 3.
218 CESCR General Comment No. 3 para 10.
219 CESCR General Comment No. 3 para 10.
220 TAC.
221 Mazibuko.
222 See Grootboom paras 23–33; TAC paras 26–39; Mazibuko paras 51–62. The Court pointed to
the difficulty of defining the content of minimum core obligations, a concern that any
definition would not reflect the diversity of needs of differently placed groups, and an
incompatibility with the institutional roles and competencies of the courts.
223 Grootboom para 33.
224 Grootboom para 31.
225 TAC para 34.
226 Mazibuko para 59.
227 Grootboom para 33.
228 Musila, GM ‘Testing two standards of compliance: A modest proposal on the adjudication
of positive socio-economic rights under the new constitution’ in Biegon, J and Musila, GM
(2011) Judicial Enforcement of Socio-Economic Rights under the New Constitution 87.
229 Liebenberg (2014) 168.
230 CESCR General Comment No. 3 para 9.
231 CESCR General Comment No. 3 para 9.
232 Grootboom para 45.
233 Grootboom para 45.
234 Grootboom para 45.
235 President of the Republic of South Africa v Moddderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd (CCT20/04)
[2005] ZACC 5; 2005 (5) SA 3 (CC); 2005 (8) BCLR 786 (CC) (13 May 2005) para 49.
236 Mazibuko para 40.
237 Liebenberg (2010) 188.
238 CESCR General Comment No. 3 para 9.
239 Liebenberg (2010) 191.
240 Liebenberg (2010) 191.
241 Blue Moonlight Properties para 74.
242 Riedel, E ‘Economic, social and cultural rights’ in Krause, C and Scheinin, M (eds) (2009)
International Protection of Human Rights: A Textbook 2nd ed rev service 137.
243 Liebenberg (2010) 192
See United Nations Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights An Evaluation of
244 the Obligations to Take Steps to the Maximum of Available Resources under an Optional
Protocol to the Covenant (2007) UN Doc E/C.12/2007/1 para 5.
245 CESCR (2007) para 8.
246 Soobramoney.
247 Soobramoney para 24.
248 Soobramoney paras 27–8.
249 Soobramoney para 28.
250 Soobramoney para 61.
251 Soobramoney para 61.
252 Ray (2016) 157.
253 South Africa is a state party to the ICESCR which it ratified on 12 January 2015.
254 (CCT 13/03, CCT 12/03) [2004] ZACC 11; 2004 (6) SA 505 (CC); 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC) (4
March 2004).
255 Act 59 of 1992.
256 Khosa para 61.
257 Khosa para 62.
258 Chenwi, L and Tissington, K (2010) Engaging Meaningfully with Government on Socio-
Economic Rights: A Focus on the Right to Housing 8.
259 Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers (CCT 53/03) [2004] ZACC 7; 2005 (1) SA
217 (CC); 2004 (12) BCLR 1268 (CC) (1 October 2004).
260 Olivia Road. The remedy was also applied in Residents of Joe Slovo Community, Western
Cape v Thubelisha Homes, Minister for Housing and Minister of Local Government and
Housing, Western Cape (Centre on Housing Rights and Evictions and Community Law
Centre, University of the Western Cape as amicus curiae) (CCT 22/08) [2009] ZACC 16, 2009
(9) BCLR 847 (CC); 2010 (3) SA 454 (CC) (10 June 2009) and Schubart Park Residents
Association v City of Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality (CCT 23/12) [2012] ZACC 26; 2013
(1) SA 323 (CC); 2013 (1) BCLR 68 (CC) (9 October 2012).
261 Olivia Road para 3.
262 Olivia Road para 21.
263 Olivia Road para 15.
264 Olivia Road para 16.
265 Bilchitz (2018) 59.
266 Bilchitz (2018) 59.
267 Liebenberg (2014) 162.
268 Ray (2016) 116.
269 Ray (2016) 116.
270 Ray (2016) 117.
271 Liebenberg (2014) 153.
272 Biegon (2011) 49.
273 Biegon (2011) 50.
274 Biegon (2011) 49.
275 Fose v Minister of Safety and Security (CCT14/96) [1997] ZACC 6; 1997 (7) BCLR 851; 1997
(3) SA 786 (CC) (5 June 1997) para 94.
276 Fose para 69.
277 See s 85 of the Constitution.
278 S 172(1)(a).
279 S 172(1)(b).
280 S v Bhulwana; S v Gwadiso (CCT12/95, CCT11/95) [1995] ZACC 11; 1996 (1) SA 388 (CC);
1995 (12) BCLR 1579 (29 November 1995) para 32.
281 Liebenberg (2008) 98.
282 Trengove, W (1999) Judicial remedies for violations of socioeconomic rights ESR Review
4:8–11.
283 Liebenberg (2008) 100.
284 Liebenberg (2010) 434.
285 See Sabel, CF and Simon, WH (2004) Destabilization rights: How public law litigation
succeeds Harvard Law Review 117:1015–1101 at 1085.
286 Biegon (2011) 49.
287 Act 19 of 1998.
288 City of JHB Metropolitan Municipality v Blue Moonlight Properties [2011] ZACC 33; 2012 (2)
SA 104 (CC); 2012 (2) BCLR 150 (CC) (1 December 2011).
289 Blue Moonlight.
290 Vally, S (1999) Violence in South African schools Current Issues in Comparative Education
2(1):1–9. See also Brown, K (2006) ‘New’ educational injustices in the ‘new’ South Africa: A
call for justice in the form of vertical equity Journal of Educational Administration
44(5):509–19.
291 Universal Declaration of Human Rights, GA Res 217A (III), UN Doc A/810 at 71 (1948).
292 International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, (1967) 6 ILM 360 993.
Apart from the UDHR and the ICESCR, the right to education is also guaranteed in a
number of other international and regional instruments, such as Article 28(a) of the United
Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child; Article 17 of the African Charter of Human
and Peoples ‘Rights’ and Articles 11(2) and (3) of the African Charter on the Rights and
Welfare of the Child.
293 Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights General Comment Number 13. The
Right to Education (Twenty First Session. 1999). UN Doc E/C.12.1999.10 (1999) para 1.
294 Head of Department: Mpumalanga Department of Education and Another v Hoërskool
Ermelo and Another (CCT40/09) [2009] ZACC 32; 2010 (2) SA 415 (CC); 2010 (3) BCLR 177
(CC) (14 October 2009) para 46.
295 Act 47 of 1953
296 Spaull, N ‘Education in South Africa: A tale of two systems’ 31 August 2012 Politicsweb
available at https://www.politicsweb.co.za/news-and-analysis/education-in-sa-a-tale-of-
two-systems.
297 Chisholm, L ‘The state of South Africa’s schools’ in J Daniel, R Southall and J Lutchman
(eds) (2004) State of the Nation: South Africa 2004-2005 217. See also Spaull, N (2013)
Poverty and Privilege: Primary school inequality in South Africa Working Paper No 13/12,
Stellenbosch University, Department of Economics 437.
298 Zoch, A (2013) The effect of neighbourhoods and school quality on education and labour
market outcomes in South Africa Working Paper No 08/2017, Stellenbosch University,
Department of Economics 3.
299 The Regulations Relating to Minimum Uniform Norms and Standards for Public School
Infrastructure (2013) sets out the basic infrastructure items that all schools must receive as
well as timeframes within which the state is required to deliver these. The minimum
infrastructure standards listed in these regulations includes water, electricity, sanitation,
security, classrooms, computers, libraries, laboratories and sport fields.
300 Draga, L ‘Infrastructure and Equipment’ in F Veriava and T Fish Hodgson (eds) (2017) Basic
Education Rights Handbook: Education Rights in South Africa.
301 Juma Musjid para 43.
302 Hassim, A (2014) The right to education: A textbook case 8–9.
303 MEC for Education: KwaZulu-Natal and Others v Pillay (CCT 51/06) [2007] ZACC 21; 2008
(1) SA 474 (CC); 2008 (2) BCLR 99 (CC) (5 October 2007) para 121.
304 S 26(1).
305 S 27(1).
306 S 29(1)(b).
307 Juma Musjid.
308 Juma Musjid para 37.
309 Woolman, S and Fleish, B The Constitution in the Classroom: Law and Education in South
Africa 1994-2008 (2009) 120.
310 Woolman and Fleish (2009) 121.
311 Woolman and Fleish (2009) 121.
312 Centre for Child Law and Others v Minister of Basic Education and Others (2840/2017)
[2019] ZAECGHC 126; [2020] 1 All SA 711 (ECG); 2020 (3) SA 141 (ECG) (12 December
2019).
313 Centre for Child Law para 90.
314 Centre for Child Law para 98.
315 Centre for Child Law para 99.
316 Gauteng Provincial Legislature: In re Gauteng School Education Bill of 1995 (CCT39/95)
[1996] ZACC 4; 1996 (3) SA 165 (CC); 1996 (4) BCLR (CC) (4 April 1996).
317 Gauteng Provincial Legislature para 9.
318 White Paper on Education and Training GN 196 in GG 16312 of 15 March 1995 ch 7, para
14.
319 World Declaration on Education for Al, accessed on 10 June 2020 available at
https://www.right-to-education.org/sites/right-to-education.org/files/resource-
attachments/UNESCO_World_Declaration_For_All_1990_En.pdf
320 Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1999) General Comment Number 13.
The Right to Education (Twenty First Session. 1999). UN Doc E/C.12.1999.10 para 1.
321 CESCR General Comment No. 13 para 6(a).
322 CESCR General Comment No. 13 para 6(b).
323 CESCR General Comment No. 13 para 6(c).
324 CESCR General Comment No. 13 para 6(d).
325 [2015] ZASCA 198; [2016] 1 All SA 369 (SCA); 2016 (4) SA 63 (SCA). See also Section 27 v
Minister of Basic Education (24565/2012) [2012] ZAGPPHC 114; [2012] 3 All SA 579 (GNP);
2013 (2) BCLR 237 (GNP); 2013 (2) SA 40 (GNP) (17 May 2012) and Basic Education for All v
Minister of Basic Education (23949/14) [2014] ZAGPPHC 251; 2014 (4) SA 274 (GP); [2014] 3
All SA 56 (GP); 2014 (9) BCLR 1039 (GP) (5 May 2014).
326 Basic Education for All para 41.
327 Basic Education for All para 42.
328 Basic Education for All para 43.
329 Juma Musjid.
330 Centre for Child Law.
331 Freedom Stationery (Pty) Ltd v MEC for Education, Eastern Cape (59/2011) [2011]
ZAECELLC 1(16 March 2011).
332 Madzodzo and Others v Minister of Basic Education and Others (2144/2012) [2014]
ZAECMHC 5; [2014] 2 All SA 339 (ECM); 2014 (3) SA 441 (ECM) (20 February 2014).
333 Tripartite Steering Committee and Another v Minister of Basic Education and Others
(1830/2015) [2015] ZAECGHC 67; 2015 (5) SA 107 (ECG); [2015] 3 All SA 718 (ECG) (25 June
2015).
334 Western Cape Forum for Intellectual Disability v Government of the Republic of South Africa
and Another 2011 (5) SA 87 (WCC); 2010] ZAWCHC 544; 18678/2007 (11 November 2010).
335 Giliomee, H (2004) The rise and possible demise of Afrikaans as a public language
Nationalism and Ethnic Politics 10(1):25.
336 South Africa Act (9 Edw. VII c9) 1909.
337 Afrikaans replaced Dutch as an official language in 1925 following the enactment of the
official Languages Act of the Union Act 8 of 1925.
338 Woolman, S and Fleish, B The Constitution in the Classroom: Law and Education in South
Africa 1994-2008 (2009) 46
339 Woolman and Fleish (2009) 46
340 Afriforum para 2.
341 Woolman and Fleish (2009) 48
342 Woolman and Fleish (2009) 48
343 Gelyke Kanse para 84.
344 Hoërskool Ermelo para 52.
345 Hoërskool Ermelo para 53.
346 Hoërskool Ermelo para 52.
347 S 5A(3) of the Schools Act.
348 Norms and Standards for Language Policy in Public Schools GN 1701 in GG 18546 of 19
December 1997.
349 Language in Education Policy GN 1701 in GG 18546 of 19 December 1997.
350 Stein N ‘Language in Schools’ in Veriava F and Fish Hodgson TF (eds) (2017) Basic
education rights handbook: Education Rights in South Africa 216.
351 Woolman, S and Fleisch, B (2014) The Problem of the ‘Other’ Language Constitutional
Court Review 5:142.
352 Afriforum para 48.
353 Afriforum para 50.
354 Afriforum para 52.
355 Afriforum para 53.
356 Afriforum para 62.
357 Gelyke Kanse para 28.
358 Gelyke Kanse para 30.
359 Gelyke Kanse para 31.
360 Gelyke Kanse para 38.
361 Gelyke Kanse para 41.
362 The Higher Education Act 101 of 1997.
363 S 8(1) of the Constitution read with S 29(2).
364 Language Policy for Higher Education GN R1485 in GG 24101 of 25 November 2002.
365 University of the Free State v Afriforum and Another (1027/2016) [2017] ZASCA 32; [2017] 2
All SA 808 (SCA); 2017 (4) SA 283 (SCA) (28 March 2017) para 26.
366 Afriforum paras 49–53.
367 This call is going hand in hand with a call for decolonisation of the curriculum and thus in
favour of decolonised education. This is a response to a complaint that in South African
universities, a particular epistemic hierarchy exists within which African knowledge and
resources are under-valued. See Morreira, S (2017) Steps Towards Decolonial Higher
Education in Southern Africa? Epistemic Disobedience in the Humanities Journal of Asian
and African Studies, 52(3):287–301.
368 Report of the Commission of Enquiry into Higher Education and Training to the President
of the Republic of South Africa 115.
369 Juma Musjid para 37.
370 LEXICO, https://www.lexico.com/definition/availability.
371 The Presidency (2017) Report of the Commission of Inquiry into Higher Education and
Training to the President of the Republic of South Africa 59.
372 LEXICO, https://www.lexico.com/definition/accessibility.
373 Report of the Commission of Inquiry 59.
374 Report of the Commission of Inquiry 59.
375 Grootboom para 35.
376 Grootboom para 37.
377 Grootboom para 36.
378 Grootboom para 36.
379 Grootboom para 36.
380 Grootboom para 41.
381 Grootboom para 44.
382 Grootboom para 46.
383 Grootboom para 45.
384 Grootboom para 45.
385 Grootboom para 45.
386 Grootboom para 46.
Books
Ackermann, L (2012) Human Dignity: Lodestar for Equality in South Africa Cape Town: Juta
Akiba, O (ed) (2004) Constitutionalism and Society in Africa Aldershot, Hants, England;
Burlington VT: Ashgate
Akiba, O ‘Constitutional government and the future of constitutionalism in Africa’ in Akiba, O
(ed) (2004) Constitutionalism and Society in Africa Aldershot, Hants, England; Burlington
VT: Ashgate
Albertyn, C and Goldblatt, B ‘Equality’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2013) Constitutional
Law of South Africa 2nd ed (rev service 5) Cape Town: Juta
Alston, P and Tomasevski, K (eds) (1984) The Right to Food Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff
Publishers
An-Na’im, AA ‘To affirm the full human rights standing of economic, social and cultural rights’
in Ghai, Y and Cottrell, J (2004) Economic, Social and Cultural Rights in Practice: The Role of
Judges in Implementing Economic, Social and Cultural Rights Commonwealth Secretariat
Andrews, P and Ellmann, S (eds) (2001) The Post-Apartheid Constitutions: Perspectives on South
Africa’s Basic Law Johannesburg: Witwatersrand University Press
Badura, P and Dreier, H (eds) (2001) Festschrift 50 Jahre Bundesverfassungsgericht Tubingen:
Mohr Siebeck
Bakan, J ‘What’s wrong with social rights’ in Bakan, J and Schneiderman, D (eds) (1992) Social
Justice and the Constitution: Perspectives on a Social Union for Canada Ottawa: Carleton
University
Bakan, J and Schneiderman, D (eds) (1992) Social Justice and the Constitution: Perspectives on a
Social Union for Canada Ottawa: Carleton University
Barkan, JD (ed) (2009) Legislative Power in Emerging African Democracies Boulder, Colo: Lynne
Rienner Publishers
Barnett, H (2019) Constitutional and Administrative Law 13th ed Ubingdon, UK: Routledge
Basson, DA and Viljoen, HP (1988) South African Constitutional Law 2nd ed Cape Town: Juta
Basson, DA and Viljoen, HP (1988) Suid-Afrikaanse Staatsreg 2de uitg Cape Town: Juta
Bauman, Z (2007) Consuming Life Cambridge; Malden MA: Polity Press
Baxter, L (1984) Administrative Law Cape Town: Juta
Beaudoin, GA and Mendes, E (eds) (1996) The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms
Scarborough, Ont: Carswell Legal
Beinart, W and Delius, P ‘The Natives Land Act of 1913: A template but not a turning point’ in
Cousins, B and Walker, C (eds) (2015) Land Divided Land Restored: Land Reform in South
Africa for the 21st Century Johannesburg: Jacana Media (Pty) Ltd
Benhabib, S (1996) Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political
Princeton, N.J. Princeton University Press
Bennett, T and Murray, C ‘Traditional leaders’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (2013)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed (rev service 5) Lansdowne, Cape Town: Juta
Bennett, TW (2004) Customary Law in South Africa Cape Town: Juta
Berger, JM and Kapczynski, A ‘The story of the TAC case: The potential and limits of socio-
economic rights litigation in South Africa’ in Hurwitz, DR and Satterthwaite, ML (eds) (2009)
Human Rights Advocacy Stories New York: Foundation Press
Bickel, AM (1962) The Least Dangerous Branch: The Supreme Court at the Bar of Politics
Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
Biegon, J ‘The inclusion of socio-economic rights in the 2010 constitution: Conceptual and
practical issues’ in Biegon, J and Musila, GM (eds) (2011) Judiciary Watch Report: Judicial
Enforcement of Socio-Economic Rights under the new Constitution: Challenges and
Opportunities for Kenya Nairobi, Kenya: Kenya Section of the International Commission of
Jurists
Biko, S (1987) I Write What I Like London: Heinemann
Bilchitz, D ‘The performance of socio-economic rights in the South African Constitution’ in
Dixon, R and Roux, T (eds) (2018) Constitutional Triumphs, Constitutional Disappointments:
A Critical Assessment of the 1996 South African Constitution’s Local and International
Influence Cambridge [UK]; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press
Bishop, M ‘Remedies’ in Woolman, S, Bishop, M and Brickhill, J (eds) (2013) Constitutional Law
of South Africa 2nd ed (rev service 5) Cape Town: Juta
Bishop, M and Woolman, S ‘Freedom and Security of the Person’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M
(eds) (2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed (rev service 5) Cape Town: Juta
Bishop, M and Raboshakga, N ‘National legislative authority’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M
(2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed (rev service 5) Cape Town: Juta
Bloed, A et al (eds) (1993) Monitoring Human Rights in Europe: Comparing International
Procedures and Mechanisms Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff
Blyberg, A and Ravindran, DJ (eds) (2000) A Circle of Rights: Economic, Social and Cultural
Rights: A Training Resource New York: International Human Rights Internship
Programme/Asian Forum for Human Rights Development
Bogdanor, V (2009) The New British Constitution Oxford; Portland OR: Hart
Botha, H, Van der Walt, AJ and Van der Walt, JC (2003) Rights and Democracy in a
Transformative Constitution Stellenbosch: African Sun Media
Brand, D ‘The minimum core content of the right to food in context: A response to Rolf
Künneman’ in Brand, D and Russell, S (eds) (2002) Exploring the Core Content of Socio-
economic Rights: South African and International Perspectives Pretoria: Protea Book House
Brand, D ‘The proceduralisation of South African socio-economic rights jurisprudence, or
“What are socio-economic rights for?”’ in Botha, H, Van der Walt, AJ and Van der Walt, JC
(2003) Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution Stellenbosch: African Sun
Media
Brand, D and Russell, S (eds) (2002) Exploring the Core Content of Socio-economic Rights: South
African and International Perspectives Pretoria: Protea Book House
Braun, S (2004) Democracy Off Balance: Freedom of Expression and Hate Propaganda Law in
Canada Toronto: University of Toronto Press
Bronstein, V ‘Conflicts’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa
2nd ed (rev service 5) Cape Town: Juta
Budlender, G ‘Justiciability of socio-economic rights: Some South African experiences’ in Ghai,
Y and Cottrell, J (eds) (2004) Economic, Social and Cultural Rights in Practice: The Role of
Judges in Implementing Economic, Social and Cultural Rights Commonwealth Secretariat
Calland, R (2013) The Zuma Years: South Africa’s Changing Face of Power Cape Town: Zebra
Press
Cameron, E (2014) ‘Dignity and disgrace: Moral citizenship and constitutional protection’ in
Corder, H, Federico, V and Orrù, R (eds) The Quest for Constitutionalism: South Africa since
1994 Farnham, Surrey, England; Burlington, VT, USA: Ashgate
Carnelley, M and Hoctor, S (eds) (2011) Law, Order and Liberty: Essays in Honour of Tony
Matthews Pietermaritzburg: UKZN Press
Carpenter, G (1987) Introduction to South African Constitutional Law Durban: Butterworths
Chanock, M (2001) The Making of South African Legal Culture, 1902-1936: Fear, Favour and
Prejudice Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press
Chaskalson, M et al (eds) (1996) Constitutional Law of South Africa 1st ed Cape Town: Juta
Cheadle, MH ‘Limitation of rights’ in Cheadle, MH, Davis, DM and Haysom, NRL (eds) (2002)
South African Constitutional Law: The Bill of Rights Durban: Butterworths
Cheadle, MH ‘Labour relations’ in Cheadle, MH, Davis, DM and Haysom, NRL (2005) South
African Constitutional Law: The Bill of Rights 2nd ed Durban: LexisNexis Butterworths
Cheadle, MH, Davis, DM and Haysom, NRL (2005) South African Constitutional Law: The Bill of
Rights 2nd ed Durban: LexisNexis
Chemerinsky, E (2009) Constitutional Law 3rd ed New York: Wolters Kluwer Law & Business
Chenwi, L and Tissington, K (2010) Engaging Meaningfully with Government on Socio-Economic
Rights: A Focus on the Right to Housing Bellville: Community Law Centre, University of the
Western Cape
Chenwi, L ‘An appraisal of international law mechanisms for litigating socio-economic rights,
with a particular focus on the Optional Protocol to the International Covenant on Economic,
Social and Cultural Rights and the African Commission and Court’ in Liebenberg, S and
Quinot, G (eds) (2012) Law and Poverty: Perspectives from South Africa and Beyond
Claremont [South Africa]: Juta
Chikane, F (2012) Eight Days in September: The Removal of Thabo Mbeki Johannesburg: Picador,
Africa
Chirwa, DM and Nijzink, L (eds) (2012) Accountable Government in Africa: Perspectives from
Public Law and Political Studies New York: United Nations University Press
Chirwa, DM and Chenwi, L ‘The protection of economic, social and cultural rights in Africa’ in
Chirwa, DM and Chenwi, L (2016) The Protection of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights in
Africa: International, Regional and National Perspectives Cambridge, United Kingdom:
Cambridge University Press
Chisholm, L ‘The state of South Africa’s schools’ in J Daniel, R Southall and J Lutchman (eds)
(2005) State of the Nation: South Africa 2004-2005 Cape Town: HSRC Press; East Lansing,
Michigan: Michigan State University Press
Chothia, F and Jacobs, S ‘Remaking the Presidency: The tension between co-ordination and
centralisation’ in Jacobs, S and Calland, R (eds) (2002) Thabo Mbeki’s World: The Politics and
Ideology of the South African President Pietermaritzburg: University of Natal Press
Claassens, A and Cousins, B (eds) (2008) Land, Power and Custom: Controversies Generated by
South Africa’s Communal Land Rights Act Cape Town: UCT Press; Legal Resources Centre
Claassens, A ‘Law, land and custom, 1913-2014: What is at stake today?’ in Cousins, B and
Walker, C (eds) (2015) Land Divided Land Restored: Land Reform in South Africa for the 21st
Century Auckland Park, South Africa: Jacana
Courchene, TJ and Allen, JR (eds) (2011) The Federal Idea: Essays in Honour of Ronald L Watts
Kingston, Ont: Institute of Intergovernmental Relations, Queens University
Cousins, B and Walker, C (eds) (2015) Land Divided Land Restored: Land Reform in South Africa
for the 21st Century Auckland Park, South Africa: Jacana
Cousins, B and Walker, C (eds) ‘Land divided, land restored: Introduction’ in Cousins, B and
Walker, C (eds) (2015) Land Divided Land Restored: Land Reform in South Africa for the 21st
Century Auckland Park, South Africa: Jacana
Craven, M ‘Introduction to the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights’
in Blyberg, A and Ravindran, DJ (eds) (2000) A Circle of Rights: Economic, Social and
Cultural Rights: A Training Resource New York: International Human Rights Internship
Programme/Asian Forum for Human Rights Development
Currie, I and De Waal, J (2005) The Bill of Rights Handbook 5th ed Cape Town: Juta
Currie, I and De Waal, J (2013) The Bill of Rights Handbook 6th ed Cape Town: Juta
Currie, I and De Waal, J et al (eds) (2001) The New Constitutional and Administrative Law: Vol 1,
Constitutional Law Cape Town: Juta Law
Curtis, MK et al (2006) Constitutional Law in Context 2nd ed vol 1 Durham, NC: Carolina
Academic Press
Davenport, TRH (1987) South Africa: A Modern History 3rd ed Basingstoke; MacMillan New
York: St Martin’s Press
Davis, D (1999) Democracy and Deliberation: Transformation and the South African Legal Order
Cape Town: Juta
Davis D, Chaskalson, M and De Waal, J ‘Democracy and constitutionalism: The role of
constitutional interpretation’ in Van Wyk, DH et al (eds) (1994) Rights and
Constitutionalism: The New South African Legal Order Cape Town: Juta
Davis, DM ‘Freedom and Security of the Person’ in Cheadle, MH, Davis, DM & Haysom, NRL
(eds) (2005) South African Constitutional Law: The Bill of Rights 2nd ed Durban: LexisNexis
Butterworths
De Montesquieu, C (1748) De l’Esprit des Loix (Nugent T (tr), Neumann F (ed) (1949) The Spirit
of the Laws) New York: Hafner Press
De Smith, SA and Brazier, R (1994) Constitutional and Administrative Law 7th ed London,
England; New York, N.Y., USA: Penguin Books
De Smith, SA and Brazier, R (1998) Constitutional and Administrative Law 8th ed London; New
York: Penguin Books
De Ville, J (2005) Judicial Review of Administrative Action in South Africa Durban: LexisNexis
De Ville, J and Steytler, N (1996) Voting in 1999: Choosing an Electoral System Durban:
Butterworths
De Vos, P ‘South Africa’s experience with proportional representation’ in De Ville, J and Steytler,
N (1996) Voting in 1999: Choosing an Electoral System Durban: Butterworths
De Vos, P (2010) On ‘Shoot the Boer’ Hate Speech and the Banning of Struggle Songs Pretoria:
Pretoria University Law Press (PULP)
De Vos, P ‘Balancing independence and accountability: The role of Chapter 9 institutions in
South Africa’s constitutional democracy’ in Chirwa, DM and Nijzink, L (eds) (2012)
Accountable Government in Africa: Perspectives from Public Law and Political Studies New
York: United Nations University Press
De Vos, P and Freeman, W (2014) South African Constitutional Law in Context Cape Town:
Oxford University Press
Delius, P ‘Contested Terrain: Land Rights and Chiefly Power in Historical Perspective’ in
Claassens, A and Cousins, B (eds) (2008) Land, Power & Custom: Controversies generated by
South Africa’s Communal Land Rights Act Athens, OH: Ohio University Press: Legal
Resources Centre
Devenish, GE (1998) A Commentary on the South African Constitution Durban: Butterworths
Devenish, GE (2005) The South African Constitution Durban: LexisNexis Butterworths
Dicey, AV (1885; 1959) Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution 10th ed
Johannesburg: MacMillan
Dlamini, CRM (1995) Human Rights in Africa: Which Way South Africa? Durban: Butterworths
Draga, L ‘Infrastructure and Equipment’ in Veriava F, Thom, A & Fish Hodgson, T (eds) (2017)
Basic Education Rights Handbook: Education Rights in South Africa Braamfontein,
Johannesburg: SECTION27
Dugard, J (1978) Human Rights and the South African Legal Order Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press
Du Bois, F (ed) (2007) Wille’s Principles of South African Law 9th ed Cape Town: Juta
Du Plessis, L and Corder, H (1994) Understanding South Africa’s Transitional Bill of Rights
Kenwyn: Juta
Du Plessis, LM (1999) An Introduction to Law 3rd ed Kenwyn: Juta
Du Plessis M, Penfold G and Brickhill J (2013) Constitutional Litigation Claremont, Cape Town:
Juta
Du Plessis, WJ ‘The public purpose requirement in the calculation of just and equitable
compensation’ in Hoops B et al (eds) (2016) Rethinking Expropriation Law I: Public Interest
in Expropriation [South Africa]; The Hague: Juta: Eleven International Publishing
Du Toit, D et al (2006) Labour Relations Law: A Comprehensive Guide 5th ed Durban: LexisNexis
Dworkin, R (1978) Taking Rights Seriously London: Duckworth
Dworkin, R (1986) Law’s Empire London: Fontana Press
Dyzenhaus, D (1991) Hard Cases in Wicked Legal Systems: South African Law in the Perspective
of Legal Philosophy New York: Oxford University Press
Dyzenhaus, D (1998) Judging the Judges, Judging Ourselves: Truth, Reconciliation and the
Apartheid Legal Order Oxford: Hart
Dyzenhaus, D (2003) Judging the Judges, Judging Ourselves: Truth, Reconciliation and the
Apartheid Legal Order Oxford, England: Hart
Ebrahim, H (1998) The Soul of a Nation: Constitution-making in South Africa Cape Town: Oxford
University Press
Eide, A, Krause, C and Rosas, A (1995) Economic, Social and Cultural Rights: A Textbook
Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff
Ellmann, SJ (1992) In a Time of Trouble: Law and Liberty in South Africa’s State of Emergency
New York: Oxford University Press
Ely, JH (1980) Democracy and Distrust: A Theory of Judicial Review Cambridge: Harvard
University Press
Farlam, P ‘Freedom of religion, belief and opinion’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (2013)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed (rev service 5) Cape Town: Juta
Forsyth, CF (1985) In Danger for Their Talents: A Study of the Appellate Division of the Supreme
Court of South Africa From 1950-1980 Cape Town: Juta
Friedman, S ‘No easy stroll to dominance: Party dominance, opposition and civil society in
South Africa’ in Giliomee, HB and Simkins, CEW (eds) (1999) The Awkward Embrace: One
Party Domination and Democracy Australia: Harwood Academic Publishers
Friedman E and Wong J (eds) (2008) Political Transitions in Dominant Party Systems: Learning
to Lose Abingdon, Oxon; New York: Routledge
Ghai, Y and Cottrell, J (2004) Economic, Social and Cultural Rights in Practice: The Role of Judges
in Implementing Economic, Social and Cultural Rights Commonwealth Secretariat
Ghai, Y and Cottrell, J ‘The role of the courts in the protection of economic, social and cultural
rights’ in Ghai, Y and Cottrell, J (2004) Economic, Social and Cultural Rights in Practice: The
Role of Judges in Implementing Economic, Social and Cultural Rights Commonwealth
Secretariat
Gildenhuys, A (2001) Onteieningsreg 2de uitg Durban: Butterworths
Giliomee, HB and Simkins, CEW (eds) (1999) The Awkward Embrace: One Party Domination
and Democracy Australia: Harwood Academic Publishers
Ginsburg, T and Dixon, R (eds) (2011) Comparative Constitutional Law Cheltenham, UK;
Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar
Goldman, I ‘How does government evaluation in South Africa contribute to democracy?’ in
Podems, D (2017) Democratic Evaluation and Democracy: Exploring the Reality Charlotte,
NC: IAP, Information Age Publishing, Inc.
Govindjee, A ‘Freedom of expression’ in Govindjee, A and Vrancken, P (eds) (2009) Introduction
to Human Rights Law Durban: LexisNexis
Govindjee, A and Olivier, M ‘Finding the boundary: The role of the courts in giving effect to
socio-economic rights in South Africa’ in Osode, PC and Glover, G (eds) (2010) Law and
Transformative Justice in Post-Apartheid South Africa Louis Trichardt: Spekboom Publishers
Govindjee, A and Vrancken, P (eds) (2009) Introduction to Human Rights Law Durban:
LexisNexis
Griffith, JAG and Ryle, M (1989) Parliament: Functions, Practice and Procedures London: Sweet
& Maxwell
Grogan, J (2009) Workplace Law 10th ed Cape Town: Juta
Gross, AM ‘The right to health in an era of privatisation and globalisation: National and
international perspectives’ in Barak-Erez, D and Gross, AM (2007) Exploring Social Rights:
Between Theory and Practice Oxford; Portland, Or.: Har.
Gumede, WM (2006) Thabo Mbeki and the Battle for the Soul of the ANC Cape Town: Zebra Press
Gutto, S (2001) Equality and Non-Discrimination in South Africa: The Political Economy of Law
and Law Making Cape Town: NAE
Gwyn, WB (1965) The Meaning of the Separation of Powers: An Analysis of the Doctrine from its
Origin to the Adoption of the United States Constitution New Orleans: Tulane University
Hahlo, HR and Kahn, E (1960) The Union of South Africa: The Development of its Laws and
Constitution London: Stevens
Hall, DE, Bailey, SJD and Barron, C (2006) Constitutional Law Albany, New York: Delmar Pub
Hall, R ‘Who, what, where how why? The many disagreements about land redistribution in
South Africa’ in Cousins, B and Walker, C (eds) (2015) Land Divided Land Restored: Land
Reform in South Africa for the 21st Century Auckland Park, South Africa: Jacana
Hall, R ‘Two cycles of land policy in South Africa: Tracing the contours’ in Anseeuw, W and
Alden, C (eds) (2010) The Struggle Over Land in Africa: Conflicts, Politics and Change Cape
Town, South Africa: HSRC Press
Handley, A, Murray, C and Simeon, R ‘Learning to lose, learning to win: Government and
opposition in South Africa’s transition to democracy’ in Friedman, E and Wong, J (eds)
(2008) Political Transitions in Dominant Party Systems: Learning to Lose Abingdon, Oxon;
New York: Routledge
Handmaker, J and Berkhout, R (eds) (2010) Mobilising Social Justice in South Africa: Perspectives
from Researchers and Practitioners. The Hague: ISS and Hivos
Hassen, E (1998) The Soul of a Nation: Constitution-Making in South Africa Cape Town: Oxford
University Press
Hassim, A (2014) The right to education: A textbook case
Hatsell, J (1818) Precedents of Proceedings in the House of Commons: With Observations vol 1
London: Hansard
Haynie, SL (2003) Judging in Black and White: Decision Making in the South African Appellate
Division 1950-1990 New York: P Lang
Haysom, N ‘Federal features of the final Constitution’ in Andrews, P and Ellmann, S (eds) (2001)
The Post-Apartheid Constitutions: Perspectives on South Africa’s Basic Law Johannesburg:
Witwatersrand University Press
Haysom, N ‘Dignity’ in Cheadle, H, Davis, D and Haysom, N (eds) (2005) South African
Constitutional Law: The Bill of Rights Durban: LexisNexis
Haysom, N and Kahanovitz, S ‘Courts and the State of Emergency’ in Moss, G and Obery, I (eds)
(1987) South African Review 4 Johannesburg: Ravan Press
Hendricks, FT, Ntsebeza, L and Helliker, K ‘Land questions in South Africa’ in Hendricks, FT,
Ntsebeza, L and Helliker, K (eds) (2013) The Promise of Land: Undoing a Century of
Dispossession in South Africa Auckland Park, South Africa: Jacana Media
Herman, ES and Chomsky, N (1988) Manufacturing Consent: The Political Economy of the Mass
Media New York: Pantheon Books
Heun, W (2010) The Constitution of Germany: A Contextual Analysis Oxford: Hart
Hiebert, JL ‘Constitutional experimentation: Rethinking how a bill of rights functions’ in
Ginsburg, T and Dixon, R (eds) (2011) Comparative Constitutional Law Cheltenham, UK;
Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar
Himonga, C and Nhlapo, T (eds) (2014) African Customary Law in South Africa: Post-apartheid
and Living Law Perspectives 3rd ed Cape Town, South Africa: Oxford University Press
Southern Africa
Hobsbawm, E and Ranger, T (eds) (1983) The Invention of Tradition Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press
Hoexter, C (2007) Administrative Law in South Africa Cape Town: Juta
Hoexter, C ‘The rule of law and the principle of legality in South African administrative law
today’ in Carnelley, M and Hoctor, S (eds) (2011) Law, Order and Liberty: Essays in Honour of
Tony Matthews Pietermaritzburg: UKZN Press
Hogg, PW (2007) Constitutional Law of Canada 5th ed Scarborough, Ontario: Thomson
Carswell
Holness, D and Vrancken, P ‘Non-judicial enforcement of human rights’ in Govindjee, A and
Vrancken, P (eds) (2009) Introduction to Human Rights Law Durban: LexisNexis
Holness, D ‘The right of access to information’ in Govindjee, A and Vrancken, P (2009)
Introduction to Human Rights Law Durban: LexisNexis
Houston, G (ed) (2001) Public Participation in Democratic Governance in South Africa Pretoria:
HSRC
Houston, G, Liebenberg, I and Dichaba, W ‘The social dynamics of public participation in
legislative processes in South Africa’ in Houston, G (ed) (2001) Public Participation in
Democratic Governance in South Africa Pretoria: HSRC
Hueglin, TO and Fenna, A (2006) Comparative Federalism: A Systematic Inquiry Peterborough:
Ontario
Hurwitz, DR and Satterthwaite, ML (eds) (2009) Human Rights Advocacy Stories New York:
Foundation Press
Institute for Public Policy Research (1991) A Written Constitution for the United Kingdom
London: Mansell
Jacobs, S and Calland, R (eds) (2002) Thabo Mbeki’s World: The Politics and Ideology of the South
African President Pietermaritzburg: University of Natal Press
Kairys, D (ed) (1998) The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique New York: Basic Books
King, AS (2007) The British Constitution Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press
Klaaren, J and Penflod, G ‘Just administrative action’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2013)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Klaaren, J ‘Federalism’ in Chaskalson, M et al (eds) (1996) Constitutional Law of South Africa 1st
ed Cape Town: Juta
Klug, H (2010) The Constitution of South Africa: A Contextual Analysis Oxford; Portland Or: Hart
Kok, A ‘Privatisation and the right to access to water’ in Feyter, K de and Gomez Isa, F (eds)
(2005) Privatisation and Human Rights in the Age of Globalisation Antwerp: Intersentia;
Holmes Beach, Florida: Distribution for North America, Gaunt, Inc.
Kommers, DP (1997) The Constitutional Jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany
Durham, NC: Duke University Press
Kommers, DP, ‘The Basic Law of the Federal Republic of Germany: An Assessment After Forty
Years’ in Merkl, PH (ed) (1989) The Federal Republic of Germany at Forty, New York: New
York University Press
Kotze, H (1997) Take Us to Our Leaders: The South African National Assembly and Its Members
Johannesburg: Konrad-Adenauer-Stiftung
Kriel, R and Monadjem, M ‘Public finance’ in Woolman S and Bishop M (2013) Constitutional
Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Kunig, P ‘Der Rechtsstaat’ in Badura, P and Dreier, H (eds) (2001) Festschrift 50 Jahre
Bundesverfassungsgericht Tubingen: Mohr Siebeck
Lacey, M (1981) Working for Boroko: The Origins of a Coercive Labour System in South Africa
Johannesburg: Ravan Press
Langford, M ‘The justiciability of social rights: From practice to theory’ in Langford, M (ed)
(2008) Social Rights Jurisprudence: Emerging Trends in International and Comparative Law
Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press
Le Roux, R ‘Employment’ in Du Bois, F (ed) (2007) Wille’s Principles of South African Law 9th ed
Cape Town: Juta
Liebenberg, S (2010) Socio-Economic Rights Adjudication Under a Transformative Constitution
Cape Town: Juta
Liebenberg, S ‘The interpretation of socio-economic rights’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds)
(2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed (rev service 5) Cape Town: Juta
Liebenberg, S ‘Adjudicating socio-economic rights under a transformative constitution’ in
Langford, M (ed) (2008) Socio-Economic Rights: Emerging Trends in International and
Comparative Law Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press
Locke, J (1690; 1986) Second Treatise of Government Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Co
Lugard, FJD (1922) The Dual Mandate in British Tropical Africa 200–2003 Edinburgh; London:
Blackwood
Luthuli, A (1962) Let My People Go New York: McGraw-Hill
Mamdani, M (1996) Citizen and Subject: Contemporary Africa and the Legacy of Late
Colonialism Kampala: Fountain; Cape Town: David Phillip; London: James Currey
Mann, FA (1990) Further Studies in International Law Oxford: Clarendon Press
Mathenjwa, M (2017) Supervision of Local Government Claremont, Cape Town: Juta
Matlosa, K (2004) The Politics of State Resources: Party Funding in South Africa Johannesburg:
Konrad-Adenauer-Stiftung
Mbazira, C (2009) Litigating socio-economic rights in South Africa: A choice between corrective
and distributive justice [Pretoria] South Africa: Pretoria University Law Press (PULP)
Mbeki, G (1964) South Africa: The Peasants Revolt Baltimore, Md: Penguin Books
McLean, K (2009) Constitutional Deference, Courts and Socio-Economic Rights in South Africa
Pretoria: Pretoria University Law Press (PULP)
Mendes, E ‘The crucible of the Charter’ in Beaudoin, GA and Mendes, E (eds) (1996) The
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms Scarborough, Ont: Carswell Legal
Merkl, PH (ed) (1989) The Federal Republic of Germany at Forty, New York: New York University
Press
Michelman, F ‘The rule of law, legality and the supremacy of the Constitution’ in Woolman, S
and Bishop, M (2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town:
Juta
Minow, M (1990) Making All the Difference: Inclusion, Exclusion and American Law Ithaca:
Cornell University Press
Moss, G and Obery, I (eds) (1987) South African Review 4 Johannesburg: Ravan Press
Motala, Z (1994) Constitutional Options for a Democratic South Africa: A Comparative
Perspective Washington DC: Howard University Press 1994
Moyo, K ‘The advocate, peacemaker, judge and activist: A chronicle on the contributions of
Justice Johann Kriegler to South African constitutional jurisprudence’ in Bohler-Muller, N,
Cosser, M and Pienaar, G (eds) (2018) Making the Road by Walking: The Evolution of the
South African Constitution Pretoria]: Pretoria University Law Press (PULP)
Moyo, K ‘Taming the leviathan: An analysis of the extraterritorial application of the right to
water under the African system for the protection of human rights’ in Chenwi, L and Bulto, T
(eds) (2018) Justice Beyond Borders: The Extraterritorial Reach of African Human Rights
Instruments Antwerp: Intersentia
Mqeke, RB (1997) Basic Approaches to Problem Solving in Customary Law: A Study of
Conciliation and Consensus Amongst the Cape Nguni Grahamstown: Grocott & Sherry
Mtshaulana, PM ‘The history and role of the Constitutional Court in South Africa’ in Andrews, P
and Ellmann, S (2001) The Post-Apartheid Constitutions: Perspectives on South Africa’s Basic
Law Johannesburg: Witwatersrand University Press
Munro, CR (1999) Studies in Constitutional Law 2nd ed London: Butterworths
Murray, C and Stacey, R ‘The President and the National Executive’ in Woolman, S and Bishop,
M (2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Musila, GM ‘Testing two standards of compliance: A modest proposal on the adjudication of
positive socio-economic rights under the new constitution’ in Biegon, J and Musila, GM
(2011) Judiciary Watch Report: Judicial Enforcement of Socio-Economic Rights under the New
Constitution: Challenges and Opportunities for Kenya Nairobi, Kenya: Kenya Section of the
International Commission of Jurists
Nash, A ‘Post-apartheid accountability: The transformation of a political idea’ in Chirwa, DM
and Nijzink, L (2012) Accountable Government in Africa: Perspectives from Public Law and
Political Studies Cape Town: University of Cape Town Press
Ndlovu-Gatsheni, SJ ‘Racism and “blackism” in a world scale’ in Rutazibwa, OU and Shilliam, R
(eds) (2018) Routledge Handbook of Postcolonial Politics Abingdon, Oxon; New York, NY:
Routledge
Nijzink, L and Murray, C (2002) Building Representative Democracy: South Africa’s Legislatures
and the Constitution Cape Town: Parliamentary Support Programme
Norman-Major, KA and Gooden, ST (eds) (2012) Cultural Competence for Public Administrators
Routledge
Ntsebeza, L (2005) Democracy compromised: Chiefs and the politics of the land in South Africa
Leiden: Brill
Nussbaum, MC (2000) Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach
Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press
Oomen, B (2005) Chiefs in South Africa, Law, Power and Culture in the Post-Apartheid Era
Oxford: James Currey
Osode, PC and Glover, G (eds) (2010) Law and Transformative Justice in Post-Apartheid South
Africa Louis Trichardt: Spekboom Publishers
O’ Sullivan, M ‘Reproductive rights’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2006) Constitutional
Law of South Africa 2nd ed original service chap Cape Town: Juta
Patel, L (2015) Decolonizing Educational Research: From Ownership to Answerability New York:
Routledge
Patzer, GL (1985) The Physical Attractiveness Phenomena New York: Plenum Press
Peires, J (1981) The House of Phalo: A history of the Xhosa people in the days of their
independence Johannesburg: Ravan Press
Penfold, G and Reyburn, P ‘Public procurement’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (2013)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Pienaar, JM (2014) Land Reform Claremont: Juta
Plaatje, ST (2007) Sol Plaatje’s Native Life in South Africa: Past and Present Johannesburg: Wits
University Press
Pottinger, B (1988) The Imperial Presidency: PW Botha, The First Ten Years Stellenbosch:
Southern Book Publishers
Pradham, R (ed) (2002) Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law in Social, Economic and Political
Development International Centre for the Study of Nature, Environment and Culture
Quinot, G and Liebenberg, S ‘Narrowing the Band: reasonableness review in administrative
justice and socio-economic rights jurisprudence in South Africa’ in Liebenberg, S and
Quinot, G (eds) (2012) Law and Poverty: Perspectives from South Africa and Beyond
Claremont [South Africa]: Juta
Rautenbach, IM and Malherbe, EFJ (2009) Constitutional Law 5th ed Durban: LexisNexis
Rautenbach, IM and Malherbe, EFJ (2012) Constitutional Law 6th ed Durban: LexisNexis
Rautenbach, I (2011) ‘Introduction to the Bill of Rights’ in The Bill of Rights Compendium (1996)
(one vol loose-leaf ) Durban: LexisNexis
Rautenbach, IM and Venter, R (2018) Rautenbach-Malherbe Constitutional Law 7th ed Durban:
LexisNexis
Ray, BE (2016) Engaging with social rights: Procedure, participation and democracy in South
Africa’s second wave Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Reynolds, A (1999) Electoral Systems and Democratisation in Southern Africa New York: Oxford
University Press
Riedel, E ‘Economic, social and cultural rights’ in Krause, C and Scheinin, M (eds) (2009)
International Protection of Human Rights: A Textbook 2nd ed rev service Turku: Åbo
Akademi University. Institute for Human Rights
Roach, K ‘Crafting Remedies for Violations of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights’ in Squires, J
(ed) (2005) The Road to a Remedy: Current Issues in the Litigation of Economic, Social and
Cultural Rights Geneva, Switzerland: Centre for Housing Rights and Eviction
Roederer, C ‘Founding provisions’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (2013) Constitutional Law of
South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Roux, T (2013) The politics of principle: The first South African Constitutional Court, 1995–2005
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Roux, T ‘Assessing the social transformation performance of the South African Constitutional
Court: From totalitarianism to the rule of law’ in Jenkins, C and du Plessis, M (eds) (2014)
Law, Nation-Building and Transformation: The South African Experience in Perspective
Cambridge; Antwerp: Intersentia
Roux, T ‘Democracy’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa
2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Roux, T ‘Property’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2013) Constitutional law of South Africa
2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Sachs, A ‘The judicial enforcement of socio-economic rights: The Grootboom case’ in Jones, P
and Stokke, K (eds) (2005) Democratising Development: The Politics of Socio-Economic
Rights in South Africa Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff; Biggleswade: Extenza Turpin
Scheinin, M ‘Economic and social rights as legal rights’ in Eide, A, Krause, C and Rosas, A (1995)
Economic, Social and Cultural Rights: A Textbook Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff
Schutter, O de (2010) International Human Rights: Cases, Materials, Commentary Cambridge;
New York: Cambridge University Press
Seedorf, S and Sibanda, S ‘Separation of powers’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2013)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Sepulveda, MM (2003) The Nature of Obligations under the International Covenant on
Economic, Social and Cultural Rights Antwerp: Intersentia
Shue, H (1980) Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence and US Foreign Policy Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press
Sinclair, J (1996) The Law of Marriage, Vol 1 Cape Town: Juta
Singer, JW (2000) The edges of the field: Lessons on the Obligations of Ownership Boston: Beacon
Press
Slade, BV ‘Less invasive means: The relationship between sections 25 and 36 of the Constitution
of the Republic of South Africa, 1996’ in Hoops, B et al (eds) (2015) Rethinking Expropriation
Law I: Public Interest in Expropriation [South Africa]; The Hague: Juta: Eleven International
Publishing
Smuts, D and Westcott, S (eds) (1991) The Purple Shall Govern: A South African A-Z of
Nonviolent Action Cape Town: Oxford University Press, Centre For Intergroup Studies
Sparks, AH (1994) Tomorrow is Another Country: The Inside Story of South Africa’s Revolution
Johannesburg: Struik
Spitz, R and Chaskalson, M (2000) The Politics of Transition: A Hidden History of South Africa’s
Negotiated Settlement Johannesburg: Witwatersrand University Press
Squires, J (ed) (2005) The Road to a Remedy: Current Issues in the Litigation of Economic, Social
and Cultural Rights Geneva, Switzerland: Centre for Housing Rights and Eviction
Stein N ‘Language in Schools’ in Veriava F and Fish Hodgson TF (eds) (2017) Basic education
rights handbook: Education Rights in South Africa Braamfontein, Johannesburg: SECTION27
Stern, K (1977) Das Staatsrecht der Bundesrepublik Deutschland vol 1 Munchen: Beck
Steytler, N ‘The legislative framework governing party funding in South Africa’ in Matlosa, K
(2004) The Politics of State Resources: Party Funding in South Africa Johannesburg: Konrad-
Adenauer-Stiftung
Steytler, N ‘Co-operative and coercive models of intergovernmental relations: A South African
case study’ in Courchene, TJ and Allen, JR (eds) (2011) The Federal Idea: Essays in Honour of
Ronald L Watts Kingston, Ont: Institute of Intergovernmental Relations, Queens University
Steytler, N and De Visser, J ‘Local government’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2013)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Stone, GR (ed) (1996) Constitutional Law 3rd ed Boston: Little, Brown
Tribe, LH (1988) American Constitutional Law 2nd ed Foundation Press
Underkuffler, LS (2003) The idea of property: Its Meaning and Power Oxford; New York: Oxford
University Press
Vail, L (ed) (1989) The Creation of Tribalism in Southern Africa London: James Currey
Van der Walt, AJ (2011) Constitutional Property Law 3rd ed Cape Town: Juta Law
Van der Walt, AJ ‘The future of common law landownership’ in Van der Walt, AJ (ed) (1991)
Land reform and the future of landownership in South Africa Cape Town: Juta
Van der Walt, AJ ‘A South African reading of Frank Michelman’s theory of social justice’ in
Botha, H, Van der Walt, AJ and Van der Walt, JC (2003) Rights and Democracy in a
Transformative Constitution Stellenbosch: African Sun Media
Van der Walt, AJ and Kleyn, DG ‘Duplex dominium: The history and significance of the concept
of divided ownership’ in Visser, DP (ed) (1989) Essays on the History of Law Cape Town: Juta
Van der Walt, AJ and Pienaar, GJ (2016) Introduction to the Law of Property 7th ed Claremont:
Juta
Van Hoof, GJH (1984) ‘The legal nature of economic, social and cultural rights: A rebuttal of
some traditional views’ in Alston, P and Tomasevski, K (eds) (1984) The Right to Food
Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers
Van Niekerk, A (2012) Law@Work 2nd ed Durban: LexisNexis
Van Wyk, DH et al (eds) (1994) Rights and Constitutionalism: The New South African Legal Order
Cape Town: Juta
Vani, MS ‘Customary law and modern governance of natural resources in India: Conflicts,
prospects for accord and strategies’ in Pradham, R (ed) (2002) Legal Pluralism and
Unofficial Law in Social, Economic and Political Development International Centre for the
Study of Nature, Environment and Culture
Venter, F (2000) Constitutional Comparison: Japan, Germany, Canada and South Africa as
Constitutional States Cape Town: Juta
Vile, MJC (1967) Constitutionalism and the Separation of Powers Oxford: Clarendon
Viljoen, S (2016) The law of landlord and tenant Cape Town: Juta
Viljoen, F (2012) International Human Rights Law in Africa 2nd ed Oxford, UK: Oxford
University Press
Wade, ECS and Bradley, AW (1993) Constitutional and Administrative Law 11th ed London:
Longman
Waldron, J (1999) Law and Disagreement New York: Oxford University Press
Welsh, D (1971) The Roots of Segregation: Native Policy in Colonial Natal 1845-1910 Cape Town,
New York: Oxford University Press
Welsh, D ‘Can South Africa become a nation state?’ in van Vuuren, DJ et al (eds) (1991) South
Africa in the Nineties Pretoria, South Africa: HSRC
Williams, LA ‘Welfare and legal entitlements: The social roots of poverty’ in Kairys, D (ed) (1998)
The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique New York: Basic Books
Woolman, S ‘Community rights: Language, culture and religion’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M
(2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Woolman, S ‘Application’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2013) Constitutional Law of
South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Woolman, S ‘Assembly, demonstration, picket and petition’ in Currie, I and De Waal, J (2013)
The Bill of Rights Handbook 6th ed Cape Town: Juta
Woolman, S ‘Freedom of association’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (2013) Constitutional Law
of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Woolman, S ‘The widening gyre of dignity’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (2013) Constitutional
Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5 Cape Town: Juta
Woolman, S & Botha, H ‘Limitations’ in Woolman S, Roux T & Bishop M (eds) (2013)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5
Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed rev service 5
Cape Town: Juta
Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2008) Constitutional Conversations Pretoria: Pretoria
University Law Press
Woolman, S and Fleish, B (2009) The Constitution in the Classroom: Law and Education in South
Africa 1994-2008 Pretoria: Pretoria University Law Press (PULP)
Woolman, S and Roux, T ‘Co-operative government and intergovernmental relations’ in
Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2013) Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed (rev
service 5) Cape Town: Juta
Woolman, S and Swanepoel, J ‘Constitutional history’ in Woolman, S and Bishop, M (eds) (2013)
Constitutional Law of South Africa 2nd ed (rev service 5) Cape Town: Juta
Young, RJC (2003) Postcolonialism: A very short introduction Oxford; New York: Oxford
University Press
Zakrzewski, R (2005) Remedies Reclassified Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press
Encyclopaedias
Britannica Academic Edition available at
http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/231865/gerrymandering
Freedman, DW (2009) ‘Constitutional law: Bill of Rights’ in Joubert, WA (ed) (2012) Law of South
Africa 2nd ed Vol 5 Part 4 Durban: Butterworths
Freedman, DW (2009) ‘Constitutional law: Structures of government’ in Joubert, WA (ed) (2012)
Law of South Africa 2nd ed Vol 5 Part 4 Durban: Butterworths
Kohn, L and Corder, H (2013) ‘Judicial regulation of administrative action’ International
Encyclopaedia of Laws available at http://www.ielaws.com/index.htm
Van der Vyver, JD (2009) ‘Religion’ in Joubert, WA (ed) Law of South Africa 2nd ed Vol 23
Durban: Butterworths
Journal articles
(1987) Limburg Principles on the Implementation of the Covenant on Economic, Social and
Cultural Rights Human Rights Quarterly 9(2):122–35
(1995, December) Bangalore Declaration and Plan of Action reprinted in International
Commission of Jurists 55:219–27
(1998) The Maastricht Guidelines on Violations of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights Human
Rights Quarterly 20(3):691–704
Ackerman, B (2000) The new separation of powers Harvard Law Review 113(3):633–729
Ackermann, BA (1984) The Storrs Lectures: Discovering the Constitution Yale Law Journal
93:1013–72
African National Congress (1989) ‘Constitutional Guidelines for a Democratic South Africa’
reprinted in South African Journal on Human Rights 5(2):129–32
Albertyn, CH (2015) Adjudicating affirmative action within a normative framework of
substantive equality and the employment equity act – An opportunity missed? South African
Police Service v Solidarity obo Barnard South African Law Journal 132(4):711–34
Albertyn, C (2015) Claiming and defending abortion rights in South Africa Revista Direito GV
11(2):429–54
Albertyn, C (2018) Getting it right in equality cases. The evaluation of positive measures, groups
and subsidiarity in Solidariteit v Minister of Basic Education South African Law Journal
135(3): 403–418
Albertyn, C and Goldblatt, B (1998) Facing the challenge of transformation: Difficulties in the
development of an indigenous jurisprudence of equality South African Journal on Human
Rights 14(2):248–76
Alence, R (2004) South Africa after apartheid: The first decade Journal of Democracy 15(3):78–92
Alston, P and Scott, C (2000) Adjudicating constitutional priorities in a transnational context: A
comment on Soobramoney’s legacy and Grootboom’s promise South African Journal on
Human Rights 16(2):206–68
Badenhorst, P and Young, C (2017) The notion of constitutional property in South Africa: An
analysis of the Constitutional Court’s approach in Shoprite Checkers (Pty) Ltd v MEC for
Economic Development, Eastern Cape 2015 (6) SA 125 (CC) Stellenbosch Law Review
28(1):26–46
Banda, C (2019) Redefining religion? A critical Christian reflection on CRL Rights Commission’s
proposal to regulate religion in South Africa Verbum et Ecclesia 40(1):7
Bandes, S (1990) The negative constitution: A critique Michigan Law Review 88(8):2271–347
Basson, D (1987) Judicial activism in a State of Emergency: An examination of recent decisions
of the South African courts South African Journal on Human Rights 3(1):28–43
Beall, J, Mkhize, S and Vawda, S (2005) Emergent democracy and ‘resurgent’ tradition:
Institutions, chieftancy and transition in KwaZulu-Natal Journal of Southern African Studies
31(4):755–71
Beetham, D (2004) Towards a universal framework for democracy assessment Democratization
11(2):1–17
Berger, JM (2001) Litigation strategies to gain access to treatment for HIV/AIDS: The case of
South Africa’s Treatment Action Campaign Wisconsin International Law Journal 20:595–614
Berman, G and Feinblatt, J (2001) Problem-solving courts: A brief primer Law and Policy
23(2):125–40
Bilchitz, D (2003) Towards a reasonable approach to the minimum core: Laying the foundations
for future socio-economic rights jurisprudence South African Journal on Human Rights
19(1):1–26
Bilchitz, D (2011) Should religious organisations be entitled to discriminate? South African
Journal on Human Rights 27(2):219–48
Birks, P (1985) The Roman law concept of dominium and the idea of absolute ownership Acta
Juridica 1–38
Bishop, M and Brickhill, J (2010) Constitutional Law Juta’s Annual Survey of South African Law
224
Bishop, M and Brickhill, J ‘Constitutional law’ (2010) Juta’s Annual Survey of South African Law
Cape Town: Juta
Bishop, M, Brickhill, J and Moshikaro, K (2016) ‘Constitutional Law’ Juta’s Quarterly Review
2.14.2
Blaauw-Wolf, L and Wolf, J (1996) A comparison between German and South African limitation
provisions South African Law Journal 113:267–96
Boggenpoel, ZT (2013) The decision to order transfer of encroached-upon land: A constitutional
analysis Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 76:1–15
Bollyky, TJ (2002) R if C>P+B: A paradigm for judicial remedies of socio-economic rights
violations South African Journal on Human Rights 18(2):161–200
Botha, H (2009) Equality, plurality and structural power South African Journal on Human Rights
25(1):1–37
Botha, H (2010) Instituting public freedom or extinguishing constituent power? Reflections on
South Africa’s Constitution-making experiment South African Journal on Human Rights
26(1):66–84
Brand, D (1999) The South African Human Rights Commission: First economic and social rights
report ESR Review 2(1):18–20
Brand, D (2002) Disclaimers in hospital admission contracts and constitutional health rights:
Cases ESR Review 3(2)17–8
Brand, D and Liebenberg, S (2000) The South African Human Rights Commission: The second
economic and social rights report ESR Review 2(3):12–6
Brandt, AM (1978) Racism and Research: The Case of the Tuskegee Syphilis Study The Hastings
Center Report 8(6):21–9
Brits, R (2014) The statutory security right in section 118(3) of the Local Government: Municipal
Systems Act 32 of 2000 – does it survive transfer of the land? [Discussion of City of Tshwane
Metropolitan Municipality v Mathabathe 2013 4 SA 319 (SCA)] Stellenbosch Law Review
25(3):536–46
Bronstein, V and Robinson, K (1996) Constitutional jurisprudence and the Bill of Rights Juta’s
Annual Survey of South African Law 53
Brown, J (2012) Judges’ history: On the use of history in the Malema judgment South African
Journal on Human Rights 28(2):316-27
Brown, K (2006) ‘New’ educational injustices in the ‘new’ South Africa: A call for justice in the
form of vertical equity Journal of Educational Administration 44(5):509–19
Calabresi, SG, Berghausen, ME and Albertson, S (2012) The rise and fall of the separation of
powers Northwestern University Law Review 106(2):527–50
Cameron, E (1982) Legal chauvinism, executive- mindedness and justice: LC Steyn’s impact on
South African law South African Law Journal 99(1):38–75
Cameron, E (1993) Sexual orientation and the Constitution: A test case for human rights South
African Journal on Human Rights 110(3):450–72
Carstens, PA and Kok, JA (2003) An assessment of the use of disclaimers against medical
negligence by South African hospitals in view of constitutional demands, foreign law and
medico-legal considerations SA Public Law 18(2):430–55
Chaskalson, A (2000) The Third Bram Fischer Lecture: Human dignity as a foundational value of
our constitutional order South African Journal on Human Rights 16(2):193–205
Chemerinsky, E (1989) Foreword: The vanishing Constitution Harvard Law Review 103:43–102
Choudry, S (2009) ‘He had a mandate’: The South African Constitutional Court and the African
National Congress in a dominant party democracy Constitutional Court Review 2:1–86
Claassens, A (2011) Resurgence of tribal levies: Double taxation for the rural poor South African
Crime Quarterly 35: 11
Corder, H (2004) Judicial authority in a changing South Africa Legal Studies 24(2):253–74
Cowen, S (2001) Can dignity guide South Africa’s equality jurisprudence? South African Journal
on Human Rights 17(1):34–58
Craven, M (1993) The domestic application of the International Covenant on Economic, Social
and Cultural Rights Netherlands International Law Review 40(3):367–404
Czapanskiy, K and Manjoo, R (2008) The right of public participation in the law-making process
and the role of the legislature in the promotion of this right Duke Journal of Comparative
and International Law 19:6. 118
Davis, DM (1992) The case against the inclusion of socio-economic demands in a bill of rights
except as directive principles South African Journal on Human Rights 8(4):475–90
Davis, DM (1999) Equality: The majesty of legoland jurisprudence South African Law Journal
116:398–414
Davis, DM (2006) Adjudicating the socio-economic rights in the South African Constitution:
Towards deference lite South African Journal on Human Rights 22(2):301–27
Davis, DM (2010) Judicial appointments in South Africa Advocate 40–43
Davis, DM (2012) How many positivist legal philosophers can be made to dance on the head of
a pin? A reply to Professor Fagan South African Law Journal 129(1):59–72
Davis, DM (2013) The importance of reading: A rebuttal to the jurisprudence of Anton Fagan
South African Law Journal 130(1):52–9
Davis, DM and Klare, K (2010) Transformative constitutionalism and the common and
customary law South African Journal on Human Rights 26(3):403-509
Davis, RPB (1914) Women as advocates and attorneys South African Law Journal 31(4):383–86
De Lange, R and Mevis, PAM (2007) Constitutional guarantees for the independence of the
judiciary Electronic Journal of Comparative Law 11(1):1–17
De Villiers, B (1994) Intergovernmental relations: The duty to co-operate – A German
perspective SA Public Law 9(1–2):430–7
De Villiers, N (2002) Social grants and the Promotion of Administrative Justice Act South African
Journal on Human Rights 18(3):320–49
De Vos, P (1997) Pious wishes or directly enforceable human rights: Social and economic rights
in South Africa’s 1996 Constitution South African Journal on Human Rights 13(1):67–101
De Vos, P (2000) Equality for all? A critical analysis of the equality jurisprudence of the
Constitutional Court Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 63(1):62–75
De Vos, P (2001) A bridge too far? History as context in the interpretation of the South African
Constitution South African Journal on Human Rights 17(1):1–33
De Vos, P (2001) Grootboom, the right of access to housing and substantive equality as
contextual fairness South African Journal on Human Rights 17(2):258–76
De Vos, P (2004) The Promotion of Equality and Prevention of Unfair Discrimination Act and
socio-economic rights ESR Review 5(2):7–11
De Vos, P (2009) Freedom of assembly and its limits Without Prejudice 9(8):4–5
De Vos, P (2012) The past is unpredictable: Race, redress and remembrance in the South African
Constitution South African Law Journal 129(1):73–103
De Vos, P (2015) It’s my party (and I’ll do what I want to?): internal party democracy and section
19 of the South African Constitution South African Journal on Human Rights 31:30–55
De Vos, P (2017) Rejecting the free marketplace of ideas: a value-based conception of the limits
of free speech South African Journal on Human Rights 33(3):359–79
De Vos, P (2018) The constitutional limits of disruptive protest: the case of student protest in
South Africa Journal for Human Rights/Zeitschrift für Menschenrechte 51(4): 64–86
Deflem, M (1999) Warfare, political leadership and state formation: The case of the Zulu
Kingdom, 1808-1879 Ethnology 38(4):371–91
Douwes, R, Stuttaford, M and London, L (2018) Social solidarity, human rights, and collective
action: Considerations in the implementation of the national health insurance in South
Africa Health and Human Rights Journal 20(2):185–96
Du Bois, F (2002) Tenure on the Constitutional Court South African Law Journal 119(1):1–17
Du Plessis, M (2002) Between apology and utopia: The Constitutional Court and public opinion
South African Journal on Human Rights 18(1):1–40
Du Plessis, M and Penfold, G (2008) Bill of Rights Jurisprudence: Operational provisions of the
Bill of Rights Juta’s Annual Survey of South African Law 50
Du Plessis, M and Penfold, G ‘Bill of Rights jurisprudence: Operational provisions of the Bill of
Rights’ (2008) Juta’s Annual Survey of South African Law Cape Town: Juta
Du Plessis, M and Scott, S (2013) The variable standard of rationality review: Suggestions for
improved legality jurisprudence South African Law Journal 130(3):597–620
Du Plessis, M and Palmer, T (2018) Property rights and their continued open-endedness – A
critical discussion of Shoprite and the Constitutional Court’s property clause jurisprudence
Stellenbosch Law Review 29(1):73–89
Dubow, S (1992) Afrikaner nationalism, apartheid and the conceptualization of race Journal of
African History 33(2):209–37
Dugard, J (1990) A Bill of Rights for South Africa Cornell International Law Journal 23(3):441
Dugard, J (2007) Judging the judges: Towards an appropriate role for the role of the judiciary in
South Africa’s transformation Leiden Journal of International Law 20(4):965–81
Dugard, J and Seme, N (2018) Property rights in court: An examination of judicial attempts to
settle section 25’s balancing act re restitution and expropriation South African Journal on
Human Rights 34:1, 33–56
Dupper, O (2004) In defence of affirmative action South African Law Journal 12(1):187–215
Dupper, O, MacEwan, M and Louw, A (2006) Employment equity in the tertiary sector in the
Western Cape International Journal of Discrimination and the Law 8(3):191–212
Dyzenhaus, D (2007) The pasts and future of the rule of law in South Africa South African Law
Journal 124(4):734–61
Ebadolahi, M (2008) Using structural interdicts and the South African Human Rights
Commission to achieve judicial enforcement of economic and social rights in South Africa
New York University Law Review 83(5):1565–606
Elliot, M (2004) United Kingdom: Parliamentary sovereignty under pressure International
Journal of Constitutional Law 2(3):545–627
Ellmann, SJ (1995) Law and legitimacy in South Africa Law and Social Inquiry 20(2):407–79
Fagan, A (1998) Dignity and unfair discrimination: A value misplaced and a right
misunderstood South African Journal on Human Rights 14(2):220–47
Fagan, A (2010) The secondary role of the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights in the
common law’s development South African Law Journal 127(3):611–27
Fagan, A (2012) A straw man, three red herrings and a closet rule-worshipper: A rejoinder to
Davis JP South African Law Journal 129(3):788–98
Forsyth, C (1991) Interpreting a bill of rights: The future task of a reformed judiciary South
African Journal on Human Rights 7(1):1–23
Freeman, G (1983) The misguided search for the constitutional definition of religion
Georgetown Law Journal 71(6):1519–66
Friedman, B (2002) The birth of an academic obsession: The history of the counter-majoritarian
difficulty Part Five Yale Law Journal 112(2):153–260
Fuller, L and Winston, KI (1978–1979) The forms and limits of adjudication Harvard Law Review
92(2):353–409
Gaibie, S (2015) The Constitutional Court decision in Barnard: A sequel to the Van Heerden
judgment Industrial Law Journal 36(1):80–93
Gibson, JL and Caldeira, GA (2003) Defenders of democracy? Legitimacy, popular acceptance
and the South African Constitutional Court Journal of Politics 65(1):1–30
Giliomee, HB (1998) South Africa’s emerging dominant-party regime Journal of Democracy
9(4):128–42
Giliomee, HB, Myburgh, J and Schlemmer, L (2001) Dominant party rule, opposition parties and
minorities in South Africa Democratization 8(1):161–82
Giliomee, H (2004) The rise and possible demise of Afrikaans as a public language Nationalism
and Ethnic Politics 10(1):25
Group of Experts on Limburg Principles (1998) The Maastricht Guidelines on Violations of
Economic, Social and Cultural Rights Human Rights Quarterly 20(3):691–704
Hall, R (2004) Land restitution in South Africa: Rights, development, and the restrained state
Canadian Journal of African Studies 38(3):654–71
Hamill, J (2004) The elephant and the mice: Election 2004 and the future of opposition politics
in South Africa The Round Table: The Commonwealth Journal of International Affairs
93(377):691–708
Harms, D (2017) Does the Constitutional Court have plenary (unlimited) appeal jurisdiction?
De Rebus (April)13
Hendricks, F and Ntsebeza, L (1999) Chiefs and rural local government in post-apartheid South
Africa African Journal of Political Science 4(1):99–126
Heyns, CH (1997) Extended medical training and the Constitution: Balancing civil and political
rights and socio-economic rights De Jure 30(1):1–17
Heywood, M (2009) South Africa’s Treatment Action Campaign: Combining law and social
mobilization to realize the right to health Journal of Human Rights Practice 1(1):14–36
Higginbotham, FM (1994) Sins from the past and lessons for the future: Eliminating apartheid in
South African public accommodation and the challenge to an enlightened judiciary Boston
University International Law Journal 12(1):1–56
Hoexter, C (2004) The principle of legality in South African administrative law Macquarie Law
Journal 3(4):165–86
Hutchinson, AC (1990) Mice under a chair: Democracy, courts and the administrative state
University of Toronto Law Journal 40(3):374–404
Iles, K (2007) A fresh look at limitations: Unpacking section 36 South African Journal on Human
Rights 23(1):68–92
Issacharoff, S (2002) Gerrymandering and political cartels Harvard Law Review 116(2):593–648
Iyer, D (2012) Is the determination of compensation a pre-requisite for the constitutional
validity of expropriation? Haffejee NO and Others v Ethekwini Municipality and Others
Speculum Juris 2:66–74
Jenkins, D and Johnston, LB (2004) Unethical Treatment of Gay and Lesbian People with
Conversion Therapy Families in Society 85(4):557–61
Kaganas, F and Murray, C (1994) The Contest between Culture and Gender Equality under
South Africa’s Interim Constitution Journal of Law and Society 21(4):409–33
Kateb, G (1981) The moral distinctiveness of representative democracy Ethics 91(3):357–74
Keightley, R (2011) The challenges of litigating socio-economic rights in South Africa New
Zealand Law Review 2011(2): 296–99
Kentridge, S (2003) The highest court: Selecting the judges Cambridge Law Journal 62(1):55–71
Kerr, AJ (1984) Back to the problems of a hundred or more years ago: Public policy concerning
contracts relating to marriages that are potentially or actually polygamous South African
Law Journal 101(3):445–56
Khunou, SF (2009) Traditional leadership and independent Bantustans of South Africa: Some
milestones of transformative constitutionalism beyond apartheid Potchefstroom Electronic
Law Journal 12(4):81–87
Klare, K (1998) Legal culture and transformative constitutionalism South African Journal on
Human Rights 14(1):146–88
Klare, K (2008) Legal subsidiarity and constitutional rights: A reply to AJ Van der Walt
Constitutional Court Review 1:129–40
Kloppers, HJ and Pienaar, GJ (2014) The historical context of land reform in South Africa and
early policies Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal 17:677–706
Kollapen, J (1999) Monitoring socio-economic rights: What has the SA Human Rights
Commission done? ESR Review 1(4):18–20
Kuper, A (1997) Review: The Mfecane Aftermath: Reconstructive Debates in Southern African
History by Carol Hamilton Current Anthropology 38(3): 471–3
Kurki, M (2012) Democracy and conceptual contestability: Reconsidering conceptions of
democracy in democracy promotion International Studies Review 12(3):362–86
Langa, P (2006) Transformative constitutionalism Stellenbosch Law Review 17(3):351–60
Larkins, CM (1996) Judicial independence and democratization: A theoretical and conceptual
analysis American Journal of Comparative Law 44(4):605–25
Leckie, S (1998) Another step towards indivisibility: identifying the key features of violations of
economic, social and cultural rights Human Rights Quarterly 20(1):81–124
Lenta, P (2001) Just gaming? The case for postmodernism in South African legal theory South
African Journal on Human Rights 17(2):173–209
Lenta, P (2004) Democracy, rights disagreements and judicial review South African Journal on
Human Rights 20(1):1–31
Lenta, P (2012) The right of religious associations to discriminate South African Journal on
Human Rights 28(2):231–57
Liebenberg, S (1995) ‘The International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights and
its implications for South Africa South African Journal on Human Rights 11(2):359–78
Liebenberg, S (2005) The value of human dignity in interpreting socio-economic rights South
African Journal on Human Rights 21(1):1–31
Liebenberg, S (2014) Judicially enforceable socio-economic rights in South Africa: Between light
and shadow Dublin University Law Journal 37:137–72
Lodge, T (2004) The ANC and the development of party politics in modern South Africa Journal
of Modern African Studies 42(2):189–219
Lowry, MP (2008) Legitimizing elections through the regulation of campaign financing: A
comparative constitutional analysis and hope for South Africa Boston College International
and Comparative Law Review 31(2):185–212
Lucas M (2006) On gay porn Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 18(1):299–302
Madala, T (2001) Rule under apartheid and the fledging democracy in post-apartheid South
Africa: The role of the judiciary North Carolina Journal of International Law and Commercial
Regulation 26(3):743–66
Madlingozi, T (2018) South Africa’s first black lawyers, amaRespectables and the birth of
evolutionary constitution – a review of Tembeka Ngcukaitobi’s The Land is Ours: South
Africa’s First Black Lawyers and the Birth of Constitutionalism South African Journal on
Human Rights 34(3):517–29
Madlingozi, T (2007) Post-Apartheid Social Movements and the Quest for the Elusive `New’
South Africa Journal of Law and Society 34(1):77–98
Madlingozi, T (2017) Social justice in a time of neo-apartheid constitutionalism: critiquing the
anti-black economy of recognition, incorporation and distribution Stellenbosch Law Review
8(1):123–47
Mafunisa, MJ (2008) The role of codes of conduct in promoting ethical conduct in the South
African public service South African Journal of Labour Relations 32(1):81–92
Magen, A (2008) The rule of law and its promotion abroad: Three problems of scope Stanford
Journal of International Law 45(1):51–116
Mahomed, I (1998) The independence of the judiciary South African Law Journal 115(4):658–67
at 658
Mahomed, I (1998) The role of the judiciary in a constitutional state South African Law Journal
115(1):111–15
Malherbe, EFJ (1998) The South African National Council of Provinces: Trojan horse or white
elephant? Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 1:77–96
Malherbe, R (2007) Some thoughts on unity, diversity and human dignity in the new South
Africa Journal of South African Law 70(1):127–33
Malleson, K (1999) Assessing the performance of the Judicial Service Commission South African
Law Journal 116(1):36–49
Marais, EJ (2015) When does state interference with property (now) amount to expropriation?
An analysis of the Agri SA court’s state acquisition requirement (Part I) Potchefstroom
Electronic Law Journal 18(29):2982–3031
Marais, EJ (2016) Expanding the contours of the constitutional property concept Tydskrif vir die
Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 576–92
Marais, EJ and Maree, PJH (2016) At the intersection between expropriation law and
Administrative law: Two critical views on the constitutional court’s Arun judgment
Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal 19:1–54
Maseko, TW (2009) The right of blind and visually impaired citizens to vote in secret: Is there a
duty to do more? SA Public Law 24(2):623–39
Matlosa, K (2004) Electoral systems, constitutionalism and conflict management in Southern
Africa African Journal on Conflict Resolution 4(2):11–53
Mbazira, C (2004) Reading the right to food into the African Charter on Human and Peoples’
Rights ESR Review 5(1):5–7
Mbazira, C (2008) Enforcement of socio-economic rights in South Africa: Strengthening the
reasonableness approach Nordisk Tidsskrift for Menneskerettigheter 26:131–47
Mbiada, CJT (2017) The Public Protector as a mechanism of political accountability: The extent
of its contribution to the realisation of the right to access adequate housing in South Africa
Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal (20):1–34
McClain, CV (2002) The SA Human Rights Commission and socio-economic rights: Facing the
challenges ESR Review 3(1):8–9
McWhinney, E (1957) The German Federal Constitutional Court and the Communist Party
decision Indiana Law Journal 32(3):295–312
Michelman, FL (2003) The constitution, social rights, and liberal political justification
International Journal of Constitutional Law 1(1):13–34
Ministerial Legal Task Team (1995, January) Explanatory Memorandum Industrial Law Journal
16(2):278–336
Mnisi Weeks, S (2011) Beyond the Traditional Courts Bill: Regulating customary courts in line
with living customary law and the Constitution South African Crime Quarterly 35(31):32
Mnisi Weeks, S and Claassens, A (2011) Tensions between vernacular values that prioritise basic
needs and state versions of customary law that contradict them Stellenbosch Law Review
22(2):823–44
Modiri, J (2013) Race, realism and critique: The politics of race and Afri-forum v Malema in the
Equality Court South African Law Journal 130(2):274–93
Modiri, J (2018) Conquest and constitutionalism: first thoughts on an alternative jurisprudence
South African Journal on Human Rights 34(3):300–25
Moerane, M (2003) The meaning of transformation of the judiciary in the new South African
context South African Law Journal 120(4):708–18
Mokgoro, Y (2010) Judicial appointments Advocate 43–8
Mokgoro, JY (1998) Ubuntu and the law in South Africa Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal
1(1):1
Morreira, S (2017) Steps towards decolonial higher education in Southern Africa? Epistemic
disobedience in the humanities Journal of Asian and African Studies 52(3):287–301
Moseneke, D (2009) Transformative constitutionalism: its implications for the law of contract
Stellenbosch Law Review 20(1):3–13
Mostert, H (2010) Engaged citizenship and the enabling state as factors determining the
interference parameter of property: A comparison of German and South African law South
African Law Journal 127(2):238–73
Motileng, BB, Wagner, C and Cassimjee, N (2006) Black middle managers’ experience of
affirmative action in a media company SA Journal of Industrial Psychology 32(1):11–6
Motshabi, KB and Volks, SG (1991) Towards democratic chieftaincy: Principles and procedures
Acta Juridica 104–15
Mureinik, E (1994) A bridge to where? Introducing South Africa’s interim Bill of Rights South
African Journal on Human Rights 10(1):31–48
Murphy, TF (2019) Adolescents and body modification for gender identity expression Medical
Law Review 27(4):623–39
Murray, C (2001) A constitutional beginning: Making South Africa’s final Constitution University
of Arkansas at Little Rock Law Review 23:809–38
Murray, C (2006) The Human Rights Commission et al: What is the role of South Africa’s Chapter
9 institutions? Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal 9(2):122–47
Murray, C and Simeon, R (1999) From paper to practice: The National Council of Provinces after
its first year SA Public Law 14(1):96–141
Murray, C and Simeon, R (2000) South Africa’s financial constitution: Towards better delivery SA
Public Law/Publiekreg 15(2):477–504
Murray, C and Simeon, R (2006) Tagging Bills in Parliament: Section 75 or 76? South African
Law Journal 123(2):232–63
Nagan, WP (1989) Law and post-apartheid South Africa Fordham International Law Journal
12(3):399–451
Nettle, D (2002) Height and Reproductive Success in a Cohort of British Men Human Nature
13(4):473–91
Norris, P (1997) Choosing electoral systems: Proportional majoritarian and mixed systems
International Political Science Review 18(3):297–312
Ntlama, N (2005) Unlocking the future: Monitoring court orders in respect of socio-economic
rights Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 68(1):81–9
Ntlama, N (2011) The Hlophe saga: the question for the institutional integrity of the judiciary
US-China Law Review 8(8):758–99
O’Regan, K (2004) Human rights and democracy – A new global debate: Reflections on the first
ten years of South Africa’s Constitutional Court International Journal of Legal Information
38(2):200–16
O’Regan, K (2005) Checks and balances: Reflections on the development of the doctrine of
separation of powers under the South African Constitution Potchefstroom Electronic Law
Journal 8(1):120–50
Patella-Rey, PJ (2018) Beyond privacy: Bodily integrity as an alternative framework for
understanding non-consensual pornography Information Communication & Society
21(5):786–91
Pejan, R (2004) The right to water: the road to justiciability The George Washington International
Law Review 36:1181–210
Pienaar, JM (2014) Reflections on the South African land reform programme: Characteristics,
dichotomies and tensions (part 1) Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 425–46
Pieterse, M (1999) A different shade of red: Socio-economic dimensions of the right to life in
South Africa South African Journal on Human Rights 15(3):372–85
Pieterse, M (1999) Traditional leaders win battle in undecided war South African Journal on
Human Rights 15: 179–87
Pieterse, M (2003) Towards a useful role for section 36 of the Constitution in social rights cases?
Residents of Bon Vista Mansions v Southern Metropolitan Local Council South African Law
Journal 120(1):41–8
Pieterse, M (2004) Coming to terms with judicial enforcement of socio-economic rights South
African Journal on Human Rights 20:383–417
Pieterse, M (2004) Possibilities and pitfalls in the domestic enforcement of social rights:
Contemplating the South African experience Human Rights Quarterly 26(4):882–905
Pieterse, M (2005) What do we mean when we talk about transformative constitutionalism? SA
Public Law/Publiekreg 20:155–66
Pieterse-Spies, A (2011) Reasonableness, subsidiarity and service delivery: A case discussion SA
Public Law 26(1):329–40
Pillay, K (2002) Implementation of Grootboom: Implications for the enforcement of socio-
economic rights Law, Democracy and Development 6(2):255–77
Pillay, N and Prinsloo, C (1995) The changing face of ‘traditional courts’ De Jure 1:383
Plasket, C (2007) Post-1994 administrative law in South Africa: The Constitution, the Promotion
of Administrative Justice Act 3 of 2000 and the common law Speculum Juris 21(1):25–40
Powell, C and Franco, J (2004) The meaning of institutional independence in Van Rooyen v S
South African Law Journal 121(3):562–79
Pretorius, JL (2001) Constitutional standards for affirmative action in South Africa: A
comparative overview Heidelberg Journal of International Law 61(8):403–57
Pretorius, JL (2010) Fairness in transformation: A critique of the Constitutional Court’s
affirmative action jurisprudence South African Journal on Human Rights 26(3):536–70
Pretorius, JL (2013) The use of official languages act: Diversity confirmed Potchefstroom
Electronic Law Journal 16(1):281–319
Price, A (2013) The evolution of the rule of law South African Law Journal 130:649
Pruitt, LR (2002) No black names on the letterhead? Efficient discrimination and the South
African legal profession Michigan Journal of International Law 23(3):545–676
Rautenbach, IM (2015) Dealing with the social dimensions of property Tydskrif vir die Suid-
Afrikaanse Reg 825–29
Rosenfeld, M (2001) The rule of law and the legitimacy of constitutional democracy Southern
California Law Review 74(5):1307–52
Roux, T (2002) Understanding Grootboom: A response to Cass R Sunstein Constitutional Forum
12(2):41–51
Roux, T (2003) Legitimating transformation: Political resource allocation in the South African
Constitutional Court Democratisation 10:92–111
Roux T (2009) Principle and pragmatism on the Constitutional Court of South Africa
International Journal of Constitutional Law 7(1):106–38
Sabel, CF and Simon, WH (2004) Destabilisation rights: How public law litigation succeeds
Harvard Law Review 117(4):1016–101
Sarakinsky, I (2007) Political party finance in South Africa: Disclosure versus secrecy
Democratization 14(1):111–28
Scarrow, SE (2001) Direct democracy and institutional change: A comparative investigation
Comparative Political Studies 34(6):651–65
Scott, IG (1987) The role of the Attorney-General and the Charter of Rights Criminal Law
Quarterly 29(2):187–99
Shai, I (2019) Radical transformation and the limits of law Acta Academica 51(1):144–62
Sherman, JG (1995) Love speech: The social utility of pornography Stanford Law Review
47(4):661–706
Shirin Heidari (2015) Sexual rights and bodily integrity as human rights Reproductive Health
Matters 23:46, 1–6
Sibanda, S (2011) Not Purpose-made! Transformative constitutionalism, post-independence
constitutionalism and the struggle to eradicate poverty Stellenbosch Law Review (Jan 2011)
22(3):482–500
Simeon, R and Murray, C (2001) Multi-sphere governance in South Africa: An interim
assessment Publius: The Journal of Federalism 31(4):65–92
Simon, WH (1986) Rights and redistribution in the welfare system Stanford Law Review
38(6):1431–1516
Slade, BV (2016) Compensation for what? An analysis of the outcome in Arun Property
Development (Pty) Ltd v Cape Town City Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal 19:1–25
Slade, BV (2016) Constitutional property law Juta’s Quarterly Review 3:para 2.1
Slade, BV (2013) The less invasive means argument in expropriation law Tydskrif vir die Suid-
Afrikaanse Reg 199–216
Slade, BV (2014) “Public purpose or public interest” and third party transfers Potchefstroom
Electronic Law Journal 17:166–206
Southall, R (1994) The South African elections of 1994: The remaking of a dominant-party state
The Journal of Modern African Studies 32(4):629–55
Southall, R (1998) The centralization and fragmentation of South Africa’s dominant party system
African Affairs 97(389):443–69
Southall, R (2001) Conclusion: Emergent perspectives on opposition in South Africa
Democratization 8(1):275–84
Southall, R (2001) Opposition in South Africa: Issues and problems Democratization 8(1):1–24
Southall, R (2005) The ‘dominant party debate’ in South Africa Afrika Spectrum 40(1):61–82
Sprigman, C and Osborne, M (1999) Du Plessis is not dead: South Africa’s 1996 Constitution and
the application of the Bill of Rights to private disputes South African Journal on Human
rights 15(1):25–51
Steytler, N and Williams, RF (2012) Squeezing out provinces’ legislative competence in Premier:
Limpopo Province v Speaker: Limpopo Provincial Legislative and others I and II South
African Law Journal 129(4):621–37
Stone, L (2018) A sign of the times: South Africa’s politico-legal retrogression as illustrated
through the intention to withdraw from the Rome Statute Southern African Public Law
33(1):1–32
Summers, CW (1964) Freedom of association and compulsory unionism in Sweden and the
United States University of Pennsylvania Law Review 112(5):674–96
Sunstein, CR (2001) Social and economic rights? Lessons from South Africa Constitutional
Forum 11(4):123–32
Sunstein, CR Against positive rights: Why social and economic rights don’t belong in the new
constitutions of postcommunist Europe East European Constitutional Review 2:35–8
Suttner, R (2006) Party dominance theory: Of what value? Politikon: SA Journal of Political
Studies 33(3):277–97
Tladi, D (2002) One step forward, two steps back for constitutionalising the common law: Afrox
Health Care v Strydom SA Public Law 17(2):473–78
Tomaselli, KJ (2008) Exogenous and endogenous democracy: South African politics and media
International Journal of Press/Politics 13(2):171–80
Trengove, W (1999) Judicial remedies for violations of socio-economic rights ESR Review 1(4):8–
11
Tshitereke, C (2002) Securing democracy: Party finance and party donations – The South African
challenge Institute for Security Studies 63:1–12
Vally, S (1999) Violence in South African schools Current Issues in Comparative Education
2(1):1–9
Van der Merwe, D (1989) Land tenure in South Africa: A brief history and some reform
proposals Journal of South African Law 4:663–92
Van der Vyver JD (1993) The separation of powers SA Public Law/Publiekreg 8:177–91
Van der Walt, AJ (1992) Roman-Dutch and environmental land-use control South African Public
Law 1(11):4
Van der Walt, AJ (1992) The South African law of ownership: A historical and philosophical
perspective De Jure 25:446–457
Van der Walt, AJ (1999) Property rights and hierarchies of power: a critical evaluation of land-
reform policy in South Africa Koers: Bulletin for Christian Scholarship 64(2/3):259–94
Van der Walt, J and Botha, H (2000) Democracy and rights in South Africa: Beyond a
constitutional culture of justification Constellations 7(3):341–62
Van der Walt, AJ (2002) Exclusivity of ownership, security of tenure, and eviction orders: A
model to evaluate South African land-reform legislation Journal of South African Law 2:254–
89
Van der Walt, AJ (2002) Sosiale geregtigheid, prosedurele billikheid, en eiendom: Alternatiewe
perspektiewe op grondwetlike waarborge (Deel Een) Stellenbosch Law Review 13(5):59–82
Van der Walt, AJ (2004) Striving for a better interpretation – A critical reflection on the
Constitutional Court’s Harksen and FNB decisions on the property clause South African Law
Journal 121:854–878
Van der Walt, AJ (2005) Retreating from the FNB arbitrariness test already? Mkontwana v Nelson
Mandela Metropolitan Municipality; Bissett v Buffalo City Municipality; Transfer Rights
Action Campaign v MEC for Local Government and Housing, Gauteng South African Law
Journal 123:75–89
Van der Walt, AJ (2008) Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term
Constitutional Court Review 1:77
Van der Walt, AJ (2011) Constitutional Property Law Juta’s Quarterly Review 3:2.2.1
Van der Walt, AJ (2012) Procedurally arbitrary deprivation of property Stellenbosch Law Review
23(1):88–94
Van der Walt, AJ and Marais, EJ (2012) The constitutionality of acquisitive prescription: A section
25 analysis Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 714–36
Van der Walt, AJ and Raphulu, TN (2014) The right of way of necessity: A constitutional analysis
Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 77:468–84
Van der Walt, AJ (2015) Sharing servitudes European Property Law Journal 4(3):162–222
Van der Walt, AJ (2016) Section 25 vortices (part 1) Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 3:412–27
Van der, AJ Walt (2016) Section 25 vortices (part 2) Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 4:597–
621
Van der Walt, AJ and Dhliwayo, P (2017) The notion of absolute and exclusive ownership: A
doctrinal analysis South African Law Journal 134(1):34–52
Van der Walt, AJ (2017) Property law in the constitutional democracy Stellenbosch Law Review
28(1):8–25
Van Reenen, TP (1997) Equality, discrimination and affirmative action: An analysis of section 9
of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa SA Publiekreg/Public Law 12(1):151–65
Van Wyk, J (2010) Feasibility of restoration as a factor in land restitution claims South African
Public Law 25:590–601
Van Wyk, J (2016) Planning and Arun’s (not so straight and narrow) roads Potchefstroom
Electronic Law Journal 19:1–29
Van Wyk, J (2017) Compensation for land reform expropriation Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse
Reg 21–35
Van Zyl, D (2009) The judiciary as a bastion of the legal order in challenging times Potchefstroom
Electronic Law Journal 12(2):1–13
Venter, F (2010) Liberal democracy: The unintended consequence – South African constitution-
writing propelled by the winds of globalisation South African Journal on Human Rights
26(1):45–65
Visser, DP (1985) The “absoluteness” of ownership: The South African common law in
perspective Acta Juridica 39–52
Webb, TJ (2010) Verbal poison-criminalizing hate speech: A comparative analysis and a
proposal for the American system Washburn Law Journal 50:445–82
Wesson, M and Du Plessis, M (2008) Fifteen years on: Central issues relating to the
transformation of the South African judiciary South African Journal on Human Rights
24(2):187–213
Wesson, M (2018) The limits of constitutional justice Public Law Review 29(1):63
Westen, P (1982) The empty idea of equality Harvard Law Review 95(3):537–96
White, S (1997) Freedom of association and the right to exclude The Journal of Political
Philosophy 5(4):373–91
White, J (1994) Constitutional litigation and interpretation, and fundamental rights Annual
Survey of South African Law 35–6
White, J Constitutional litigation and interpretation, and fundamental rights (1994) Annual
Survey of South African Law Cape Town: Juta
Woolman, S (2007) The amazing vanishing Bill of Rights South African Law Journal 124(4):762–
94
Woolman S, (2011) My tea party, your mob, our social contract: Freedom of assembly and the
constitutional right to rebellion in Garvis v SATAWU (Minister for Safety & Security, third
party) 2010 (6) SA 280 (WCC) South African Journal on Human Rights 27:346–53
Woolman, S (2012) Seek justice elsewhere: An egalitarian pluralist’s reply to David Bilchitz on
the distinction between differentiation and domination South African Journal on Human
Rights 28(2):273–95
Woolman, S (2016) A Politics of accountability: how South Africa’s judicial recognition of the
binding legal effect of the Public Protector’s recommendations had a catalysing effect that
brought down a President Constitutional Court Review 8:155–92
Woolman, S and Fleisch, B (2014) The problem of the ‘Other’ language Constitutional Court
Review 5:142
Woolman, S and Davis, D (1996) The last laugh: Du Plessis v De Klerk, classical liberalism, creole
liberalism and the application of fundamental rights under the interim and final
Constitutions South African Journal on Human Rights 12(2):361–404
Papers
Barkan, J (2005) Emerging legislature or rubber stamp? The South African National Assembly
after ten years of democracy Working paper No 134, Centre for Social Science Research:
Democracy in Africa Research Unit, University of Cape Town at 9–11, available at
https://open.uct.ac.za/handle/11427/19368
Conradie, J (2011, April) The evolution of accounting standards in the public sector,
Unpublished Paper, available at http://www.accountancysa.org.za
Cowen, S (2013) Judicial selection in South Africa, Democratic Governance Rights Unit (DGRU)
Working Paper Series 15, available at
http://www.dgru.uct.ac.za/usr/dgru/downloads/Judicial%20SelectionOct2010.pdf
Lewis, C (2008, 14 October) The troubled state of South Africa’s judiciary, Paper presented at the
South African Institute of Race Relations, available at
http://www.politicsweb.co.za/politicsweb/view/politicsweb/en/page71619?
oid=106544&sn=Detail
Ntlama, N (2009, 16–20 July) The Hlophe saga: the question for the institutional integrity of the
judiciary, Paper presented at the Law Teachers Conference in Pietermaritzburg, available at
http://wenku.baidu.com/view/6c6473f0fab069dc50220111.html
The South African National Assembly after ten years of democracy Working paper No 134,
Centre for Social Science Research: Democracy in Africa Research Unit, University of Cape
Town at 9–11, available at
http://www.cssr.uct.ac.za/sites/cssr.uct.ac.za/files/pubs/wp134.pdf
Spaull, N (2013) Poverty and Privilege: Primary school inequality in South Africa Working Paper
No 13/12, Stellenbosch University, Department of Economics
Zoch, A (2013) The effect of neighbourhoods and school quality on education and labour
market outcomes in South Africa Working Paper No 08/2017, Stellenbosch University,
Department of Economics
Reports
African National Congress (November 2018) Report on the Possible Review of Section 25 of the
Constitution
Annual Report of Parliament 1999 and 2000 available at
http://www.pmg.org.za/minutes/20011018-sita-annual-report-19992000-briefing
Black First Land First (June 2018) Written Submission to Parliament on Review of the Land
Clause of the Constitution
Economic Freedman Fighters (November 2018) Report on the Review and Amendment of
Section 25 of the Constitution
Foundation for Human Rights (November 2018) Submission to the Constitutional Review
Committee
Gordon, A and Bruce, D (2006) Transformation and independence of the judiciary in South
Africa, Centre for Study of Violence and Reconciliation (CSVR) 1–61
Hendricks, C (2005) ‘Party strategy not popular prejudice: Electoral politics in South Africa’ in
Piper L (ed) South Africa’s 2004 Election: The Quest for Democratic Consolidation, EISA
Research Report no 12, Johannesburg: EISA
High Level Panel on the Assessment of Key Legislation and the Acceleration of Fundamental
Change Final Report November 2017
Hoexter Commission of Inquiry into the Structure and Functioning of the Courts (1983) RP
78/83 Part IV
Joint Constitutional Review Committee (2018) Report on the possible review of section 25 of the
Constitution (November 2018)
National Development Plan: Vision for 2030 (2011) ‘Office of the Chief Justice Annual Report
2018/19’, p 18, accessed on 20 October 2019 at
https://www.judiciary.org.za/images/Annual-Reports/OCJ_Annual_Report_2018-19.pdf
Parliament of the Republic of South Africa (2007) Report of the Ad Hoc Committee on the
Review of Chapter 9 and Associated Institutions, A report to the National Assembly of the
Parliament of South Africa, Cape Town, South Africa, 9 available at
https://www.parliament.gov.za/storage/app/media/
The Presidency (2017) Report of the Commission of Inquiry into Higher Education and Training
to the President of the Republic of South Africa
Presidential Review Commission (1998) Report on the Reform and Transformation of the Public
Service in South Africa available at
http://www.info.gov.za/otherdocs/1998/prc98/index.html
Presidential Advisory Committee on Land Reform and Agriculture Final Report May 2019
Report of the Commission of Enquiry into Higher Education and Training to the President of the
Republic of South Africa
Report of the Hearings on the Commercialisation of Religion and Abuse of People’s Belief
Systems (2017), accessed on 17 April 2020 at
http://www.crlcommission.org.za/docs/Final%20Report%20on%20the%20Commercialisati
on%20 of%20Religion.pdf
Report of the Independent Panel Assessment of Parliament (Govender Report) 53, available at
https://www.gov.za/sites/default/files/gcis_document/201409/panelassessparl.pdf
Report of the Presidential Review Commission on the Reform and Transformation of the Public
Service in South Africa, Pretoria (1998) para 1.3, available at
https://www.gov.za/documents/report-presidential-review-commission-reform-and-
transformation-public-service-south
South Africa Commission of Inquiry into Labour Legislation Wiehahn, NE (1980) Report of the
Commission of Inquiry into Labour Legislation Republic of South Africa, Department of
Manpower Utilisation
South African Human Rights Commission (2006) The Exclusionary Policies of Voluntary
Associates: Constitutional Considerations Pretoria: South African Human Rights
Commission
South African Human Rights Commission (2010) Golden Key Awards Report on Access to
Information in South Africa (with the Open Democracy Advice Centre) available at
http://www.opendemocracy.org.za/wp-content/uploads/2010/10/2010-GKA-REPORT.pdf
South African Law Reform Commission (2003) Customary Law: Report on Traditional Courts
and the Judicial Function of Traditional Leaders Project 90 1, accessed on 25 January 2013 at
http://www.justice.gov.za/salrc/reports/r_prj90_ tradlead_2003jan.pdf
Truth and Reconciliation Commission of South Africa (1998) Report: Volume 1 Chapter 8 The
Destruction of Records para 24; Volume 2 Chapter 2 The State Outside SA Between 1960 and
1990
Government publications
Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1991) General Comment No. 3 on the
Nature of States
Department of Provincial and Local Government White Paper on Traditional Leadership and
Governance GN 2336 in GG 25438 of 10 September 2000
Department of Rural Development and Land Reform Green Paper on Land Reform (2011)
Department of Rural Development and Land Reform (DRDLR) Policy Framework for Land
Acquisition and Land Valuation in a Land Reform Context (2012)
Education and Training Unit (2016) How Government Works
Government of the Republic of South Africa (2011) National Development Plan
Language in Education Policy GN 1701 in GG 18546 of 19 December 1997
Language Policy for Higher Education GN R1485 in GG 24101 of 25 November 2002
Norms and Standards for Language Policy in Public Schools GN 1701 in GG 18546 of 19
December 1997
White Paper on Education and Training GN 196 in GG 16312 of 15 March 1995
Blogs
Andrews, P (2017, 4 July) South Africa’s problems lie in political negligence, not its Constitution
The Conversation accessed on 6 August 2019 at https://theconversation.com/south-africas-
problems-lie-in-political-negligence-not-its-constitution-80474
Bazana, S (2016) How to fix the deeply flawed public protector appointment process The
Conversation, August 30, accessed on 25 October 2019 at
https://theconversation.com/south-africa-should-use-a-more-scientific-approach-to-
appoint-its-public-protector-64077
De Vos, P (2008, 8 December) National security, the last refuge of scoundrels? Constitutionally
Speaking available at http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/national-security-the-last-
refuge-of-scoundrels/
De Vos, P (2011, 31 May) Let me tell you a secret … Constitutionally Speaking available at
http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/let-me-tell-you-a-secret/
De Vos, P (2011, 12 September) Malema judgment: A re-think on hate speech needed
Constitutionally Speaking available at http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/malema-
judgment-a-re-think-on-hate-speech-needed
De Vos, P (2011, 24 November) Cabinet statement on transformation of judicial system
Constitutionally Speaking available at http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/cabinet-
statement-on-transformation-of-judicial-system/
De Vos, P (2012, 14 August) Towards a parliament for the people Constitutionally Speaking
available at http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/towards-a-parliament-for-the-people/
De Vos, P (2012, 25 September) Sharp divisions on the Constitutional Court about the right to
strike Constitutionally Speaking available at http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/sharp-
divisions-on-the-constitutional-court-about-the-right-to-strike/
De Vos, P (2012, 10 October) One small step for Parliament, one giant leap for Ambrosini
Constitutionally Speaking available at http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/once-small-
step-for-parliament-one-giant-leap-for-ambrosini/
De Vos, P (2013, 21 January) Judicial appointments: The JSC’s transformation problem
Constitutionally Speaking available at http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/judicial-
appointments-the-jscs-transformation-problem/
De Vos, P (2013, 11 April) The JSC must redefine merit to advance judicial transformation
Constitutionally Speaking available at http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/the-jsc-must-
redefine-merit-to-advance-judicial-transformation/
De Vos, P (2016, 14 November) ‘Why state schools cannot promote a Christian ethos’
Constitutionally Speaking accessed on 15 April 2020 at
https://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/why-state-schools-cannot-promote-achristian-
ethos/
De Vos, P (2019, 12 February) Political Party Funding Act should be brought into operation
forthwith Constitutionally Speaking, available at
https://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/political-party-funding-act-should-be-brought-
intooperation-forthwith/
De Vos, P (2019, 12 March) ‘Why Court Ruled Against Dutch Reformed Church in Same Sex
Marriage Case and What it May Mean for Other Churches Who Discriminate Against Gays
and Lesbians’ Constitutionally Speaking accessed on 10 April 2020 at
https://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/why-court-ruled-against-dutchreformed-church-in-
same-sex-marriage-case-and-what-it-may-mean-for-other-churches-who-discriminate-
against-gaysand-lesbians/
De Vos, P (2019, 20 November) Why is a DA MP demanding that the President act
unconstitutionally? Constitutionally Speaking, accessed on 26 February 2020 at
https://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/why-is-a-da-mp-demanding-that-the-president-act-
unconstitutionally/
De Vos, P (2020, 12 February) Neither SONA nor any disruption will improve the quality of
governance in South Africa Constitutionally Speaking, accessed on 20 February 2020 at
https://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/neither-sona-nor-any-disruption-will-improve-the-
quality-of-governance-in-south-africa/
Deputy Chief Justice Dikgang Moseneke ‘Reflections on South Africa’s Constitutional
Democracy – Transition and Transformation’, keynote speech delivered on 12 November
2014 at the Mistra-Tmali-UNISA Conference, accessed on 30 January 2020 at
https://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/dcj-moseneke-reflections-on-south-african-
constitutional-democracy-transition-and-transformation/
Gauntlett, J and Du Plessis, M (2011, 25 August) Ex Parte: Freedom under Law, In re: The
Appointment of the Chief Justice Memorandum 10–11 Constitutionally Speaking available at
http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/ful-proposes-changes-to-appointment-of-chief-
justice/
Hartley, R (2008, 23 September) The five big mistakes that cost Mbeki the Presidency TimesLive
available at http://blogs.timeslive.co.za/hartley/2008/09/23/the-five-big-mistakes-that-
cost-mbeki-the-presidency
Judicial Service Commission, Summary of the Criteria Used by the Judicial Service Commission
when Considering Candidates for Judicial Appointments Constitutionally Speaking available
at http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/criteria-used-by-jsc-when-considering-judicial-
appointments/
Moseneke, D (2015, May 15) The Media, Courts and Technology: Remarks on the Media
Coverage of the Oscar Pistorius Trial and Open Justice Constitutionally Speaking available at
https://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/dcj-dikgangmoseneke-the-media-courts-and-
technology-remarks-on-the-media-coverage-of-the-oscar-pistorius-trial-and-openjustice/
Yacoob, Z (2012) ‘The Dynamic Constitution’, Keynote Address, University of Cape Town
Constitution Week, 12 March 2012, available at
http://constitutionallyspeaking.co.za/justice-zac-yacoob-on-the-dynamic-constitution/
Webliography
African National Congress Constitutional Committee ‘A Discussion Document of Structures and
Principles of a Constitution for a Democratic South Africa’ (1991, 8 April) at 16, accessed on
7 March 2019 at https://dullahomarinstitute.org.za/about-us/our-historical-
publications/anc-discussion-document-on-structures-and-principles-of-a-constitution-for-
democrcatic-sa.pdf
African National Congress 53rd National Conference Resolutions 4. Legislature and Governance
4.2.1 28 available at http://www.anc.org.za/docs/res/2013/resolutions53r.pdf
African National Congress Constitution, as amended and adopted at the 52nd National
Conference, Polokwane, 2007, available at https://www.sahistory.org.za/sites/default/fi
les/constit_amend.pdf
African National Congress Constitution, as amended and adopted at the 53nd National
Conference, Mangaung, 2012, available at http://www.anc.org.za/show.php?id=10177
African National Congress Constitution as amended and adopted at the 54th National
Conference, Nasrec, Johannesburg, 2017, available at
https://www.anc1912.org.za/constitution-anc
African National Congress National Disciplinary Committee (2012, 29 February) Luthuli House,
Johannesburg: Public Announcement on the Disciplinary Hearing of Floyd Shivambu,
Sindiso Magaqa and Julius Malema available at https://www.sahistory.org.za/archive/anc-
national-disciplinary-committee-29-february-2012-luthuli-house-johannesburg
Centre for Human Rights University of Pretoria Law of Lagos available at
http://www1chr.up.ac.za/images/files/documents/ahrdd/theme36/rule_of_law_lagos_1961
.pdf
Centre for Law and Society, available at
http://www.cls.uct.ac.za/usr/lrg/docs/TCB/2012/lrg_feb2012_ncopsubmission.pdf
Chief Albert John Mvumbi Luthuli, available at https://www.sahistory.org.za/people/chief-
albert-john-mvumbi-luthuli
Code of Conduct for Assembly and Permanent Council Members, available at
https://www.parliament.gov.za/code-conduct-for-na-ncop-members
CODESA Declaration of Intent available at
https://omalley.nelsonmandela.org/omalley/index.php/site/q/03lv02039/04lv02046/05lv0
2047/06lv02049/07lv02052.htm
Congress for a Democratic South Africa (CODESA): Declaration of Intent signed on 21
December 1991 available at http://www.anc.org.za/show.php?id=3968&t=Transition
Constitution Seventeenth Amendment Act 72 of 2013, available at
https://www.justice.gov.za/legislation/acts/const17th_2013gg36128no72.pdf
De Casanova, EM (2004) “No Ugly Women”: Concepts of Race and Beauty among Adolescent
Women in Ecuador Gender and Society 18(3):287–308. Accessed 19 October 2020 at
http://www.jstor.org/stable/4149403
Democratic Alliance (2010) Regulations for the Nomination of Candidates, available at
http://www.myvotecounts.org.za/wp-content/uploads/2019/04/Regulations-for-
Nomination-of
-Candidates-2019-approved-by-Fedex-5-May-2018.pdf
Department of Land Affairs White Paper on South Africa Land Policy (1997) available at
http://www.ruraldevelopment.gov.za/phocadownload/White-
Papers/whitepaperlandreform.pdf
Economic Freedom Fighters Constitution, adopted on 27 July 2013, available at
http://effighters.org.za/documents/constitution/
Electoral Commission Results Dashboard – National Assembly 2019, accessed on 5 February
2020 at https://www.elections.org.za/NPEDashboard/app/dashboard.html
The Harare declaration: The ANC’s chapter for negotiations (1990, 1 January) accessed on 6
March 2019 at https://www.africaportal.org/publications/the-harare-declaration-the-ancs-
chapter-for-negotiations/
Henderson, B (2005) Open letter to the Kansas State School Board. Available at
https://www.spaghettimonster.org/about/open-letter/n
Henderson, B (2009) The Gospel of the Flying Spaghetti Monster, available at
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Flying_Spaghetti_Monster#cite_note-56
Inter-Parliamentary Union (2013) Women in national parliaments available at
http://www.ipu.org/wmn-e/classif.htm
Kirshner, J and Phokela, C (2010) Khutsong and xenophobic violence: Exploring the case of the
dog that didn’t bark particularly 8–14. Available at
https://www.researchgate.net/publication/285729554_Khutsong_and_xenophobic_violenc
e_Exploring_the_case_of_the_dog_that_didn’t_bark
Land and Accountability Research Centre (LARC) Submission on the Traditional and Khoi-San
Leadership Bill, 2015. 7 September 2018, accessed on 17 August 2020 at
http://www.larc.uct.ac.za/sites/default/files/image_tool/images/347/Submissions/LARC%
20submission%20on%20TKLB_NCOP_20180907.pdf
Law of Lagos International Commission of Jurists (1961) 3(1) at 9, available at
https://www.icj.org/wp-content/uploads/2013/08/ICJ-Journal-III-1-1961-eng.pdf
Law, Race and Gender Institute (Centre for Law and Society) (2012) Submission on the
Traditional Courts Bill (B1-2012) available at
http://www.cls.uct.ac.za/usr/lrg/docs/TCB/2012/lrg_feb2012_ncopsubmission.pdf
LEXICO, https://www.lexico.com/definition/availability
Lowe Morna, C, Rama, K and Mtonga, L (2009, 15 July) Gender in the 2009 South African
elections, Gender links for equality and justice, available at
http://www.genderlinks.org.za/article/gender-in-the-2009-south-african-elections-2009-
07-15
Marais, EJ Is onteiening sonder vergoeding werklik die antwoord? Litnet Akademies available at
https://www.litnet.co.za/onteiening-sonder-vergoeding-werklik-die-antwoord/
Meacham, T (2019) I, Pastafari: We all have something to learn from the Church of the Flying
Spaghetti Monster The Conversation 18 October 2019. Available at
https://theconversation.com/i-pastafari-we-all-have-something-to-learn-from-the-church-
of-the-flying-spaghetti-monster-124035
Memeza, M (2006) A critical review of the implementation of the Regulation of Gatherings Act
205 of 1993: A local government and civil society perspective available at
http://www.fxi.org.za
Mthembu, J (2012, 4 February) ANC statement on the National Disciplinary Committee of
appeal today, available at https://www.polity.org.za/article/anc-statement-by-jackson-
mthembu-african-national-congress-spokesperson-on-the-national-disciplinary-
committe-of-appeal-process-04022012-2012-02-04
Murray, C (2001) A constitutional beginning: Making South Africa’s final Constitution University
of Arkansas at Little Rock Law Review 23:809–38(3):809–38 at 813, available at
https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/lawreview/vol23/iss3/3
National Council of Provinces (NCOP) available at https://www.parliament.gov.za/press-
releases/parliaments-mid-term-address-chairperson-national-council-provinces-
honourable-thandi-modise (accessed 11 February 2019)
National prosecuting authority (NPA) Prosecution Policy, revised June 2013, accessed on 24
October 2019 at
https://www.npa.gov.za/sites/default/files/Library/Prosecution%20Policy%20%28Final%20
as%20Revised%20in%20June%202013.%2027%20Nov%202014%29.pdf
Online Oxford English Dictionary available at
http://www.oxforddictionaries.com/definition/english/language
Parliament of the Republic of South Africa (2009) Oversight and Accountability Model:
Asserting Parliament’s Oversight Role in Enhancing Democracy 2.2.1, available at
http://pmg-assets.s3-website-eu-west-1.amazonaws.com/docs/080319oversightmodel.pdf
Parliament of the Republic of South Africa (2008, March) Rules of the National Council of
Provinces 9th ed available at http://www.pmg.org.za/parlinfo/ncoprules
Parliament of the Republic of South Africa (2011, June) Rules of the National Assembly 7th ed,
available at http://www.pmg.org.za/files/doc/2012/NA%20Rules%207th%20edition-1.pdf
Parliament of the Republic of South Africa (2016, 26 May) Rules of the National Assembly 9th ed,
available at https://www.parliament.gov.za/storage/app/media/Rules/NA/2016-09-
28_NA_RULES.pdf
Policy Framework on the Traditional Justice System under the Constitution, Department of
Justice and Constitutional Development 10, available at http://www.pmg.org.za/policy-
documents/2009/03/02/policy-framework-traditional-justice-system-under
Rama, K and Lowe Morna, C (2019) Beyond Numbers: Gender Audit of the May 2019 South
African Elections 3, accessed on 5 February 2020 at https://genderlinks.org.za/wp-
content/uploads/2019/06/GENDER-IN-2019-SA-ELECTIONS-LR.pdf
Record of Understanding signed on 26 September 1992, available at
http://www.anc.org.za/show.php?id=4206
Role and Functions of the South African Reserve Bank available at
http://www.resbank.co.za/AboutUs/Functions/Pages/default.aspx
Segalwe, O (2011, 16 March) Chief Justice Ngcobo highlights the importance of the Public
Protector available at http://www.pprotect.org
South Africa: 2009 National Assembly Election Results, Electoral Institute for Sustainable
Democracy in Africa, available at http://www.eisa.org.za/WEP/sou2009results1.htm
South Africa: 2019 National Assembly Election Results, IEC, available at
https://www.elections.org.za/NPEDashboard/app/dashboard.html
South African History Online ‘The ANC unveils its proposed constitutional principles’ accessed
on 6 March 2019 at https://www.sahistory.org.za/dated-event/anc-unveils-its-proposed-
constitutional-principles
South African History Online ‘Elections in post-apartheid South Africa’ available at
http://www.sahistory.org.za/elections-post-apartheid-south-africa
Traditional Courts Bill B1–2012, available at http://www.justice.gov.za/legislation/bills/2012-
b01tradcourts.pdf
United Nations (1996) International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights available at
http://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/pages/ccpr.aspx
United Nations (1996) International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights available
at http://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/pages/CESCR.aspx
World Declaration on Education for Al, accessed on 10 June 2020 available at
https://www.right-to-education.org/sites/right-to-education.org/files/resource-
attachments/UNESCO_World_Declaration_For_All_1990_En.pdf
A
AAA Investments (Proprietary) Limited v Micro Finance Regulatory Council and Another (CCT51/05) [2006]
ZACC 9; 2006 (11) BCLR 1255 (CC); 2007 (1) SA 343 (CC) (28 July 2006) 63, 176
Abahlali baseMjondolo Movement SA and Another v Premier of the Province of KwaZulu-Natal and Others
2010 (2) BCLR 99 (CC) (14 October 2009) 323, 324, 485
AB and Another v Minister of Social Development (CCT155/15) [2016] ZACC 43; 2017 (3) SA 570 (CC);
2017 (3) BCLR 267 (CC) (29 November 2016) 431, 545, 547, 548, 552, 583, 584, 586
Absa Bank Limited and Others v Public Protector and Others (48123/2017; 52883/2017; 46255/2017)
[2018] ZAGPPHC 2; [2018] 2 All SA 1 (GP) (16 February 2018) 356
Acting Chairperson: Judicial Service Commission and Others v Premier of the Western Cape Province
(537/10) [2011] ZASCA 53; 2011 (3) SA 538 (SCA); [2011] 3 All SA 459 (SCA) (31 March 2011) 252
Affordable Medicines Trust and Others v Minister of Health and Another (CCT27/04) [2005] ZACC 3; 2006 (3)
SA 247 (CC); 2005 (6) BCLR 529 (CC) (11 March 2005) 80, 207
African Christian Democratic Party v Electoral Commission and Others (CCT 10/06) [2006] ZACC 1; 2006(3)
SA 305 (CC); 2006(5) BCLR 579 (CC) (24 February 2006) 718
Afri-Forum and Another v Malema and Others (20968/2010) [2011] ZAEQC 2; 2011 (6) SA 240 (EqC);
[2011] 4 All SA 293 (EqC); 2011 (12) BCLR 1289 (EqC) (12 September 2011) 691
Afriforum and Another v University of the Free State (CCT101/17) [2017] ZACC 48; 2018 (2) SA 185 (CC);
2018 (4) BCLR 387 (CC) (29 December 2017) 658, 659, 660, 831, 833, 834, 836
Agri SA v Minister for Minerals and Energy (CCT 51/12) [2013] ZACC 9; 2013 (4) SA 1 (CC); 2013 (7) BCLR
727 (CC) (18 April 2013) 764
Alberta Union of Provincial Employees v Alberta (AG) (1987), 28 C.R.R. 305. (SCA) 596
Albutt v Centre for the Study of Violence and Reconciliation and Others (CCT 54/09) [2010] ZACC 4; 2010
(3) SA 293 (CC); 2010 (2) SACR 101 (CC); 2010 (5) BCLR 391 (CC) (23 February 2010) 80, 81, 203,
206, 207
Alexkor Ltd and Another v Richtersveld Community and Others (CCT19/03) [2003] ZACC 18; 2004 (5) SA
460 (CC); 2003 (12) BCLR 1301 (CC) (14 October 2003) 233, 365, 373, 427
Allpay Consolidated Investment Holding (Pty) Ltd and Others v Chief Executive Officer of the South African
Social Security Agency and Others (CCT 48/13) [2013] ZACC 42; 2014 (1) SA 604 (CC); 2014 (1) BCLR
1 (CC) (29 November 2013) 359, 481, 482
Amnesty International and Others v Sudan, African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights, Comm. No.
48/90, 50/91, 52/91, 89/93 (1999) 641
Amod v Multilateral Motor Vehicle Accidents Fund (CCT4/98) [1998] ZACC 11; 1998 (4) SA 753; 1998 (10)
BCLR 1207 (27 August 1998) 243, 244
AParty and Another v The Minister for Home Affairs and Others, Moloko and Others v The Minister for Home
Affairs and Another (CCT 06/09, CCT 10/09) [2009] ZACC 4; 2009 (3) SA 649 (CC); 2009 (6) BCLR 611
(CC) (12 March 2009) 137, 138, 241, 242, 713
August and Another v Electoral Commission and Others (CCT8/99) [1999] ZACC 3; 1999 (3) SA 1 (CC); 1999
(4) BCLR 363 (1 April 1999) 90, 135, 136, 446, 447, 509–510, 722, 724, 726, 730
Azanian Peoples Organization (AZAPO) and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others
(CCT17/96) [1996] ZACC 16; 1996 (8) BCLR 1015; 1996 (4) SA 672 (25 July 1996) 28, 221, 473
B
Bangindawo v Head of the Nyanda Regional Authority; Hlantlalala v Head of the Western Tembuland Regional
Authority (1998) 3 BCLR 314 (Tk) 272
Bapedi Marota Mamone v Commission on Traditional Leadership Disputes and Claims (CCT 67/14) [2014]
ZACC 36; 2015 (3) BCLR 268 (CC) (15 December 2014) 367, 368
Barkhuizen v Napier (CCT72/05) [2007] ZACC 5; 2007 (5) SA 323 (CC); 2007 (7) BCLR 691 (CC) (4 April
2007) 234
Basic Education for All v Minister of Basic Education (23949/14) [2014] ZAGPPHC 251; 2014 (4) SA 274
(GP); [2014] 3 All SA 56 (GP); 2014 (9) BCLR 1039 (GP) (5 May 2014) 828, 829
Bato Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v Minister of Environmental Affairs and Tourism and Others (CCT 27/03) [2004]
ZACC 15; 2004 (4) SA 490 (CC); 2004 (7) BCLR 687 (CC) (12 March 2004) 206, 234
Beinash and Ernst & Young (CCT12/98) [1998] ZACC 19; 1999 (2) SA 116 (CC); 1999 (2) BCLR 125 (CC) (2
December 1998) 439
Bernstein v Bester NO (CCT23/95) [1996] ZACC 2; 1996 (2) SA 751 (CC); 1996 (4) BCLR 449 (CC) (27
March 1996) 440, 444, 462, 574, 575, 587, 588
Bertie Van Zyl (Pty) Ltd and Another v Minister for Safety and Security and Others (CCT 77/08) [2009] ZACC
11; 2010 (2) SA 181 (CC); 2009 (10) BCLR 978 (CC) (7 May 2009) 422
Besserglik v Minister of Trade Industry and Tourism and Others (Minister of Justice intervening) (CCT34/95)
[1996] ZACC 8; 1996 (6) BCLR 745; 1996 (4) SA 331 (14 May 1996) 241
Bhe and Others v Khayelitsha Magistrate and Others (Commission for Gender Equality as Amicus Curiae) (CCT
49/03) [2004] ZACC 17; 2005 (1) SA 580 (CC); 2005 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) (15 October 2004) 224, 366,
373, 374, 375, 427, 462, 498, 524, 648, 649, 650
Biowatch Trust v Registrar, Genetic Resources and Others (CCT 80/08) [2009] ZACC 14; 2009 (6) SA 232
(CC); 2009 (10) BCLR 1014 (CC) (3 June 2009) 792
Black Sash Trust v Minister of Social Development and Others (Freedom Under Law NPC Intervening) (CCT
48/17) [2017] ZACC 8; 2017 (3) SA 335 (CC); 2017 (5) BCLR 543 (CC) (17 March 2017) 512
Black Sash Trust v Minister of Social Development and Others (Freedom Under Law NPC Intervening) (CCT
48/17) [2018] ZACC 36; 2018 (12) BCLR 1472 (CC) (27 September 2018) 512
Black Sash Trust v Minister of Social Development and Others (Freedom Under Law NPC Intervening)
(CCT48/17) [2017] ZACC 20; 2017 (9) BCLR 1089 (CC) (15 June 2017) 415
Blue Moonlight Properties 39 (Pty) Ltd v Occupiers of Saratoga Avenue and Another 2009 (1) SA 470 (W)
501, 815, 816, 818–819
Brink v Kitshoff NO (CCT15/95) [1996] ZACC 9; 1996 (4) SA 197; 1996 (6) BCLR 752 (15 May 1996) 241,
518, 521, 524, 533, 552
Brown v Leyds NO (1897) 4 Off Rep 17 7
Bruce and Another v Fleecytex Johannesburg CC and Others (CCT1/98) [1998] ZACC 3; 1998 (2) SA 1143;
1998 (4) BCLR 415 (24 March 1998) 241, 242
Buckley v Valeo 424 U.S. 1 (1976) 719
C
Calibre Clinical Consultants (Pty) Ltd and Another v National Bargaining Council for the Road Freight Industry
and Another (410/09) [2010] ZASCA 94; 2010 (5) SA 457 (SCA); [2010] 4 All SA 561 (SCA) (19 July
2010) 415, 416, 417
Cape Bar Council v Judicial Service Commission and Others (11897/2011) [2011] ZAWCHC 388; 2012 (4)
BCLR 406 (WCC); [2012] 2 All SA 143 (WCC) (30 September 2011) 258
Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security (Centre for Applied Legal Studies Intervening) (CCT 48/00)
[2001] ZACC 22; 2001 (4) SA 938 (CC); 2001 (10) BCLR 995 (CC) (16 August 2001) 54, 234, 241,
410, 424, 425
Case and Another v Minister of Safety and Security and Others, Curtis v Minister of Safety and Security and
Others (CCT20/95, CCT21/95) [1996] ZACC 7; 1996 (3) SA 617 (CC); 1996 (5) BCLR 608 (CC) (9 May
1996) 493, 668, 670
Cassim and Solomon v The State (1892) Cape Law Journal 9:58 6
Cavanaugh v Nebraska 178 F.Supp 3d 819 (2016) 625
CDA Boerdery (Edms) Bpk en Andere v Nelson Mandela Metropolitan Municipality (526/05) [2007] ZASCA 1;
2007 (4) SA 276 (SCA) (6 February 2007) 302
Centre for Child Law and Others v MEC for Education, Gauteng and Others 2008 (1) SA 223 (T) 225G–226A
415
Centre for Child Law and Others v Media 24 Limited and Others (CCT261/18) [2019] ZACC 46; 2020 (4) SA
319 (CC); 2020 (3) BCLR 245 (CC) (4 December 2019) 431, 444, 445, 487, 684, 685, 686
Centre for Child Law and Others v Minister of Basic Education and Others (2840/2017) [2019] ZAECGHC
126; [2020] 1 All SA 711 (ECG); 2020 (3) SA 141 (ECG) (12 December 2019) 826, 829
Centre for Child Law v Minister for Justice and Constitutional Development and Others (CCT98/08) [2009]
ZACC 18; 2009 (2) SACR 477 (CC); 2009 (6) SA 632 (CC); 2009 (11) BCLR 1105 (CC) (15 July 2009)
471
Certification of the Amended Text of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (CCT37/96)
[1996] ZACC 24; 1997 (1) BCLR 1; 1997 (2) SA 97 (CC) (4 December 1996) 25, 149, 150, 306, 309,
595
Certification of the Amended Text of the Constitution of the Western Cape, 1997 (CCT29/97) [1997] ZACC 15;
1997 (12) BCLR 1653; 1998 (1) SA 655 (18 November 1997) 240
Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (CCT 23/96) [1996] ZACC 26; 1996 (4)
SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC) (6 September 1996) 17, 19, 21, 22, 25, 59, 60, 61, 62, 101,
103, 108, 109, 146, 149, 211, 269, 276, 277, 345, 346, 370, 371, 401, 404, 436, 662, 787, 788,
793, 794, 841
Certification of the Constitution of the Western Cape, 1997 (CCT6/97) [1997] ZACC 8; 1997 (4) SA 795
(CC); 1997 (9) BCLR 1167 (CC)(2 September 1997) 240
Certification of the Constitution of the Western Cape, 1997 (CCT29/97) [1997] ZACC 15; 1998 (1) SA 655
(CC); 1997 (12) BCLR 1653 (CC) (18 November 1997) 314
Certification of the Kwazulu-Natal Constitution (CCT15/96) [1996] ZACC 17; 1996 (11) BCLR 1419; 1996
(4) SA 1098 (6 September 1996) 240, 314
Chassagnou v France (1999) 29 EHRR 615 132, 600, 603
Chetty v Naidoo 1974 (3) SA 13 (A) 20; Gien v Gien 1979 (2) SA 1113 (T) 1120 743
Chief Lesapo v North West Agricultural Bank and Another (CCT23/99) [1999] ZACC 16; 2000 (1) SA 409
(CC); 1999 (12) BCLR 1420 (16 November 1999) 82, 459
Christian Education South Africa v Minister of Education (CCT4/00) [2000] ZACC 11; 2000 (4) SA 757 (CC);
2000 (10) BCLR 1051 (18 August 2000) 430, 432, 433, 463, 464, 466, 467, 614, 615, 620, 629,
630, 631, 639, 643, 645
Christian Education South Africa v Minister of Education (CCT13/98) [1998] ZACC 16; 1999 (2) SA 83; 1998
(12) BCLR 1449 (14 October 1998) 241, 456
Christian Lawyers Association of SA v Minister of Health 1998 (11) BCLR 1434 (T), 1998 (4) SA 1113 (T)
(Christian Lawyers I) 403, 586
Christian Lawyers Association v Minister of Health 2005 (1) SA 509 (T) (Christian Lawyers II) 586
The Citizen 1978 (Pty) Ltd and Others v McBride (CCT 23/10) [2011] ZACC 11; 2011 (4) SA 191 (CC); 2011
(8) BCLR 816 (CC) (8 April 2011) 462
City Council of Pretoria v Walker (CCT8/97) [1998] ZACC 1; 1998 (2) SA 363 (CC); 1998 (3) BCLR 257 (CC)
(17 February 1998) 521, 524, 530, 546, 549, 550, 555, 562
City of Cape Town and Others v Robertson and Others (CCT 19/04) [2004] ZACC 21; 2005 (2) SA 323 (CC)
(29 November 2004) 302, 336
City of Johannesburg Metropolitan Municipality v Blue Moonlight Properties 39 (Pty) Ltd and Another (CC)
[2011] ZACC 33; 2012 (2) SA 104 (CC); 2012 (2) BCLR 150 (CC) (1 December 2011) 504, 796, 814,
821
City of Johannesburg Metropolitan Municipality v Gauteng Development Tribunal and Others (CCT89/09)
[2010] ZACC 11; 2010 (6) SA 182 (CC); 2010 (9) BCLR 859 (CC) (18 June 2010) 338, 339, 340
City of Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality v Afriforum and Another (157/15) [2016] ZACC 19; 2016 (6) SA
279 (CC); 2016 (9) BCLR 1133 (CC) (21 July 2016) 330, 331, 332, 333
City of Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality v Link Africa (Pty) Ltd and Others (CCT184/14) [2015] ZACC 29;
2015 (6) SA 440 (CC); 2015 (11) BCLR 1265 (CC) (23 September 2015) 755
Coetzee v Government of the Republic of South Africa; Matiso and Others v Commanding Officer Port Elizabeth
Prison and Others (CCT19/94, CCT22/94) [1995] ZACC 7; 1995 (4) SA 631 (CC); 1995 (10) BCLR
1382 (CC) (22 September 1995) 431, 466, 492, 498
Collins v Minister of the Interior 1957 (1) SA 552 (A) 11
Committee for the Commonwealth of Canada v Canada (1991) 77 DLR (4th) 385 (SCC) 448
Constitutionality of the Mpumalanga Petitions Bill, 2000 (CCT 11/01) [2001] ZACC 10; 2002 (1) SA 447
(CC); 2001 (11) BCLR 1126 (5 October 2001) 63, 176
Corruption Watch (RF) NPC and Another v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others; Council for the
Advancement of the South African Constitution v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others
(Corruption Watch) (62470/2015) [2017] ZAGPPHC 743; [2018] 1 All SA 471 (GP); 2018 (1) SACR
317 (GP) (8 December 2017) 193, 198, 213, 277
Corruption Watch NPC and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others; Nxasana v
Corruption Watch NPC and Others (Corruption Watch II) (CCT 333/17; CCT 13/18); [2018] ZACC 23;
2018 (10) BCLR 1179 (CC); 2018 (2) SACR 442 (CC) (13 August 2018) 194, 198, 274, 279, 280, 496
D
Daniels v Campbell and Others (CCT 40/ 03) [2004] ZACC 14; 2004 (5) SA 331 (CC); 2004 (7) BCLR 735
(CC) (11 March 2004) 225, 421, 422
Daniels v Scribante and Another (CCT50/16) [2017] ZACC 13; 2017 (4) SA 341 (CC); 2017 (8) BCLR 949
(CC) (11 May 2017) 563, 569, 738, 747, 748, 749, 750, 779, 798, 799, 800
Dawood and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others; Shalabi and Another v Minister of Home Affairs
and Others; Thomas and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others (CCT35/99) [2000] ZACC 8; 2000
(3) SA 936; 2000 (8) BCLR 837 (7 June 2000) 83, 403, 449, 481, 482, 485, 497, 514, 515, 565,
566, 569, 597
De Lange v Presiding Bishop of the Methodist Church of Southern Africa for the time being and Another
(CCT223/14) [2015] ZACC 35; 2016 (2) SA 1 (CC); 2016 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) (24 November 2015) 528
De Lange v Smuts NO and Others (CCT26/97) [1998] ZACC 6; 1998 (3) SA 785 (CC); 1998 (7) BCLR 779
(28 May 1998) (CC) 59, 103, 248, 570, 575, 576, 577, 583
De Lille and Another v Speaker of the National Assembly 1998 (3) SA 430 (C) 89, 119, 120
Democratic Alliance and Another v Masondo NO and Another 2003 (2) SA 413 (CC) 164
Democratic Alliance v Minister of International Relations and Co-operation and Others (Council for the
Advancement of the South African Constitution as Intervening Party) (83145/2016); [2017] ZAGPPHC
53; [2017] 2 All SA 123 (GP); 2017 (3) SA 212 (GP); [2017] 2 All SA 123 (GP); 2017 (1) SACR 623
(GP) (22 February 2017) 194, 484
Democratic Alliance v President of South Africa and Others (CCT 122/11) [2012] ZACC 24; 2012 (12) BCLR
1297 (CC); 2013 (1) SA 248 (CC) (5 October 2012) 80, 81, 198, 206, 207, 208, 274, 276
Democratic Alliance v President of South Africa and Others (18392/13) [2014] ZAWCHC 31; [2014] 2 All SA
569 (WCC); 2014 (4) SA 402 (WCC); 2014 (7) BCLR 800 (WCC) (13 March 2014) 321
Democratic Alliance v Public Protector; Council for the Advancement of the South African Constitution v Public
Protector (11311/2018; 13394/2018) [2019] ZAGPPHC 132; [2019] 3 All SA 127 (GP); 2019 (7)
BCLR 882 (GP) (20 May 2019) 293, 298, 299
Democratic Alliance v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others 2016 (3) SA 487 (CC) 120, 121, 122,
123, 488, 489
De Reuck v Director of Public Prosecutions (Witwatersrand Local Division) and Others (CCT5/03) [2003] ZACC
19; 2004 (1) SA 406 (CC); 2003 (12) BCLR 1333 (CC) (15 October 2003) 243, 440, 441, 464, 465,
673, 674
De Vos N.O. and Others v Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development and Others (CCT 150/14)
[2015] ZACC 21; 2015 (2) SACR 217 (CC); 2015 (9) BCLR 1026 (CC) (26 June 2015) 575
Dikoko v Mokhatla (CCT62/05) [2006] ZACC 10; 2006 (6) SA 235 (CC); 2007 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) (3 August
2006) 117, 427
Director of Public Prosecutions, Transvaal v Minister for Justice and Constitutional Development (CCT 36/08)
[2009] ZACC 8; 2009 (4) SA 222 (CC); 2009 (7) BCLR 637 (CC) (1 April 2009) 431, 432
Director of Public Prosecutions Cape of Good Hope v Bathgate 2000 (2) BCLR 151 (C) 756
Dladla and Another v City of Johannesburg and Others (CCT124/16) [2017] ZACC 42; 2018 (2) SA 327 (CC);
2018 (2) BCLR 119 (CC) (1 December 2017) 446, 447, 565, 566
Doctors for Life International v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others (CCT12/05) [2006] ZACC 11;
2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC); 2006 (6) SA 416 (CC) (17 August 2006) 85, 88, 93, 94, 101, 102, 103,
115, 116, 124, 125, 126, 127, 145, 146, 147, 150, 162, 163, 168, 240, 286, 479, 498, 503
Dormehl v Minister of Justice and Others (CCT10/00) [2000] ZACC 4; 2000 (2) SA 825; 2000 (5) BCLR 471
(CC) (14 April 2000) 241
Dube and Others v Zikalala and Others (7904/2016P) [2017] ZAKZPHC 36; [2017] 4 All SA 365 (KZP) (12
September 2017) 110, 716
Du Plessis; Amod v Multilateral Motor Vehicle Accidents Fund (CCT4/98) [1998] ZACC 11; 1998 (4) SA 753
(CC); 1998 (10) BCLR 1207 (CC) (27 August 1998) 424
Du Plessis and Others v De Klerk and Another (CCT8/95) [1996] ZACC 10; 1996 (3) SA 850 (CC); 1996 (5)
BCLR 658 (CC) (15 May 1996) 414, 417
Du Toit and Another v Minister of Welfare and Population Development and Others (CCT40/01) [2002] ZACC
20; 2003 (2) SA 198 (CC); 2002 (10) BCLR 1006 (CC) (10 September 2002) 524
Du Toit v Minister of Transport (CCT22/04) [2005] ZACC 9; 2006 (1) SA 297 (CC); 2005 (11) BCLR 1053
(CC) (8 September 2005) 767, 768, 769
E
Eaton v Brant County Board of Education [1997] 1 SCR 241 560
Economic Freedom Fighters and Others v Speaker of the National Assembly and Another (CCT76/17) [2017]
ZACC 47; 2018 (3) BCLR 259 (CC); 2018 (2) SA 571 (CC) (29 December 2017) 227, 288
Economic Freedom Fighters v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others; Democratic Alliance v Speaker of
the National Assembly and Others (CCT 143/15; CCT 171/15) [2016] ZACC 11; 2016 (5) BCLR 618
(CC); 2016 (3) SA 580 (CC) (31 March 2016) 106, 107, 183, 184, 240, 292, 294, 295, 296
Economic Freedom Fighters v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others v Speaker of the National
Assembly and Others 2018 (3) BCLR 259 (CC); 2018 (2) SA 571 (CC) 66, 113, 156, 157, 185
Electoral Commission v Mhlope and Others (CCT55/16) [2016] ZACC 15; 2016 (5) SA 1 (CC); 2016 (8)
BCLR 987 (CC) (14 June 2016) 724, 725
Engelbrecht v Road Accident Fund (CCT57/06) [2007] ZACC 1; 2007 (6) SA 96 (CC); 2007 (5) BCLR 457
(CC) (6 March 2007) 451
Engel v Vitale 370 US 421 (1962) 431 620
Estate Agency Affairs Board v Auction Alliance (Pty) Ltd and Others (CCT 94/13) [2014] ZACC 3; 2014 (3) SA
106 (CC); 2014 (4) BCLR 373 (CC) (27 February 2014) 485
Everson v Board of Education of the Township of Ewing 330 US 1 (1947) 618
Executive Council of the Province of the Western Cape v Minister for Provincial Aff airs and Constitutional
Development and Another, Executive Council of KwaZulu-Natal v President of the Republic of South Africa
and Others (CCT15/99, CCT18/99) [1999] ZACC 13; 2000 (1) SA 661 (CC); 1999 (12) BCLR 1360 (15
October 1999) 63, 176, 177, 178, 204, 337
Executive Council of the Western Cape Legislature and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and
Others (CCT27/95) [1995] ZACC 8; 1995 (4) SA 877 (CC); 1995 (10) BCLR 1289 (CC) (22 September
1995) 33, 63, 64, 168, 175, 176, 204, 241, 325, 495, 497, 498
Ex parte Chairperson of the Constitutional Assembly: In re Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of
South Africa, 1996 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC) (6 September 1996) 149, 305,
370
Ex parte Minister of Safety and Security: In re S v Walters (CCT28/01) [2002] ZACC 6; 2002 (4) SA 613 (CC);
2002 (7) BCLR 663 (CC) (21 May 2002) 438, 443, 462
Ex parte Minister of Safety and Security: In re S v Williams (CCT20/94) [1995] ZACC 6; 1995 (3) SA 632
(CC); 1995 (7) BCLR 861 (CC) (9 June 1995) 431, 441, 461, 562, 579, 581
Ex Parte President of the Republic of South Africa: In re Constitutionality of the Liquor Bill (CCT12/99) [1999]
ZACC 15; 2000 (1) SA 732; 2000 (1) BCLR 1 (11 November 1999) 170, 174, 175, 321, 322, 323, 338
F
Federation of Governing Bodies for South African Schools (FEDSAS) v Member of the Executive Council for
Education, Gauteng and Another [2016] ZACC 14; 2016 (4) SA 546 (CC); 2016 (8) BCLR 1050 (CC) (20
May 2016) 326
Fedsure Life Assurance Ltd and Others v Greater Johannesburg Transitional Metropolitan Council and Others
(CCT7/98) [1998] ZACC 17; 1999 (1) SA 374 (CC); 1998 (12) BCLR 1458 (14 October 1998) 79, 80,
199, 206, 302, 347
Ferreira v Levin NO and Others; Vryenhoek and Others v Powell NO and Others (CCT5/95) [1995] ZACC 13;
1996 (1) SA 984 (CC); 1996 (1) BCLR 1 (6 December 1995) 407, 408, 420, 482, 483, 563, 572, 573,
574
First National Bank of SA Limited t/a Wesbank v Commissioner for the South African Revenue Services and
Another; First National Bank of SA Limited t/a Wesbank v Minister of Finance (CCT19/01) [2002] ZACC 5;
2002 (4) SA 768 (CC); 2002 (7) BCLR 702 (16 May 2002) 437, 442, 443, 746, 750, 751, 752, 753,
756, 759, 760, 761, 762, 763, 764, 779
FNM v The Refugee Appeal Board and Others (71738/2016) [2018] ZAGPPHC 532; [2018] 4 All SA 228
(GP); 2019 (1) SA 468 (GP) (12 July 2018) 403
Forum for Black Journalists v Katy Katopodis Case ref no.: GP/2008/0161/L BIOS 611, 612
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security (CCT12/95, CCT11/95) [1995] ZACC 11; 1996 (1) SA 388 (CC); 1995
(12) BCLR 1579 (CC) (29 November 1995) 478, 485
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security (CCT14/96) [1997] ZACC 6; 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC); 1997 (7) BCLR
851 (CC) (5 June 1997) 503, 819
Fraser v Children’s Court Pretoria North and Others (CCT31/96) [1997] ZACC 1; 1997 (2) SA 218 (CC); 1996
(8) BCLR 1085 (CC) (5 February 1997) 497, 498
Fraser v Naude and Another (Fraser II) (CCT14/98) [1998] ZACC 13; 1999 (1) SA 1 (CC); 1998 (11) BCLR
1357 (CC) (23 September 1998) 481, 485
Freedom of Religion South Africa v Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development and Others
(CCT320/17) [2019] ZACC 34; 2020 (1) SA 1 (CC); 2019 (11) BCLR 1321 (CC) (18 September 2019)
514, 566, 567, 569, 578, 579
Freedom Stationery (Pty) Ltd v MEC for Education, Eastern Cape (59/2011) [2011] ZAECELLC 1 (16 March
2011) 829
Freedom Under Law v Acting Chairperson: Judicial Service Commission and Others (2011 (3) SA 549 (SCA);
[2011] 3 All SA 513 (SCA)) [2011] ZASCA 59; 52/2011 (31 March 2011) 265
G
Gaum and Others v Van Rensburg and Others (40819/17) [2019] ZAGPPHC 52; [2019] 2 All SA 722 (GP) (8
March 2019) 626, 627, 628
Gauteng Provincial Legislature In re: Gauteng School Education Bill of 1995 (CCT39/95) [1996] ZACC 4;
1996 (3) SA 165 (CC); 1996 (4) BCLR 537 (CC) (4 April 1996) 653, 827
Gauteng Provincial Legislature v Killian and 29 Others 2001 (2) SA 68 (SCA) 142
Geldenhuys v Minister of Safety and Security and Another 2002 (4) SA 719 (C) 728G–I 54
Gelyke Kanse and Others v Chairperson of the Senate of the University of Stellenbosch and Others (CCT
311/17) [2019] ZACC 38; 2020 (1) SA 368 (CC); 2019 (12) BCLR 1479 (CC) (10 October 2019) 514,
789, 831, 834, 835
Giant Concerts CC v Rinaldo Investments (Pty) Ltd and Others (CCT 25/12) [2012] ZACC 28; 2013 (3) BCLR
251 (CC) (29 November 2012) para 23 408, 409
Glenister v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others 2011 (3) SA 347 (CC) 101
Glenister v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (Glenister I) 2009 (1) SA 287 (CC) 101, 102
Glenister v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT 48/10) [2011] ZACC 6; 2011 (3) SA
347 (CC); 2011 (7) BCLR 651 (CC) (17 March 2011) 795, 796
Gory v Kolver NO and Others (CCT28/06) [2006] ZACC 20; 2007 (4) SA 97 (CC); 2007 (3) BCLR 249 (CC)
(23 November 2006) 524
Governing Body of the Rivonia Primary School and Another v MEC for Education: Gauteng Province and Others
(11/08340) [2011] ZAGPJHC 182; [2012] 1 All SA 576 (GSJ); 2012 (5) BCLR 537 (GSJ) (7 December
2011) 655
Governing Body of the Rivonia Primary School and Another v MEC for Education: Gauteng Province and Others
(161/12) [2012] ZASCA 194; 2013 (1) SA 632 (SCA); [2013] 1 All SA 633 (SCA) (30 November 2012)
655
Government of the Republic of South Africa and Others v Grootboom and Others (CCT11/00) [2000] ZACC
19; 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC); 2000 (11) BCLR 1169 (CC) (4 October 2000) 525, 526, 562, 564, 746, 789,
790, 792, 797, 798, 800, 802, 803, 805–806, 807, 808, 810, 811, 812, 813, 820, 838, 839, 840
Government of the Republic of South Africa v Sunday Times Newspaper and Another 1995 (2) SA 221 (T) 676
Growthpoint Properties Ltd v South Africa Commercial Catering and Allied Workers Union (SACCAWU) and
Others (6467/2010) [2010] ZAKZDHC 38; 2011 (1) BCLR 81 (KZD); [2011] 1 All SA 537 (KZD); (2010)
31 ILJ 2539 (KZD) (3 September 2010) 703, 704
Gumede (born Shange) v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT 50/08) [2008] ZACC 23;
2009 (3) SA 152 (CC); 2009 (3) BCLR 243 (CC) (8 December 2008) 427, 637, 650
Gundwana v Steko Development CC and Others (CCT 44/10) [2011] ZACC 14; 2011 (3) SA 608 (CC); 2011
(8) BCLR 792 (CC) (11 April 2011) 802
H
Hamata and Another v Chairman, Peninsula Technikon Internal Disciplinary Committee and Others 2000 (4)
SA 621 (C) 671
Harksen v Lane NO and Others (CCT9/97) [1997] ZACC 12; 1998 (1) SA 300 (CC); 1997 (11) BCLR 1489
(CC) (7 October 1997) 521, 524, 525, 531, 545, 546, 547, 551, 552, 558, 751
Harris and Others v Minister of the Interior and Another 1952 (2) SA 428 (A) 11, 45
Harvey v Umhlatuze Municipality and Others (4387/08) [2010] ZAKZPHC 86; 2011 (1) SA 601 (KZP); 2011
(4) BCLR 379 (KZP) (3 December 2010) 766
Head of Department, Department of Education, Free State Province v Welkom High School and Another; Head
of Department, Department of Education, Free State Province v Harmony High School and Another (CCT
103/12) [2013] ZACC 25; 2014 (2) SA 228 (CC); 2013 (9) BCLR 989 (CC) (10 July 2013) 480
Head of Department: Mpumalanga Department of Education and Another v Hoërskool Ermelo and Another
(CCT40/09) [2009] ZACC 32; 2010 (2) SA 415 (CC); 2010 (3) BCLR 177 (CC) (14 October 2009) 652,
653, 657, 789, 823, 831, 832, 834
Helen Suzman Foundation v Judicial Service Commission (CCT289/16) [2018] ZACC 8; 2018 (4) SA 1 (CC);
2018 (7) BCLR 763 (CC) (24 April 2018) 252, 253, 254, 493
Herbert N.O. and Others v Senqu Municipality and Others (CCT 308/18) [2019] ZACC 31; 2019 (6) SA 231
(CC); 2019 (11) BCLR 1343 (CC) (22 August 2019) 497, 531
Hoërskool Ermelo (CC) and Minister of Education (Western Cape) v Mikro Primary School Governing Body
(140/2005) [2005] ZASCA 66; [2005] 3 All SA 436 (SCA) (27 June 2005) 655, 656
Hoffmann v South African Airways (CCT17/00) [2000] ZACC 17; 2001 (1) SA 1 (CC); 2000 (11) BCLR 1211
(CC); (28 September 2000) 521, 524, 548, 552, 606
Hofmeyr v Minister of Justice and Another 1992 (3) SA 108 (C) 191
Holomisa v Argus Newspaper 1996 (2) SA 588 (W) 855–56 677
Hotz and Others v University of Cape Town (CCT280/16) [2017] ZACC 10; 2018 (1) SA 369 (CC); 2017 (7)
BCLR 815 (CC) (12 April 2017) 604
Hotz and Others v University of Cape Town (730/2016) [2016] ZASCA 159; [2016] 4 All SA 723 (SCA); 2017
(2) SA 485 (SCA) (20 October 2016) 604
Hurley v Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston 515 US 557 (1995) 603
I
Independent Electoral Commission v Langeberg Municipality (CCT 49/00) [2001] ZACC 23; 2001 (3) SA 925
(CC); 2001 (9) BCLR 883 (CC) (7 June 2001) 133, 135, 288, 289, 309, 310, 407
Independent Newspapers (Pty) Ltd v Minister of Intelligence Services: In re Masetlha v President of the
Republic of South Africa and Another (CCT 38/07) [2008] ZACC 6; 2008 (5) SA 31 (CC); 2008 (8) BCLR
771 (CC) (22 May 2008) 475, 687, 688
Ingonyama Trust v eThekwini Municipality (149/2011) [2012] ZASCA 104; 2013 (1) SA 564 (SCA) (1 June
2012) 351
In re: KwaZulu-Natal Amakhosi and Iziphakanyiswa Amendment Bill of 1995, In re: Payment of Salaries.
Allowances and Other Privileges to the Ingonyama Bill of 1995 (CCT1/96, CCT6/96) [1996] ZACC 15;
1996 (7) BCLR 903; 1996 (4) SA 653 (5 July 1996) 170, 325
Institute for Democracy in South Africa and Others v African National Congress and Others (9828/03) [2005]
ZAWCHC 30; 2005 (5) SA 39 (C); [2005] 3 All SA 45 (C) (20 April 2005) 607
International Trade Administration Commission v SCAW South Africa (Pty) Ltd (CCT 59/09) [2010] ZACC 6;
2012 (4) SA 618 (CC); 2010 (5) BCLR 457 (CC) (9 March 2010) 227
Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic Offences and Others v Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd and
Others In re: Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd and Others v Smit NO and Others (CCT1/00) [2000]
ZACC 12; 2000 (10) BCLR 1079 (CC); 2001 (1) SA 545 (CC) (25 August 2000) 27, 233, 421, 422,
486, 588, 589
Islamic Unity Convention v Independent Broadcasting Authority and Others (CCT36/01)) [2002] ZACC 3;
2002 (4) SA 294 (CC) 2002 (5) BCLR 433 (11 April 2002) 243, 401, 456, 464, 465, 466, 494, 666,
667, 671, 672, 690
Ismail v Ismail 1983 (1) SA 1006 (A) 1026 616, 636
J
Jaftha v Schoeman and Others; Van Rooyen v Stoltz and Others (CCT74/03) [2004] ZACC 25; 2005 (2) SA
140 (CC); 2005 (1) BCLR 78 (CC) (8 October 2004) 457, 801, 821
J and Another v Director General, Department of Home Affairs and Others (CCT46/02) [2003] ZACC 3; 2003
(5) SA 621 (CC); 2003 (5) BCLR 463 (CC) (28 March 2003) 485, 497–498, 524
Janse van Rensburg and Another v Minister of Trade and Industry and Another (CCT13/99) [2000] ZACC 18;
2001 (1) SA 29; 2000 (11) BCLR 1235 (CC) (29 September 2000) 83
Janse van Rensburg NO v Minister van Handel en Nywerheid 1999 (2) BCLR 204 (T) 221 756
Johannesburg Municipal Council v Rand Townships Registrar and Others 1910 TS 1314 1319 743
Johncom Media Investments Ltd v M (CCT 08/08) [2009] ZACC 5; 2009 (4) SA 7 (CC); 2009 (8) BCLR 751
(CC) (17 March 2009) 431, 457, 462, 686, 687
Jooste v Score Supermarket Trading (Pty) Ltd (Minister of Labour intervening) (CCT15/98) [1998] ZACC 18;
1999 (2) SA 1 (CC); 1999 (2) BCLR 139 (CC) (27 November 1998) 532
Jordaan and Another v City of Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality and Others; New Ventures Consulting and
Services (Pty) Ltd and Others v City of Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality and Another; Livanos and Others
v Ekurhuleni Metropolitan Municipality and Another; Oak Plant Rentals (Pty) Ltd and Others v Ekurhuleni
Metropolitan Municipality (74195/2013; 13039/2014; 13040/2014; 19552/2015; 23826/2014)
[2016] ZAGPPHC 941; [2017] 1 All SA 585 (GP); 2017 (2) SA 295 (GP) (7 November 2016) 760, 761,
762
Jordaan and Others v City of Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality and Others; City of Tshwane Metropolitan
Municipality v New Ventures Consulting and Services (Pty) Limited and Others; Ekurhuleni Metropolitan
Municipality v Livanos and Others (CCT283/16, CCT293/16, CCT294/16, CCT283/16) [2017] ZACC 31;
2017 (6) SA 287 (CC); 2017 (11) BCLR 1370 (CC) (29 August 2017) 420, 425
Joseph and Others v City of Johannesburg and Others (CCT 43/09) [2009] ZACC 30; 2010 (4) SA 55 (CC);
2010 (3) BCLR 212 (CC) (9 October 2009) 329, 330, 789
JT Publishing (Pty) Ltd and Another v Minister of Safety and Security and Others (CCT49/95) [1996] ZACC 23;
1997 (3) SA 514 (CC); 1996 (12) BCLR 1599 (CC) (21 November 1996) 506
Judicial Service Commission and Another v Cape Bar Council and Another 2012 (11) BCLR 1239 (SCA);2013
(1) SA 170 (SCA) [2013] 1 All SA 40 (SCA) (14 September 2012) 67, 258
Justice Alliance of South Africa v President of Republic of South Africa and Others, Freedom Under Law v
President of Republic of South Africa and Others, Centre for Applied Legal Studies and Another v President
of Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT 53/11, CCT 54/11, CCT 62/11) [2011] ZACC 23; 2011 (5)
SA 388 (CC); 2011 (10) BCLR 1017 (CC) (29 July 2011) 63, 64, 67, 177, 178, 179, 204, 205, 229,
261, 262, 263
K
Kham and Others v Electoral Commission and Another (CCT64/15) [2015] ZACC 37; 2016 (2) BCLR 157
(CC); 2016 (2) SA 338 (CC) (30 November 2015) 724, 725
Khosa and Others v Minister of Social Development and Others, Mahlaule and Another v Minister of Social
Development (CCT 13/03, CCT 12/03) [2004] ZACC 11; 2004 (6) SA 505 (CC); 2004 (6) BCLR 569
(CC) (4 March 2004) 125, 403, 489, 526, 527, 552, 553, 789, 810, 816, 821
Khumalo and Governing Body of the Juma Musjid Primary School & Others v Essay NO and Others (CCT
29/10) [2011] ZACC 13; 2011 (8) BCLR 761 (CC) (11 April 2011) 418, 419, 670, 675, 676, 798, 799,
824, 825, 829, 838
Khumalo and Others v Holomisa (CCT53/01) [2002] ZACC 12; 2002 (5) SA 401 (CC); 2002 (8) BCLR 771
(CC) (14 June 2002) 412, 413, 414, 515, 569, 701
Komape and Others v Minister of Basic Education (1416/2015) [2018] ZALMPPHC 18 (23 April 2018) 509
Komape v Minister of Basic Education (754/2018 and 1051/2018) [2019] ZASCA 192 (18 December 2019)
509
Kruger v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT 57/07) [2008] ZACC 17; 2009 (1) SA
417 (CC); 2009 (3) BCLR 268 (CC) (2 October 2008) 206, 407, 408
K v Minister of Safety and Security (CCT52/04) [2005] ZACC 8; 2005 (6) SA 419 (CC); 2005 (9) BCLR 835
(CC); [2005] 8 BLLR 749 (CC) (13 June 2005) 234, 424, 426
L
Land Access Movement of South Africa and Others v Chairperson of the National Council of Provinces and
Others 2016 (5) SA 635 (CC); 2016 (10) BCLR 1277 (CC) 94, 124
Langa and Others v Hlophe (697/08) [2009] ZASCA 36; [2009] 3 All SA 417 (SCA); 2009 (8) BCLR 823
(SCA) (31 March 2009) 507
Larbi-Odam v MEC for Education (North West Province) (CCT2/97) [1997] ZACC 16; 1998 (1) SA 745 (CC);
1997 (12) BCLR 1655 (CC) (26 November 1997) 456, 524, 548
Laugh it Off Promotions CC v South African Breweries International (Finance) BV t/a Sabmark International
(CCT42/04) [2005] ZACC 7; 2006 (1) SA 144 (CC); 2005 (8) BCLR 743 (CC) (27 May 2005) 462, 672
Law Society of South Africa and Others v Minister for Transport and Another (CCT 38/10) [2010] ZACC 25;
2011(1) SA 400 (CC); 2011 (2) BCLR 150 (CC) (25 November 2010) 577, 578
Law v Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration) 1 SCR 497 (1999) 562–563
Lawyers for Human Rights and Others v Minister of Home Affairs and Others (CCT 18/03) [2004] ZACC 12;
2004 (4) SA 125 (CC); 2004 (7) BCLR 775 (CC) (9 March 2004) 403, 407–408, 457
Le Sueur and Another v eThekwini Municipality and Others 2013 JDR 0178 (KZP) 343, 344
Liberal Party v The Electoral Commission and Others (CCT 10/04) [2004] ZACC 1; 2004 (8) BCLR 810 (CC)
(5 April 2004) 718
Lingwood and Another v The Unlawful Occupiers of R/E of Erf 9 Highlands 2008 (3) BCLR 325 (W) 501
Lochner v New York (CCT23/95) [1996] ZACC 2; 1996 (2) SA 751 (CC); 1996 (4) BCLR 449 (CC) (27 March
1996) 574
Lourens v Speaker of the National Assembly (20827/2014) [2016] ZASCA 11; [2016] 2 All SA 340 (SCA)
(10 March 2016) 661
Lovelace v Canada CCPR/C/13/D/24/1977 646, 648
Luitingh v Minister of Defence (CCT29/95) [1996] ZACC 5; 1996 (4) BCLR 581; 1996 (2) SA 909 (4 April
1996) 241
Lyng v Northwest Indian Cemetery 485 US 439 623
M
Maccsand (Pty) Ltd v City of Cape Town and Others (CCT103/11) (CC) [2012] ZACC 7; 2012 (4) SA 181
(CC); 2012 (7) BCLR 690 (CC) (12 April 2012) 338
Mackey v US 401 US 667 (1971) 691 495
Madzodzo and Others v Minister of Basic Education and Others (2144/2012) [2014] ZAECMHC 5; [2014] 2
All SA 339 (ECM); 2014 (3) SA 441 (ECM) (20 February 2014) 829
Magajane v Chairperson, North West Gambling Board (CCT49/05) [2006] ZACC 8; 2006 (5) SA 250 (CC);
2006 (10) BCLR 1133 (CC) (8 June 2006) 457
Magidimisi v Premier of the Eastern Cape and Others (2180/04, ECJ031/06) [2006] ZAECHC 20 (25 April
2006) 214
Malachi v Cape Dance Academy International (Pty) Ltd (CCT 05/10) [2010] ZACC 13; 2010 (6) SA 1 (CC);
2010 (11) BCLR 1116 (CC) (24 August 2010) 570, 575
Malema and Another v Chairman of the National Council of Provinces and Another 2015 (4) SA 145 (WCC)
120
Mandla and Another v Dowell Lee and Another [1983] 1 All ER 1062 (HL) 644
Mansingh v General Council of the Bar and Others (CCT 43/13) [2013] ZACC 40; 2014 (2) SA 26 (CC); 2014
(1) BCLR 85 (CC) (28 November 2013) 190
Masetlha v President of the Republic of South Africa and Another (CCT 01/07) [2007] ZACC 20; 2008 (1) SA
566 (CC); 2008 (1) BCLR 1 (3 October 2007) 80, 201, 203, 206, 211, 212, 562
Mashavha v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others 2005 (2) SA 476 (CC); 2004 (12) BCLR
1243 (CC) 326, 327
Masiya v Director of Public Prosecutions Pretoria (The State) and Another (CCT54/06) [2007] ZACC 9; 2007
(5) SA 30 (CC); 2007 (8) BCLR 827 (10 May 2007) 234, 243
Masuku and Another v South African Human Rights Commission obo South African Jewish Board of Deputies
(1062/2017) [2018] ZASCA 180; 2019 (2) SA 194 (SCA); [2019] 1 All SA 608 (SCA) (4 December
2018) 692
Matatiele Municipality and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others 2007 (1) BCLR 47
(CC) 124
Matatiele Municipality and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT73/05) [2006]
ZACC 2; 2006 (5) SA 47 (CC); 2006 (5) BCLR 622 (CC) (27 February 2006) 334
Mayelane v Ngwenyama and Another (CCT 57/12) [2013] ZACC 14; 2013 (4) SA 415 (CC); 2013 (8) BCLR
918 (CC) (30 May 2013) 427, 637, 638
May v Udwin 1981 (1) SA 1 (A) 266
Mazibuko and Others v City of Johannesburg and Others (CCT 39/09) [2009] ZACC 28; 2010 4 SA 1 (CC);
2010 (3) BCLR 239 (CC) (8 October 2009) 788, 789, 790, 792, 793, 794, 797, 798, 803, 809, 812,
814
Mazibuko v Sisulu and Another 2013 (6) SA 249 (CC) 102, 113, 116, 158, 159, 187, 189
McBride v Minister of Police and Another (CCT255/15) [2016] ZACC 30; 2016 (2) SACR 585 (CC); 2016 (11)
BCLR 1398 (CC) (6 September 2016) 494
MEC: Department of Agriculture, Conservation and Environment v HTF Developers (Pty) Ltd (CCT 32/07)
[2007] ZACC 25; 2008 (2) SA 319 (CC); 2008 (4) BCLR 417 (CC) (6 December 2007) 473
MEC for Education: Kwazulu-Natal and Others v Pillay (CCT 51/06) [2007] ZACC 21; 2008 (1) SA 474 (CC);
2008 (2) BCLR 99 (CC) (5 October 2007) 234, 404, 467, 472, 528, 558, 559, 560, 562, 595, 596,
597, 629, 644, 825
MEC for the Department of Welfare v Kate (580/04) [2006] ZASCA 49; 2006 (4) SA 478 (SCA); [2006] 2 All
SA 455 (SCA) (30 March 2006) 504, 505
Merafong Demarcation Forum and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT 41/07)
[2008] ZACC 10; 2008 (5) SA 171 (CC); 2008 (10) BCLR 968 (CC) (13 June 2008) 87, 124, 152
Mhlanganisweni Community v Minister of Rural Development and Land Reform and Others (MalaMala) (LCC
156/2009) [2012] ZALCC 7 (19 April 2012) 768, 769
Mhlekwa & Feni v Head of the Western Tembuland Regional Authority 2000 (9) BCLR 979 (Tk) 272
Midi Television (Pty) Limited t/a e-tv v Director of Public Prosecutions (100/06) [2007] ZASCA 56; [2007] 3
All SA 318 (SCA); 2007 (9) BCLR 958 (SCA) (18 May 2007) 612, 677
Millennium Waste Management (Pty) Ltd v Chairperson of the Tender Board: Limpopo Province and Others
[2008] 2 All SA 145; 2008 (2) SA 481 (CC); 2008 (5) BCLR 508 (CC); 2008 (2) SA 481 (SCA) 356,
357
Minister for Justice and Constitutional Development v Chonco and Others (CCT 42/09) [2009] ZACC 25; 2010
(1) SACR 325 (CC); 2010 (2) BCLR 140 (CC); 2010 (4) SA 82 (CC) (30 September 2009) 206
Minister of Agriculture, Forestry and Fisheries v National Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals (CCT
122/15) [2015] ZACC 27; 2015 (11) BCLR 1387 (CC) (28 August 2015) 497
Minister of Agriculture, Forestry and Fisheries v National Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals
(CCT186/16) [2016] ZACC 26; 2016 (11) BCLR 1419 (CC) (25 August 2016) 497
Minister of Basic Education v Basic Education for All [2015] ZASCA 198; [2016] 1 All SA 369 (SCA); 2016
(4) SA 63 (SCA) 828
Minister of Constitutional Development and Another v South African Restructuring and Insolvency Practitioners
Association and Others (CCT13/17) [2018] ZACC 20; 2018 (5) SA 349 (CC); 2018 (9) BCLR 1099 (CC)
(5 July 2018) 533, 536, 539, 541, 543, 544, 561
Minister of Education (Western Cape) v Mikro Primary School Governing Body (140/2005) [2005] ZASCA 66;
[2005] 3 All SA 436 (SCA) (27 June 2005) 655, 656, 658
Minister of Finance and Others v Van Heerden (CCT 63/03) [2004] ZACC 3; 2004 (6) SA 121 (CC); 2004
(11) BCLR 1125 (CC); (29 July 2004) 29, 520, 521, 527, 529, 533, 534, 536, 537, 538, 539, 540,
541, 542, 543, 552, 561
Minister of Health and Another v New Clicks South Africa (Pty) Ltd and Others (CCT 59/2004) [2005] ZACC
14; 2006 (2) SA 311 (CC); 2006 (8) BCLR 872 (CC) (30 September 2005) 554
Minister of Health and Others v Treatment Action Campaign and Others (CCT 08/02) [2002] ZACC 15; 2002
(5) SA 721 (CC); 2002 (10) BCLR 1033 (CC) (5 July 2002) 69, 102, 564, 790
Minister of Home Affairs and Another v Fourie and Another (CCT 60/04) [2005] ZACC 19; 2006 (1) SA 524
(CC); 2006 (3) BCLR 355 (CC) (1 December 2005) 498, 499, 500, 524, 549, 568, 614, 616, 617,
618, 636, 637
Minister of Home Affairs and Another v Public Protector of the Republic of South Africa (308/2017) [2018]
ZASCA 15; [2018] 2 All SA 311 (SCA); 2018 (3) SA 380 (SCA) (15 March 2018) 292, 298
Minister of Home Affairs and Others v Watchenuka and Others (010/2003) [2003] ZASCA 142; [2004] 1 All
SA 21 (SCA) (28 November 2003) 403
Minister of Home Affairs v Eisenberg & Associates In re: Eisenberg & Associates v Minister of Home Affairs and
Others (CCT15/03) [2003] ZACC 10; 2003 (8) BCLR 838; 2003 (5) SA 281 (CC) (27 June 2003) 407,
408
Minister of Home Affairs v Liebenberg (CCT22/01) [2001] ZACC 3; 2001 (11) BCLR 1168; 2002 (1) SA 33
(CC) (8 October 2001) 209
Minister of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime Prevention and the Re-Integration of Offenders (NICRO)
and Others (CCT 03/04) [2004] ZACC 10; 2005 (3) SA 280 (CC); 2004 (5) BCLR 445 (CC) (3 March
2004) 90, 136, 137, 468, 469, 712, 730, 731, 732
Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development and Others v Prince (Clarke and Others Intervening);
National Director of Public Prosecutions and Others v Rubin; National Director of Public Prosecutions and
Others v Acton (CCT108/17) [2018] ZACC 30; 2018 (6) SA 393 (CC); 2018 (10) BCLR 1220 (CC) (18
September 2018) 431, 457, 459, 490, 569, 590, 591, 624
Minister of Justice v Ntuli (CCT15/97, CCT17/95) [1997] ZACC 7; 1997 (6) BCLR 677; 1997 (3) SA 772 (5
June 1997) 241
Minister of Justice v Ntuli (CCT15/97, CCT17/95) [1997] ZACC 7; 1997 (3) SA 772 (CC); 1997 (6) BCLR
677 (CC) (5 June 1997) 499
Minister of Local Government, Environmental Affairs and Development Planning, Western Cape v The Habitat
Council and Others; Minister of Local Government, Environmental Affairs and Development Planning,
Western Cape v City of Cape Town and Others (117/13) [2014] ZACC 9; 2014 (4) SA 437 (CC); 2014 (5)
BCLR 591 (CC) (4 April 2014) 340
Minister of Local Government, Environmental Affairs and Development Planning of the Western Cape v
Lagoonbay Lifestyle Estate (Pty) Ltd and Others (CCT 41/13) [2013] ZACC 39; 2014 (1) SA 521 (CC);
2014 (2) BCLR 182 (CC) (20 November 2013) 340
Minister of Minerals and Energy v Agri South Africa (458/2011) [2012] ZASCA 93; 2012 (5) SA 1 (SCA);
[2012] 3 All SA 266 (SCA); 2012 (9) BCLR 958 (SCA) (31 May 2012) 766
Minister of Safety and Security v South African Hunters and Game Conservation Association (CCT177/17)
[2018] ZACC 14; 2018 (2) SACR 164 (CC); 2018 (10) BCLR 1268 (CC) (7 June 2018) 545
Minister of Social Development and Others v Phoenix Cash & Carry Pmb CC (189/06, 244/06) [2007] ZASCA
26; [2007] 3 All SA 115 (SCA); 2007 (9) BCLR 982 (SCA) (27 March 2007) 358
Mistry v Interim National Medical and Dental Council (CCT13/97) [1998] ZACC 10; 1998 (4) SA 1127 (CC);
1998 (7) BCLR 880 (CC) (29 May 1998) 439
Mkhize v Umvoti Municipality and Others (628/2010) [2011] ZASCA 184; 2012 (1) SA 1 (SCA); [2011] 4 All
SA 460 (SCA); 2012 (6) BCLR 635 (SCA) (30 September 2011) 487
Mkontwana v Nelson Mandela Metropolitan Municipality and Another and Others; Transfer Rights Action
Campaign and Others v MEC, Local Government and Housing, Gauteng, and Others (Kwazulu-Natal Law
Society and Msunduzi Municipality as amici curiae) (CCT 57/03) [2004] ZACC 9; 2005 (1) SA 530 (CC);
2005 (2) BCLR 150 (CC) (6 October 2004) 27, 754, 755, 756, 757, 759
Mlungwana and Others v S and Another (CCT32/18) [2018] ZACC 45; 2019 (1) BCLR 88 (CC); 2019 (1)
SACR 429 (CC) (19 November 2018) 707, 708
Mnquma Local Municipality and Another v Premier of the Eastern Cape and Others [2012] JOL 28311 (ECB)
345
Moise v Greater Germiston Transitional Local Council: Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development
Intervening (Women’s Legal Centre as Amicus Curiae) (CCT 54/00) [2001] ZACC 21; 2001 (4) SA 491
(CC); 2001 (8) BCLR 765 (CC) (4 July 2001) 431, 468
Moodley v Kenmont School and Others (CCT281/18) [2019] ZACC 37; 2020 (1) SA 410 (CC); 2020 (1)
BCLR 74 (CC) (9 October 2019) 457
Moseneke and Others v Master of the High Court (CCT51/00) [2000] ZACC 27; 2001 (2) BCLR 103; 2001
(2) SA 18 (6 December 2000) 241, 524
Moutse Demarcation Forum v President of the Republic of South Africa 2011 (11) BCLR 1158 (CC) 124
Moyo and Another v Minister of Police and Others; Sonti and Another v Minister of Police and Others
(CCT174/18; CCT178/18) [2019] ZACC 40; 2020 (1) BCLR 91 (CC); 2020 (1) SACR 373 (CC) (22
October 2019) 487
Mphele v Government of the Republic of South Africa 1996 (7) BCLR 921 (CK) 954E 212
Msiza v Director-General, Department of Rural Development and Land Reform 2016 (5) SA 513 (LCC) 766,
767, 768, 769, 770
Mthembi-Mahanyele v Mail & Guardian Ltd and Another (054/2003) [2004] ZASCA 67; [2004] 3 All SA 511
(SCA) (2 August 2004) 671
Mukaddam v Pioneer Foods (Pty) Ltd and Others (CCT 131/12) [2013] ZACC 23; 2013 (5) SA 89 (CC); 2013
(10) BCLR 1135 (CC) (27 June 2013) 409
Mulowayi and Others v Minister of Home Affairs and Another (CCT249/18) [2019] ZACC 1; 2019 (4) BCLR
496 (CC) (29 January 2019) 497
Multani v Commission Scolaire Marguerite – Bourgeoys [2006] 1 SCR 256 632
Multichoice (Proprietary) Limited and Others v National Prosecuting Authority and Another, In Re; S v Pistorius,
In Re; Media 24 Limited and Others v Director of Public Prosecutions North Gauteng and Others
(10193/2014) [2014] ZAGPPHC 37; [2014] 2 All SA 446 (GP); 2014 (1) SACR 589 (GP) (25 February
2014) 681, 682, 683
My Vote Counts NPC v Minister of Justice and Correctional Services and Others (CCT249/17) [2018] ZACC
17; 2018 (5) SA 380 (CC); 2018 (8) BCLR 803 (CC) (21 June 2018) 88, 607–608, 609, 719, 720, 721
My Vote Counts NPC v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others (CCT121/14) [2015] ZACC 31 (30
September 2015) 528
N
NAACP v Alabama 357 U.S. 449 (1958) 602
Nandutu and Others v Minister of Home Affairs and Others (CCT114/18) [2019] ZACC 24; 2019 (5) SA 325
(CC); 2019 (8) BCLR 938 (CC) (28 June 2019) 446, 487
National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality and Another v Minister of Justice and Others (CCT11/98)
[1998] ZACC 15; 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC); 1998 (12) BCLR 1517 (CC) (9 October 1998) 29, 420, 457, 462,
464, 484, 486, 487, 488, 494, 495, 496, 497, 514, 520, 524, 529, 545, 552, 553, 567, 568, 583,
587, 589, 590, 597, 614
National Director of Public Prosecutions and Others v Freedom Under Law (67/2014) [2014] ZASCA 58;
2014 (4) SA 298 (SCA); 2014 (2) SACR 107 (SCA); [2014] 4 All SA 147 (SCA) (17 April 2014) 274
National Director of Public Prosecutions v Mohamed NO and Others (CCT44/02) [2003] ZACC 4; 2003 (4) SA
1 (CC); 2003 (5) BCLR 476 (CC) (3 April 2003) 506
National Director of Public Prosecutions v Zuma (573/08) [2009] ZASCA 1; 2009 (2) SA 277 (SCA); 2009
(1) SACR 361 (SCA); 2009 (4) BCLR 393 (SCA); [2009] 2 All SA 243 (SCA) (12 January 2009) 274,
275
National Education Health & Allied Workers Union (NEHAWU) v University of Cape Town and Others (CCT2/02)
[2002] ZACC 27; 2003 (2) BCLR 154; 2003 (3) SA 1 (CC) (6 December 2002) 234, 473
National Gambling Board v Premier of KwaZulu-Natal and Others (CCT32/01) [2001] ZACC 8; 2002 (2) BCLR
156; 2002 (2) SA 715 (21 December 2001) 241, 244
National Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals v Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development
and Another (29677/2013) [2014] ZAGPPHC 763 (8 October 2014) 404
Ndlwana v Hofmeyr NO and Others 1937 AD 229 11
Nelson Mandela Foundation Trust and Another v Afriforum NPC and Others (EQ02/2018) [2019] ZAEQC 2;
[2019] 4 All SA 237 (EqC); 2019 (10) BCLR 1245 (EqC); 2019 (6) SA 327 (GJ) (21 August 2019) 671,
696, 697
Nel v Le Roux NO (CCT30/95) [1996] ZACC 6; 1996 (3) SA 562 (CC); 1996 (4) BCLR 592 (CC) (4 April
1996) 583
New National Party v Government of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT9/99) [1999] ZACC 5; 1999
(3) SA 191 (CC); 1999 (5) BCLR 489 (CC) (13 April 1999) 90, 135, 136, 288, 289, 290, 291, 712,
722, 723, 726, 727, 728, 729, 732
New Nation Movement NPC and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT 110/19)
[2020] ZACC 11; 2020 (8) BCLR 950 (CC) (11 June 2020) 128, 131, 132, 133, 134, 595, 599, 600,
601, 712, 714, 733, 734, 735
Ngewu and Another v Post Office Retirement Fund and Others (CCT 117/11) [2013] ZACC 4; 2013 (4) BCLR
421 (CC) (7 March 2013) 532
Ngomane and Others v City of Johannesburg Metropolitan Municipality and Another (734/2017) [2019]
ZASCA 57; [2019] 3 All SA 69 (SCA); 2020 (1) SA 52 (SCA) (3 April 2019) 505
Ngqukumba v Minister of Safety and Security and Others (CCT 87/13) [2014] ZACC 14; 2014 (7) BCLR 788
(CC); 2014 (5) SA 112 (CC); 2014 (2) SACR 325 (CC) 82
Nhlabathi and Others v Fick 2003 (7) BCLR 806 (LCC) 765
Nkabinde and Another v Judicial Service Commission and Others (20857/2014) [2016] ZASCA 12; [2016] 2
All SA 415 (SCA); 2016 (4) SA 1 (SCA) (10 March 2016) 507
Nokotyana and Others v Ekurhuleni Metropolitan Municipality and Others (CCT 31/09) [2009] ZACC 33; 2010
(4) BCLR 312 (CC) (19 November 2009) 528, 789
O
Occupiers of 51 Olivia Road, Berea Township and 197 Main Street Johannesburg v City of Johannesburg and
Others (24/07) [2008] ZACC 1; 2008 (3) SA 208 (CC); 2008 (5) BCLR 475 (CC) (19 February 2008)
501, 502, 509, 564, 809, 817, 818
Offit Enterprises (Pty) Ltd and Another v Coega Development Corporation (Pty) Ltd and Others 2011 (1) SA
293 (CC) 754, 755
Organisasie vir Godsdienste-Onderrig en Demokrasie v Laerskool Randhart and Others (29847/2014) [2017]
ZAGPJHC 160; [2017] 3 All SA 943 (GJ); 2017 (6) SA 129 (GJ) (27 June 2017) 635
Oriani-Ambrosini, MP v Sisulu, MP Speaker of the National Assembly (CCT 16/12) [2012] ZACC 27; 2012 (6)
SA 588 (CC); 2013 (1) BCLR 14 (CC) (9 October 2012) 113, 163, 164, 165, 166
P
Paulsen and Another v Slip Knot Investments 777 (Pty) Limited (CCT 61/14) [2015] ZACC 5; 2015 (3) SA
479 (CC); 2015 (5) BCLR 509 (CC) (24 March 2015) 235, 236, 425
Penrice v Dickinson 1945 AD 6 266
Phaahla v Minister of Justice and Correctional Services and Another (Tlhakanye Intervening) (CCT44/18)
[2019] ZACC 18; 2019 (2) SACR 88 (CC); 2019 (7) BCLR 795 (CC) (3 May 2019) 485, 524, 530
Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of South Africa and Another: In re Ex parte President of the
Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT31/99) [2000] ZACC 1; 2000 (2) SA 674 (CC); 2000 (3) BCLR
241 (CC) (25 February 2000) 50, 51, 80, 82, 206, 207, 233
Pheko and Others v Ekurhuleni Metropolitan Municipality and Others (Pheko II) (CCT19/11) [2016] ZACC 20;
2016 (10) BCLR 1308 (CC) (26 July 2016) 508
Pheko and Others v Ekurhuleni Metropolitan Municipality (CCT 19/11) [2011] ZACC 34; 2012 (2) SA 598
(CC); 2012 (4) BCLR 388 (CC) (6 December 2011) 508
Phillips and Another v Director of Public Prosecutions and Others (CCT20/02) [2003] ZACC 1; 2003 (3) SA
345 (CC); 2003 (4) BCLR 357 (CC) (11 March 2003) 671
Pilane and Another v Pilane and Another 2013 (4) BCLR 431 (CC) (28 February 2013) 98, 375, 376
Police and Prisons Civil Rights Union v South African Correctional Services Workers’ Union and Others
(CCT152/17) [2018] ZACC 24; 2019 (1) SA 73 (CC); 2018 (11) BCLR 1411 (CC) (23 August 2018) 446
Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers (CCT 53/03) [2004] ZACC 7; 2005 (1) SA 217 (CC); 2004
(12) BCLR 1268 (CC) (1 October 2004) 427, 501, 745, 746, 817
Potgieter v Lid van die Uitvoerende Raad: Gesondheid, Provinsiale Regering Gauteng (CCT 26/01) [2001]
ZACC 4; 2001 (11) BCLR 1175 (8 October 2001) 465
Premier: Limpopo Province v Speaker of the Limpopo Provincial Legislature and Others (CCT 94/10) [2011]
ZACC 25; 2011 (6) SA 396 (CC); 2011 (11) BCLR 1181 (CC) (11 August 2011) 317, 318, 319, 325,
353
Premier, Province of Mpumalanga and Another v Executive Committee of the Association of Governing Bodies
of State Aided Schools: Eastern Transvaal (CCT10/98) [1998] ZACC 20; 1999 (2) SA 91; 1999 (2) BCLR
151 (2 December 1998) 201
Premier of KwaZulu-Natal and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT36/95)
[1995] ZACC 10; 1995 (12) BCLR 1561; 1996 (1) SA 769 (29 November 1995) 239
Premier of the Eastern Cape and Others v Ntamo and Others (169/14) [2015] ZAECBHC 14; 2015 (6) SA
400 (ECB); [2015] 4 All SA 107 (ECB) (18 August 2015) 380
Premier of the Western Cape and Others v Overberg District Municipality and Others (801/201) [2011]
ZASCA 23; 2011 (4) SA 441 (SCA); [2011] 3 All SA 385 (SCA) (18 March 2011) 346, 347
President of the Republic of South Africa and Another v Hugo (Hugo) (CCT11/96) [1997] ZACC 4; 1997 (6)
BCLR 708; 1997 (4) SA 1 (18 April 1997) 33, 190, 199, 200, 206, 208, 448, 521, 524–525
President of the Republic of South Africa and Another v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd (CCT20/04) [2005]
ZACC 5; 2005 (5) SA 3 (CC); 2005 (8) BCLR 786 (CC) (13 May 2005) 503, 813, 814
President of the Republic of South Africa and Others v M & G Media Ltd (CCT 03/11) [2011] ZACC 32; 2012
(2) BCLR 181 (CC); 2012 (2) SA 50 (CC) (29 November 2011) 201
President of the Republic of South Africa and Others v South African Rugby Football Union and Others (SARFU
III) (CCT16/98) [1999] ZACC 11; 2000 (1) SA 1 (CC); 1999 (10) BCLR 1059 (10 September 1999) 80,
182, 190, 191, 199, 202, 203, 207, 209, 210, 214, 239
President of the Republic of South Africa and Others v South African Rugby Football Union and Others –
Judgment on recusal application (SARFU II) (CCT16/98) [1999] ZACC 9; 1999 (4) SA 147; 1999 (7)
BCLR 725 (4 June 1999) 248
President of the Republic of South Africa v Office of the Public Protector and Others (91139/2016) [2017]
ZAGPPHC 747; 2018 (2) SA 100 (GP); [2018] 1 All SA 800 (GP); 2018 (5) BCLR 609 (GP) (13
December 2017) 192
President of the Republic of South Africa v Public Protector 2018 (2) SA 100 (GP); [2018] 1 All SA 800 (GP);
2018 (5) BCLR 609 (GP) 192
Primedia Broadcasting (a division of Primedia (Pty) Ltd) and Others v Speaker of the National Assembly and
Others (784/2015) [2016] ZASCA 142; [2016] 4 All SA 793 (SCA); 2017 (1) SA 572 (SCA) (29
September 2016) 115
Prince v Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development and Others; Rubin v National Director of Public
Prosecutions and Others; Acton and Others v National Director of Public Prosecutions and Others
(4153/2012) [2017] ZAWCHC 30; [2017] 2 All SA 864 (WCC); 2017 (4) SA 299 (WCC) (31 March
2017) 490
Prince v President of the Law Society of the Cape of Good Hope (CCT36/00) [2002] ZACC 1; 2002 (2) SA
794 (CC); 2002 (3) BCLR 231 (CC) (25 January 2002) 450, 451, 457, 459, 464, 467, 490, 620, 623,
624, 629, 631, 632
Prinsloo v Van der Linde and Another (CCT4/96) [1997] ZACC 5; 1997 (3) SA 1012 (CC); 1997 (6) BCLR
759 (CC) (18 April 1997) 33, 207, 521, 524, 525, 528, 529, 530, 531, 545
Print Media South Africa and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Another (CCT 113/11) [2012] ZACC 22;
2012 (6) SA 443 (CC); 2012 (12) BCLR 1346 (CC) (28 September 2012) 675, 688, 689
The Public Protector v Mail & Guardian Ltd and Others (2011 (4) SA 420 (SCA)) [2011] ZASCA 108; 422/10
(1 June 2011) 293
Public Protector v South African Reserve Bank (CCT107/18) [2019] ZACC 29; 2019 (9) BCLR 1113 (CC) (22
July 2019) 297, 298
Q
Qwelane v South African Human Rights Commission and Another (686/2018) [2019] ZASCA 167; [2020] 1
All SA 325 (SCA); 2020 (2) SA 124 (SCA); 2020 (3) BCLR 334 (SCA) (29 November 2019) 693, 694,
695, 697
R
Rail Commuters Action Group v Transnet Ltd t/a Metrorail (CCT 56/03) [2004] ZACC 20; 2005 (2) SA 359
(CC); 2005 (4) BCLR 301 (CC) (26 November 2004) 506, 578
Ramakatsa and Others v Magashule and Others 2013 (2) BCLR 202 (CC) 110, 128, 129, 609, 611, 712,
713, 714, 715
Reflect-All 1025 CC and Others v MEC for Public Transport, Roads and Works, Gauteng Provincial Government
and Another (CCT 110/08) [2009] ZACC 24; 2009 (6) SA 391 (CC); 2010 (1) BCLR 61 (CC) (27 August
2009) 742, 756, 757
The re-opened inquest into the death of Ahmed Essop Timol (IQ01/2017) [2017] ZAGPPHC 652 (12 October
2017) 571, 572, 573
Residents of Joe Slovo Community, Western Cape v Thubelisha Homes, Minister for Housing and Minister of
Local Government and Housing, Western Cape (Centre on Housing Rights and Evictions and Community
Law Centre, University of the Western Cape as amicus curiae) (CCT 22/08) [2009] ZACC 16, 2009 (9)
BCLR 847 (CC); 2010 (3) SA 454 (CC) (10 June 2009) 510, 817
Richter v The Minister for Home Affairs and Others (CCT03/09, CCT 09/09) [2009] ZACC 3; 2009 (3) SA 615
(CC); 2009 (5) BCLR 448 (CC) (12 March 2009) 90, 137, 713, 726, 732, 733
Roberts v United States Jaycees 468 U.S. 609 (1984) 601, 602
Royal Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals (RSPCA) v Attorney-General [2002] 1 WLR 448 603
R v Big M Drug Mart (1985) 13 CRR 64 103 (SCC) 440
R v Big M Drug Mart Ltd (1985) 18 DLR (4th) 33
R v Oakes 132 (1986) 19 CRR 308 (SCC) 434, 435, 449, 450, 451, 475
R v Paty (Case of the Men of Aylesbury) (1704) 2 Lord Raym 1105, 91 ER 817 118
S
Sachs v Minister of Justice; Diamond v Minister of Justice 1934 AD 11 13
Sailing Queen Investments v The Occupants La Colleen Court (4480 / 07) [2008] ZAGPHC 15; 2008 (6)
BCLR 666 (W) (25 January 2008) 501
Salem Party Club and Others v Salem Community and Others (CCT26/17) [2017] ZACC 46; 2018 (3) SA 1
(CC); 2018 (3) BCLR 342 (CC) (11 December 2017) 425
Sanderson v Attorney-General, Eastern Cape (CCT10/97) [1997] ZACC 18; 1998 (2) SA 38 (CC); 1997 (12)
BCLR 1675 (CC) (2 December 1997) 515
S and Others v Van Rooyen and Others (General Council of the Bar of South Africa Intervening) (CCT21/01)
[2002] ZACC 8; 2002 (5) SA 246; 2002 (8) BCLR 810 (11 June 2002) 83, 245, 248, 249, 250, 268,
269, 270, 288, 484
Sarrahwitz v Martiz N.O. and Another (CCT93/14) [2015] ZACC 14; 2015 (4) SA 491 (CC); 2015 (8) BCLR
925 (CC) (4 June 2015) 493, 531
Satchwell v President of Republic of South Africa and Another (CCT45/01) [2002] ZACC 18; 2002 (6) SA 1
(CC); 2002 (9) BCLR 986 (CC) (25 July 2002) 524
Sauve v Canada (Chief Electoral Officer) 2002 SCC 68 731
Schubart Park Residents’ Association and Others v City of Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality and Another
(CCT 23/12) [2012] ZACC 26; 2013 (1) SA 323 (CC); 2013 (1) BCLR 68 (CC) (9 October 2012) 509
Schubart Park Residents Association v City of Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality (CCT 23/12) [2012] ZACC
26; 2013 (1) SA 323 (CC); 2013 (1) BCLR 68 (CC) (9 October 2012) 817
Section 27 v Minister of Basic Education (24565/2012) [2012] ZAGPPHC 114; [2012] 3 All SA 579 (GNP);
2013 (2) BCLR 237 (GNP); 2013 (2) SA 40 (GNP) (17 May 2012) 828
Seedat’s Executors v The Master (Natal) 1917 AD 302 616
Shabalala and Others v Attorney-General of the Transvaal and Another (CCT23/94) [1995] ZACC 12; 1996 (1)
SA 725 (CC); 1995 (12) BCLR 1593 (CC) (29 November 1995) 666, 667
Shilubana and Others v Nwamitwa (Commission for Gender Equality, National Movement of Rural Women and
The Congress of Traditional Leaders of South Africa as Amici Curiae) (CCT 03/07) [2008] ZACC 9; 2008
(9) BCLR 914 (CC); 2009 (2) SA 66 (CC) (4 June 2008) 224, 372, 374, 375
Shoprite Checkers (Pty) Limited v Premier, Gauteng Province and Others (71551/2011) [2016] ZAGPPHC (11
October 2016) 341
Shoprite Checkers (Pty) Ltd v MEC for Economic Development, Eastern Cape and Others (CCT 216/14)
[2015] ZACC 23; 2015 (6) SA 125 (CC); 2015 (9) BCLR 1052 (CC) (30 June 2015) 742
Sibiya and Others v Director of Public Prosecutions: Johannesburg High Court and Others (Sibiya I)
(CCT45/04) [2005] ZACC 6; 2005 (5) SA 315 (CC); 2005 (8) BCLR 812 (CC) (25 May 2005) 510, 575
Sibiya and Others v Director of Public Prosecutions (Sibiya III) (CCT45/04B) [2006] ZACC 22; 2006 (2) BCLR
293 (CC) (30 November 2006) 510
Sigurjónsson v Iceland (1993) 16 EHRR 462 132, 600
Social Justice Coalition and Others v Minister of Police and Others (EC03/2016) [2018] ZAWCHC 181; 2019
(4) SA 82 (WCC) (14 December 2018) 556
Solidariteit Helpende Hand NPC & Another v Minister of Basic Education & Others (58189/2015) [2017]
ZAGPPHC 1220 (8 November 2017) 561
Solidarity and Others v Department of Correctional Services and Others (CCT 78/15) [2016] ZACC 18; 2016
(5) SA 594 (CC); 2016 (10) BCLR 1349 (CC) (15 July 2016) 535
Sonderup v Tondelli 2001 (1) SA 1171 (CC); 2001 (12) BCLR 152 (CC) 585
Soobramoney and Minister of Health and Others v Treatment Action Campaign and Others (No 2) (CCT8/02)
[2002] ZACC 15; 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC); 2002 (10) BCLR 1033 (CC) (5 July 2002) 789, 793, 794, 797,
798, 803, 804, 808, 811, 812
Soobramoney v Minister of Health (Kwazulu-Natal) (CCT32/97) [1997] ZACC 17; 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC);
1997 (12) BCLR 1696 (CC) (27 November 1997) 27, 35, 786, 797, 803–804, 815, 816
S.O.S. Support Public Broadcasting Coalition and Others v South African Broadcasting Corporation SOC
Limited and Others (81056/14); [2017] ZAGPJHC 289 (17 October 2017) 194
South African Association of Personal Injury Lawyers v Heath and Others (CCT27/00) [2000] ZACC 22; 2001
(1) SA 883 (CC); 2001 (1) BCLR 77 (28 November 2000) 60, 67, 101, 793
South African Broadcasting Corporation Limited v National Director of Public Prosecutions and Others
(CCT58/06) [2006] ZACC 15; 2007 (1) SA 523 (CC); 2007 (2) BCLR 167 (CC); (21 September 2006)
675, 677
South African Broadcasting Corporation Ltd v National Director of Public Prosecutions and Others (CCT58/06)
[2006] ZACC 15; 2007 (1) SA 523 (CC); 2007 (2) BCLR 167 (CC) (21 September 2006) 439, 474
South African Broadcasting Corporation Soc Ltd and Others v Democratic Alliance and Others (393/2015)
[2015] ZASCA 156; [2015] 4 All SA 719 (SCA); 2016 (2) SA 522 (SCA) (8 October 2015) 286, 293,
295
South African Broadcasting Corporation v Downer NO and Shaik (435/06) [2006] ZASCA 90; [2006] SCA 89
(RSA); [2007] 1 All SA 384 (SCA) (24 August 2006) 680, 681
South African Diamond Producers Organisation v Minister of Minerals and Energy NO and Others (CCT234/16)
[2017] ZACC 26; 2017 (6) SA 331 (CC); 2017 (10) BCLR 1303 (CC) (24 July 2017) 754, 755
South African Human Rights Commission v Qwelane and Another (EQ44/2009; EQ13/2012) [2017] ZAGPJHC
218; [2017] 4 All SA 234 (GJ); 2018 (2) SA 149 (GJ) (18 August 2017) 691, 692
South African Human Rights Commission v Velaphi Khumalo (EQ6-2016; EQ1-2018) [2018] ZAGPJHC 528;
2019 (1) SA 289 (GJ); [2019] 1 All SA 254 (GJ) (5 October 2018) 694
South African Municipal Worker’s Union v Minister of Co-Operative Governance and Traditional Affairs
(3558/2013) [2016] ZAGPPHC 733 (23 February 2016) 321
South African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence and Others (CCT65/06) [2007] ZACC 10; 2007
(5) SA 400 (CC); 2007 (8) BCLR 863 (CC); (30 May 2007) 528
South African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence (CCT27/98) [1999] ZACC 7; 1999 (4) SA 469;
1999 (6) BCLR 615 (26 May 1999) 403, 456, 458, 460, 466, 667, 701
South African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence (CCT65/06) [2007] ZACC 10; 2007 (5) SA 400
(CC); 2007 (8) BCLR 863 (CC) (30 May 2007) 440, 497
South African National Road Agency Ltd v The Toll Collect Consortium and Another (796/2012) [2013] ZASCA
102; [2013] 4 All SA 393 (SCA); 2013 (6) SA 356 (SCA) (12 September 2013) 361
South African Police Service v Police and Prisons Civil Rights Union and Another (CCT 89/10) [2011] ZACC
21; 2011 (6) SA 1 (CC); 2011 (9) BCLR 992 (CC) (9 June 2011) 421
South African Police Service v Solidarity obo Barnard (CCT 01/14) [2014] ZACC 23; 2014 (6) SA 123 (CC);
2014 (10) BCLR 1195 (CC); (2 September 2014) 521, 535, 536
South African Reserve Bank and Another v Shuttleworth and Another (CCT194/14, CCT199/14) [2015] ZACC
17; 2015 (5) SA 146 (CC); 2015 (8) BCLR 959 (CC) (18 June 2015) 63
South African Reserve Bank v Public Protector and Others (43769/17) [2017] ZAGPPHC 443; [2017] 4 All
SA 269 (GP); 2017 (6) SA 198 (GP) (15 August 2017) 299, 300
South African Social Security Agency and Another v Minister of Social Development and Others (CCT 48/17)
[2018] ZACC 26; 2018 (10) BCLR 1291 (CC) (30 August 2018) 512
South African Social Security Agency and Another v Minister of Social Development and Others (CCT48/17)
[2018] ZACC 26; 2018 (10) BCLR 1291 (CC) (30 August 2018) 497
South African Transport and Allied Workers Union and Another v Garvas and Others (SATAWU) (CCT 112/11)
[2012] ZACC 13; 2013 (1) SA 83 (CC); 2012 (8) BCLR 840 (CC) (13 June 2012) 86, 699, 700, 701,
707, 710, 711
South African Veterinary Association v Speaker of the National Assembly 2019 (2) BCLR 273 (CC) 124
Southern Africa Litigation Centre v Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development and Others
(27740/2015) [2015] ZAGPPHC 402; 2016 (1) SACR 161 (GP); 2015 (5) SA 1 (GP); [2015] 3 All SA
505 (GP); 2015 (9) BCLR 1108 (GP) (24 June 2015) 484
Speaker of the National Assembly v De Lille MP and Another (297/98) [1999] ZASCA 50; [1999] 4 All SA
241 (A) (26 August 1999) 118
State Information Technology Agency SOC Limited v Gijima Holdings (Pty) Limited (CCT254/16) [2017] ZACC
40; 2018 (2) SA 23 (CC); 2018 (2) BCLR 240 (CC) (14 November 2017) 405, 406
Strydom v Nederduitse Gereformeerde Gemeente Moreleta Park 2009 (4) SA 510 (T) 404, 626
Sunday Times v The United Kingdom (1979) 2 EHRR 245 448
S v Baloyi (Minister of Justice Intervening) (CCT29/99) [1999] ZACC 19; 2000 (2) SA 425 (CC); 2000 (1)
BCLR 86 (CC) (3 December 1999) 578, 585
S v Bequinot (CCT24/95) [1996] ZACC 21; 1996 (12) BCLR 1588; 1997 (2) SA 887 (18 November 1996)
241, 420
S v Bhulwane, S v Gwadiso (CCT12/95, CCT11/95) [1995] ZACC 11; 1996 (1) SA 388 (CC); 1995 (12) BCLR
1579 (CC) (29 November 1995) 451, 456, 459, 463, 478, 486, 495, 496, 498, 819
S v Boesak (CCT25/00) [2000] ZACC 25; 2001 (1) BCLR 36; 2001 (1) SA 912 (1 December 2000) 234,
235, 236, 237
S v Dodo (CCT 1/01) [2001] ZACC 16; 2001 (3) SA 382 (CC); 2001 (5) BCLR 423 (CC) (5 April 2001) 59,
104, 459, 579, 580
S v Jordan and Others (Sex Workers Education and Advocacy Task Force and Others as Amici Curiae
(CCT31/01) [2002] ZACC 22; 2002 (6) SA 642 (CC); 2002 (11) BCLR 1117 (CC) (9 October 2002)
439, 444, 456, 457, 464, 550, 555, 588, 589
S v Lawrence, S v Negal; S v Solberg (CCT38/96, CCT39/96, CCT40/96) [1997] ACC 11; 1997 (4) SA 1176
(CC); 1997 (10) BCLR 1348 (CC) (6 October 1997) 616, 618, 619, 620, 621, 622, 633, 634
S v Makwanyane and Another (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3; 1995 (6) BCLR 665 (CC); 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC);
1995 (2) SACR 1 (CC) (6 June 1995) 27, 29, 32, 33, 43, 44, 69, 71, 72, 100, 222, 247, 433, 434,
435, 436, 437, 438, 440, 452, 454, 457, 459, 462, 468, 475, 510, 514, 562, 581, 582
S v Mamabolo (eTV and Others Intervening (CCT 44/00); [2001] ZACC 17; 2001 (3) SA 409 (CC); 2001 (5)
BCLR 449 (CC) (11 April 2001) 50, 226, 401, 462, 666, 668, 672
S v Manamela (CCT25/99) [2000] ZACC 5; 2000 (3) SA 1 (CC); 2000 (5) BCLR 491 (CC) (14 April 2000)
456, 463, 487
S v Mbatha, S v Prinsloo (CCT19/95, CCT35/95) [1996] ZACC 1; 1996 (3) BCLR 293; 1996 (2) SA 464 (9
February 1996) 241, 498
S v Mhlungu and Others (CCT25/94) [1995] ZACC 4; 1995 (3) SA 867 (CC); 1995 (7) BCLR 793 (CC) (8
June 1995) para 59; Zantsi v Council of State, Ciskei and Others (CCT24/94) [1995] ZACC 9; 1995 (4)
SA 615 (CC); 1995 (10) BCLR 1424 (CC) (22 September 1995) 420
S v M [2007] ZACC 18; 2008 (3) SA 232 (CC); 2007 (12) BCLR 1312 (CC) (26 September 2007) 567
S v Niemand (CCT 28/00) [2001] ZACC 11; 2002 (1) SA 21 (CC); 2002 (3) BCLR 219 (8 October 2001)
579, 580, 581
S v Ntsele (CCT25/97) [1997] ZACC 14; 1997 (11) BCLR 1543 (CC) (14 October 1997) 495
S v Ntuli (CCT17/95) [1995] ZACC 14; 1996 (1) SA 1207 (CC); 1996 (1) BCLR 141 (CC) (8 December
1995) 530
S v Singo (CCT49/01) [2002] ZACC 10; 2002 (4) SA 858; 2002 (8) BCLR 793 (12 June 2002) 457
S v Steyn (CCT19/00) [2000] ZACC 24; 2001 (1) SA 1146 (CC); 2001 (1) BCLR 52 (CC) (29 November
2000) 469
S v Yengeni [2005] ZAGPHC 117; 2006 (1) SACR 405 (T) 275
S v Zuma and Others (CCT5/94) [1995] ZACC 1; 1995 (2) SA 642 (CC); 1995 (4) BCLR 401 (SA); 1995 (1)
SACR 568; [1996] 2 CHRLD 244 (5 April 1995) 4, 33, 241, 247, 440, 495
T
Tanganyika Law Society v United Republic of Tanzania; Mtikila v United Republic of Tanzania No. 009/2011
ACHPA 2011 133, 600
Tantoush v Refugee Appeal Board and Others (13182/06) [2007] ZAGPHC 191; 2008 (1) SA 232 (T) (11
September 2007) 403
Taylor v Kurstag NO and Others 2005 (1) SA 362 (W); 2005 (7) BCLR 705 (W); [2004] 4 All SA 317 (W)
624, 646, 647, 648
Teddy Bear Clinic for Abused Children v Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development (CCT 12/13)
[2013] ZACC 35; 2014 (2) SA 168 (CC); 2013 (12) BCLR 1429 (CC) (3 October 2013) 461, 470, 471,
514, 515, 562, 568, 569, 590
Thebus and Another v S (CCT36/02) [2003] ZACC 12; 2003 (6) SA 505 (CC); 2003 (10) BCLR 1100 (CC)
(28 August 2003) 234, 425, 426, 583
Thint Holdings (Southern Africa) (Pty) Ltd and Another v National Director of Public Prosecutions, Zuma v
National Director of Public Prosecutions (CCT 90/07, CCT 92/07) [2008] ZACC 14; 2009 (1) SA 141
(CC); 2009 (3) BCLR 309 (CC) (31 July 2008) 671
Tlouamma and Others v Mbete, Speaker of the National Assembly of the Parliament of the Republic of South
Africa and Another 2015 (2) SA 534 (WCC) 143, 144, 188
Tongoane and Others v National Minister for Agriculture and Land Affairs and Others (CCT100/09) [2010]
ZACC 10; 2010 (6) SA 214 (CC); 2010 (8) BCLR 741 (CC) (11 May 2010) 98, 170, 171, 172, 323,
368, 369, 393, 770
Torcaso v Watkins 367 U.S. 488 633
Transvaal Agricultural Union v Minister of Land Affairs and Another (CCT21/96) [1996] ZACC 22; 1996 (12)
BCLR 1573; 1997 (2) SA 621 (18 November 1996) 241
Tripartite Steering Committee and Another v Minister of Basic Education and Others (1830/2015) [2015]
ZAECGHC 67; 2015 (5) SA 107 (ECG); [2015] 3 All SA 718 (ECG) (25 June 2015) 829
Tronox KZN Sands (Pty) Ltd v KwaZulu-Natal Planning and Development Appeal Tribunal and Others
(CCT114/15) [2016] ZACC 2; 2016 (3) SA 160 (CC); 2016 (4) BCLR 469 (CC) (29 January 2016) 341
Trustees for the time being of the Children’s Resource Centre Trust and Others v Pioneer Foods (Pty) Ltd and
Others (050/2012) [2012] ZASCA 182; 2013 (2) SA 213 (SCA); 2013 (3) BCLR 279 (SCA); [2013] 1
All SA 648 (SCA) (29 November 2012) 409
Tsotetsi v Mutual and Federal Insurance Company Ltd (CCT16/95) [1996] ZACC 19; 1997 (1) SA 585 (CC);
1996 (11) BCLR 1439 (CC) (12 September 1996) 481, 485
Tulip Diamonds FZE v Minister for Justice and Constitutional Development and Others (CCT 93/12) [2013]
ZACC 19; 2013 (10) BCLR 1180 (CC); 2013 (2) SACR 443 (CC) (13 June 2013) 407
U
Union of Refugee Women and Others v Director, Private Security Industry Regulatory Authority and Others (CCT
39/06) [2006] ZACC 23; 2007 (4) SA 395 (CC); 2007 (4) BCLR 339 (CC) (12 December 2006) 547
United Democratic Movement and Others v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others 2017 (5) SA 300
(CC) (22 June 2017) 61, 66, 142
United Democratic Movement (UDM) v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (African Christian
Democratic Party and Others intervening; Institute for Democracy in South Africa and Others as Amici
Curiae (No 2) (CCT23/02) [2002] ZACC 21; 2003 (1) SA 495 (CC); 2002 (11) BCLR 1179 (4 October
2002) 90, 91, 239
United Democratic Movement v Speaker of the National Assembly and Others (CCT89/17) [2017] ZACC 21;
2017 (8) BCLR 1061 (CC); 2017 (5) SA 300 (CC) (22 June 2017) 109, 156, 186, 187, 188
University of Stellenbosch Legal Aid Clinic and Others v Minister of Justice and Correctional Services and
Others; Association of Debt Recovery Agents NPC v University of Stellenbosch Legal Aid Clinic and Others;
Mavava Trading 279 (Pty) Ltd and Others v University of Stellenbosch Legal Aid Clinic and Others
(CCT127/15) [2016] ZACC 32; 2016 (6) SA 596 (CC); (CC) 2016 (12) BCLR 1535 (CC) (13 September
2016) 494
University of the Free State v Afriforum and Another (1027/2016) [2017] ZASCA 32; [2017] 2 All SA 808
(SCA); 2017 (4) SA 283 (SCA) (28 March 2017) 836
Uthukela District Municipality and Others v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT7/02)
[2002] ZACC 11; 2003 (1) SA 678 (CC); 2002 (11) BCLR 1220 (CC) (12 June 2002) 309
Uys N.O. and Another v Msiza and Others (1222/2016) [2017] ZASCA 130; 2018 (3) SA 440 (SCA) (29
September 2017) 767
V
Van Breda v Media 24 Limited and Others; National Director of Public Prosecutions v Media 24 Limited and
Others 682, 683, 684
Van der Merwe v Road Accident Fund and Another (CCT48/05) [2006] ZACC 4; 2006 (4) SA 230 (CC); 2006
(6) BCLR 682 (CC) (30 March 2006) 532
Van der Spuy v General Council of the Bar of South Africa (CCT48/01) [2002] ZACC 17; 2002 (5) SA 392;
2002 (10) BCLR 1092 (18 July 2002) 241
Van Der Walt v Metcash Trading Limited (CCT37/01) [2002] ZACC 4; 2002 (4) SA 317 (CC); 2002 (5) BCLR
454 (CC) (11 April 2002) 530
Van Zyl v New National Party and Others [2003] 3 All SA 737 (C) 149
Viking Pony Africa Pumps (Pty) Ltd t/a Tricom Africa v Hidro-Tech Systems (Pty) Ltd and Another (CCT 34/10)
[2010] ZACC 21; 2011 (1) SA 327 (CC); 2011 (2) BCLR 207 (CC) (23 November 2010) 407
Volks NO v Robinson and Others (CCT12/04) [2005] ZACC 2; 2005 (5) BCLR 446 (CC) (21 February 2005)
524
Von Abo v President of the Republic of South Africa (CCT 67/08) [2009] ZACC 15; 2009 (10) BCLR 1052
(CC); 2009 (5) SA 345 (CC) (5 June 2009) 209
W
Walele v City of Cape Town and Others (CCT 64/07) [2008] ZACC 11; 2008 (6) SA 129 (CC); 2008 (11)
BCLR 1067 (CC) (13 June 2008) 528
Wallach v High Court of South Africa (Witwatersrand Local Division) and Others (CCT2/03) [2003] ZACC 6;
2003 (5) SA 273 (CC) (4 April 2003) 244
Western Cape Forum for Intellectual Disability v Government of the Republic of South Africa and Another 2011
(5) SA 87 (WCC); [2010] ZAWCHC 544; 18678/2007 (11 November 2010) 829
Western Cape Provincial Government and Others In Re: DVB Behuising (Pty) Limited v North West Provincial
Government and Another (CCT22/99) [2000] ZACC 2; 2000 (4) BCLR 347; 2001 (1) SA 500 (2 March
2000) 170, 270, 368
Wittmann v Deutscher Schulverein 1998 (4) SA 423 (T) 633, 635
Women’s Legal Trust v President of the Republic of South Africa and Others (CCT13/09) [2009] ZACC 20;
2009 (6) SA 94 (CC) (22 July 2009) 238, 240
Y
Young, James and Webster v The United Kingdom (1981) 4 EHRR 38 132, 600
Z
Zealand v Minister for Justice and Constitutional Development and Another (CCT54/07) [2008] ZACC 3; 2008
(4) SA 458 (CC); 2008 (6) BCLR 601 (CC) (11 March 2008) 575
Zuma v National Director of Public Prosecutions (8652/08) [2008] ZAKZHC 71; [2009] 1 All SA 54 (N);
2009 (1) BCLR 62 (N) (12 September 2008) 251, 275, 487
Attorney-General Act 92 of 1992 272
Section 3(1)(b) 272
Section 4 272
Bill of Rights (chapter 2 of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996) 15, 26, 29, 84, 119, 171,
191, 198, 199, 200, 201, 202, 203, 216, 218, 247, 392, 397, 398, 399, 400, 402, 403, 404, 405,
406, 408, 409, 410, 411, 412, 413, 414, 415, 417, 418, 420, 421, 422, 423, 424, 425, 426, 428,
430, 433, 434, 438, 440, 446, 456, 471, 472, 474, 477, 478, 479, 480, 483, 486, 503, 506, 514,
515, 516, 517, 518, 562, 564, 565, 569, 572, 573, 574, 577, 592, 601, 610, 628, 638, 639, 640,
644, 645, 647, 648, 649, 654, 713, 722, 726, 728, 735, 748, 769
Section 7(2) 798
Section 8 399
Section 8(1) 413
Section 9 518, 519, 521
Section 9(3) 627
Section 12(2) 583
Section 15 614
Section 15(1) 614, 642
Section 15(2) 614
Section 16 464, 474
Section 19 110
Section 26(2) 807
Section 27(2) 807
Section 31(1)(a) 642
Section 33 201, 507
Section 34 507
Section 35(3)(h) 236
Section 36 399
Section 37 399
Section 38 399
Section 39 399
Black Administration Act 38 of 1927 (BAA) 12, 13, 270, 271, 368, 648, 649
Section 1 12
Section 12 12, 270, 271
Section 12(4) 271
Section 20 270, 271
Section 20(6) 271
Commission for the Promotion and Protection of the Rights of Cultural, Religious and Linguistic
Communities Act 19 of 2002
Section 5 641
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 200 of 1993 (interim Constitution) 18, 19, 20, 21, 22,
24, 56, 59, 72, 79, 99, 100, 191, 199, 204, 214, 229, 232, 243, 304, 326, 370, 414, 432, 433, 434,
462, 474, 485, 573, 742
Chapter 5 20
Schedule 4 56, 305, 787
Section 10 434
Section 11 434
Section 11(1) 573, 574
Section 11(2) 581
Section 12 434
Section 14(1) 434
Section 15 434
Section 16 434
Section 17 434
Section 18 434
Section 21 434
Section 22 473
Section 23 434
Section 24 434
Section 25 434
Section 28 742
Section 30(1)(d) 434
Section 30(1)(e) 434
Section 30(2) 434
Section 33 434, 436, 451
Section 33(1) 432, 434, 435, 436, 449
Section 35(3) 417
Sections 68–73 20
Section 68(1) 20
Section 68(2) 20
Section 68(3) 20
Section 71(2) 20
Section 71(3) 22
Sections 72–73 24
Section 73(1) 20
Section 73(2) 20
Section 73(8) 24
Section 82(1) 192
Section 97(2)(a) 21
Section 98(6) 495
Section 99(3) 21
Section 99(4) 21
Section 99(5) 21
Section 109 268
Section 126(3) 326
Section 181(1) 370
Section 182 370
Section 183 370
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (final Constitution) 4, 5, 6, 8, 9, 10, 15, 20, 21, 22,
23, 24, 25, 26, 27, 32, 35, 39, 42, 44, 46, 49, 50, 51, 53, 54, 56, 59, 60, 62, 66, 69, 79, 83, 87, 95,
97, 99, 100, 101, 103, 123, 126, 155, 160, 178, 183, 191, 192, 196, 204, 229, 232, 234, 237, 243,
269, 272, 273, 346, 364, 394, 462, 583, 618, 774, 782
Chapter 1 58
Chapter 2 722
Chapter 3 54, 55, 97, 162, 289, 308, 309
Chapter 4 62, 97, 100
Chapter 5 65, 97, 100, 196
Chapter 6 66, 97, 313
Chapter 7 97, 337
Chapter 8 66, 97, 100
Chapter 9 283, 291, 309, 642
Chapter 11 406
Chapter 12 270, 364, 394
Chapter 13 348, 349, 362
Chapter 14 50
Preamble 84, 94, 393, 678
Schedule 2 183, 190
Schedule 4 97, 163, 172, 307, 308, 314, 315, 316, 317, 318, 320, 321, 322, 323, 324, 325, 327,
338, 339, 345, 361
Schedule 4A 306, 338, 342, 343
Schedule 4B 306, 336, 337, 338, 339, 340, 343, 344, 362
Schedule 5 97, 163, 172, 307, 308, 314, 316, 317, 318, 320, 321, 322, 323, 324, 327, 328, 337,
338, 339, 345, 361
Schedule 5A 307, 342
Schedule 5B 307, 336, 337, 339, 340, 343, 344, 362
Schedule 6
Section 16 270
Section 1 26, 28, 50, 52, 53, 54, 75, 84, 89, 100, 141, 171, 239, 574, 576, 712, 727, 784
Section 1(a) 30, 256, 514, 562, 652
Section 1(c) 49, 79, 101, 299, 400
Section 1(d) 84, 85, 89, 90, 109, 127, 391, 718
Section 2 26, 49, 50, 482
Section 6 285, 639, 651, 653, 661
Section 6(1) 652, 660
Section 6(2) 652, 660
Section 6(3) 660, 661
Section 6(4) 639, 651, 661
Section 7 28, 100, 417
Section 7(1) 30, 94
Section 7(2) 26, 29, 577, 584, 795
Section 7(3) 430, 471
Section 7(6) 638
Section 8 646
Section 8(1) 101, 410, 411, 412, 413, 414, 417, 418, 419, 420, 428, 798, 836
Section 8(2) 29, 410, 411–412, 413, 417, 418, 419, 420, 428, 479, 480, 647, 648, 798
Section 8(3) 412, 413, 479, 480, 647, 648
Section 8(3)(b) 413
Section 8(4) 404, 428
Section 9 404, 468, 498, 523, 524, 527, 528, 551, 554, 555, 560, 562, 591, 638, 640
Section 9(1) 402, 445, 523, 524, 527, 528, 529, 530, 531, 532, 545, 591, 653, 685
Section 9(2) 442, 527, 529, 530, 532, 533, 534, 536, 537, 539, 540, 541, 542, 543, 544, 545, 558,
560, 561, 591, 592, 653
Section 9(3) 442, 524, 525, 527, 528, 529, 530, 534, 536, 540, 541, 545, 546, 547, 548, 550, 551,
554, 555, 556, 557–558, 567, 569, 591, 592, 627, 638, 639, 640, 645, 649, 652, 653, 654,
816, 830
Section 9(4) 29, 234, 472, 554, 592, 654
Section 9(5) 546, 551
Section 10 445, 562, 564, 569, 592, 685, 791
Section 11 402, 404
Section 12 570, 572, 583
Section 12(1) 570, 572, 573, 577, 578, 583
Section 12(1)(a) 575, 577
Section 12(1)(b) 575, 576
Section 12(1)(c) 566, 567, 577, 578–579
Section 12(1)(e) 579, 580, 581
Section 12(2) 570, 582, 583, 584, 585, 586
Section 12(2)(a) 586
Section 12(2)(b) 586
Section 13 402
Section 14 404, 441, 445, 587, 592, 618
Section 15 617, 618, 623, 630, 632, 633, 685, 789
Section 15(1) 618, 627, 636, 639
Section 15(2) 619, 620, 633, 634, 635, 636
Section 15(3) 472, 636, 637, 638
Section 15(3)(a)(i) 636
Section 16 119, 404, 412, 442, 494, 667, 671, 672, 676, 690, 693, 694, 735
Section 16(1) 441, 608, 667, 672, 673, 675, 690, 691, 692, 694, 720
Section 16(2) 441, 640, 667, 672, 673, 686, 690, 691, 692, 694, 695
Section 16(2)(a) 690
Section 16(2)(b) 690
Section 16(2)(c) 691–692, 695
Section 17 86, 430, 697, 699, 700, 701, 705, 707, 708, 711
Section 18 404, 595, 734, 735
Section 19 89, 90, 91, 109, 129, 402, 404, 608, 609, 712, 713, 716, 720, 735
Section 19(1) 90, 607, 712, 714, 715, 722, 734
Section 19(1)(a) 403, 734
Section 19(1)(b) 734
Section 19(1)(c) 734
Section 19(2) 90, 135, 607, 712, 722
Section 19(3) 90, 135, 446, 447, 712, 727, 728, 729, 733
Section 19(3)(a) 731
Section 19(3)(b) 131, 132, 133, 134, 599, 733, 734, 735
Section 20 402
Section 22 402, 471, 656
Section 23 789
Section 23(2)(a) 403, 458
Section 23(5) 472
Section 24 343, 344, 473, 789, 790
Section 24(b) 442, 790
Section 25 324, 404, 437, 438, 740, 741, 742, 746, 758, 763, 764, 766, 767, 768, 769, 770, 771,
772, 775, 779, 790
Section 25(1) 442, 740, 742, 750, 751, 753, 754, 755, 756, 757, 758, 760, 761, 762, 763, 764
Section 25(1)–(3A) 771
Section 25(2) 471, 740, 751, 758, 763, 764, 765, 766, 769, 771
Section 25(2)(a) 750, 751, 766
Section 25(2)(b) 750, 751, 765
Section 25(3) 459, 740, 763, 764, 765, 766, 767, 770
Section 25(4) 740
Section 25(5) 740, 741, 777, 790
Section 25(6) 740, 741, 747, 748
Section 25(7) 740, 741, 777, 778
Section 25(8) 740, 741
Section 25(5)–(9) 774
Sections 26–28 29
Section 26 746, 787, 789, 790, 801, 802, 803, 805, 806, 807, 811, 821
Section 26(1) 789, 790, 801, 805, 806, 810, 812, 813, 825, 837, 838
Section 26(2) 501, 789, 790, 791, 801, 805, 806, 810, 812, 813
Section 26(3) 790
Section 27 404, 504, 787, 789, 790, 801, 802, 803, 805, 811, 812, 821
Section 27(1) 790, 806, 808, 810, 825, 837
Section 27(1)(a) 804, 808, 810, 815
Section 27(1)(b) 797, 809
Section 27(1)(c) 810, 816
Section 27(2) 789, 790, 791, 808, 809, 810, 813, 815
Section 27(3) 790, 804
Section 28 402
Section 28(1)(a) 403
Section 28(1)(c) 789, 790, 791, 805
Section 28(2) 445, 685
Section 29 787, 789, 798, 821, 822
Section 29(1) 418, 653, 789, 822, 825, 837
Section 29(1)(a) 791, 821, 825, 828, 837, 838
Section 29(1)(b) 790, 825, 837, 838, 839, 840, 841
Section 29(2) 639, 652, 654, 657, 658, 659, 660, 789, 822, 830, 831, 832, 833, 834, 835, 836
Section 29(3) 635, 636, 640, 822
Section 30 639, 640, 642, 643, 644, 645, 646, 652, 789
Section 31 622, 630, 639, 640, 642, 643, 644, 645, 646, 652, 654, 789
Section 31(1) 645, 653
Section 31(2) 645
Section 32 29, 201, 404, 608, 720, 791, 797
Section 33 29, 119, 201, 202, 203, 404, 405, 406, 436, 462, 757, 791
Section 33(1) 406, 459
Section 33(2) 406
Section 33(3) 406, 472
Section 34 29, 66, 119, 404, 511, 577
Section 35 402
Section 35(1)(a) 436
Section 35(2)(e) 789, 791
Section 35(3) 576
Section 35(3)(h) 236
Section 35(3)(o) 237, 469, 470
Section 36 136, 398, 399, 430, 432, 447, 471, 472, 558, 562, 612, 613, 630, 751, 791, 800, 801,
802, 803, 841
Section 36(1) 94, 430, 431, 432, 436, 437, 438, 442, 443, 445, 446, 448, 449, 450, 451, 456, 458,
459, 463, 468, 471, 472, 473, 474, 475, 555, 558, 586, 591, 648, 695, 728, 741, 800, 802
Section 36(1)(b) 450, 456
Section 36(1)(c) 463
Section 36(1)(d) 450
Section 36(1)(e) 450
Section 36(2) 473
Section 36(6) 741
Section 37 399
Section 38 29, 399, 407, 479, 480, 506, 819
Section 38(a)–(e) 406, 407
Section 38(e) 407
Section 39 399, 426
Section 39(1) 30, 94
Section 39(1)(b) 247
Section 39(1)(c) 247
Section 39(2) 29, 237, 242, 374, 410, 419, 420, 421, 423, 424, 425, 426, 428, 479, 480, 486, 752
Section 40(1) 54, 170, 302, 308
Section 40(2) 29, 308
Section 41 94, 308
Section 41(1) 29, 308, 347
Section 41(1)(e) 171, 308, 339
Section 41(1)(f) 308, 339
Section 41(1)(g) 308
Section 41(1)(h) 308
Section 41(1)(h)(i)–(vi) 54
Section 41(1)(h)(iv) 171
Section 41(3) 308
Section 42(1) 62, 107, 127
Section 42(3) 89, 107, 140, 154
Section 42(4) 107, 145, 329
Section 42(6) 108
Section 43(a) 62
Section 44 163, 339
Section 44(1) 339
Section 44(1)(a) 62
Section 44(1)(a)(i) 163
Section 44(1)(a)(ii) 163, 337
Section 44(1)(a)(iii) 163, 176, 341, 342
Section 44(1)(b)(i) 163
Section 44(1)(b)(ii) 163
Section 44(1)(b)(iii) 163
Section 44(2) 163, 172, 307, 320, 322, 323, 327, 328, 361
Section 44(2)(b) 62
Section 44(4) 62, 337
Section 45 113
Section 46 62
Section 46(1) 127
Section 46(1)(b) 727
Section 46(1)(c) 135, 727
Section 46(1)(d) 89, 110
Section 46(2) 127
Section 47 62, 138
Section 47(1)(b) 138
Section 47(1)(c) 138
Section 47(1)(d) 138
Section 47(1)(e) 138
Section 47(3)(b) 139
Section 47(3)(c) 139, 188, 716
Section 49(1) 138, 139
Section 49(2) 139
Section 50(1) 139
Section 50(2) 139
Section 51(1) 140
Section 51(1)(a)–(c) 286
Section 51(2) 140
Section 51(3) 108, 140
Section 52 140
Section 53(1)(a) 141
Section 53(1)(b) 141
Section 53(1)(c) 141
Section 53(2)(a) 141
Section 53(2)(b) 141
Section 54 141
Section 55 65, 141
Section 55(1) 154
Section 55(2) 65, 108, 142, 163
Section 55(2)(a) 154, 160
Section 55(2)(b) 154, 161
Section 56 114, 157
Section 56(d) 705
Section 57 62, 89, 113
Section 57(1) 113, 153, 188
Section 57(1)(a) 142, 159
Section 57(1)(b) 89, 142
Section 57(2) 113, 153
Section 57(2)(a) 144
Section 57(2)(b) 89, 144, 716
Section 57(2)(c) 109
Section 57(2)(d) 109
Section 58 62
Section 58(1) 119, 120, 121
Section 58(1)(a) 118, 120, 122, 489
Section 58(1)(b) 118
Section 58(2) 119, 120
Section 59 94, 116, 141
Section 59(1) 124
Section 59(1)(a) 123, 155
Section 59(1)(b) 115, 155
Section 59(2) 116, 155
Section 60 62, 147
Section 60(2)(a) 147
Section 60(2)(a)(i) 147
Section 60(2)(a)(ii) 147
Section 60(2)(b) 147
Section 60(3) 147
Section 61 62
Section 61(4) 148
Section 62(2) 148
Section 62(4) 148
Section 62(4)(c) 149
Section 63(3) 108
Section 64(1) 153
Section 64(2) 153
Section 64(3) 153
Section 65(1) 153
Section 65(2) 150, 153, 172
Section 66(1) 151
Section 68 65, 154
Section 69 114, 151, 157
Section 70 62
Section 70(1) 113, 153
Section 70(2) 113
Section 70(2)(a) 153
Section 70(2)(b) 153
Section 70(2)(c) 154
Section 71 62
Section 71(1)(a) 118, 122
Section 71(1)(b) 118
Section 71(2) 119
Section 72 94, 116
Section 72(1) 124
Section 72(1)(a) 123, 124, 155
Section 72(1)(b) 115, 155
Section 72(2) 116, 155
Section 73(1) 171
Section 73(2) 63, 163
Section 74 169, 171, 174, 180, 391
Section 74(1) 50, 171
Section 74(1)(a) 53, 141
Section 74(1)(b) 53
Section 74(2) 171
Section 74(2)(a) 141
Section 74(3) 50
Section 74(3)(b) 171
Section 74(8) 171
Section 75 169, 171, 172, 173, 174, 180, 322
Section 75(1) 150, 171
Section 75(1)(a)–(d) 172
Section 75(2) 150, 153, 171
Section 76 169, 172, 173, 174, 180, 322
Section 76(1) 172
Section 76(1)(d) 173
Section 76(1)(e) 173
Section 76(2) 172
Section 76(2)(d) 173
Section 76(2)(e) 173
Section 76(3) 172
Section 76(4) 172
Section 76(5) 108, 172
Section 77 169, 174, 180, 391
Section 77(1) 174
Section 77(3) 174
Section 78(1) 173
Section 78(2) 173
Section 79 168, 174, 175, 238
Section 79(1) 63, 168, 174
Section 79(4) 174
Section 79(4)(b) 168
Section 79(5) 175
Section 80 238
Section 80(1) 175
Section 80(2) 175
Section 80(2)(a) 238
Section 80(2)(b) 239
Section 80(3) 175
Section 83(a) 65, 190
Section 83(b) 65
Section 84 200, 315
Section 84(1) 65
Section 84(2) 190, 192, 202, 203
Section 84(2)(g) 86
Section 84(2)(k) 190
Section 85 819
Section 85(1) 65, 193
Section 85(1)(b) 63
Section 85(1)(d) 63
Section 85(2) 190, 193, 213, 214
Section 85(2)(a)–(e) 65
Section 86 108, 110
Section 86(1) 140, 183
Section 86(2) 140
Section 86(3) 183
Section 87 183
Section 88(2) 184
Section 89 108, 110, 139, 156, 185, 186, 217, 227, 228
Section 89(1) 113, 141, 157, 160, 184, 185, 186
Section 89(2) 186
Section 90(1) 190, 193
Section 90(1)(a) 277
Section 90(2) 190
Section 90(3) 190
Section 90(4) 190
Section 91(1) 65, 210
Section 91(2) 65, 193, 200, 210, 211, 213, 300
Section 91(3) 63, 65, 108
Section 91(3)(a) 210
Section 91(3)(b) 210
Section 91(3)(c) 210
Section 91(4) 193
Section 91(5) 213, 217
Section 92 154
Section 92(1) 213, 216
Section 92(2) 65, 154, 155, 211, 213, 214
Section 92(3)(b) 66, 215
Section 96 215
Section 96(2) 215
Section 96(3) 214
Section 98 216
Section 99 216, 341, 342
Section 100 312, 328, 329
Section 100(1) 328
Section 100(1)(a) 328
Section 100(1)(b) 162
Section 100(2)(a) 328
Section 100(2)(b) 328
Section 101(1) 199
Section 101(2) 190, 199
Section 102 66, 108, 110, 139, 187, 189, 211, 217
Section 102(1) 212
Section 102(2) 61, 158, 159, 187, 212
Section 103(1) 313
Sections 104–124 313
Section 104 145
Section 104(1) 339
Section 104(1)(b) 308
Section 104(1)(b)(i) 314
Section 104(1)(b)(ii) 314
Section 104(1)(b)(iii) 315, 317
Section 104(1)(b)(iv) 315, 317
Section 104(1)(c) 315, 341, 342
Section 104(2) 315
Section 104(4) 315
Section 105(1)(d) 89
Section 105(2) 315
Section 106 315
Section 109 315
Section 113 315
Section 115 705
Section 118 94, 116
Section 118(1)(a) 124
Section 121 238, 317
Section 122 238
Section 122(2)(a) 238
Section 122(2)(b) 239
Sections 125–141 313
Section 125(2) 316
Section 125(2)(c) 313
Section 125(3) 316
Section 125(4) 162, 316
Section 126 316, 341, 342
Section 126(b)(1) 458
Section 127(2) 315
Section 127(2)(f) 86
Section 128 316
Section 130(3) 316
Section 139 312, 346, 347
Section 139(1) 345, 347
Section 139(1)(b) 162
Section 139(1)(b)(i) 346
Section 139(1)(b)(ii) 346
Section 139(1)(b)(iii) 346
Section 139(1)(c) 346
Section 139(3) 347
Section 139(4) 346, 347
Section 139(5) 347, 348
Section 141 316
Section 142 314
Section 144 240
Section 146 163, 306, 310, 320, 325, 326, 327, 361
Section 146(1) 325
Section 146(2) 307, 325, 326
Section 146(2)(a) 326
Section 146(2)(b) 326
Section 146(2)(c) 326
Section 146(3) 325, 327
Section 146(5) 320
Section 147(2) 307, 328
Section 149 307, 326
Section 151(4) 307, 342, 344, 362
Section 152 330
Section 152(1) 329, 362
Section 152(1)(d) 343
Section 153 329, 330
Section 154(1) 345
Section 154(2) 392
Section 155 333, 335, 362
Section 155(3)(b) 334
Section 155(4) 335
Section 155(5) 319
Section 155(6) 345
Section 155(6)(a) 339
Section 155(7) 339, 340, 345
Section 156 336
Section 156(1) 339
Section 156(1)(a) 336, 337
Section 156(1)(b) 336
Section 156(2) 336
Section 156(3) 307, 344, 362
Section 156(4) 341, 342
Section 156(5) 336, 337, 342, 344
Section 157(2)(a) 89, 735
Section 160(6) 117
Section 161 117
Section 163 172
Section 165 100, 269, 511
Section 165(1) 66, 100
Section 165(2) 67, 100, 255, 272
Section 165(3) 67
Section 165(4) 67
Section 165(5) 49
Section 165(6) 229, 267
Section 166 229
Section 166(a)–(e) 66
Section 166(b) 230
Section 166(d) 269
Section 167 400
Section 167(1) 229
Section 167(3) 232, 233, 237
Section 167(3)(a) 66, 235, 242
Section 167(3)(b) 233, 242
Section 167(3)(b)(ii) 235, 236
Section 167(3)(c) 235, 242
Section 167(4)(a) 234, 238
Section 167(4)(b) 238
Section 167(4)(c) 238
Section 167(4)(d) 239
Section 167(4)(e) 239, 240
Section 167(5) 67, 101, 237, 244, 761
Section 167(6) 240
Section 167(7) 233
Section 168 400
Section 168(1) 230
Section 168(3) 232
Section 168(3)(a) 243
Section 169 230, 400
Section 169(1)(a) 244
Section 169(2) 230
Section 170 66, 231, 244
Section 172 67, 400, 819
Section 172(1) 49, 101, 234, 479, 480, 482
Section 172(1)(a) 226, 479, 480, 482, 492, 819
Section 172(1)(b) 479, 480, 486, 686, 819
Section 172(1)(b)(i) 480, 495
Section 172(1)(b)(ii) 480, 497, 499
Section 172(2) 120, 480, 489
Section 172(2)(a) 240
Section 173 424, 474, 475, 511, 682
Section 174 67
Section 174(1) 246, 251, 254
Section 174(2) 246, 251, 254, 256, 257, 258
Section 174(3) 198, 253
Section 174(4) 254
Section 174(4)(a) 254
Section 174(4)(b) 254
Section 174(4)(c) 254
Section 174(5) 254
Section 174(6) 198, 254
Section 174(7) 269
Section 174(8) 260
Section 176 260, 261
Section 176(1) 68, 179, 205, 261, 262, 263
Section 176(2) 68, 263
Section 176(3) 68, 266
Section 177 68, 260, 264
Section 177(2) 68
Section 177(3) 264
Section 178 99, 251
Section 178(1) 252
Section 178(1)(a)–( j) 251
Section 179 97, 272, 273, 274, 275, 276
Section 179(1) 276
Section 179(1)(a) 194, 198
Section 179(4) 276
Section 179(5)(a) 273
Section 179(5)(c) 273
Section 179(5)(d) 274
Section 181 642, 723
Sections 181–194 97
Section 181(1)(a) 99
Section 181(1)(e) 99
Section 181(1)(f) 99, 135
Section 181(2) 284, 285, 723
Section 181(3) 285, 290, 723
Section 181(4) 285
Section 181(5) 284, 291, 723
Section 182 172
Section 182(1) 292
Section 182(2) 135, 292
Section 185 291, 641
Section 190 723
Section 190(1) 723
Section 190(1)(a)–(c) 135
Section 190(1)(b) 725
Section 192 285, 690
Section 193(1) 286
Section 193(2) 286
Section 193(3) 286
Section 193(4) 108, 198, 286
Section 193(5)(b)(i) 286
Section 193(5)(b)(ii) 286
Section 193(6) 286
Section 194(1) 287
Section 194(2)(a) 288
Section 194(2)(b) 288
Section 194(3)(a) 288
Section 194(3)(b) 288
Section 195 312, 317, 319, 400
Section 195(3) 172
Section 195(4) 172
Section 196 172
Section 196(2) 285
Section 196(3) 285
Section 197 172
Section 197(1) 182
Section 197(3) 714
Section 199 422
Section 200(1) 456
Section 202(1) 194
Section 203 162
Section 207(1) 194
Section 209 203
Section 209(2) 194, 201, 203
Section 211 27, 364, 365, 370, 372, 373, 376, 394
Section 211(1) 270, 364, 391
Section 212 27, 364, 365, 376, 377, 394
Section 212(1) 270, 377, 378
Section 212(1)(a) 388
Section 212(2) 377, 388
Section 212(2)(a) 98
Section 213 354
Section 214 174, 355
Section 214(1) 351, 352
Section 214(2) 352
Section 215 317, 319, 353, 354
Section 215(1) 353, 362
Section 215(2) 353
Section 215(3) 353
Section 216 317, 319, 354
Section 216(3)(b) 162
Section 217 356, 357, 358, 359, 362
Section 217(1) 360, 481
Section 217(2) 356, 360
Section 220(2) 285
Section 223 355
Section 224(1) 355
Section 224(2) 355
Section 226 355
Section 227 353
Section 228 386
Section 228(1) 349
Section 228(2) 350
Section 229 386
Section 229(1) 350
Section 229(2) 350
Section 231 484
Section 231(1) 194
Section 231(2) 484
Section 234 29
Section 236 718
Section 237 50, 168, 174
Section 239 135, 161, 285, 288, 309, 414, 416
Section 239(2) 288
Section 239(b)(i) 416
Section 239(b)(ii) 416
Cross-Boundary Municipalities Laws Repeal and Related Matters Act 23 of 2005 334
Electoral Act 73 of 1998 135, 136, 137, 717, 725, 729, 735
Schedule 1A 131, 134, 733, 735
Schedule 3 127, 315
Section 1 727
Section 6 727, 728
Section 6(1) 728
Section 8 727
Section 8(2)(f) 731
Section 16(3) 725
Section 24B(1) 136
Section 24B(2) 136, 731
Sections 26–31 717
Section 26(b) 717
Section 27 717
Section 33 137
Section 33(1)(b) 733
Section 33(1)(e) 732, 733
Section 39 728
Section 57A 131
Section 96 724
Section 99 717
Extension of Security of Tenure Act 62 of 1997 (ESTA) 740, 747, 748, 770
Section 5 747
Section 6 747
Section 13 748
Implementation of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court Act 27 of 2002 483
Local Government: Municipal Structures Act 117 of 1998 334, 335, 337
Section 1 333
Section 2 333
Section 3 333
Section 7 334
Section 8 335
Section 9 335
Section 10 335
Section 28 117
Section 28(1) 117
Section 28(2) 117
Medicines and Related Substances Control Act 101 of 1965 491, 492
Section 22A(9) 624
Section 22A(10) 623, 624
Mental Health Act 18 of 1973 728
Section 68(4) 465
Money Bills Amendment Procedure and Related Matters Act 9 of 2009 174
National House of Traditional Leaders Act 22 of 2009 (NHTLA) 98, 365, 366, 377, 388, 389, 390, 392,
394
Section 1 388
Section 2(1) 388
Section 2(2) 390
Section 2(3) 390
Section 3(1) 388
Section 3(2) 389
Section 3(3) 389
Section 3(4) 389
Section 4(7) 388
Section 5(a) 389
Section 5(b) 389
Section 5(c) 390
Section 5(d) 390
Section 5(e) 390
Section 5(f) 390
Section 5(g) 390
Section 8(4) 391
Section 8(6) 391
Section 8(7) 391
Section 9(1) 390
Section 9(2) 390
Section 9(3) 390
Section 9(4) 390
Section 9(9) 391
Section 9(13) 391
Section 11(1)(a) 392
Section 11(2)(a) 391
Section 11(2)(b) 392
Section 11(2)(c) 392
Section 11(2)(e) 392
Section 21 390
National Prosecuting Authority Act 32 of 1998 (NPA Act) 275, 276, 281, 487
Section 7 278
Section 9 198
Section 12(4) 198
Section 12(6)(a) 278
Section 12(6)(c) 278
Section 12(6)(e) 278
Section 12(8) 279
Section 12(8)(a)(ii) 279
Section 20 273
Section 22(1) 273
Section 22(1)(c) 274
Section 22(2)(a) 273
Section 22(2)(b) 273
Section 32(1)(a) 275
Section 32(1)(b) 275
Section 33(1) 275
Section 33(2) 275
Section 41(1) 275
North West Traditional Leadership and Governance Act 2 of 2005 375, 387
Orange Free State Constitution of 1854 6
Powers, Privileges and Immunities of Parliament and Provincial Legislatures Act 4 of 2004 (PPI Act) 118
Section 7 121, 489
Section 11 120, 121, 489, 490
Section 27 121, 489
Prevention of Illegal Eviction From and Unlawful Occupation of Land Act 19 of 1998 (PIE Act) 324, 746,
820
Section 6 745
Section 6(1) 745
Section 6(3)(a) 745
Section 6(3)(b) 745
Section 6(3)(c) 745
Section 26(3) 746
Promotion of Access to Information Act 2 of 2000 (PAIA) 201, 607, 608, 609, 719, 720, 791
Promotion of Administrative Justice Act 3 of 2000 (PAJA) 298, 357, 360, 405, 416, 472, 655, 757
Section 4 472
Section 5 358
Section 7(1) 405
Promotion of Equality and Prevention of Unfair Discrimination Act 4 of 2000 (PEPUDA) 234, 468, 523,
528, 554, 555, 592, 605, 626, 654, 692, 736
Section 1 555, 556, 654
Section 6 605, 654
Section 10 692, 693
Section 10(1) 694, 695, 696, 697
Section 10(1)(a) 693
Section 10(1)(b) 693
Section 10(1)(c) 693
Section 12 693
Section 13 556
Section 14 472, 530, 557, 558, 559, 560
Section 14(1) 529, 561
Section 14(2) 555, 557, 605
Section 14(2)(a) 557
Section 14(2)(b) 557
Section 14(3) 555, 557, 558, 605
Regulation of Gatherings Act 205 of 1993 (Gatherings Act) 702, 705, 706, 709, 710, 736
Section 1(v) 702
Section 1(vi) 702
Section 3(5)(c) 706
Section 4(1) 706
Section 4(4)(b) 706
Section 4(4)(c) 706
Section 5 706
Section 9(2)(e) 706
Section 11(1) 709, 710
Section 11(2) 709, 710, 711
Section 12(1)(a) 707, 708
Republic of South Africa Constitution Act 110 of 1983 14, 20, 183, 191
Section 14 14
Section 15 14
Section 16 14
South African Schools Act 84 of 1996 (SASA) 351, 656, 657, 658, 832
Section 5A(3) 832
Section 7 635
Section 10 432, 433, 630
Section 22 656
Traditional Leadership and Governance Framework Act 41 of 2003 (TLGFA) 365, 366, 375, 377, 378,
379, 380, 381, 382, 383, 384, 385, 387, 394
Section 1 366, 378, 379, 388
Section 2 382, 385
Section 2(1) 366, 381
Section 2(2) 382
Section 2(3) 382
Section 2A 382
Section 2B 382
Section 3(1) 382
Section 3(2)(a) 383
Section 3(2)(b) 383
Section 3(2)(c) 383
Section 3(2)(d) 383
Section 3A 383
Section 3B 383
Section 4(1) 384
Section 4(2) 386
Section 4(3)(b) 386
Section 4A 385
Section 4C 385
Section 8 378
Section 9 379
Section 10A 379
Section 11 379
Section 18 391
Section 18(1)(a) 391
Section 18(1)(b) 391
Section 19 381
Section 20 385
Section 28(1) 271
Section 28(3) 382
Section 28(4) 383
Union of South Africa Act, 1909 (the South Africa Act or the 1910 Union Constitution) 5, 9, 10, 11, 45,
46, 48
Section 35 10
Section 137 11, 830
Section 147 10
Section 152 11
Use of Official Languages Act 12 of 2012 661
FOREIGN LEGISLATION
CANADA
Charter of Rights and Freedoms
Article 1 434
Section 2(a) 632
Constitution Act (1982) Part 1 434
Indian Act 1970 646
FRANCE
Constitution of the Fifth Republic 217
Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen 401
GERMANY
German Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany (Constitution) 147, 304
Article 8 702
Article 8(1) 701
Article 21(2) 606
Article 50 147
Article 79(3) 53
KENYA
The Constitution of Kenya, 2010
Item 23 in Schedule 6 246
SPAIN
Constitution of Spain, 1931 401
UNION OF SOVIET SOCIALIST REPUBLICS
Constitution of the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics, 1936 401
TURKEY
Anti-Terror Act 3713 of 1991 654
UNION OF SOVIET SOCIALIST REPUBLICS
Constitution of the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics, 1936 401
UNITED KINGDOM
Colonial Laws Validity Act, 1865 10
Human Rights Act of 1998 603
Statute of Westminster, 1931 10
British or Westminster Constitution 3, 46
UNITED STATES OF AMERICA
Bill of rights 401
Constitution 618
First Amendment 633
analogous ground: A ground of discrimination, such as HIV status, not explicitly mentioned in the Constitution,
but sufficiently similar to the grounds mentioned in the Constitution because it also deals with different
treatment of people who have suffered past discrimination, prejudice or marginalisation because of their
membership of the group.
apartheid: A system of absolute racial segregation and political and economic discrimination applied against
non-European groups in the Republic of South Africa by the white minority. Grand apartheid envisaged that
white South Africans would govern the vast majority of the South African territory while black South Africans
would be provided with independent or semi-independent homelands in which they would be ‘allowed’ to
exercise political rights.
apex court: The highest court of law in a country which usually has the final say on any matter of law. A court
can be an apex court for certain subject matters like constitutional issues only (as is the case in South
Africa) or it can be the apex court for all legal issues (as is the case in the US).
authoritarian system: A system of government that favours a concentration of power in a leader, a political
party or an elite who are not democratically elected by the majority of the people, are not accountable to
them and do not rule in their best interest.
autonomy: The ability to make decisions freely about your life as an individual without being forced to do so by
your family, your community or other cultural or religious institutions.
bicameralism: The legislative system which has two distinct houses of the legislature whose members are
elected or appointed in two distinct ways to serve different interests. The houses are jointly tasked with
fulfilling the various tasks of the legislature, including the passing of legislation which usually requires the
support of a majority of members from both houses of the legislature to become law.
bifurcated state: A state in which different systems of government apply to different people within the same
territory, based on the race, ethnicity, language or other characteristics of the governed.
Bill: A draft law that the legislature is discussing and considering. Once the President duly passes and signs
the Bill, it becomes an Act of the legislature.
blue rights: The collective name for a group of human rights often distinguished (somewhat arbitrarily) from
other types of rights on the basis that they are first generation rights consisting largely of civil and political
rights.
branch of government: The name given in constitutional theory to the three pillars of government usually
distinguished from each other when discussing the separation of powers doctrine. These three pillars are
the legislature, the executive and the judiciary.
burden of proof or justification: The question of which party has to provide evidence to prove or disprove
relevant facts and what standard will be used to decide whether the party has managed to prove or
disprove the relevant set of facts.
case law: The binding legal principles developed by courts when handing down judgments on the interpretation
and application of statutes, common law or customary law.
certification process: The process which required the Constitutional Court to test the final Constitution to
determine whether it complied with the 34 Constitutional Principles contained in the interim Constitution.
checks and balances: The concept is closely associated with the doctrine of separation of powers which
envisages that each of the three branches of government (the legislature, the executive and the judiciary)
will act as a check (or brake) on the exercise of power by the other two branches to prevent the abuse of
power and to ensure accountable government.
citizenship: The status acquired by individual persons formally associated with (or linked to) a state and
consequently who have certain rights and duties in relation to the state. These rights and duties include
the right to live and work in the country and to obtain a passport from the state. A person with citizenship
in a state is called a citizen of the state.
civil and political rights: The collective name for a group of human rights often distinguished (somewhat
arbitrarily) from other types of rights such as social and economic rights on the basis that they are first
generation rights as they emerged early in the development of human rights. This set of rights includes
rights such as the right to vote, freedom of speech and assembly, freedom of religion and the right to
equality.
coalition government: A government formed jointly by the elected representatives of two or more political
parties, usually when none of the parties had obtained a majority of more than 50% of seats in the
legislature. The government then governs according to principles set out in a coalition agreement
concluded by the parties which enter the coalition.
collective accountability: The principle that each member of the executive is accountable for the decisions
and actions of all other members of the executive and should, hence, not publicly criticise the statements
or actions of fellow members of the executive. This principle is based on the assumption that the members
of the executive branch of government act as a team and approve all important decisions of the executive.
colonialism: The establishment, maintenance, acquisition and expansion of colonies in one territory by people
from another territory. It is a process whereby an economically and militarily powerful government claims
the right to govern the people of another territory, imposing its language, values and government structures
on the colony and establishing an unequal, exploitative relationship with that colony.
common law: The set of legal rules and principles not contained in legislation duly passed by the legislature,
but rather inherited from the colonial powers and which are continuously being developed and enforced by
the judiciary.
conscience: The awareness of a moral or ethical aspect to one’s conduct together with the urge to prefer right
over wrong, regardless of whether that awareness stems from religious beliefs or from ethical commitments
not related to religious beliefs at all.
constitutional damages: Where a court finds that a person or institution has infringed the constitutional rights
of an individual and (in the absence of other appropriate remedies) orders the person or institution to pay
a sum of money to the aggrieved party to remedy the constitutional infringement.
constitutional democracy: Also known as a liberal democracy, this is a common form of representative
democracy in which citizens take part in regular, free and fair elections in a competitive political process,
but a constitution sets out the limits of the powers to be exercised by those representatives elected to
represent the people.
contextual analysis: The opposite of considering a legal question in the abstract as if the surrounding
circumstances prevalent in a society are irrelevant. Contextual analysis takes into account the differences
in the economic position as well as the social status of individuals and the way in which the society is
structured to privilege some and disadvantage others.
counter-majoritarianism: The conceptual difficulty associated with the enforcement of the provisions of a
supreme constitution by the judiciary. This difficulty arises because unelected judges without a mandate
from voters are empowered to thwart the will of the democratically elected legislature and executive by
declaring invalid their actions, thus acting in a counter-majoritarian manner.
customary law: Traditional common rule or practice that has become an intrinsic part of the accepted and
expected conduct in a community, is enforced by that community and can also be changed over time by
that community. In South Africa, customary law usually refers to the laws developed and applied by
indigenous peoples and is contrasted to the common law imposed by colonial rulers.
damages: The sum of money a court orders a person or institution to pay to somebody to compensate for the
financial or emotional harm or ‘damage’ suffered by the aggrieved party because of actions taken by the
person or institution ordered to pay the damages.
delegation of legislative authority: Where a legislature (parliament or provincial legislature) entrusts the
power it originally had to pass primary or subordinate legislation to another body which is then empowered
legally to pass the said legislation despite not originally having been entitled to do so.
developing the common law: A process through which judges, hearing specific cases, continuously revisit the
general principles of the common law and adapt these rules to ensure that they are in line with the general
norms embodied in the Bill of Rights.
dialogic model of the separation of powers: The idea that the tension between the legislature, executive and
judiciary, arising from the separation of powers between them, can be resolved by envisaging the
relationship between these three branches as one in which a structured conversation shapes the
relationship between the branches.
direct discrimination: Where a rule or policy explicitly distinguishes between groups of people to the detriment
of one group, based on either a ground listed in section 9(3) of the Constitution or on a similar analogous
ground.
disputes of interest: Such disputes arise in the labour law context but, unlike other labour disputes, they are
not based on any existing right. Instead, employees or their unions approach the employer to establish a
new right. If the employer does not want to give employees what they want and the matter remains
unresolved, then the employees may exercise their right to strike after following the appropriate procedures.
diversity: Diversity refers to the fact that not all individuals have the same cultures, languages or religious
beliefs, creating a diverse population whose differences must be accommodated without harming others.
divided model of federalism: A model of federalism in which the Constitution strictly divides the subject
matters in respect of which policies and laws may be made by each sphere of government. Each level or
sphere of government, therefore, has its own exclusive powers and there are very few, if any, concurrent or
shared powers.
doctrine of objective invalidity: Also referred to as the doctrine of objective unconstitutionality, this is the
principle that any legislative provision or action which is in conflict with the Constitution is assumed to be
invalid from the moment that the conflict first arose. When a court confirms the unconstitutionality and
hence invalidity of the legislative provision or action, it will automatically be invalid retrogressively from the
moment the conflict arose unless the court orders otherwise.
electoral system: The mechanism through which the number of votes cast by voters for each political party is
translated into the number of seats for each of the parties in the legislature. Different electoral systems
produce different levels of representation for different parties in the legislature.
equitable: A requirement that different institutions, beliefs or practices must be treated fairly, but excluding the
requirement that they must be treated in an identical fashion.
final Constitution: The Constitution finally adopted by the democratically elected Constitutional Assembly in
1996 in terms of which South Africa has been governed since 1997.
first generation rights: See the definition for ‘civil and political rights’.
formal equality: The idea that individuals are born free and equal and that the law should treat people the
same, regardless of their personal circumstances, their history, their social and economic status, and
whether they have been discriminated against in the past or still face discrimination in the present. The
concept explicitly denies the need to take into account the social and economic context or the differences
in power, status and opportunities between individuals or groups of individuals when judging whether the
equality injunction has been breached or not.
good faith: The presumption that a person (in constitutional law often a public official exercising public power)
will act honestly and fairly and not out of spite or in an arbitrary, capricious, dishonest or corrupt manner.
green rights: Also sometimes (somewhat loosely) referred to as third generation rights. These are a set of
rights that emerged recently (towards the end of the twentieth century) and are aimed at protecting society
more broadly. The rights include the right to self-determination, the right to development and the right to a
healthy environment.
guardian of the Constitution: Normally refers to the judiciary whose task it is to interpret and enforce the
Constitution and hence to guard against breaches of the Constitution.
heterogeneous: Made up of different parts. In the context of constitutional law, it refers to the fact that there
are many different people from different races, cultures, languages and social and economic backgrounds
living in South Africa.
horizontal application: Traditionally, a constitution only binds the state and prohibits it from infringing on the
rights of private individuals and institutions (and is said to apply vertically only). The South African
Constitution applies horizontally as, in certain cases, it also binds private individuals and institutions and
prohibits them from infringing on the rights of others.
horizontal dispute: A legal dispute between private parties (in other words, a dispute in which state
institutions are not involved) regarding the scope and content of the duties imposed on such a private
party by any of the rights in the Constitution.
human rights: A set of norms and standards contained in a bill of rights or international human rights treaty
aimed at protecting the human dignity and other fundamental interests of individuals, which binds the
state (and sometimes other parties) and is usually enforced by independent courts or tribunals.
in limine: Literally, ‘at the threshold’, this Latin term refers to a motion made before a trial begins which asks
the court, for example, to rule on a preliminary legal point or on the exclusion of certain evidence.
incidental power: Usually refers to powers that strictly speaking fall outside the matters over which a particular
branch in a specific sphere of government has legislative or executive authority, but which are so closely
connected to the effective performance of its functions that they are considered to be a part of the matters
over which the body has authority.
indigenous populations: Ethnic groups who lived in a territory before the arrival of a colonising power. They are
groups of people whose members share a cultural identity that has been shaped by their geographical
region and by their experiences of oppression.
indirect discrimination: Different treatment either on grounds listed in section 9(3) or on analogous grounds
where the ground for the different treatment is based on a seemingly ‘neutral’ factor (such as a person’s
height or where a person lives), but where the differentiation disproportionately affects a group listed in
section 9(3) or a group analogous to section 9(3).
individual accountability: The principle that individual members of the executive (members of the cabinet at
national level) are responsible for their own portfolios and are accountable for what occurs in their
departments.
integrated model of federalism: Where some subject matters are allocated exclusively to one level or sphere
of government, but most powers are concurrent or shared and where the subject matters in respect of
which policies and laws may be made are thus not strictly divided between the different levels or spheres
of government.
interim Constitution: The South African Constitution agreed to by the undemocratic MPNF in 1993, according
to which South Africa was governed between 1994 and 1996 while a final Constitution was being
negotiated. It contained the 34 Constitutional Principles with which the final Constitution had to comply
and prescribed the process for the adoption of the final Constitution.
judicial authority: The term for the power given to judges that allows them to hear a case and to decide in
favour of one party.
judicial independence: The notion that judges should be free from interference by the other branches of
government or private parties and which is achieved by providing institutional safeguards.
judicial review: The process through which judges review the constitutionality of actions taken by the
legislature, executive or private parties and declare such actions invalid if they are in conflict with the
Constitution.
judiciary: One of the three branches of government, staffed by judicial officers and led by the Chief Justice.
jurisdiction: The legal authority of members of the judiciary to hear and determine judicial disputes in a
specific geographical area or on a specific subject matter.
juristic person: An artificial entity through which the law allows a group of natural persons to act as if they
were a single composite individual for certain purposes. This legal fiction does not mean these entities are
human beings, but rather that the law recognises them and allows them to act as natural persons for some
purposes − most commonly lawsuits, property ownership and contracts.
justiciability: Concerns the limits on legal issues over which a court can exercise its judicial authority and thus
refers to factual or legal questions capable of being decided by a court.
justiciable: In constitutional law, a matter is justiciable if courts can apply the Constitution to the factual or
legal dispute and can declare invalid action in conflict with the Constitution.
law-making power: The power of an institution such as a legislature, derived from a constitution, to pass valid
law.
limitation of rights: When law or conduct infringes on one or more of the rights protected in the Bill of Rights,
this is called a limitation of the right. A limitation can be justified in terms of section 36 (and is then
constitutionally valid) or it can be unjustified (and is then unconstitutional).
meaningful engagement: A duty imposed by courts on parties to a dispute that requires them to talk to each
other with a view to solving the dispute.
mere differentiation: The distinctions made by the law between groups of people where these distinctions are
not based on harmful stereotypes or other problematic personal attributes or characteristics (like a
person’s race, sex or sexual orientation), but rather on the basis of historically harmless criteria.
nation state: A political unit consisting of an autonomous state inhabited predominantly by a people sharing a
common history.
National Assembly: The lower House of the National Parliament of South Africa comprising 400 members
elected in a general election through the system of proportional representation to represent the interests of
the whole electorate.
National Council of Provinces: The second House of the National Parliament of South Africa comprising 10
delegates from each province, primarily representing the interests of provinces in the national law-making
process.
natural person: A human being as opposed to a legal entity and who is treated as the bearer of rights and
duties.
negative duties: The legal duties to refrain from acting in a manner in conflict with provisions in the
Constitution, often contrasted with positive duties which require those bound by the Constitution to act in a
certain manner to give effect to the provisions of the Constitution.
norms: Values or principles that direct proper, or in constitutional law, legally permissible behaviour in a
society.
notional severance: A technique of interpretation that focuses on the words of a legal provision and, rather
than eliminating specific words in the provision, interprets the provision, usually by narrowing its scope and
by indicating circumstances to which the provision is not applicable to ensure it will be interpreted in
conformity with the Constitution.
operational provisions of the Bill of Rights: The set of provisions in the Constitution that indicates whom the
rights in the Bill of Rights binds, who is protected by the provisions of the Bill of Rights and how these
provisions must be applied.
organ of state: Any department of state or administration in the national, provincial or local sphere of
government; or any other functionary or institution that exercises a power or performs a function in terms of
the Constitution or a provincial constitution; or that exercises a public power or performs a public function
in terms of any legislation. However, it does not include a court or a judicial officer.
pardons: Where a person has been convicted of a crime and the President, exercising a Head of State power,
decides to excuse the crime, thus wiping the slate clean and allowing the convicted criminal to live as if
the conviction had never occurred.
Parliament: In South African constitutional law it is the collective name for the National Assembly and the
National Council of Provinces, the two Houses of the national legislature empowered jointly to pass
legislation and to fulfil the other duties of the national legislature.
parliamentary privilege: The rule that Members of Parliament have legal immunity that protects them against
civil or criminal liability for actions done or statements made in the course of their legislative duties.
parliamentary supremacy: This is also called parliamentary sovereignty or legislative supremacy and is a
concept in the constitutional law of some parliamentary democracies. With parliamentary sovereignty, a
legislative body (usually the democratically elected parliament) has absolute sovereignty, meaning it is
supreme to all other government institutions, including the executive and the judiciary. This means that the
legislative body may change or repeal any previous legislation and is not constrained by the constitution in
what legislation it can pass.
participatory democracy: The idea that the public has a right and duty to participate in public affairs,
including discussions about the passing of legislation and the formulation of government policies.
patterns of disadvantage: The deeply entrenched, historically created and continuing social and economic
exclusion experienced by black people, women, gay men and lesbians and other marginalised groups in
society.
plenary law-making power: The complete power, bestowed by the constitution on the relevant body, to pass
laws on a particular topic with no limitations.
pluralism: A condition or a state in which numerous distinct ethnic, religious or cultural groups are present and
in which the beliefs and practices of individuals who belong to such groups are accommodated.
polygynous marriage: A marriage conducted in terms of customary law rules in which a husband is permitted
to be married to more than one wife at the same time.
portfolio committees: The various committees of the National Assembly tasked with processing legislation and
overseeing the implementation of legislation relating to the portfolio of each member of the Cabinet.
positive duties: The legal duties which require those bound by the Constitution to act in a certain manner to
give effect to the provisions of the Constitution, often contrasted with negative duties to refrain from acting
in a manner in conflict with provisions in the Constitution.
primogeniture rule: The rule of inheritance that the first-born male child has the right to inherit to the
exclusion of other children.
principle of legality: The legal ideal that requires all exercises of public power to be rational, non-arbitrary and
authorised by law that is clear, ascertainable and non-retrospective.
principle of rationality: The legal ideal that the exercise of public power must be for a legitimate purpose and
that there should be a rational link between the purpose for which the power is exercised and the action
taken.
principle of subsidiarity: The rule that where legislation gives effect to a constitutional right, a litigant must,
where possible, rely on the provisions of the legislation and cannot rely directly on the right concerned.
prior restraints: Judicial suppression of material before it can be published or broadcast on the grounds that it
is libellous or harmful.
proportional representation: The principle of electoral law that there should be a direct correlation between
the percentage of votes cast for a specific political party and the percentage of seats allocated to that
party in the legislature.
proportionality: A legal principle used to decide how the right balance should be struck between conflicting
interests to accommodate the various interests optimally, usually in a fair and just manner. In limitation
analysis this means, broadly speaking, that the interests of the state and of society must be weighed
against the interests of those whose rights are being infringed and must be done in a manner that is
acceptable in an open and democratic society.
prosecuting authority: The body that makes decisions about who to prosecute and who not to prosecute for
the commission of an alleged offence and is responsible for such prosecutions.
public administration: The collective name for the group of individuals employed by the state to implement
government policies and programmes, including employees of all organs of state.
public service: The collective name for those persons who work for the national and provincial government
departments.
pure proportional representation electoral system: The electoral system in which voters vote for political
parties and not individual candidates and in which each party is allocated seats in the legislature in direct
proportion to the percentage of votes cast for that party in the election.
quasi-federal system: A system in which the power to pass and implement legislation is distributed between
the national government and provincial governments but in which the power of provincial governments is
limited.
rational connection: Identifying the purpose to be achieved by a legal provision on the one hand and the
nature of the legal provision seeking to achieve that purpose on the other, and asking whether there is a
rational link between the two.
rationality: A legal test that is not aimed at enquiring into the wisdom or reasonableness of the impugned
legal provision, but rather asks, first, whether the legal provision aims to achieve a legitimate government
purpose and, second, whether there is a rational relationship between the legal provision and the purpose
sought to be achieved by it.
reading down: The principle of legal interpretation which requires that ordinary legislation is interpreted in line
with the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights if the words are reasonably capable of such an
interpretation or are not unduly strained.
reading in conformity: The principle of legal interpretation requiring that the courts must prefer interpretations
that fall within the boundaries of the Bill of Rights over those that do not, provided that such an
interpretation can be reasonably ascribed to the provision.
reasonable accommodation: The need of both private and public institutions to take reasonable steps – within
what is financially affordable and practically possible – to accommodate the practices, beliefs and ways of
living of diverse groups of people to ensure their full and equal participation in society.
red rights: Also referred to as second generation rights and usually thought to include social and economic
rights.
regular intervention: The power of the executive at national or provincial level to intervene in the affairs of the
province or municipality respectively when a province or municipality cannot or does not fulfil an executive
obligation in terms of the Constitution or legislation.
reparation: Making amends for past injustice by providing those disadvantaged by past unjust acts or laws
with opportunities, benefits and rewards to compensate them for the loss incurred by them because of the
unjust actions of others in the past.
representative democracy: The notion that the voters are represented by elected representatives serving in
legislatures and the executive.
retrospective invalidation of legislation: Where, because of the doctrine of objective invalidity, legislation is
declared invalid and renders the legislation invalid from the moment the clash with the Constitution arose.
rule of law: An evolving constitutional principle enforceable by courts and closely related to the principle of
legality and the rechtsstaat which, at a minimum, requires the legislature and the executive in every sphere
only to exercise power and perform functions if authorised to do so by law and then only in a rational
manner.
rule of stare decisis: The basic rule applicable in common law jurisdictions that a court is bound by the legal
precedent established by court judgments of a court at the same or higher level of authority.
second generation rights: Refer to rights which were developed after the Second World War, usually social and
economic rights.
separation of powers: The principle that there must be some separation of function and, in some cases,
personnel of the three branches of government.
severance: The remedy which allows a court to delete those words or phrases from the provision which renders
the provision unconstitutional to fix the unconstitutionality of a legal provision.
social and economic rights (also socio-economic rights): Also generally referred to as second generation
rights, the set of rights that ensures that the basic social and economic needs of individuals are met.
spirit, purport and objects of Bill of Rights: The human rights-based norms and values that are derived from
the specific substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights.
standing: The right of either an individual or an organisation to bring a case to a specific court and to have
that case heard in that court.
state: An organised political community occupying a certain territory and whose members live under the
authority of a constitution. The state is therefore a far broader concept than the government.
statutes: Legislation passed by the duly authorised legislature on a particular topic.
strict party discipline: The principle that elected representatives of a political party are required to obey and
follow the decisions made by that political party on a specific policy or legal issue.
structural interdict: A remedy handed down by a court ordering the government to take certain steps and to
report back to the court at regular intervals about the steps taken to comply with the Constitution.
substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights: The provisions relating to the protection of specific rights.
suspension of an order of invalidity: A remedy in which the court, after declaring a legal provision
constitutionally invalid, suspends that order, allowing the provision to remain in operation, usually for a set
period of time to allow the legislature to fix the invalidity of the provision.
teleological interpretation: An interpretative method that asks what the purpose of a specific provision is –
why was it included in the Constitution and formulated in the way that it was – to assist with determining
the exact meaning of that provision.
tenure: The right to keep a job for life or for a fixed period of time.
third generation rights: See the definition of ‘green rights’.
ubi ius ubi remedium: The notion that when a person’s right is violated, the victim will have an equitable
remedy under law.
values: Important and lasting beliefs or ideals contained in a constitution and/or shared by the members of a
culture about what is good or bad and desirable or undesirable.
vertical dispute: A legal dispute between the state and an individual.
vote of no confidence: When the majority of members of a legislature, having decided to stop supporting the
government of the day, decide to unseat that government by supporting a vote to that effect.
Westminster system: Also called a parliamentary system, this system of government is based on the British
model in which the members of the executive branch (usually the Prime Minister and his or her Cabinet
Ministers) are appointed from among the Members of Parliament and obtain their democratic legitimacy
from the Parliament. They are members of, as well as accountable to, that body, meaning that the
executive and legislative branches are intertwined.
A
affirmative action 532–544, 592 see also redress measures
affirmative state duties 28, 29
African Christian Democratic Party (ACDP)
1994 election 23
African Court of Human and Peoples’ Rights 133
African government 304, 305 see also chief
African National Congress (ANC) see also history, South Africa
Constitutional Committee 21
dominant party democracy 92
electoral dominance 37, 38
liberation movement 14, 17
1994 election 23
African Union 17 see also Organisation of African Unity (OAU)
Afrikaans
medium education, history 829–831
medium public schools 655
all-at once approach 452, 453 see also limitation
amici curiae in socio-economic rights litigation 791, 792 see also socio-economic rights
analogous ground 528 see also equality
annual budget 353–355 see also fiscal powers
apartheid, legacy and racial segregation 5, 11–14, 42, 48, 49, 220–225, 737, 783
Appellate Division of the Supreme Court 223 see also Supreme Court of Appeal
assembly see freedom of assembly
associated rights 598
association see freedom of association
Auditor General
appointing 198
Chapter 9 institution 284, 300
independent 284–291, 300
report to National Assembly 300
role 99, 283, 284, 300
authoritarian race-based autocracy 5
autonomy 595 see also freedom of association
Azanian People’s Organisation (AZAPO)
as liberation movement 15
B
balancing and proportionality 449–456 see also limitations
balancing and proportionality proper 461–468 see also limitations
Bantu Education 823, 824 see also education
Bantu peoples 365
Bantustans 775, 776 see also land reform
basic education 827–829 see also education; socio-economic rights
bicameralism 107, 127, 145, 179 see also Parliament
bifurcated state 9, 11, 12, 38, 39, 48
Bill of Rights, South Africa 397–428
abused by private persons 411
adjudication 399
application stage 399, 402–426
bound to respect 409–411
child 403
citizen 403
claim, entitled to 402–409
classical liberal 28
common law 426–428
differing interpretations 424, 425
dignity, value in 514, 515
direct application 410, 428
direct horizontal application 417–419
direct vertical application 411–414
enforcing rights of 18, 406–409
‘everyone’ 403
Freedom Charter 16
guardians 26
horizontal application 29, 428
horizontal disputes 410, 417, 418
human rights culture 15
indirect application 419–421, 428
indirect application to common law and customary law 423–428
indirect application to legislation 421–423
juristic persons 398, 403–406
limitations 430, 431, 433–438, 445–458, 471–476
litigation 399, 400, 401, 428
natural persons 402
operational provisions 399, 400
‘organs of state’ 414–417
principle of avoidance or subsidiarity 311, 420, 528
procedural (application) stage 399
promotion of 233
reading down or reading in 410
reading in conformity 421, 422
remedy stage 399
rights classification 400, 401
special limitations 471–473
standing provisions 406–409
structure 399
substantive stage 399
vertical application 428
vertical dispute 410
worker 403
Black Consciousness Movement
as liberation movement 15
Black Wednesday 666 see also freedom of expression
bodily and psychological integrity 582–586
Botha, PW 14
bottom-up approach 338, 339 see also municipalities
branches of government 104
Britain
constitution 46
British colonies 46
British Commonwealth 46
British Parliament 5
budgetary process 353–355
C
Cabinet of the Republic of South Africa
accountability 217, 218
appointment 210–212
impeachment of President and Cabinet 217
leaders of majority party 217
motion of no confidence 218
national executive 217
powers 213–216, 218
removal 210–212
resignation 217
vote of no confidence 217
Canadian Supreme Court 33, 475
cannabis 590, 591
Cape Colony 8
Cape Parliament 8
censorship 666, 667 see also freedom of expression
central bank see Reserve Bank
Chapter 9 institutions see also separation of powers
independence of 284–291
institutions under Chapter 9 of the Constitution 283, 284
Public Protector, special case 291–300
role of 283, 284
Chaskalson, P. 64, 468
checks and balances, principle of separation of powers doctrine 57, 97, 182 see also separation of powers
doctrine
chief see traditional leader(s)
Chief Justice 267, 268
appointment 281
head of judiciary 229, 267, 268
Johannesburg seat 230
child 403 see also Bill of Rights
Children’s Court 231
church’s core activities 628 see also freedom of religion
citizen 403 see also Bill of Rights
CODESA see Congress for a Democratic South Africa
colonialism 5, 42, 737 see also history, South Africa
colonial rulers 38 see also history, South Africa
Commission for Gender Equality
appointing 198
Chapter 9 institution 284, 300
independent 284–291, 300
role 283, 284, 300
Commission for the Promotion and Protection of the Rights of Cultural, Religious and Linguistic Communities
Chapter 9 institution 283
independent 284–291
role 284
Commission of Enquiry Regarding the Transformation and Reform of the Public Service 195 see also
Presidential Review Commission
common law, development 426 see also Bill of Rights; customary law
Congress for a Democratic South Africa (CODESA) 18, 19
Constitution
amending founding provisions of a 53
apex 26
certification of text of final Constitution 21, 24, 25, 39
exclusive jurisdiction on 280
factual disputes 236, 237
final say on provisions 25
founding document 3, 4
interpretation of the Constitution 4, 5, 32, 33, 34
judges of 21
jurisdiction 233–242
living document 4
open-ended language 4
points of law 236, 237
transforming the legal system 245
Constitutional Court
court of appeal considering constitutional and other matters of legal doctrine 280
extension of jurisdiction in 2013 233–242
final court 229
hierarchal structure 229
specialist court until August 2013 233
transforming legal system 245
constitutional damages 503–506
constitutional democracy 5, 85, 94–96 see also democracy
Constitutional Guidelines 16, 17
constitutional history, South Africa 5–38, 46
constitutionalism see also constitutionalism, South Africa
concept of 42, 43, 95
descriptively understood 42–45
disregard for substantive justice 45
norms and values of prescriptive 45
prescriptively understood 45, 46
constitutionalism, South Africa
rule of law, principle of respect for 75
South Africa, overview 46–49
unique nature of South African 43, 44
constitutional law, South Africa based on separation of powers 106
constitutional matters 233 see also non-constitutional matters
Constitutional Principles (34)
as described by the Constitutional Court 21, 22
certification by the Constitutional Court
co-operative government and the co-ordination of intergovernmental relations 306–312
principles of co-operative government 306–308
structure of government 305, 306
subsidiarity 311
teleologically application 25
constitutional remedies 477–512
breaches 480
declaration of invalidity 482–494
defined 477, 478
direct horizontal application of the Bill of Rights 479, 480
direct vertical application of the Bill of Rights 479, 480
function 478
indirect vertical and horizontal application of the Bill of Rights 479, 480
interdicts 480, 508–512
kinds of 479
limiting retrospective effect of an order of invalidity 495–497
meaningful engagement 480, 501, 502
nature of 478, 479
suspension of an order of invalidity 497–500
constitutional supremacy 49–52, 55
critique of 55
constitutional system 45, 52–55
democratic self-government 45
human rights 45
judiciary 45
rule of law 45
separation of powers 45
contextual analysis 521
co-operative federalism 54, 55 see also constitutionalism
co-operative government 306–312
co-ordination of intergovernmental relations 308–312
principles 306–308
counter-majoritarian dilemma, South Africa 69–75 see also judiciary; separation of powers
courts, South Africa see also Constitutional Court; High Court; judges; Magistrates’ Courts; Supreme Court of
Appeal
constitutional jurisdiction 232
declaration of invalidity any law or conduct 482–485
hierarchal structure 229
interpret and enforce the Constitution 227, 228
notional severance 493, 494
order, state failing court 511
reading down 485
reading in 487–492
roll in constitutional democracy 225–228
severance 492, 493
cultural communities 639–650 see also religious communities
clash between rights 645
cultural liberties, international protection 640–642
internal modifiers 644–650
pluralism 639
scope and content in the Constitution 642–644
customary law
applied to black people colonial times 38
Bill of Rights 233, 234, 426–428
content of 373, 374
developing common or 233, 234, 426–428
judicial system democratic era 224, 225, 372–377
judicial system pre-democratic era 223, 367–370
normative arrangements 366
pre-Union 7
reading down 234
women’s rights 372
customary principles 638
D
dagga see cannabis
damages 503 see also constitutional damages
death penalty 581, 582
Declaration of Intent 18 see also Congress for a Democratic South Africa
declaration of invalidity see also constitutional remedies
law or conduct inconsistent with the Constitution 482–502
notional severance 493, 494
reading down 485–487
reading in 487–492
retrospective invalidation of legislation 495–497
severance 492, 493
declaration of rights 506–508
decolonisation 22, 23, 330–333 see also local government; street renaming
De Klerk, FW 14
delegation of legislative authority 204
De Lille, Patricia 118–120
democracy
conceptions of 85–95
constitutional 5, 85, 94–96
description of 85
direct 85–88, 96
elected representatives of a 96
forms of 84–96
Greek words ‘demos’ and ‘kratos’ 84
limitations of the system of 92
meaning of word 84, 85
one-party 35, 225
overlapping forms of 96
participatory 85, 92–94, 96, 502, 503
post-apartheid 85–95
representative 85, 88–92, 96
struggle for liberation, South Africa 84
democratic constitutional South African dispensation within system of separation of powers 99–104 see also
separation of powers
Democratic Party (DA)
1994 election 23
democratic self-government 45
‘demos’ (citizenry) 84, 85 see also democracy
demonstration see freedom of demonstration
Deputy Chief Justice
appointment 281
role 229
Deputy National Directors of Public Prosecutions 273
Deputy President of the Republic of South Africa see also President
appointment 210–212
as acting President 190
national executive 217
powers 213–217
removal 210–212
role 190, 217
dialogic model of separation of powers 102–104
Dicey, AV 75, 76 see also rule of law
Diceyean conception of the rule of law 75, 76
differentiation 523, 524
dignity
agency respected 566, 567
Bill of Rights 514–517
enforceable right 562, 563
family life 565, 566
right 564, 565
unfair discrimination 567–569
value of 514–517, 564, 565
direct democracy 85–88, 96 see also democracy
direct horizontal application of the Bill of Rights 479, 480
direct vertical application of the Bill of Rights 479, 480
Directors of Public Prosecutions (DPP) 273
discrimination see also unfair discrimination
before 1994 38
differentiation 546–550
direct 549
hidden forms of 550, 551
indirect 549
mere differentiation 523, 524
non-statutory imposed 554, 555
on the basis of language 654
reasonable accommodation 558, 560
under PEPUDA 555
unfair 545, 551–554, 592
districts
forty-four 303
diversity, South Africa 598
divided model of federalism 303 see also integrated model of federalism
doctrine of objective invalidity 482, 495
doctrine of separation of powers see separation of powers
dominant party democracy 92 see also ANC; representative democracy
Domestic Violence Courts 231
E
Economic Freedom Fighters (EFF) 115, 116, 120
education see also socio-economic rights
Bantu Education 823, 824
basic education 822–829
immediately realisable socio-economic right 821–842
Language in Education Policy 832, 833
language of one’s choice 654–660, 829–836
tertiary education, free 837–841
elections, free, fair and regular 127, 722–726 see also political parties
Electoral Act, remedying the defects of 134 see also independent candidates
Electoral Commission
appointing 198
Chapter 9 institution 284, 300
Defect in Electoral Act 134
independent 135, 284–291, 300
report to National Assembly 300
role 99, 284, 300
vote, role of 135–138
electoral system 108, 187
electoral term 183
English common law tradition 75 see also rule of law
equality see also social rights
affirmative action 532–544
analogous grounds 528
concept of 28
differentiation 523, 524, 530
discrimination 523, 524
formal 519–523
freedom 570–586
human dignity 524–527, 562–569
legal tests apply in an equality complaint 527–530
mere-discrimination 524, 528, 530–532
non-discrimination 524
PEPUDA 528, 529
principle of subsidiarity 528
privacy 586–591
substantive 517–519, 522, 523
unfair discrimination 545–561
ethnic nationalism 13
European Court of Human Rights 132, 133
European Union 47
‘everyone’ 403, 404 see also Bill of Rights
executive 65, 66, 182 see also national executive; President
expropriation of property 763–774 see also land reform; property
compensation 765–770
description 763–765
without compensation 770–774
F
Facebook 670
final Constitution 20 see also Constitution
financial affairs see fiscal powers
first peoples see Khoi-San
fiscal powers 348–362 see also local, national, provincial spheres of government
budgetary process 353–355
central bank see Reserve Bank
condonation permissible 357, 358
distribution of revenue 351–353
power to collect and spend public funds 348–351
procurement 356–361
Reserve Bank 355, 356
floor-crossing, controversial constitutional amendment 91
founding document of a nation 3, 4 see also constitution
Founding Values and the Bill of Rights 198
freedom
definitive right 570
general right 570
integrity 582–586
negative definition 574, 575
punishment 579–582
right to 572–574
substantive and procedural aspects 575–577
termination of pregnancy 585, 586
violence 577–579
Freedom Charter 15, 16
Freedom Front (FF)
1994 election 23
freedom of assembly 697–703 see also freedom of demonstration; pickets; petitions
freedom of association 595–613
balancing rights 611–613
communal nature of people 595–598
competing rights 611–613
excluding others justifiably 613
indispensable where a group holds dissident beliefs 602, 603
justifiably exclude others 613
not to associate 599–601
right to protest and 604
scope and content of section 18 of the Constitution 599–604
societal interests limiting 605–610
freedom of demonstration 697, 702, 703
freedom of expression 666–696
freedom of other media 675–690
freedom of petition 697–699, 705
freedom of picket 697–699, 703, 704
freedom of religion and practices
church’s core activities and other activities, drawing the line 628
distribution of religious beliefs, South Africa 615
freedom to practice beliefs 614–618, 621, 622
reasonable accommodation 629
religious marriages 636–638
religion or not 624, 625
right not to believe 632
scope and content in the Constitution 618–628
sectarian sphere of society 617, 618
secular sphere of society 617, 618
state and 633–636
traditional marriages 636–638
freedom of the press 675–690 see also police
Frontline States 17
G
gatherings see also Regulation of Gatherings Act 205 of 1993
liability for damage during 709–711
Gender Commission see Commission for Gender Equality
general affairs 14 see also tricameral parliament
General Assembly of the United Nations 17
German Bundesrat 146, 147
golden handshake 279, 280
government
acts and is it limited by a written constitution 42
formed by majority party 182
horizontal power 302
three branches of, South Africa 104
grand narrative as interpretative tool 34
Growth and Redistribution Policy (GEAR) 785
H
Harare Declaration 17
hate speech 690–697
heterogeneous society, South Africa 594
High Courts of South Africa
declare invalid provisions 244, 280
divisions 230, 231
Eastern Cape Division Grahamstown 230
Free State Division Bloemfontein 230
Gauteng Division Pretoria 230
hierarchy 66
jurisdiction 230, 244
KwaZulu-Natal Division Pietermaritzburg 230
Limpopo Division Polokwane 230
Mpumalanga Division Nelspruit 230
Northern Cape Division Kimberley 231
North-West Division Mahikeng 231
referral to Constitutional Court 244, 280
streamlined in 2013 230, 231
superior courts 233
Western Cape Division Cape Town 231
historical self-consciousness 29, 30
history, South Africa
African government before colonial occupation 304, 305
chiefs and chiefdoms 7
CODESA 18, 19
colonial conquest 5–9
constitutionalism, overview South Africa 46–49
discrimination during colonial and apartheid periods 517, 518
dispossession of land during colonial and apartheid periods 737–740
diversity 594
divided and unequal during apartheid period 783
final Constitution 20, 23–26
first democratic election 15–18
freedom of expression during apartheid period 666
interim Constitution 20
judiciary under apartheid 220–225
Mandela, Nelson, negotiations with 17
National Party (NP) 11–14
political 5–14
pre-Union 6–9
racial segregation 11–14
Republic of South Africa 1961 11
South African Constitution of 1996 26–31
‘three tiers of authority’ 304, 305
traditional leadership apartheid period 367–370
traditional leadership colonial period 367–370
traditional leadership during transitional period 370–371
traditional leadership pre-colonial period 366, 367
transitional period 15–18
two-stage transition 19–23
Union of South Africa 9–14
white domination 783, 784
Hoexter Commission of Inquiry 1983 268 see also magistrates’ courts
horizontal application of Bill of Rights 29
Houses of Parliament
bicameral parliament 1996 Constitution 107, 127, 145, 180
tricameral parliament 1983 Constitution 14
human dignity 524–569
human rights 45
Human Rights Commission, South Africa see South African Human Rights Commission
I
impeachment 185, 186, 217, 218
impugned law or conduct 443–445 see also limitations
independent candidates 131–134
independent judiciary 45
indigenous governance structures 8, 9
indigenous peoples see Khoi-San
indirect vertical and horizontal application of the Bill of Rights 479, 480
inegalitarian South African society 35
inferior specialist courts 231 see also superior specialist courts
Children’s Court 231
Domestic Violence Courts 231
Maintenance Courts 231
Inkatha Freedom Party (IFP)
1994 election 23
integrated model of federalism 303 see also quasi-federal system
integrity-protecting, exclusionary rule 603 see also freedom association
interdict 480, 508–512, 689
structural interdict 508–512
interim Constitution 20 see also Constitution
invalidity see doctrine of objective invalidity
J
Joint Tagging Mechanism 180 see also Parliament
judges
apartheid 220–225, 245
appointment 250–259
Chief Justice 267, 268
complaints against 265, 266
composition, pre-democratic era 223
criteria for appointment 255
financial security 286
impartiality 245–250
independence, pre-1994 222
judicial oath of office 260
Judicial Service Commission 251–259
limitation of civil liability 266, 267
oath of office 260
parliamentary supremacy 222
political influence 222
tenure 260–264
vetting old-order 246
judicial authority 269
judicial oath of office 260 see also judges
‘judicial overreach’ 227, 228
Judicial Service Commission (JSC)
Advising President 264
appointment of judges 251–256
Chapter 9 institution 99
complaints against judges 265, 266
composition 251, 281
criteria for appointment of judiciary 253
provision for newly established 21
role 251–259
transform judiciary 256–259
vacancies in a court 252
judiciary, South Africa see also separation of powers
apartheid 220–225, 281
‘bastion of legal order’ 225
composition in 2019 257
constitutional dispensation 229–244
counter-majoritarian dilemma 69–75
courts 225–228
customary law 223–225
enforcing provisions of the Constitution 104
esteem and respect of society 227
independence and impartial 245–250, 280
interpreting and enforcing Constitution 281
power to check President and Cabinet 218
separation in personnel as bedrock principle 66–69
separation of powers system 280
structure, 1996 Constitution 229–231
unique 104
jurisdiction
constitutional issues 232
non-constitutional matters 232
juristic persons 403 see also Bill of Rights
justification see also limitation
burden of 468–471
enquiry 453–455
K
Kenyan model 246 see also judges
Khoi-San 5, 38, 365, 380 see also history
‘kratos’ (rule) 84 see also democracy
L
Labour Court
employers and employees 231
‘Lagden Commission’ see Native Affairs Commission
land, dispossession of 737–742 see also land reform
Land Claims Court
land claims 231
land reform 774–780 see also redistribution of land; restitution of land
Language in Education Policy 832, 833
language of one’s choice 654–660, 829–836
language rights
competing rights 652, 653
education 654, 655–660
official languages of South Africa 660–662
Pan South African Language Board 662, 663
parity of esteem 651, 652
unfairly discriminated 654
laws, conflicting national, provincial and municipal 344
law of general application 446–449 see also limitations
Law of Lagos 77, 78 see also rule of law
legal personality of juristic persons 406 see also Bill of Rights
legislature, South Africa 60–65, 68, 69, 104 see also separation of powers
electoral system weaken power 63, 64
‘level’ of government 302 see also ‘spheres’ of government
liberation movements 14
limitations of the Bill of Rights see also Bill of Rights
all-at once approach 452, 453
alternative means of 459–461
analysis 442, 443, 445
balancing and proportionality 449–456
balancing and proportionality proper 461–468
balancing as an adjudicative strategy 437, 438
burden of justification 468–471
constitutional provisions limitations 473–475
criticisms of the balancing process 455, 456
first stage of limitation analysis 438, 439
general limitation clause, evolution 433–438
impugned law or conduct 443–445
infringing or violating the right 438, 439
internal modifiers 441, 442
justification enquiry, steps 453–455
law of general application 446–449
‘less restrictive alternative means’ 459–461
limiting measure’s side of the balancing scales 463, 464
practical purpose 442, 443
protected right 439–443
purpose of 456–458
rational connection requirement 458, 459
reasonable accommodation 466–468
‘reasonable and justifiable’ requirements 449–456
rights in the Bill of Rights 430, 431
rights side of the balancing scales 462, 463
sequential and structured approach 451
special limitations 471–473
specific rights and the limitation clause 472, 473
substantive, value-based approach to the first stage of the limitation analysis 439
threshold questions 454, 455
two-stage enquiry 431–433
litigants 477–482 see also constitutional remedies
litigation, Bill of Rights 399, 400–401, 415 see also Bill of Rights
‘living customary law’ see customary law
local government 329–348 see also municipalities
objectives 329–333
structure 333–335
supervision of 344–348
Locke, John 58, 59 see also separation of powers
lower courts 268–270 see also magistrates courts; traditional courts
independence under interim Constitution 268
independence under the 1996 Constitution 269, 270
traditional courts 270–272
Lugard, Frederick 393
M
Magistrates Commission 269
magistrates’ courts, South Africa
administration of justice 231
before 1993 268
hierarchy 66, 229
Hoexter Commission of Inquiry 268
independence under 1996 Constitution 269, 281
judicial authority 269
jurisdiction 244
Magistrates Commission role 269, 270
Maintenance Courts 231
Mandela, Nelson see also President
capacity of the Presidency 195
Presidential Review Commission 195
release of 14
secret negotiations with 17
signing of final version of 1996 Constitution 25
marriages
religious 636–638
traditional marriages 636–638
meaningful engagement 501–503
media see freedom of other media
Members of Parliament (MPs)
duty of 109
personal matters 117
power over elected members by their party, reasons 110–113
powers and privileges 116–123, 180
mere differentiation 524, 530–532
metropolitan councils
eight councils 303
Minister of Performance and Evaluation 196 see also National Planning Commission
Montesquieu, Charles Baron de 58 see also separation of powers
motion of no confidence 218
multiculturalism 29
Multi-Party Negotiating Process (MPNP) 19
multi-party system of democratic government 127
multisphere government 302, 303
municipalities see also local government
assigned powers 341, 342
bottom-up approach 338, 339
boundaries, determined by independent authority 334
category A 362
category B 362
category C 362
conflicting laws 344
horizontal division of power 361
incidental powers 342, 343
powers 336–344, 362
quasi-federal system of government 361
subject matter, determine 343
N
Natal Indian Congress
as liberation movement 15
National Assembly (NA), South Africa see also National Council of Provinces (NCOP); Parliament
bicameralism 107, 127, 145, 180
composition of 127, 128
constitutionally and politically dominant House 107
democratic link between voters and legislature 108
directly elected House of Parliament 179
disadvantages of party proportional representative system 130, 131
dissolution of 139, 140
duration of 139, 140
election of President 183, 184, 217
electoral system 108
electoral term 183
eligibility for election to 138, 139
five years 139
fixed number of (400) four hundred 127
functioning of 140–145
house in Parliament 107–109
impeachment of President and Cabinet 217
independent candidates 131–134
joint rules and orders with National Council of Provinces 113
members 180, 181
national legislative authority in Parliament 62, 63, 100
openness an transparency 115–116
party proportional representation electoral system 128–131, 179
powers and function 140–145, 184, 185, 217
power to determine and control own internal arrangements 113, 114
public involvement in 123–127
remove of President 184–188
right to vote 135–138
sittings 139, 140
Speaker role 143, 144
vote of no confidence 217
voters, role in law-making process 126
national common voters’ roll 127
National Council of Provinces (NCOP) see also National Assembly; Parliament
bicameralism 107, 127, 145, 180
committees 153, 154
composition and functioning 145–152
democratic link between voters 108
functioning 145–152
German Bundesrat, resembles 146, 147
house of Parliament 107
indirectly selected House of Parliament 179
influences on the operation of NCOP 149
internal arrangements 153, 154
joint rules and orders with National Assembly 113
national legislative authority 62
procedures 153, 154
represents interests of provinces 179
strict party discipline 151, 152
National Development Plan (NDP) 784
National Director of Public Prosecutions (NDPP) 207, 208, 272–278, 281
national executive
comprised of 217
Deputy President 180, 217
members of the Cabinet 181, 182, 217
members of the leaders of the majority party in the NA 181, 182, 217
President as head of the National Executive 65, 181, 217
national government see also local government; provincial government
composition of 303
conflicting laws 344
conflict with provincial government 325–328
financial power 362
horizontal division of power 361
integrated model of federalism 303
quasi-federal system of government 303, 361
spheres of government 303
National House of Traditional Leaders National House of Traditional Leaders 388–395
Chairperson 390, 391
composition 388, 389
Deputy-chairperson 390, 391
dissolution 390
establishment 388, 389
meetings and decisions 391
members, qualification and disqualification 389, 390
powers and duties 98, 391–393
term of office 390
National Intelligence Agency (NIA) 201
national legislature 106 see also Parliament; separation of powers
National Party (NP)
1948 election 11, 48
1994 election 23
National Planning Commission 196 see also Minister of Performance and Evaluation
National Prosecuting Authority (NPA) 97, 272–278, 281 see also separation of powers
national spheres 325–329
resolution of conflict with provincial spheres 325–328
Native Affairs Commission 8
Natives Land Act of 1913 737 see also property
native reserves see Bantustans; homelands
natural persons 402 see also Bill of Rights
New Nation Movement (NPC) v President of South Africa 131–134
Non-aligned Movement (NAM) 17
non-constitutional matters 233–235 see also constitutional matters
notional severance 493, 494
O
official languages, South Africa 11, 660–662
one-party dominant democracy 35, 37, 38 see also African National Congress (ANC)
opportunity-depriving, as exclusionary rule 603 see also freedom of association
order of invalidity
limiting 495–497
suspension 497–500
Organisation of African Unity (OAU) 17 see also African Union
own affairs 14 see also tricameral parliament
ownership, inherently unrestricted right 743–745, 779, 780 see also property
P
Pan Africanist Congress (PAC)
as liberation movement 14
1994 election 23
Pan South African Language Board 662, 663
parliamentary government 47
parliamentary privileges and immunities 62
parliamentary sovereignty
apartheid 220–225
Parliament see also National Assembly (NA); National Council of Provinces (NCOP)
accountability of executives as function 155–161
assigning of power to other legislative spheres of authority as function 176–180
bicameral legislature 107, 127, 179
Cape Town 108
citizens as members of political parties 110
delegation of legislative authority 176–179, 204
embodiment of dreams and aspirations 106
functions of 154–180
inheritance from Britain 110
irrevocable duty to serve, Members 109
legislation (law-making) as function 162–175
Members of (MPs), power and privileges 116–123
National Assembly (NA) 127–144
National Council of Provinces (NCOP) 145–154
national forum for public consideration as function 155
openness and transparency 115, 116
oversight as function 161, 162
political parties, role of 108–113
public involvement in the legislative and other processes 123–127
responsibilities 106, 107
robust discussions, Parliamentary privilege 122, 123
rules regarding the operation of 113–127
State of the Nation 2015 (SONA) 115
State Security Agency 2015 115
structure and composition of 107, 108
supremacy of 11, 12, 49
‘voice of all South Africans’ 106
participatory democracy 85, 92–94, 96 see also democracy
participatory governance 29
party leadership, actual power 212
party political funding 609 see also state capture
party (pure) proportional representation electoral system 128–131, 179
patterns of disadvantage 533
PEPUDA 528, 529, 554–561, 736
petitions see freedom of petition
picket see freedom of picket
pith and substance test for Bills 320–324 see also substantial measure test for Bills
Plaatje, Sol 737
plenary law-making power 178, 179
pluralism 639
police 676, 677
political culture, South Africa’s 35, 36, 111
political history South Africa see history, South Africa
political parties
Britain 110
citizens as members of 110
citizen participation 721
dominant political party 218
elections, free, fair and regular 722–726
electoral system 108, 111, 112
funding of political party 718–722
inheritance from Britain 110
internal culture of 111
internal discipline 715
power over elected members 110–112
prohibited donations 721, 722
regulation of 716–718
role of 108–113
state funding of 718–722
strict party discipline 111
toeing the party line 112, 113
political rights 711–735
before 1994 711, 712
choices 713–718
donations 721, 722
elections 722–726
funding of political parties 718–722
non-citizens 713
political parties 713–718
vote 726–733
polygamous marriages 638
pornography 674, 675
Premier see also provincial government
executive authority 315, 316
Presidential Review Commission 195 see also Mandela, Nelson
President of the Republic of South Africa see also Deputy President
abdicate power 193
acting President 189, 190
authority, sole 193
delegation of legislative authority 204
elected by National Assembly (NA) 183, 184, 217
executive authority 193, 194
Head of National Executive 65, 190, 193, 194, 197, 217
Head of State 65, 190–192, 217
impeachment of President and Cabinet 185, 217
internal party political considerations, role 194, 195
leader of majority party 217
limits of presidential power 197–210
Ministries in office of 196
New Nation Movement (NPC) v President 131–134
party political system constraints 194, 195
pivotal role as 183, 184
power of the 191–193, 195–197, 218, 219
Public Protector 192, 193
rational connection 207, 208
rationality 206, 207
removal of 183–189
resignation 217
State Capture 192
terms of office 183, 184
veto of Bills 168
vote of no confidence in 188, 217
press see freedom of the press
pre-Union history, South Africa 6–9
principle of avoidance or subsidiarity 311, 420, 528 see also Bill of Rights
principle of checks and balances 57, 182 see also separation of powers
principle of open justice 678–680
principle of respect for the rule of law see rule of law
principle of subsidiarity see principle of avoidance or subsidiarity
privacy, right to 586–591
private person, unauthorized decisions not law 446, 447 see also limitations
procurement 356–361 see also fiscal powers
property 737–780
deprivation of 753–763
dispossession of land by colonial and apartheid states 737, 740
expropriation of 763–774
multi-stage methodology 750–753
Natives Land Act of 1913 737
property clause, negative phraseology 742–750
social solidarity right 749, 750
property clause, negative phraseology 742–750
protected right 439–443 see also limitations
internal modifiers or ‘unqualified terms’ 433, 441, 442
protest, right to 604 see also freedom of association
provinces
developmental function 303
nine 303
provincial administration
national intervention 328, 329
Provincial Divisions of the Supreme Court 233
provincial government
administration 328, 329
conflicting laws 344
conflicts between national and 325–328
democracy 313, 314
division and demarcation of legislative competences 317–320
division of legislative and executive power between spheres 329
horizontal division of power 361
legislative competence 320–324
national intervention 328, 329
objectives 313–320
pith and substance test 320–324
Premier 315, 316
quasi-federal system of government 361
structures 313–320
provincial spheres 325–328
resolution of conflict with national sphere 325–328
public administration 182
Public Protector
appointment of 198
Chapter 9 institution 99, 283, 300
independent 284–300
remedial action 296–298
report to National Assembly 300
role and powers 300
special case as Chapter 9 institution 291–300
‘State Capture’ 192, 193
public service 182
punishment, free form cruel, inhuman or degrading 579–582
purpose-protecting, as exclusionary rule 613 see also freedom of association
Q
quasi-federal system 302, 303, 361 see also integrated model of federalism
R
racial segregation 11, 38
rational connection 207
rationality 206 see also President
reading down 485–487
reading in 487–492
reasonable accommodation 558–560
‘reasonable and justifiable’ requirements 449–456 see also limitation
Reconstruction and Development Programme/Policy (RDP) 123, 785
redistribution of land 774–780 see also restitution of land
redress measures (affirmative action)
basic approach 532–536
legality 543, 544
patterns of disadvantage 533
test for 536–543
under PEPUDA 561
Regulations of Gatherings Act 205 of 1993 705–709
religious communities 639–650
commercialisation of religion 642
remedies see constitutional remedies
reparation 527
Report on Traditional Courts 270 see also South African Law Commission
representative democracy 85, 88–92, 96 see also democracy
dominant party democracy 92
limitations of 92
republican Constitution, South Africa 48
Reserve Bank
banker of other banks 356
bank notes and coins 366
central bank 355, 356
formulation and implementation of monetary policy 355
provision of liquidity to banks 355
role 355, 356
restitution of land 774–780 see also redistribution of land
retrospective invalidation of legislation 495–497
revenue 349–353
rights
Bill of Rights 430, 431
constitutional provisions 473–476
equality 517–561
freedom 570–577
freedom of assembly, demonstration, picket and petition 697–711
freedom of expression 666–697
immediately realisable socio-economic 821, 822, 826
non-discrimination 517–561
ownership 743–745
political rights 711–736
property 742–774
protected right 439–443
socio-economic rights 782–842
rule of law
constitutional system 45, 75
Diceyean conception of the 75, 76
English common law tradition 75
expansive conceptions of the 83, 84
history of the 75–78
Law of Lagos 77, 78
narrow conceptions of the 83, 84
principles of 76
rationality, variable standards 208, 209
under 1996 Constitution, South Africa 79–84
S
Sachs, Albie 21
security, freedom to 577–579
separation of functions, principle of separation of powers doctrine 57 see also separation of powers doctrine
separation of personnel, principle of separation of powers doctrine 57 see also separation of powers doctrine
separation of powers doctrine see also judiciary; national executive; national legislature (Parliament)
branches of government and 104
checks and balances system 57, 97, 182
constitutional law based on 106
counter-majoritarian dilemma, South Africa 69–75
democratic constitutional South African dispensation within system of 99–104
dialogic model of 102–104
executive 60, 61, 65, 66, 68, 69, 97–104
history of doctrine 58–59
interpreting South African separation of powers within own historical context 59, 60
judiciary 66–69, 97–104
legislature 60–65, 68, 69, 97–104
mechanism to give effect to the principle of checks and balances 182
national executive 181
principles of 56, 57
purpose of 56, 57
socio-economic rights 793–795
United States of America 59, 60
sequential and structured approach 451 see also limitations
severance 492, 493
social engineering 13
social rights 28 see also equality
socio-economic rights 782–842
‘access to’ 806, 807
adjudication, constraints 792–795
amici curiae in litigation 791, 792
basic education 822–829
constitutionalisation of 786–792
defined 782
education and 821–842
free tertiary education 837–841
fulfil 797
guidelines in the interpretation of 795–798
immediately realisable 791, 792
justiciability debate 787, 788
language of one’s choice 829–836
limits of 785
litigation 791, 792
meaningful engagement 817–819
minimum core approach 811–813
negative duties 801, 802
obligations, enforcing 800–819
positive duties 802–819
private parties, obligation regarding 798–800
progressively realisable 789–791
progressive realisation 813–815
promote 797, 798
protect 796
reasonableness 807–811
reasonableness approach 803
reasonableness approach critique 809–811
remedies in cases 819–821
resources, availability 815–816
respect 796
separation of powers 792–795
transformative features of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa 782, 783
South African Communist Party (SACP)
as liberation movement 14
South African Constitution see also constitution
socio-economic rights in the 789–792
unique aspects of 783
South African government see also history; spheres of government
composition 303
historical development 304, 305
South African Human Rights Commission
Chapter 9 institution 283, 284
independence 284–291
role 284
South African Law Commission (SALC) 270, 271 see also traditional courts
Speaker of the National Assembly (NA) 109, 143, 144
‘spheres’ of government
divided model of federalism 303
equal constitutional status 302
fiscal powers 348–362
geographic, functional and institutional integrity 302
historical background 304, 305
integrated model of federalism 303
multisphere 313
powers 302
quasi-federal system 303
replaced ‘level’ of government 302
stand and hold office 733–736 see also political parties
state 182
‘State Capture’ Inquiry 192, 193, 609
States of Emergency 220, 221
State of the Nation Address (SONA, 2015) 115, 116
State Security Agency (2015) 115
street renaming 330–333 see also decolonisation; local government
strict party discipline 111, 151, 152 see also political parties
struggle for freedom 5 see also history
substantial measure test for Bills 322, 323 see also pith and substance test for Bills
superior courts
independent and impartial judiciary 245–250
interpreting and enforcing Constitution 281
superior specialist courts 231 see also inferior specialist courts
Labour Court 231
Land Claims Court 231
Tax Court 231
Supreme Court 223 see also High Court
Supreme Court of Appeal (SCA), South Africa
appeals from High Courts 280
before 1994 223
Bloemfontein 230
Constitutional Court on appeal from 280
Deputy President 230
entity in own right 230
headed by President or Deputy President of the SCA 230
hierarchy 66, 223, 229
jurisdiction 230, 243, 244
role 242
suspension of an order of invalidity 497–500
T
Tax Court 231
tertiary education 837–841 see also education
‘three tiers of authority’ 304, 305 see also spheres of government
traditional communities
controversy 383, 384
defined 381, 382
recognition 381, 382
traditional councils
controversy 383, 384
establishment 382, 383
functions 384–385
link to former homelands 383
traditional courts 268–272
lower court 268–272
Report on Traditional Courts 270
South African Law Commission (SALC) 270
traditional governance structures 7, 9, 304, 305, 364
traditional homelands 13, 383, 384
traditional leader(s)
African government 304, 305
apartheid era 367–370
authority 383, 384
chiefs 367
colonial era 367–370
cultural heritage of 14
customary powers of 8
democratic era 372–377
description of hierarchy 378–381
function 381
National House of Traditional Leaders 388–395
Pre-Union 7–9
recognition 378–381
role of 13
taxes, levy 386–388
transition period 370, 371
traditional leadership see also traditional leaders
accountability 376, 377
apartheid era 367–370
colonial era 367–370
constitutional framework governing 364
democratic era 372–377
legislation regulating 377–388
pre-colonial period 367
Traditional Leadership and Governance Framework Act 378
transition period 370, 371
Traditional Leadership and Governance Framework Act 378
traditional marriages 636–638
traditional peoples see Bantu
transformation, radical social and economic 785 see also social-economic rights
transformative constitutionalism 31
trias politica as principle of separation of powers doctrine 57 see also separation of powers doctrine
tricameral legislature 14
two-stage enquiry 431–433
two-stage transition 19, 20
U
ubi ius ubi remedium 512
ubuntu 516, 517
unfair discrimination see also discrimination
differentiation 546–548
distinguish between discrimination and 545
Union of South Africa 5, 9, 39, 737 see also history, South Africa
Union Parliament 10
United Democratic Front (UDF)
as liberation movement 15
United States of America 47, 59, 60, 70
universal adult suffrage 127
V
values, South African constitutional 52–54
Van Riebeeck, Jan 5, 365
veto power, President of South Africa 168
violence, free from 577–579
vote see also Electoral Commission; National Assembly
limitations to right to 136–138
of no confidence 139, 217
right to 135–138, 726–733
W
Westminster
constitutional model 46–49
executive branch 47
legislative branch 47
parliamentary system 6, 10, 39
white settlers 38 see also history
women’s rights 372
worker 403 see also Bill of Rights
Z
Zondo, DCJ 609
Zuma, Jacob 196, 261, 279