OceanofPDF.com Subject Lessons - Sanjay Seth
OceanofPDF.com Subject Lessons - Sanjay Seth
se th
Subject Lessons offers a fascinating account of how western knowledge “traveled” to India,
changed that which it encountered, and was itself transformed in the process. Beginning in
1835, India’s British rulers funded schools and universities to disseminate modern, west-
ern knowledge in the expectation that it would gradually replace indigenous ways of know-
ing. From the start, western education was endowed with great significance in India, not
only by the colonizers but also by the colonized, to the extent that today almost all “serious”
knowledge about India—even within India—is based on western epistemologies. In Subject
Lessons, Sanjay Seth’s investigation into how western knowledge was received by Indians
under colonial rule becomes a broader inquiry into how modern, western epistemology
came to be seen not merely as one way of knowing among others but as knowledge itself. Subject Lessons
Subject Lessons
were concerns that Indian students were acquiring western education by rote memoriza-
tion—and were therefore not acquiring “true knowledge”—and that western education
had plunged Indian students into a moral crisis, leaving them torn between modern, west-
ern knowledge and traditional Indian beliefs. Seth argues that these concerns, voiced by the
British as well as by nationalists, reflected the anxiety that western education was failing to
produce the modern subjects it presupposed. This failure suggested that western knowl-
edge was not the universal epistemology it was thought to be.
“Subject Lessons revives a field that has remained dormant for years: the history of education
in colonial India. This in itself is no small achievement. But Sanjay Seth does a lot more
than that. Weaving together history and philosophical critiques of historicity and moder-
nity, Seth has produced a book that is at once thoughtful and provocative. This outstanding
series editors
George Steinmetz and Julia Adams
series editorial advisory board
Fernando Coronil
Mamadou Diouf
Michael Dutton
Geoff Eley
Fatma Müge Göcek
Nancy Rose Hunt
Andreas Kalyvas
Webb Keane
David Laitin
Lydia Liu
Julie Skurski
Margaret Somers
Ann Laura Stoler
Katherine Verdery
Elizabeth Wingrove
Sanjay Seth
Acknowledgments ix
Introduction 1
Notes 197
Bibliography 235
Index 259
Acknowledgments
This book has been long in the making, and I have many people and institu-
tions to thank. I am grateful to the librarians and archivists of Indian Office
Library and Records (incorporated into the British Library partway through
my research), the National Archives of India, the Nehru Memorial Library and
Museum, the Scottish National Library, the Gokhale Institute, the Cambridge
South Asia Centre Library, the State Library of Victoria, and the Borchardt
library of La Trobe University—especially its Inter-Library Loans section. The
Australia Research Council provided small grants to facilitate research trips,
as did La Trobe University, which also provided a supportive and congenial
environment in which to write. The Japan Society for the Promotion of Sci-
ence awarded me a year-long fellowship to work on this book; I am grateful to
Professor Nariaki Nakazato and the Toyo Bunka Kenkyujo of Tokyo University
for hosting me during a blissful year when I was able to work obsessively on
the manuscript. Earlier versions of some of these chapters were presented at
New Delhi, Princeton, Minneapolis, New York, Chicago, Santa Cruz, Berlin,
Tokyo, Edinburgh, Melbourne, and Brisbane; my thanks to my audiences at
these occasions, and to the organizers of these talks.
Many friends and colleagues have answered queries, provided references,
and made helpful suggestions; my thanks to Shahid Amin, Robin Jeffrey,
Francesca Orsini, John Fitzgerald, the late Ravinder Kumar, Pauline Nestor,
Hilary McPhee, Joel Kahn, Barbara Cain, Angus McIntyre, Richard Delacy,
Sudhir Chandra, Kama Maclean, Greg Bailey, the late Fred Hardy, Ashok
Aklujkar, Dennis Altman, Joel Kahn, Robert Manne, and Kunal Chakrabarti.
My thanks also to Sarbajeet Mukherjee for rendering research assistance in
the National Library, Calcutta.
A number of colleagues read and commented on one or more chapters of
this book. I am grateful to Ranajit Guha, Sumit Sarkar, Tanika Sarkar, Robin
Archer, Leela Gandhi, Michael Dutton, Ian Hunter, Anita Ray, and Nariaki
Nakazato for taking the trouble to do so, and for their comments and criti-
ix
x Acknowledgments
cisms. I am grateful to Julia Adams and Reynolds Smith for editorial feedback
and for shepherding this book through the publication process, and to Fred
Kameny for his very professional copy editing.
Since my graduate student days Dipesh Chakrabarty has been a friend
and interlocutor, and he has read, commented upon, and discussed this book
with me over the years that it has taken to write it. It gives me pleasure to
acknowledge my debt to him, and to thank him. Barry Hindess once again
demonstrated that there is no more acute reader of an argument, with a keen
eye for flaws and evasions; I hope that there are, thanks to his comments,
fewer of these than there might have been. Akeel Bilgrami engaged me in
long-distance debates during my year in Tokyo, and his comments have never
failed to be stimulating and challenging. Rajyashree Pandey read the chapters
through their successive drafts, and offered unconditional encouragement
coupled with unconstrained criticism!
Many friends offered sustenance and hospitality while I was away from
home: in India, Sudhir Chandra, Geetanjali Shree, Atul Joshi, Jayanti Pan-
dey, Sara Rai, and Muhammad Aslam; in England, Terry Shakhanovsky, Robin
Archer, Chris Macpherson, Greg Patching, and above all the Hardy family;
and in Japan, Sonoe Matsui and her family. A community of friends in
Melbourne provided occasions for ongoing addas; my thanks to Deborah
Kessler, Pauline Nestor, and my fellow editors of Postcolonial Studies, Amanda
Macdonald, Michele Grossman, and—especially—Leela Gandhi and Michael
Dutton.
I am unusually blessed in that my siblings constitute not only my af-
fective, but also my intellectual, community. I subjected Vanita Seth and
Suman Seth to endless drafts of the manuscript, which they read with acuity
and humor. It remains a source of great sadness to me that my mother, the
person who would have derived the greatest pleasure from seeing this book in
print, is not here to see it. My father has been a source of unqualified support
and encouragement in this as in other endeavors. I owe him and my mother
more than could ever be acknowledged.
Finally, and closest to home, Rajyashree and Nishad Pandey have provided
me with a world which includes, but also extends well beyond, thinking and
writing. I dedicate this to them.
Introduction
The colonial era is roughly coterminous with the rise of a knowledge that I
will be calling ‘‘modern, western knowledge’’—‘‘modern’’ to denote its rela-
tively recent emergence, ‘‘western’’ to indicate the cultural specificity of these
historical origins. Along with guns and goods, this knowledge traveled to the
colonies, and it was in part through this knowledge that the non-western
world came to be conquered, represented, and ruled. But although it arrived
from the outside, often at the point of a bayonet, this knowledge ceased to
be merely the colonizer’s knowledge. It found a home in its new locales. A
number of agencies served to disseminate it, among them armies, railroads,
trade, and the institutions and practices of colonial government.
In India the most direct and one of the most important of these agen-
cies was western education. The 1830s witnessed a bitter dispute in the ranks
of colonial officialdom over whether the British Indian government should
patronize ‘‘Oriental’’ knowledges, or whether it should direct its attentions
solely to promoting western knowledge, initially through the medium of
English. Victory went to the ‘‘Anglicists,’’ led by Thomas Babington Mac-
aulay, and from 1835 India’s colonial rulers became the agency for promoting
‘‘western education,’’ that is, education which sought to disseminate mod-
ern, western knowledge through modern institutions and pedagogic pro-
cesses. It was anticipated and desired by the victorious party that this would
gradually supplant indigenous knowledges, which were condemned as (vari-
ously) ‘‘superstitious,’’ ‘‘mythic,’’ ‘‘primitive,’’ and, more generally, untrue; or,
as Macaulay characterized them, ‘‘medical doctrines which would disgrace an
English farrier, astronomy which would move laughter in girls at an English
boarding school, history abounding with kings thirty feet high and reigns
thirty thousand years long, and geography made of seas of treacle and seas of
butter.’’ 1
After 1835 India’s colonial rulers spent the bulk of the state money allo-
cated for educating their subjects on modern, western education. When in
1
2 Introduction
1854 the authorities in Britain gave instructions for extending the provision
of education beyond the élite classes of native society for which it had ini-
tially been intended, they made it clear that ‘‘the education which we desire
to see extended in India is that which has for its object the diffusion of the
improved arts, science, philosophy and literature of Europe; in short, Euro-
pean knowledge.’’ 2 Schools were established to teach this knowledge, and in
1857 the universities of Calcutta, Bombay, and Madras were established, soon
to be followed by universities in other parts of India.3 The British thus under-
took a task that lent its name to the title of a work by CharlesTrevelyan, one of
the architects of the decision of 1835: The Education of the People of India. While
this effort was being made, from the early decades of the nineteenth century
colonialism itself came to be seen as an essentially pedagogic enterprise.Those
aspects of British rule which had long been hailed as the justification for for-
eign rule of another peoples—the Pax Britannica which created peace where
once there had been disorder and brigandage, the ‘‘rule of law,’’ the provision
of public works, and so on—were now seen not only as goods in themselves
but also as having an educative value. A textbook of 1897 told its audience
of Indian schoolboys that the Penal Code, public works, railways, irrigation
and civil works, schools, the post office and telegraph, and a free press were
all forces working to educate India.4 The ascription of pedagogic effects and
benefits to almost all the practices and institutions of colonial rule became
pervasive, so much so that sometimes it assumed burlesque forms: in 1913
a government enquiry declared, ‘‘The Committee regards the provision of
proper latrine and urinal accommodation as not only necessary in the inter-
ests of . . . health . . . [and] sanitation . . . but also as having a distinctly educa-
tive value.’’ 5 It became common to describe formal instruction or schooling
as but an aspect or subset of this wider pedagogic mission.6 Partly because it
came to be seen in this way, western education was endowed with great sig-
nificance, even though the sums expended upon it were minuscule, and the
numbers directly affected by it a small proportion of the total population.7
There was also, for a long period, a keen awareness of the ‘‘exoticism’’ of
western knowledge. The architects of the decision of 1835 were in no doubt
as to the momentousness of the decision they had made. Charles Trevelyan
wrote, ‘‘The decision which was come to is worthy of everlasting record.
Although homely in its words, it will be mighty in its effects long after we
are mouldering in the dust.’’ 8 The Pioneer, an English-owned newspaper pub-
lished from Allahabad, wrote that ‘‘the experiment [of Western education]
Introduction 3
going on in India is onewhich, in the immensityof its scope, the gravityof the
issues depending on it, and the conditions under which it has to be carried
on, has had no parallel in the world’s history.’’ 9 Schooling, not on the face of it
the setting for high drama, was frequently treated in highly dramatic terms,
and described in flowery language. Nor was this by any means confined to the
British. Syed Mahmood wrote: ‘‘The origin, rise and progress of English edu-
cation in India . . . constitute one of the most significant episodes, not only
in the annals of India, but in the history of the civilised world.’’ 10 Not to be
outdone, a contributor to the nationalist Modern Review scaled new rhetorical
heights: ‘‘The English education of India! It is one of the most momentous
events the world has ever seen and most difficult problems the human brain
has ever faced. How to transport the learning, method, and spirit of Western
Europe to Middle Eastern Asia, among a subject race . . . and make it grow as
native of the soil . . . It is a more difficult achievement than the annihilation
of time and space by modern science.’’ 11
That sense of exoticism has long since faded. Today almost all serious,
‘‘respectable,’’ and officially disseminated knowledge about the non-western
world shares the presumptions and guiding categories of modern western
knowledge. This is so whether the sites for the production of knowledge are
located in the western world, or in the non-western world. And usually, this
fact occasions little comment, let alone sustained reflection, because western
knowledge is no longer seen as only one mode of knowing but as knowledge
itself, compared to which all other traditions of reasoning are only Unreason,
or earlier stages in the march toward Reason.
This book is a study of how western knowledge came to be disseminated
in India, such that it came to assume its current status as the obvious, and
almost the only, mode of knowing about India. The book is principally con-
cerned not with the thinking and intentions of the colonizer but with how
western education was received and consumed by the colonized. It is also,
and simultaneously, an argument that the status of modern western knowl-
edge—the assumption that it is not merely one mode of knowledge but is
knowledge ‘‘as such,’’ that it must be adequate to its Indian object because it
is adequate to all objects—is questionable, and needs to be rethought. What
follows thus has certain affinities with recent studies, some of them under-
taken under the sign of postcolonial theory, that seek not to ‘‘apply’’ our mod-
ern western knowledge to the non-western world, but rather to make that
knowledge itself a matter for investigation and problematizing.12
4 Introduction
Subject to Pedagogy
New knowledges do not simply stuff the heads of existing people with new
ideas; they serve to create new people, which is why ‘‘the history of knowl-
edge constitutes a privileged point of view for the genealogy of the subject.’’ 13
Knowledges position and construct knowers in different ways, and this was
especially true of modern, western knowledge. Why ‘‘especially’’ so? Because
modern knowledge helps initiate, and is a defining feature of, a deep trans-
formation which creates a knowing subject who is set apart from, even set up
against, the objects to be known.
This transformation has been characterized in a variety of ways, one of
the more famous of which is Max Weber’s notion of ‘‘disenchantment.’’ Ac-
cording to Weber, modern western man’s increasing capacity to ‘‘master’’ the
world is attributable to a type of knowledge that approaches the world look-
ing for laws and regularities rather than purposes and meanings.The efficacy
of what might initially be a more-or-less methodological or technical postu-
late—that we act as if the world were rationally calculable—results in turning
it into a natural stance. The world is disenchanted in the sense that no magic
and no mysteries pervade the world nor yield up knowledge of it; and in that
the world is external to us, it does not resonate with our longings and aspi-
rations. We can find no support or vindication for our choices, values, and
beliefs, for a disenchanted world does not provide us with our own reflec-
tion—it is blank, and cold. Our knowledge of it does not reveal its meaning:
the only meanings we find ‘‘out there’’ are those which we have put there.14
This knowledge is fundamentally different from the premodern knowl-
edge(s) of Europe, which were displaced by this new knowledge, and which,
Charles Taylor writes, required ‘‘understanding the world in categories of
meaning, as existing to embody or express an order of Ideas or archetypes, as
manifesting the rhythm of divine life, or the foundational acts of the gods, or
the will of God,’’ and ‘‘seeing the world as a text, or the universe as a book.’’ 15
Such knowledges presumed a very different relation between the knower and
the known, between humans and their world; for one thing, they did not
draw the line between the two so sharply. To simplify, they presumed that
humans found meaning and purpose in the world; and as modern knowledge
emerged and was defined through a critique of scholastic and other medieval
knowledges, this was seen as the source and root of the errors of premodern
knowledges. To find an order in the universe and seek to harmonize with it,
or to find the correspondences so loved by the Renaissance, or to subscribe
Introduction 5
to theories of knowledge which attribute to man an ‘‘innate’’ disposition to
assent to the good and the true—all these appeared, from an emergent, mod-
ern, and scientific perspective, as a confusing of man with his world, most
clearly manifested in attributing to the world a meaning and purpose which
in fact belongs to us, and which we have projected onto it. A conception of
knowledge that posits a knowing subject and an object external to it is also
one that makes policing this distinction the very basis of any valid knowl-
edge. Any confusion between the knowing subject and the object must be
guarded against; solipsism on the one hand, and ‘‘projecting’’ one’s desires
and purposes onto the world on the other, become the two cardinal sins to be
avoided.
This was once a novel conception of knowledge, and the subject it pre-
sumed was not found ready-to-hand but rather had to be forged, had to be
created through new pedagogic practices, and through the transformations
and disciplines enforced by industrialization and capitalism, modern armies,
and the modern novel—a process that was complex and difficult, and one
that met with resistance. All the more so in the Indian subcontinent, where
the knowledges in question were not autochthonous, and where the instru-
ments for forging the new subject had not been slowly working away through
the centuries of industrialization and the emergence of new disciplinary ma-
trixes of family, prison, school, and factory, but were heavily dependent upon
the violent and coercive agency of colonial rule.
As a study of western knowledge in colonial India, this is also a work about
subjectivities. It is about how Western education in India posited and served
to create—and sometimes failed to fully create—certain sorts of subjects.
Subject of History
This is in part a work of history, and it is also a work about writing history,
and the possibility thereof. Why it should be about writing history is readily
discernible, for this book is in a very precise sense a product of the history
which it retells. It is a history of the western, rational type, approved of—
and practised by—Macaulay, rather than, say, a Puranic history (Macaulay’s
‘‘history abounding with kings thirty feet high and reigns thirty thousand
years long’’). As a history of western knowledge in India written from within
that knowledge, a work such as this needs a reflexive moment; it needs to
ask whether the ensuing circularity is an enabling hermeneutical circle or a
disabling, self-referential one.
6 Introduction
But what could it mean to ask about the ‘‘possibility’’ of history writing?
Here I will try to explicate this question by returning to my brief descrip-
tion of Weber’s account of ‘‘disenchantment,’’ this time to complicate it by
juxtaposing it with another account.
Part of the appeal of Weber’s account is that in arguing that there are no
meanings and purposes and values ‘‘in’’ the world, he does not conclude that
meanings and values are superfluous. Weber’s well-known insistence that
the scientist seek to keep fact and values distinct is not born of a positivist
denigration of the latter; indeed, in part Weber argues, in Kantian fashion,
for a realm of objectivity in order to make room for values—as distinctly
human products.16 This yields, or can be made to yield, a historicism which
is possibly more appealing now than it was in its own day. Just as individu-
als assign meaning and choose values, so different peoples at different times
have shaped collective values and ways of being in the world. Scholars of the
human sciences can, from texts, monuments, artworks and the like, recon-
struct their world-picture or Weltanschauung—a favorite word of Weber’s,
as of a number of his contemporaries. Medieval men and women attributed
their own actions and conceptions to transcendent beings; this was a part
of their Weltanschauung, something the historian can reconstruct or piece
together from their art, their philosophy, and so on.We moderns know better,
although—the source of Weber’s melancholy—the price of our superior (self-)
knowledge may be that we are less at home in the world. In all cases, man
is a meaning-endowing and culture-secreting being, and from the material
and textual traces and remnants he leaves behind, we can piece together what
sort of man he was.
In ‘‘The Age of the World Picture’’ Martin Heidegger seems at first glance
to be offering an account similar to this one. Like Weber, he sees the more
obvious manifestations of modernity—individualism, technology, and so on
—as based upon something which is, however, more fundamental.This some-
thing ‘‘more fundamental’’ reads not entirely unlike Weber’s distinction be-
tween a subject who has become central and a world of objects which is dis-
enchanted, and Heidegger too talks of a world picture. But his account is in
fact very different.
Heidegger also states that at the heart of modernity is the rise of an abso-
lute subjectivity, such that the world appears to man as if it were ‘‘for’’ him.
But this is not a new Weltanschauung, replacing the older one: the modern
age is not distinguished from other ages by its peculiarly ‘‘modern’’ picture of
Introduction 7
the world, but rather by the very fact that it can conceive and grasp the world
as picture.17 Nor can the difference between the modern and the medieval
and ancient worlds be understood in terms of different ‘‘cultural values’’ or
‘‘spiritual values,’’ for there was nothing, writes Heidegger, like ‘‘culture’’ in
the Middle Ages or ‘‘spiritual values’’ in the ancient world: ‘‘Only in the mod-
ern era have spirit and culture been deliberately experienced as fundamental
modes of human comportment, and only in most recent times have ‘values’
been paraded as standards for such comportment.’’ 18 The difference between
our age and other ages (and other peoples, then and now) cannot be rendered
in terms of different ‘‘outlooks,’’ ‘‘views,’’ ‘‘values,’’ and ‘‘experiences,’’ because
such ways of thinking are already modern, are already products of a histori-
cal and intellectual transformation which places Man at the centre of things,
which now exist for him and only exist inasmuch as they are pictured, valued
or experienced.19
Unlike Weber and many others, who rightly urge that we recognize ‘‘our’’
way of understanding and engaging with our world as possibly specific to us
rather than part of a ‘‘human condition,’’ Heidegger goes further, question-
ing thevery idea that man has always been a culture-secreting being, and that
different men in different epochs ‘‘secreted’’ different values and meanings.
To recognize, as Weber did, that others may have viewed the world differently
is an advance over an ahistorical ascription of similarity, but under the seem-
ing defamiliarization of this sort is still an unwarranted assumption, namely
that always, everywhere, there is ‘‘Man,’’ whose way of being in the world is
to ‘‘view’’ it. One way of approaching Heidegger is thus to see him as radi-
calizing and going beyond such historicizing, and in so doing ‘‘explaining’’
its limitations. Historicizing approaches take a feature of the modern, Occi-
dental world—namely that we are subjects whose values and world-picture
become embodied in socially produced meaning—and read it into the world
as such.
Pressing into service this aspect of Heidegger’s thought, I will ask: Where
Man has not become subject and the world has not become picture, is it still
possible to write history? History writing is always the ‘‘history of ’’—that is,
it has a subject whose past it recapitulates. For modern historiography, which
is deeply imbued with humanist and anthropological premises, this subject
is Man, conceived as a being who produces culture and meaning, and whose
meanings can be deciphered from his texts and his monuments and other
‘‘traces’’ of his subjectivity. But if, as this book shall show, modern knowl-
8 Introduction
edge failed fully to produce a subject and to produce ‘‘the world as picture’’ in
India, then how do we write history, and what is the status of the knowledge
we produce when we do write it?
Subject to Pedagogy
chapter one
Knowledge/rote
education/instruction
meaning/memory
explanation/repetition
understanding, reasoning/learning by heart
own thoughts/others’ thoughts
own generalisations/second-hand-knowledge
The first and fifth contrasts are different iterations of the distinction that
Curzon is seeking to make: between genuine knowledge, the ability to under-
stand the meaning of something through one’s own reasoning processes, and
committing something to one’s memory. This difference, the last two con-
trasts indicate, is also the difference between having made knowledge one’s
own, and being ‘‘stuffed’’ with others’ ideas and therefore in possession of
only secondhand knowledge.The second and fourth contrasts refer to the dif-
ferent pedagogies corresponding to these two knowledges—one is inculcated
through an education that explains, the other through an education that re-
quires the student to repeat. Curzon also employs two metaphors to make
his point: knowledge is not like a neat collection of specimens in a museum,
and it cannot be acquired if conceived of thus any more than a language can
be acquired simply by poring over a dictionary. The contrasts and repetitions
weave in and out of each other as Curzon strives to make the same point from
different angles and by use of different metaphors, and returns, again and
again, to the distinction which he fears his student audience may not see:
Changing the Subject 31
a distinction in which good knowledge and failed knowledge map onto the
distinction between autonomy and heteronomy, between an active subject
and a passive one.
Other Knowledges
Modern knowledge, for all its diversity, is conceived as unitary. It is distin-
guished according to its objects (the human sciences, further subdivided by
discipline; and the natural sciences, similarly subdivided), rather than ac-
cording to the persons for whom it is intended. One consequence of con-
ceiving it thus is that the transmission of knowledge can be organized ac-
cording to degree of difficulty: primary, secondary, tertiary, but in principle
accessible to all. By contrast, in India knowledge was always in the plural,
always took the form of so many knowledges and practices: esoteric and re-
stricted knowledges accessible only to some social groups, ‘‘practical’’ and
more widely available knowledges, varying according to caste and region and
religion, and none of all this organized as an ‘‘educational system.’’ Collec-
tively this situation yielded a riotous variety of knowledge practices, from
unstructured and occasional ones to more structured ‘‘institutions’’ such as
maktabs and madrassas and tols and pyal ‘‘schools’’ and patshalas and others,73
with knowledge passed on by gurumahashoys and pandits and pantojis and
maulvis and upadhyayas and acharyas—only some among the variety of words
for ‘‘teacher’’ or ‘‘learned man’’ in the subcontinent.Thus we cannot compare
modern knowledge with indigenous knowledge, but rather have to specify
to what we are choosing to refer among the various indigenous knowledges
(and the practices in which they were embedded and those through which
they were transmitted).
One type of knowledge with strictly coded and prescribed forms dictat-
ing how it was to be transmitted was knowledge of the Vedas, the sacred
Hindu texts that go back some three thousand years and more. Knowledge of
the Vedas was to be cultivated by those Brahmins whose task it was to recite
from the relevant sacred sources at sacrificial occasions, and to preserve the
Vedas through recitation.74 (The Vedas had been orally composed and have
been maintained, over an extraordinary time span, by oral transmission—
Vedic texts are srutis, truths meant to be heard, which were not committed to
writing till late in the day, and the tradition has injunctions against learning
them from writing.) Each Brahmin family which cultivated Vedic knowledge
had its own sutra, to be kept and passed on (but only to those considered
authorized to receive it) through svadhyaya, oral transmission. The archaic
Sanskrit in which the Vedas were composed was superseded by classical San-
skrit and then the various vernaculars, but they continue to be recited and
transmitted in their original form. It was to become a common criticism that
Changing the Subject 35
these Brahmins were in fact unlearned, for they did not understand what
they recited. Even Indians who sought to defend indigenous traditions were
sensitive to this charge, and either denied its truth or devised ingenious argu-
ments to explain and excuse it.75 But the criticism missed the point: the Vedas
are apauruseya, of nonhuman origin, and the words are the meaning—that is,
the meaning of the texts is imbricated with their sounds and the forms of
their recitation. Hence how they were said was all-important, and the sacred
texts include elaborate instructions on how they are to be recited—with what
accents, where the tone is to fall, and so on. In svadhyaya, Frits Staal explains,
‘‘there is no sharp distinction between word and meaning.’’ 76 This does not
mean that they have no meaning, or that the meaning is unimportant, but
rather that what the reciter and the Indologist understand by ‘‘meaning’’
might be two different things; and any approach predicated on the notion
that words express or represent a meaning anterior to them will always find
this to be ‘‘mere’’ memory.
It may be objected that this example is unilluminating, because this par-
ticular knowledge of theVedas (there are others) is essentially liturgical. I have
already noted that the subcontinent had knowledges rather than knowledge,
so let us then consider other forms.
Also part of subcontinental knowledges are arts or sciences, such as (what
we would call) grammars, logic, poetics, medicine, and astrology. These are
certainly not liturgical; they involve intellectual operations like interpreta-
tion and classification. For instance, a philosophy was extracted from (or read
into) the Vedas, producing Vedanta. Here ‘‘meaning’’ in a sense that we would
recognize is very much present. But even here, we should notice two impor-
tant differences when these knowledges are contrasted with modern ones,
apart from the obvious differences of content.
First, memory learning was still an essential component of these knowl-
edges.77 The mode of transmitting knowledge invariably required commit-
ting vast amounts of material to memory (the texts memorized were usually
composed in the form of verses, aphorisms, and other mnemonic forms, in-
dicating they were composed to be memorized); and memory learning in the
form of recitation and chanting was valorized by the traditions in which these
knowledges were embedded, in the form of injunctions to memorize, prayers
asking for the gift of memory, and rituals and initiation ceremonies.
The common ‘‘explanation’’ for the emphasis on memory learning is that
books and manuscripts were scarce, in other words that memory learning
was a ‘‘technique’’ necessitated by the shortcomings of technology. We are all
36 Subject to Pedagogy
familiar with Derrida’s argument that western metaphysics privileges speech
over writing; when it comes to historical understanding, however, we appar-
ently assume that speech and memory are what you have to take recourse to
in lieu of writing (else why does memory learning need ‘‘explaining’’ at all?).
But this explanation does not account for premodern traditions of learning
even in Europe, where (as in India) even after book manuscripts were made
more widely available, memory training did not become redundant. In the
high Middle Ages Thomas Aquinas had stored an extraordinary number of
‘‘texts’’ in his memory; Aquinas’s capacity was exceptional, but the phenome-
non was still common. Books themselves were for a long time conceived of as
mnemonics, as ‘‘memorial cues and aids,’’ and people often read books in order
to commit them to memory.78 In her important The Book of Memory: A Study of
Memory in Medieval Culture, Mary Carruthers tells us that in medieval Europe
memoria was not just a ‘‘technique,’’ necessitated by the absence of the print-
ing press, but an ethical practice, a discipline, and a way of developing char-
acter, judgment, and piety.79 The knowledges of the subcontinent were very
different from those of medieval Europe, but they shared this feature—that
memory was an essential component of knowledge—implying a different re-
lation between knower and known—not simply a technique necessitated by
the absence of technology.
The second feature to note about knowledges of these higher arts is the ex-
traordinary importance attached to forms or observances—to a stylistics and
a deportment—as distinct from the content of learning. This feature is seen
above all in the emphasis on absolute respect and devotion to the teacher.
Texts which discuss how knowledge is to be transmitted devote at least as
much attention to this aspect of it as to questions of method or ‘‘curricu-
lum.’’ Indeed, the question of how matters are best learned was in large part
answered by the injunction to respect and obey the teacher. Lessons were to
be commenced and concluded by having the student clasp the teacher’s feet
in his hands; and the injunction acarya devo bhava, ‘‘may your teacher be your
god,’’ was something every student knew.
We moderns have a ready-made explanation for this. Schooling, we will
say, is not just about the transmission of knowledge but also about social-
ization, and about power. The child who is enjoined to treat his teacher with
respect is receiving lessons in authority and order, over and above the knowl-
edge he receives. If we are moderns who are capable of subjecting our own
practices to the same critical scrutiny, we will add that the same is true of
modern schooling; the discipline of the school bell, of standing in line and
Changing the Subject 37
the like, instills the more abstract notions of order and authority which our
societies require and continually reproduce.
Such an explanation of indigenous education would not be beside the
point, but it would be grievously incomplete. Power and authority in India
there were aplenty, no doubt; but the limit of this explanation is reached
when we assume that modes of transmission are separable from the knowl-
edge transmitted. We assume this for our knowledges, because a defining
feature of modern knowledge is its formal character, the assumption that it
is in principle conceivable outside of the current network of relations (and
power) which characterizes the transmission of knowledge in most societies.
Rationalization in the Weberian sense means precisely this: that knowledge
is freed from substantive contexts and can be used ‘‘technically,’’ to match
means to ends. But the same is not true of the knowledges I am describing
here. In ‘‘traditional’’ learning the content and the form are indistinguish-
able: absorbing the ‘‘information’’ or mastering the ‘‘skills’’ is not the content,
with respect and awe for one’s teacher the form, the process through which
the knowledge happens to be transmitted; all are aspects of the same process.
The knowledge transmitted was not a separable ‘‘thing,’’ which happened to
be transmitted through the guru-shishya relation; it could only be transmit-
ted through that relation. This is not to say you cannot separate the two; some
of these knowledges have now been wrenched from their contexts and have a
new life as part of modern knowledge (for example, ayurvedic medicine), even
if usually at the fringes of it. We sometimes think that this characteristic—
that these knowledges can be reproduced in and through altogether different
contexts—goes to ‘‘prove’’ that theircontexts were so much window-dressing,
contingent and inessential form rather than substantive content. In fact, of
course, it proves nothing of the sort. We can treat machines and the knowl-
edge which produces them as magical, and worship them—people do—and
we do not thereby assume that this is their reality, and that scientific pro-
tocols and factories and laboratories are so much window-dressing, fetishes
obscuring the enchantment which is the truth of these machines.
Let us finally consider one more form, or class, of knowledge practices. I
have said that in the subcontinent knowledges were related to status, for the
more ritualized and specialized knowledges were not available to all—not just
‘‘in fact,’’ because of poverty and inequality, but ‘‘in principle.’’ The knowl-
edges described above fall into that category. But therewere other knowledges
which were suitable for almost all: for higher castes that might tarry briefly
before proceeding to acquire knowledges corresponding to their status, for
38 Subject to Pedagogy
trading castes, for occupations connected with administering land and col-
lecting revenue, and even, sometimes, for the children of tillers of the soil.
The patshala and pyal schools (whether of the ‘‘basic’’ sort or the more special-
ized sort which taught account keeping, writing business letters, and other
skills to children who were to go on to the hereditary profession of their
caste) often transmitted a knowledge which, unlike that described above, had
a practical value but little or no ritual status. Moreover, these schools often
did so in a manner which was exceedingly effective. The British authorities
were sometimes obliged to acknowledge as much, though they would usu-
ally add that this ‘‘success’’ was a form of failure. Almost all observers noted
that in indigenous schools the boys memorized their times-tables with ex-
traordinary facility. A senior official of the education department reported
that the traditional or ‘‘native’’ system of math instruction, which entailed
learning tables (including fractional tables) ‘‘up to an incredible standard,’’
combined with the use of rules of thumb or formulae ( gurs), ‘‘produce in the
pupil a capacity for rapid and certain calculation which would quite nonplus
an English schoolboy’’;80 and an article in the Calcutta Review on arithmetic
teaching in indigenous schools commented, ‘‘the method employed may not
be as rational as ours, but the practical result is a much greater facility in
simple calculations and account-keeping than is gained by the pupils of Gov-
ernment schools.’’ 81
Why, then, was this a shortcoming? Because the same students, asked to
do anything out of the ordinary, could not apply their arithmetic, just as
the students could sometimes read entire passages well, but on being asked
what they meant, often could not explain them, and sometimes did not even
know that the passages had a meaning beyond their recitation. That is, these
students confused knowledge with its application, and had no knowledge
outside its application. Our conception and practice of knowledge are very
different. To be sure, we too have ‘‘applied knowledges,’’ but each of these
is an application of a knowledge which is always in principle independent
of its uses. Indeed, the processes of rationalization mean that increasingly,
knowledges and skills which could once only be acquired ‘‘on the job,’’ and
which had no existence outside their use or application, are now deemed to
have a formal component, which is a knowledge like any other; their practical
component now presupposes a mastery of the theory of which the practical
component is the application. Nursing and tourism become university sub-
jects, knowledges which have to be learned in such a way that the students
can draw upon their stock of formal knowledge and ‘‘apply’’ it according to
Changing the Subject 39
context—each person his or her own casuist. One can see why for the modern
observer the Indian child’s facility with arithmetic, however impressive, was
deemed inadequate—to modern eyes a pedagogy which cannot produce the
ability to apply a general knowledge to specific cases is a failed pedagogy.
47
48 Subject to Pedagogy
existing system of education to develop the intellectual at the expense of the
moral and religious faculties,’’ and went so far as to declare the tendency ‘‘un-
questionably the most important educational problem of the time.’’ 2 This
claim marked the climax of the discourse on the ‘‘moral decline’’ and ‘‘moral
crisis’’ of the educated Indian—a discourse expressing the fear that the im-
provement consequent upon education had not in fact occurred, but rather
that educated Indians had become less moral, less pious, and less disciplined
than before. This discourse was coterminous with the beginnings of west-
ern education, and had been gaining in intensity since the last quarter of
the nineteenth century. By the early years of the new century ‘‘moral crisis’’
was a matter of almost obsessive debate; an Englishman observed that it was
the subject of mention in ‘‘every discussion on Indian education,’’ 3 while an
Indian educator complained that the subject of the ‘‘moral decline’’ of the
educated Indian, and the commonly proposed remedies of moral or religious
education, had become a ‘‘pest of the platform.’’ 4
Western knowledge was disseminated through schools and universities
because it was presumed superior to the indigenous knowledges it replaced.
In this chapter I examine how the same knowledge being disseminated in
schools and universities was also pressed into service to characterize and ex-
plain the moral decline of the educated Indian. Howadequatewas this knowl-
edge to explaining its own, unexpected effects? Could it comprehend and
account for its own failures? And more generally, what was the relation be-
tween western knowledge as a means for comprehending social changes in
India and western knowledge as one of the agents of that change?
This intellectual and moral confusion was attributed to the need of the
educated Indian to negotiate two distinct worlds, cultural domains charac-
terized and governed by radically different conceptions of how the world
worked, what a man’s place in it was, and what constituted moral behaviour.
Other observations and complaints—the much-lamented unpunctuality of
the educated Indian, and his alleged inability to identify his interests with
the institution of which he was a part, despite his acknowledged capacity to
identify with, and sacrifice his interests to, the joint family—were similarly
interpreted as arising out of his carrying the values, practices, and rituals of
the joint family and caste into the world of the law court, office, and univer-
sity. According to this explanation, the educated Indian had lost faith in the
governing presumptions and beliefs of traditional Indian society, without yet
being in a position to embrace the mores and presumptions governing mod-
ern, western life. We have already encountered this line of reasoning: have
heard Governor Sir George Clarke explaining that the ‘‘restraining forces’’ of
ancient India had lost their force among the educated, while the restraining
forces of the West had not taken their place, resulting in a net ‘‘moral loss’’;
and Keshab Chunder Sen and other Brahmos attributing moral decline to
the Hindu’s being ‘‘emancipated’’ from his own creed without having found
another to take its place. Many other voices joined in characterizing and ex-
plaining the moral crisis of the educated Hindu in similar terms. The Pioneer
observed: ‘‘we have introduced [the educated Bengali] to a literature which
Diagnosing Moral Crisis 59
at every page proves the foolishness of his old beliefs,’’ but have ‘‘given the
native no new religion whereon to found a new morality’’; the result was that
whereas ‘‘of old he had a moral code he felt he had to obey because he feared
the displeasure of the gods by whom he believed it had been promulgated,’’
now ‘‘the Hindu Pantheon has fallen, and with it all the Bengali ever had of
morality.’’ 53 A contributor to the Educational Review similarly attributed ‘‘the
slackness of discipline, want of self control and decay of the reverential spirit
in the life of the student’’ to the fact that ‘‘the old bonds of moral and reli-
gious sanctions are loosening and the new ones have not yet got sufficient
grip.’’ 54 The author of a history of education, denying that Bengali graduates
were more immoral than graduates of other countries, nonetheless conceded
that their education ‘‘loosened the hold on them of the conventions and de-
cencies of Indian society, while it did not or could not provide regulating
principles of equal authority or usefulness.’’ 55 And a witness explained to the
Hartog Commission, ‘‘We Indians are at present at a stage of transition and
we do not know where we are.The old religious beliefs, the old traditions, the
old culture is fast slipping away from our sight and we have yet to find and
assimilate a culture which we can call our own.’’ 56
The relations in question ‘‘are not the relations between an object and its
meaning, as we would say, or between a symbol and the idea for which it
stands.’’ 85
The ‘‘primitives’’ studied by Lévy-Bruhl and the Berber-speaking Kabyle of
Algeria discussed by Mitchell are of course societies very different from that
of India. I draw attention to them not to suggest a strict analogy, but rather to
suggest that where we see an apparent absence of logic, or a ‘‘symbolism’’ run
riot, we may in fact be observing a different logic at work,86 or an ontology
which is not accessible to knowledge or experience only through the cate-
gories of a collective mind. The latter point is one to which I shall return. But
for now, let us conclude by noting that even the idea of a unified self as the
source and site of ideas and of consciousness, seemingly so undeniable, was
a category not at all self-evident to every Hindu. It has often been observed
that the Hindu philosophical tradition has a ‘‘weak’’ conception of selfhood.87
(The Buddhist doctrines of anatman, or not-self, and dependent origination
go considerably further, denying that there is a reality corresponding to the
grammatical subject of verbs, and suggesting that the personality is not a
permanent self or subject but rather a temporary constellation composed of
five forces or skandas.)88 Persons are not indivisible, bounded units but are
‘‘dividual’’ or divisible, in the sense that they are themselves composed of sub-
stances and essences. These are absorbed and passed on through various ex-
changes: in McKim Marriot’s description, ‘‘To exist, dividual persons absorb
heterogenous material influences. They must also give out from themselves
particles of their own coded substances—essences, residues, or other active
influences—that may then reproduce in others something of the nature of
Diagnosing Moral Crisis 69
the persons in whom they have originated. Persons engage in transfers of
bodily substance-codes through parentage, through marriage, and through
services and other kinds of interpersonal contacts. They transfer coded food
substances by way of trade, payments, alms, feasts or other prestations.’’ 89 In
all this ‘‘the assumption of the easy, proper separability of action from actor,
of code from substance . . . that pervades both Western philosophy and West-
ern common sense . . . is generally absent.’’ 90 E. Valentine Daniel, in his study
of personhood among Tamil Hindus, describes how the Tamil villager seeks
to find an equilibrium between his own substance and the substance of vil-
lage, house, sexual partner, and so on. Again, each person himself is assumed
to be composed of substances which are exchanged, altered, and conducive
(or not) to good health and prosperity, and this militates against the easy-
going and ‘‘natural’’ presumption that while society, group, and family can
all be decomposed into individual persons, the person or self is not subject
to further division.
The gap or mismatch between the categories employed to diagnose ‘‘moral
decline’’ and the moral and religious life of Hindus would seem to extend
even to the self. Far from being the unified, indivisible seat of consciousness
and source of moral ideas and actions presumed by our categories, the Hindu
self appears as a ‘‘leaky’’ one, with porous boundaries.91
‘‘By compartmentalizing their lives in this way,’’ Singer writes, ‘‘they are
able to function both as good Hindus and as good industrialists.’’ 97 Whereas
the discourse of moral crisis purported to find that trafficking between the
world of universities and offices and the world of home and religious ritual
produced people who were troubled and even torn, Singer concludes that the
‘‘coexistence of the traditional and the modern in India have not produced
the ‘schism in the soul’ predicted by classical [modernization] theory.’’ 98 He
does so, however, by employing the same categories of understanding and
analysis as those used by the producers of the discourse of moral crisis. Thus
he uses the verb ‘‘categorized,’’ indicating that it is the agent who assigns the
norms of belief and action to different spheres; and he explains that the in-
dustrialist divides his norms into two compartments of his mind, applying
each to the relevant sphere of social action, rather as a bilingual speaker keeps
two languages in her head, using whichever is appropriate according to con-
text. The same categories which inform the analysis of moral inconsistency
are here employed to yield a diametrically opposed result.
In Provincializing Europe, Dipesh Chakrabarty discusses a Bengali text writ-
ten by Bhabanicharan Bandyopadhyaya, a Bengali Brahmin and magazine
editor. Kalikata kamalalaya (1823) stages a debate between a Brahmin living
and working in Calcutta and a newcomer from the countryside. The new-
comer gives voice to many of the anxieties of the time, for example that
Diagnosing Moral Crisis 73
making a living in the emergent ‘‘civil society’’ of colonial Calcutta entailed
neglecting ritual observances appropriate to a high-caste Hindu: that it en-
tailed the mixing of languages, clothes, food, and so on. The resident of Cal-
cutta concedes that there are those of whom this is true, but adds that good
Hindus manage to straddle two worlds: that of obligations and rituals to the
gods and one’s male ancestors, and that of (necessary) engagement with colo-
nial civil society in the course of pursuing worldly interests such as wealth
and power. They do so by seeking to erect and maintain boundaries between
these domains—for instance, they continue to perform their ritual duties
(adjusting the times when making one’s livelihood requires this), and they
do not stay at work longer than necessary. There is nothing here, according
to Chakrabarty, ‘‘that suggests any attraction to the idea that the time of the
household should keep pace with the time of the civil-political society. The
themes of discipline, routine, punctuality . . . are absent from kk [Kalikata
Kamalalaya]. If anything, there was an emphasis to the contrary. In the world
kk depicted, the householder never spent more time at office than was mini-
mally needed and concentrated on ministering to the needs of gods and an-
cestors.The self, in its highest form,was visualized as part of the male lineage,
kula, and was thus more tied to a mytho-religious practice of time than to the
temporality of secular history.’’ 99 The Brahmin who successfully negotiates
the world of colonial civil and political society and the Hindu world of ritual
and caste obligations (and the protagonist of kk concedes that there are those
who do not successfully do so) is not riven by conflict and inconsistency—
though here, as in Singer’s account, there is a palpable tension around the
allocation of time, since the limited number of hours in the day means that
compromises must be made. The protagonist of kk explains to his interlocu-
tor (in Chakrabarty’s words) ‘‘that in spite of the new structuring of the day
required by colonial civil society, the true Hindu strove to maintain a criti-
cal symbolic boundary between the three spheres of involvement and action
(karma) that defined life. These spheres were: daivakarma (action to do with
the realm of the gods), pitrikarma (action pertaining to one’s male ancestors),
and vishaykarma (actions undertaken in pursuit of worldly interests such as
wealth, livelihood, fame, and secular power).’’ 100 The practices belonging to
colonial civil society belong to vishaykarma, and ‘‘the city-dweller’s aim was to
prevent [these practices and the words and ideas associated with them] from
polluting the ritually purer domains in which one transacted with gods and
ancestors (daivakarma and pitrikarma).’’ 101
At first glance this may seem very similar to Singer’s account: the suc-
74 Subject to Pedagogy
cessful Brahmin is one who manages to ‘‘compartmentalize,’’ to straddle two
domains requiring different values and practices without being torn or con-
flicted. However, in Chakrabarty’s reading of this text there is nothing to sug-
gest that it is the Brahmin who assigns or ‘‘categorizes,’’ as if the continued
existence of these different realms were conjured up by and maintained in
the mind, or by ‘‘culture’’ as a sort of sedimented, collective mind. Rather,
the good Brahmin is one who maintains categorical distinctions which are
not of his making, but which precede his activities and understandings; they
are what endow human activities with their boundaries and meanings, what
make a meaningful human life possible. Daivakarma, pitrikarma, and vishay-
karma are not logical categories, features of the human mind, but rather onto-
logical ones: they are not what humans use to categorize and organize experi-
ence; they are what make meaningful and ethical experience possible in the
first place.
In chapter 1 we saw that the Indian student was accused of treating west-
ern education instrumentally, as something only pertaining to worldly suc-
cess. This ‘‘decision’’ by the student was usually seen as unfortunate, even
reprehensible; here, as in Singer’s reading, the presumption was that students
did the categorizing and assigning. If we attend to the evidence carefully,
though, we will notice that the guilty parties often explained their actions
by referring to existing realms similar to those employed by the protagonist
of kk. They distinguished between ‘‘arthakari vidya’’—knowledge pertaining
to artha (worldly affairs)—and knowledges pertaining to dharma (ethical and
lawful life) and kama (pleasure); or, as with the Muslim judicial official quoted
in chapter 1, between knowledge pertaining to duniya (worldly matters) and
that pertaining to din (religious matters). Here again, as in kk, these different
domains can be seen—and were seen by those who explained their actions in
these terms—not as ways of dividing up human realms and actions but as
existing categories towhich human actions, to be ethical, had to conform.The
judgment that western knowledge belonged to the realm of artha or duniya
(rather than dharma or kama or din) was made by the student; but it was not
the student who divided the world conceptually into these domains. To the
student, as with Kant or Durkheim, these categories were the precondition
for having meaningful experience, and also for living an ethical life. But for
the student, if not for Kant or Durkheim, these distinctions were part of an
existent order, part of the furniture of the world that had to be acknowledged
and adapted to, rather than categories of the ‘‘mind’’ or of Reason, by means
of which humans organize and order their world.
Diagnosing Moral Crisis 75
We have seen that the categories of our modern, western thought, even
where they were not adequate to their object, sometimes did become so. Some
Indians did come to endorse and contribute to the discourse of moral in-
consistency and crisis. Therefore it is perfectly possible, even plausible (the
plausibility of this does not rest upon our wholly endorsing Singer’s meth-
ods or his conclusions) that the world described in kk should have yielded to
the world described by Singer, one in which educated and ‘‘modern’’ Indians,
now possessed of mind and consciousness and an indivisible self, could ex-
perience conflict—or devise ways to avoid it. Such changes have undoubtedly
occurred; we are now better placed to specify the nature of the ‘‘transition.’’
A ‘‘Transcendental Presupposition’’
Historiography thus ‘‘encodes’’ anthropological presumptions with specific
reference to the object that it constructs and of which it purports to offer
knowledge, namely the human past. Historiography is by no means the only
site where this epistemic and cultural transformation, one which marks the
birth of modern, western knowledge and culture, came to be effected. The
transformation in question is very much wider. One after another, modern
writers of diverse philosophical affiliations, working from within different
disciplines—Vico, Herder,Tylor, Cassirer, Geertz, Dilthey, Greenblatt and the
‘‘New Historicists,’’ and numerous others—testify that behind most things
lurks Man; that art and literature, religion and morality and myth, law and
custom, and common sense are all ‘‘products,’’ ‘‘expressions,’’ or ‘‘traces’’ of
‘‘societies’’ or ‘‘peoples’’ or ‘‘cultures.’’ I have designated this shift, in short-
hand, as anthropology-humanism. As observed, what precise form these pre-
sumptions take varies, across authors and also across disciplines. The differ-
ences are important, but underlying them is a more basic commonality, a
shared epistemological space. Max Weber characterized it thus: ‘‘The tran-
scendental presupposition of every cultural science . . . is that we are cultural
beings, endowed with the capacity and the will to take a deliberate attitude
towards the world and to lend it significance.’’ 52
I cite Weber not only because ‘‘transcendental presupposition’’ is a particu-
larly apt formulation, but also because Weber recognizes that the adoption of
this presupposition marks a cultural and epistemic transformation. This is
precisely the transformation which we discussed in the Introduction, a shift
from seeing the world as a text, imbued with meaning and purpose, of which
men, as creatures made in God’s image and endowed with grace and reason,
are privileged readers, to the view of the world as a social text of which men
are the authors. In Weber’s account this presupposition arises with the ‘‘dis-
enchantment of the world,’’ as modern men and women in the Occident rec-
ognize that they are cultural beings who endow the world with significance
precisely because, and in proportion to the extent to which, they are forced to
recognize the absence of meanings already in the world, waiting to be ‘‘dis-
covered’’: ‘‘The fate of an epoch which has eaten of the tree of knowledge is
Which Past? Whose History? 95
that it must know that we cannot learn the meaning of the world from the
results of its analysis, be it ever so perfect; it must rather be in a position to
create this meaning itself.’’ 53 This has not always been presumed, and thus
this disenchanted outlook has a history, consisting in the specific form that
rationalization took in Occidental religions, culminating in Protestantism
and the social and scientific developments with which it was associated.
But if the realization that we endow meaning upon the world has a his-
tory, in what sense is this a transcendental presupposition? That is, if it is borne
of the specific history of the modern West, how can it be said to be a pre-
supposition of universal import? For example, if in the past men and women
in Europe saw God as the source of reality and of meaning, whereas we dis-
enchanted moderns do not, then by what warrant do we privilege our pre-
supposition, and conclude that their God has to be understood and explained
as meanings with which they endowed their world, rather than as that which
gave them life and the world meaning? And by what right to we do so for
the nonwestern world, which may not have undergone the same processes of
rationalization, culminating in the disenchantment of the world?
The answer, according to Weber, is that while we moderns have come to
see the world as disenchanted because of a very specific (Occidental) history,
humans have always been the producers of meanings and purposes, even
when they have not realized it. David Kolb writes, ‘‘In Weber’s eyes, moder-
nity is an explicit recognition of what the self and society have been all along.
Modern identity is not just another in a sequence of historic constructions;
it is the unveiling of what has been at the root of these constructions.’’ 54
From this perspective, it is enchantment, as intellectual ‘‘error,’’ that needs
‘‘explaining’’; the disenchantment of the world, while it has a history, is the
truth finally uncovered. Like other moderns,Weber sees modernity as a privi-
leged vantage point that finally makes comprehensible all the history that
preceded it—a point to which we shall return in the Epilogue.
Weber’s analysis of disenchantment is deeply indebted to Nietzsche.When
Nietzsche has a madman announce the death of God, and when he announces
the advent of nihilism and the destruction of values, he too is announcing
that belief in a transcendent realm of values, in God, in Platonism, is near-
ing its end. At times he sounds like an upbeat Weber, one who welcomes and
celebrates this development, because it allows man to recognize as his that
which he once attributed to others: ‘‘All the beauty and sublimity we have
bestowed upon real and imaginary things I will reclaim as the property and
product of man; as his fairest apology. Man as poet, as thinker, as God, as
96 Subject to Pedagogy
love, as power; O, with what regal liberality he has lavished gifts upon things,
only to impoverish himself and make himself feel wretched! His most unself-
ish act hitherto was to admire and worship and to know how to conceal from
himself that it was he who created all that he admired.’’ 55 The transcendent
values to which men have subordinated themselves have in fact always been
their own products; every discovery was in fact an invention, every interpre-
tation a new creation. Nietzsche sees in the advent of nihilism the possibility
of a freedom to revalue all values, recognizing them all as human creations,
borne of a will to power. But there is an important difference, and it does
not simply lie in Nietzsche’s tendency to view with gaiety and lightness what
Weber announces with foreboding. The Genealogy of Morals and other writ-
ings provide also a genealogy of the subject, not as a natural being whose
essence is to be possessed of consciousness and the capacity to create meaning
but as someone created to be able to make promises, feel guilt, subscribe to
values, and the like.Thus for Nietzsche—albeit inconsistently so—the subject
is not the source and origin of meaning and value but is himself a histori-
cal product, forged on the anvil of Christian morality and Roman law. Weber
assumes that the value-creating or culture-secreting individual has always
existed, but only becomes aware of himself as such in modern times, whereas
for Nietzsche this individual is himself a creation or invention. The differ-
ence is significant, because if the presumption that humans are the source of
all values and meanings is in fact historically and culturally produced, then
we may not be entitled to presuppose it where such a subject has not been
created.
This, as we saw in the Introduction, is Heidegger’s position. Heidegger
rejects all talk of Weltanschauung and of different ways of ‘‘picturing’’ the
world precisely because it assumes that men have always pictured the world
and ascribed value to it. The difference between the medieval and modern
worlds is not, however, that modern men and women picture the world dif-
ferently and have different values. To see the world as picture, to have values
and cultures and experiences, is not to have a set of transcendental presuppo-
sitions which have finally come into their own, but rather is a consequence of
cultural and epistemic shifts, including the rise of a metaphysics of subjec-
tivity that Heidegger labels ‘‘anthropology’’: ‘‘That the world becomes picture
is one and the same event with the event of man’s becoming subiectum . . .
the more extensively and the more effectively the world stands at man’s dis-
posal as conquered, and the more objectively the object appears, all the more
subjectively . . . does the subiectum rise up, and all the more impetuously,
Which Past? Whose History? 97
too, do observation and teaching about the world change into a doctrine of
man, into anthropology. It is no wonder that humanism first arises where
the world becomes picture . . . Humanism, therefore, in the more strict histo-
riographical sense, is nothing but a moral aesthetic anthropology. The name
‘anthropology’ as used here . . . designates that philosophical interpretation
of man which explains and evaluates whatever is, in its entirety, from the
standpoint of man and in relation to man.’’ 56
The contemporary anti-humanists who are the heirs of Nietzsche and
Heidegger similarly insist that man, far from always having been a value-
creating and meaning-producing being who with modernity finally becomes
aware of that fact, is himself a historically produced, and possibly transient,
consequence of contingent historical events. One effect of their analyses is
that historiography is immediately rendered problematic: if Man is a product
of history, he cannot be the constant whose changes and transformations it
retells. Indeed, analyses of this sort reverse our normal sequence of cause and
effect, suggesting that Man is the subject of anthropology and history not be-
cause he is the origin and source of meaning and values, but rather that this
presupposition and its correlates, embedded in our culture and our thought,
serve to create and secure humanism and anthropology. Historiography is
one of the important means by which, and sites upon which, this process
is achieved. ‘‘Making historical analysis the discourse of the continuous and
making human consciousness the original subject of all historical develop-
ment and all action,’’ according to Michel Foucault, ‘‘are two sides of the same
system of thought,’’ one characterized by ‘‘the sovereignty of the subject and
the twin figures of anthropology and humanism.’’ 57 Indeed, history writing
has an especially important function to fulfill, for as this humanism and an-
thropology have come to be assailed in the studyof language, myth, sexuality,
and kinship, historiography becomes ‘‘the last resting-place of anthropologi-
cal thought,’’ 58 or in Lévi-Strauss’s words, ‘‘the last refuge of a transcendental
humanism.’’ 59
I am asking what it means, using the code of history, to write about those
who do not live by that code or recognize themselves in it. I have argued that
this question arises with reference not only to the nonwestern world but also
to premodern Europe. To explain the world of men and women of medieval
times historically is to translate their understandings into our terms or, to
repeat Certeau’s words, to ‘‘postulate a coding which inverts that of the time
we are studying.’’ However, this exercise, while anachronistic, is nonetheless
productive; even where we cannot accept the ‘‘truth’’ of texts from the past,
we gain better self-understanding, that is, understanding of the tradition
out of which we reason.
The same is not true when we apply the code of history to Indian pasts,
for the simple reason that the object of enquiry does not belong to the same
tradition as the enquiring subject.70 To write a history of India from within
western knowledge is to confront the fact that the ‘‘now’’ from which we
write is not itself linked in a thousand ways to the ‘‘then’’ of those of whom
we write, because a profound caesura has occurred: the tradition from which
we write is not the same as that of which we write. The threads connecting
the subject and the object have snapped; western education, and the rational-
ist historiography which it produced and which it sanctions, do not bear the
same relation to India as the knowledge(s) disseminated and the tradition(s)
once cultivated in the madrassa and the tol. Thus what might validate the
anachronism which is an inescapable feature of historiography even when it
encounters European pasts does not apply here, because here history ‘‘finds
the present in its object,’’ but it does not find an Indian ‘‘past in its practice.’’
The knowledge from which we write a history of India—in this case, a his-
tory of western education in India—is not continuous with the knowledges
of India. These intellectual traditions had not died of inanition when the
British first came to India; as we shall see in chapter 6, around the period that
Which Past? Whose History? 103
Conring was writing there was an explosion of scholarly writing in Sanskrit,
testifying to the vitality of an extraordinarily long and continuous intellec-
tual tradition. Some of the navya or new scholars of the seventeenth century
self-consciously saw themselves as effecting innovations; but they were still
heirs to a tradition going back two millennia, which they actively engaged,
disputed with, and developed. The same is not true of historiography, for
neither the Sanskrit tradition nor any other indigenous tradition found an
echo in the code of history which we now use to write of Indian pasts. This
code was an imposition, an act of ‘‘epistemic violence,’’ to borrow a phrase
from Gayatri Spivak. It did not engage with Indian traditions, did not re-
fute them and thereby displace them. Its victory was won cheaply—through
a colonial administrative fiat. As a result, the code of history cannot even
fulfill the hermeneutic function that it fills elsewhere, that of being one
of the modes by which men and women of the West can, through the self-
consciously anachronistic exercise of translating the lives and worlds of their
dead forebears into their own terms, illuminate both what connects and what
separates them from this past and these forebears. In India that role con-
tinued to be performed by the genealogist, the balladeer, and the storyteller,
who interpreted and refurbished the tradition to which they belonged, by re-
telling the past.71 The historian, however,was closer to the position of colonial
officials (many of whom, like James Mill and Macaulay, were also historians);
she was discontinuous with, and in a position of pure externality to, the pasts
of which she wrote.
‘‘Seeing’’ Backwardness
Why did the issue of Muslim backwardness come to be foregrounded? The
common answer, first given by nationalists, is that the British policy of ‘‘di-
vide and rule’’ was behind the colonial government’s sudden solicitude for
its Muslim subjects. For a section of the Muslim élites this newfound con-
cern was useful, because the emphasis on religious differences within South
Asia allowed them to pose as leaders of ‘‘their’’ community, and gave them an
importance and influence to which they could not otherwise lay claim. Our
concern is not with the substance of this argument, however, but rather with
a prior, epistemological question: What made it possible for ‘‘backwardness’’
to emerge as an object of knowledge? What were the enabling ‘‘epistemic con-
ditions’’ that made it possible to pose the question of Muslim backwardness,
let alone posit it as a pressing problem in need of solution?
The importance of statistics stands out, since the discourse of the ‘‘back-
ward Muslim’’ was made possible by numbers, conducted through numbers,
Governmentality and Identity 117
and indeed obsessed with numbers. The issue of Muslim educational back-
wardness first became a public concern around the time of the first all-Indian
census.This concern was in part reflected in how figures were collected,39 and
of course the census made it possible to pursue, and seek to prove or disprove,
the fact of Muslim backwardness. Religion appeared as a fundamental cate-
gory in the census, one that was cross-tabulated against a number of others—
sex, marital status, occupation (after 1881), and education. Numbers on Mus-
lim backwardness proliferated, as concern occasioned by it soon generated
further figures. The Indian Education (Hunter) Commission, confirming the
fact of Muslim backwardness, had recommended that to keep track of this
backwardness, and of the efficaciousness of measures adopted to remedy it,
the annual reports on progress in education should have a section specially
devoted to Muslims. A resolution by the Government of India in July 1885
mandated this, specifying that educational reports must provide informa-
tion on ‘‘the position and advancement of the Muhammadan community,
not merely as a whole, but with reference to local variations, in order that the
Government of India may be kept fully informed as to the state and progress
of this important section of the community.’’ 40 It is perhaps more than a co-
incidence that W. W. Hunter, who was so frequent and important a contribu-
tor to the discourse of Muslim backwardness, was also, as director general of
statistics, the compiler of many of the statistics that he mobilized. It was soon
after completing his labors of compiling the Imperial Gazetteer that Hunter
took on the role of chairman of the Indian Education Commission.
The importance of information, and of figures in particular, was not a fact
recognized only by government. The ‘‘Aims and Objectives’’ of the Muham-
madan Educational Congress, drafted by Sir Sayyid in 1886, observed that
‘‘people in one district . . . know little about the state of education of Mahome-
dans in other districts; they do not know whether their co-religionists outside
their own local circle are going forward or backward, and what are the causes
of the same.’’ It was to enable Muslims from various parts of India to gain an
overall picture of the state of Muslim education, and to allow them to ‘‘meet
together to converse on the subject of national education, and think over the
means by which it may be advanced,’’ that an annual meeting was necessary.
Delegates from districts, Sir Sayyid went on to suggest, should ‘‘read before
the meeting a statistical report of the condition of Musalmans in their dis-
tricts,’’ which among other topics would cover the number of Muslims in the
district, their residence (urban or rural), their general condition, the number
and types of schools and colleges, the kind of education imparted in them,
118 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
and the number of Muslims being educated in them.41 At one point there was
even an attempt at a nongovernmental census. In 1893 Theodore Beck, prin-
cipal of the Muhammadan Anglo-Oriental College, launched a ‘‘Mahomedan
Educational Census,’’ seeking to mobilize ‘‘public spirited Mahomedans’’ to
go door to door to collect information from their co-religionists of a type and
at a level of detail not covered by the census. The information collected was
to be used to urge and cajole those Muslims who had not been educating
their sons to begin doing so if they had the means. This was only to be the
first step: ‘‘The work of this Census must take at least ten years’ steady effort.
Money, clerks, statistics, books, pamphlets—the apparatus of this Census will
become in itself a great organization.’’ 42
Beck’s grandiose vision was never realized, but the annual sessions of the
Muhammadan Educational Conference did function, among other things, as
an occasion to hear reports on the educational status of Muslims, sometimes
in mind-numbing detail. The original text of what later became an ample-
sized book on the history of western education in India, and especially on the
education of Muslims, was delivered as a lecture in two parts by Syed Mah-
mood at the eighth and ninth annual sessions at Aligarh, in 1893 and 1894;
each lecture lasted five hours.
Statistics were thus critical to posing the problem of Muslim backward-
ness. However, it is not that statistics allowed the state to finally ‘‘see’’ and
measure what was always there. Historians and philosophers of science have
been at the forefront of cautioning against the variety of epistemological naï-
veté that assumes the objects of new knowledges to have always already been
there, only awaiting the rise of the knowledge that would unveil them and
bring them into view. In fact the discoveries made in the laboratory, for in-
stance, are products of specific technologies; it is usually impossible to distin-
guish whether they are ‘‘discovered’’ or ‘‘produced.’’ 43 Georges Canguilhem
points out that sickness, as experienced and understood by the sick person,
is different from disease, which comes to be known as a statistical deviation
from socially normative, ‘‘average’’ states.44 The latter understanding is not
one naturally and immediately available to ordinary consciousness; it is one
of ‘‘various kinds of cognition that are the historical accomplishments of spe-
cific intellectual technologies,’’ and the cognitions are not available in the
absence of the technologies.45 With regard to Muslim backwardness, statistics
were the ‘‘intellectual technology’’ that enabled the cognition of backward-
ness.
To say that backwardness is a phenomenon produced by rather than
Governmentality and Identity 119
simply measured by statistics is still, however, not a complete characteriza-
tion of the epistemic conditions which made it possible to ‘‘see’’ the ‘‘fact’’
of Muslim backwardness. We can further pursue this question by means of a
contrast with indigenous education. Many Muslims, we know, received ‘‘in-
struction’’ of different types and in different settings: maktabs, madrassas, pat-
shalas, mosques where they learned to recite quranic verses from a learned
man, and so on. These forms of instruction were a feature of Indian society
up to and after the introduction of modern, western education. It was often,
though not always, an explicit object of this instruction to pass on and re-
produce the values and norms of communities characterized, among other
things, by their adherence to Islam.46 Indeed, if ‘‘Muslim’’ and ‘‘education’’
are to be juxtaposed, they were more meaningfully juxtaposed here than in
the nonreligious education system authorized by the British.
However, the problem of ‘‘Muslim backwardness’’ could not be posed
from within this system of instruction. Why not? Because although the ma-
drassa and the maktab did indeed contain a conception of ‘‘Muslim’’ as tran-
scending the limits of class and region, it did not easily imagine this as a
subset of a wider social field. As we had occasion to observe earlier, ‘‘educa-
tion’’ in colonial India was not predicated upon a conception of society as
a horizontal field, as a population, but rather as a series of segmented and
hierarchically organized domains with correspondingly different needs and
practices. Consequently, ‘‘education’’ was not conceived of as the transmis-
sion of a unitary body of knowledge but rather as different knowledges and
different forms of instruction for different social groups—tols and maktabs
and madrassas, maulvis teaching recitation of Quranic verses in the mosque,
village patshalas providing some very basic skills, specialized patshalas pro-
viding instruction for certain professions and castes, and so on. Within this
learning, the unified social field which makes judgments about backward-
ness and forwardness possible was lacking. This social field became thinkable
only with the emergence of an educational ‘‘system’’ which presupposed the
object, ‘‘population.’’
The intellectual field in which comparisons could be made and backward-
ness discovered—including educational backwardness—was thus provided
by the idea of population. Population in turn becomes available as an object
for cognition, measurement, and regulation from a particular perspective (it
too is not an object for practical consciousness), and the perspective is that of
the state, a state concerned with the health, productivity, and numbers of the
population it governs. ‘‘Backwardness,’’ statistics, and population thus imply
120 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
each other, and they all imply the presence of a state with a particular kind
of relation to its subjects.
Colonial Governmentality
That state is the ‘‘governmentalized’’ state discussed by Michel Foucault. In
his later published works and in his lectures at the Collège de France, Fou-
cault traced a shift from a power coded in the form of sovereignty, operating
through juridical means and having as its ultimate exercise the taking of
life, to a new power that ‘‘gave itself the function of administering life,’’ ‘‘a
power whose highest function was perhaps no longer to kill, but to invest
life through and through.’’ 47 This new power was one that sought to safe-
guard and promote the health, productivity, and happiness of the population,
as a way of maximizing the wealth and power of the state. The ‘‘transition
which takes place in the eighteenth century . . . from a regime dominated by
structures of sovereignty to one ruled by techniques of government,’’ Fou-
cault writes, ‘‘turns on the theme of population.’’ 48 Foucault names this new
form of power ‘‘governmentality,’’ a neologism suggesting a particular ratio-
nality which came to underpin the exercise of government. However, this
new rationality of government was distinguished from sovereignty not only
by its solicitude toward the health and productivity and even happiness of its
population (hence the importance of statistics, to produce knowledge of the
population—their numbers, longevity, health and ill health, rates of mor-
tality), but also in that it recognized that it was not possible for the state
to completely regulate the population. If the health of the state depended
upon the well-being of its population, this was best secured by governmental
regulation and by paying scrupulous attention to the development of indi-
vidual capacities for self-regulation. This new power worked upon people as
aggregates, as ‘‘population,’’ but also as individuals; through the regulation
of populations, but also through freedom. Foucault neither denounces this
liberty as an ideological delusion nor accepts the liberal naturalization of it,
but rather seeks to analyze, in the words of one of his interpreters, ‘‘the con-
ditions under which the practice of freedom is possible,’’ 49 conditions which
are shown to be intimately linked with (rather than at odds with) the mod-
ern state.
Part of the explanatory power of the Foucauldian account of governmen-
tality lies precisely in its affording the possibility of understanding a defining
and yet seemingly paradoxical feature of the modern world, namely that an
Governmentality and Identity 121
immense increase in the reach and intervention of the state has often been
accompanied by the creation of a certain field of individual liberty. The para-
dox dissolves in Foucault’s account, because the two go hand in hand in the
form of a governmental rationality that governs through freedom. Analysis
need not be locked in a sterile antithesis where it constantly counterpoises
individual liberty to governmental regulation, presuming that the advance
of the one must mean the diminution of the other. Liberal and radical ana-
lyses of the development of modern education, Ian Hunter points out, are
usually organized around a similar antithesis, ‘‘organised around an oppo-
sition between a pedagogy ‘imposed’ by social utility or political necessity
and one developed ‘for its own sake’ as part of the self-realisation of ‘man’
or the ‘universal class.’ ’’ 50 Depending upon one’s understanding of the social
system of which education is a part, one can then either conclude that at
some point education was finally freed of its subordination to social utility
and allowed to fulfill its proper function of individual self-development,
or that this is still a task to be completed. Once thought is liberated from
this opposition, Hunter argues, we can recognize that the development of
popular education in nineteenth-century England did not oscillate between
this ‘‘exemplary opposition between the self-realising and the utilitarian,
the self-expressive and the normative’’;51 nineteenth-century educational re-
formers like David Stow and Kay-Shuttleworth explicitly proposed a model
of popular education in which ‘‘moral norms would be realised through self-
expressive techniques . . . [and] forms of self-discovery organised around the
individual would permit the realisation of new social norms at the level of
population.’’ 52 Indeed, the importance attached to education derived from
precisely its status as a site where administering the population and incul-
cating habits and techniques of freedom and self-regulation, by which indi-
vidual members of the population would administer themselves, could be
combined. The educational system that emerged in England was a ‘‘distinc-
tive governmental apparatus formed . . . in an unprecedented investigative
and administrative network which made the ‘moral and physical’ condition
of the population into an object of government. It was in this network that
the old techniques of pastoral surveillance aimed at the individual soul, and
new forms of social discipline aimed at whole populations, could combine to
form the technology of moral training.’’ 53
As has often been noted, there are parallels between the processes de-
scribed by Foucault and developments in colonial India from about the latter
third of the nineteenth century, when the forms and scope of colonial power
122 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
were extensively reorganized. In this period the censuses were begun, the law
codified, bureaucracy reorganized and rationalized, and ‘‘a whole apparatus of
specialized technical services was instituted in order to scientifically survey,
classify, and enumerate the geographical, geological, botanical, zoological,
and meteorological properties of the natural environment and the archaeo-
logical, historical, anthropological, linguistic, economic, demographic and
epidemiological characteristics of the people.’’ 54 However, those who have
noted and drawn attention to these parallels have also insisted that there
are important differences between governmentality in the metropolis and
its operations in the colonies. The ‘‘colonial’’ in ‘‘colonial governmentality’’
needs to be understood as an adjective designating the ways in which the
specificities of colonial rule qualified the functioning and character of gov-
ernmentality.55 How did it do so?
While it is premised upon a technology which seeks to govern through
freedom, liberal governmentality, as Barry Hindess reminds us, has always
also included a large number of people who are governed illiberally: ‘‘If we
were to do a head count of those subjected to liberal rule, we would have to say
that before the middle of the twentieth century, the vast majority consisted
of those who [it was thought] would benefit from being subjected to authori-
tarian rule: the subject peoples of western imperial rule and, throughout the
nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, substantial groups in western soci-
eties themselves.’’ 56 The central justification for this view was the presump-
tion ‘‘that the capacities required for autonomous conduct and the social con-
ditions that foster and sustain them can be developed in a population only
through compulsion, through the imposition of more or less extended peri-
ods of discipline.’’ 57 This was of course the prime justification for colonialism
in its heyday—the idea that colonial rule was necessary to foster ‘‘moral and
material improvement,’’ and that an extended period of tutelage was neces-
sary in order that one day natives might be capable of autonomous conduct
and self-rule. We could dismiss these justifications of colonial rule as hypoc-
risy and bad faith, which indeed they were; but at the same time we need to
recognize that they had real effects in shaping the character and function-
ing of colonial rule. Colonial governmentality functioned to at once posit the
possibility and desirability of governance through liberty, but always within
a frame where that possibility was deferred, and where autonomous conduct
was not possible—yet.
Education occupied an especially privileged place in this constellation.
We have seen that the knowledge diffused through western education, and
Governmentality and Identity 123
the practices associated with this diffusion, did posit a subject capable of
making knowledge his own; and that the concern with ‘‘moral development,’’
with the capacity to make judgments and decisions by reference to clear
and rationally derived criteria, was also very much present. The notions of
orderand orderliness which accompany this conception of the self-regulating
subject were also present, as became apparent whenever modern education
was contrasted with ‘‘indigenous education.’’ The latter was denounced for
being autocratic, but at the same time seen as highly disorderly. Lieuten-
ant T. B. Jervis of the Statistical Survey complained that at the indigenous
schools he had observed in the Bombay Presidency, pupils ‘‘sit without order,
or distinction into classes and leave their work when called for to assist their
young companions, thereby occasioning much confusion and hindrance to
others.’’ 58 The secretary to the Bengal Council of Education described his
visit to an indigenous school, where the students ‘‘were squatting upon the
clay floor, without order or regularity,’’ and contrasted it to a government-
established vernacular school across the way, which held its classes ‘‘in a
neat, open, small puckah [permanent] building,’’ and where the activities of
the students displayed ‘‘order, regularity and earnestness.’’ 59 In the modern,
government-funded or government-inspected schools, discipline and order
were thought to go hand in hand with self-regulation, for the discipline in
question was self-discipline; in indigenous schools harsh authoritarianism
and disorder went hand in hand, for an external and coercively imposed au-
thority could only operate intermittently and harshly, and therefore ineffec-
tively.
Colonial governmentality, we might say, functioned to posit the possi-
bility of self-governance and incite the desire for it, while simultaneously de-
claring it unachievable—for now. At the same time, and with perhaps greater
success, it facilitated the emergence of new collective identities.
Being Muslim
Anticolonial nationalism is South Asia succeeded in producing not one but
two nations. Why this should have been so, and how and why the bloodbath
of Partition occurred, have been among the central questions in the histori-
ography of modern South Asia. Education has sometimes been held respon-
sible for having widened the divide between Hindu and Muslim, and there
is a certain plausibility about attributing Hindu-Muslim divisions to edu-
cational and occupational disparities, because these accord neatly with the
124 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
emergence and organizational expression of new interests and voices. One of
the first Muslim organizations of the new and modern (voluntary and asso-
ciational) type to be established, the Muhammadan Educational Conference,
was founded, as we saw, to further the cause of Muslim education; but it
soon came to present itself as the Muslim counterpart and competitor to
the Indian National Congress, founded the year before. The Muslim League,
formed in 1906, was the child of the Muhammadan Educational Conference,
to which it functioned as an adjunct for the first few years of its existence.
Given all this, it is tempting to explain communal separatism as partlyarising
out of educational inequality between the two communities, an inequality
which translated into unequal access to the new sources of status and ad-
vancement, and the attempts to redress which (through organizational forms
such as Muslim associations, and government policies treating Muslims as a
distinct group) only exacerbated the communal divide.
Here I have not joined the historical debate over whether Indian Mus-
lims were ‘‘in fact’’ backward or not,60 nor have I speculated on whether and
how their alleged backwardness contributed to divisions along communal
lines. I have instead sought to explore the epistemic conditions that made
it possible and necessary to cross-tabulate ‘‘Muslim’’ and ‘‘education,’’ and
produce the figure of the backward Muslim. The production of statistics was
clearly a necessary condition, but statistics did not simply enable one to see
the fact of backwardness, and measure it, but embodied a particular per-
spective from which this fact could both be brought into being as a fact and
seen as such. The perspective was that of the governmentalized state, which
governs a population.
But as should be apparent, the ‘‘perspective’’ that made backwardness
visible only did so inasmuch as it also entailed conceiving of ‘‘Muslim’’ in a
new way. The peoples of South Asia, belonging to castes, religious communi-
ties, village communities, and so on, were reconceived once these came to be
seen as subsets of the more inclusive category, ‘‘population.’’ David Lelyveld
writes that
there were many ways to construe group identity among the people of
India. Labels existed on many levels of generality and cut across each
other in complicated ways. Those based on birth might involve a wide
range of identities, from household to property holding group, to lin-
eage, to endogamous group to a far-flung cultural category supposedly
indicating shared status. A person might also be labeled by locality—a
Governmentality and Identity 125
section of a village, a village, a cluster of villages, an old administra-
tive unit, a large geographic region. Language identification was simi-
larly ambiguous, because most Indians had command of a whole con-
tinuum of linguistic styles and dialects. Religious designations were
often unclear; below the surface of the well-known scriptural religions
one might detect an immense variety of ritual practices and objects
of worship, some purely local, others amalgamating widely different
great traditions. What is more, many of these labels were outsiders’
constructs, unfamiliar to the people they purported to describe.61
Sudipta Kaviraj describes these forms of group belonging as ‘‘fuzzy com-
munities,’’ communities without a strong sense of boundaries, and commu-
nities which did not ask ‘‘how many of them there were in the world.’’ 62 They
were also fuzzy because in them identities were relational and varied accord-
ing to context, whereas colonial categorizations of these identities assumed
so many isolated corporate groups which then entered into relations with one
another. The Muslim was at once member of an ummah, a worldwide com-
munity of the faithful, and someone who belonged to a particular locale, to a
subcommunity, spoke one or more of several possible languages, and (in some
regions of the subcontinent) was a member of the high-status ashraf class or
the plebian ajlaf. Life was lived as a network of dense and complicated hierar-
chical relations that usually made one’s identity relationally determined, and
changing according to context, rather than fixed in the manner presupposed
by enumeration.This was a fact registered, for instance, in the names of Mus-
lim ashraf, which apart from a personal name also had prefixes and suffixes in-
dicating (in lieu of a surname) their ‘‘title,’’ their lineage or local connections,
and sometimes other information, such as the place with which their family
was connected. Biographies and autobiographies are a good guide to this,
for they give the texture of such a complex and shifting range of identity-
positions in a fashion that the social sciences, products of the modern that
seek to grasp the modern, seldom can.63
The discourse of the ‘‘backward Muslim’’ not only brought into being a
backwardness that was not thinkable and seeable in precolonial society, but
in so doing it also and equally abstracted from the differences of region, class,
and culture that characterized the Muslims of South Asia. Thus in reconsti-
tuting the category Muslim the discourse of the backward Muslim—enabled
by statistics, and representing the perspective of the governmental state—
also made it available to practical consciousness, and in doing so made it pos-
126 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
sible for others to think and be Muslim in a different way. As a result edu-
cation figured not only as the site where a ‘‘colonial bourgeois subject’’ was
posited but also as a site where new forms of collective identity were enabled.
Education proved to be transformative, but not, as modernization theory
would have it, because the modern knowledge disseminated through it re-
placed pre-modern superstition with modern Reason, thereby transforming
the ‘‘traditional’’ Muslim into the modern Muslim. Education proved impor-
tant rather because modern, western education, unlike the maktab and the
madrassa, was tied up with the governmental practices of the colonial state,
and thus was a site for elaborating new ways of understanding and governing
the ‘‘population.’’ Through the material changes they effected, these ways of
understanding then became available to sections of that population. It is not
that Muslims were ‘‘transformed’’ or remade into modern subjects (though
no doubt some were), but rather that new ways of being Muslim became pos-
sible. To what extent these possibilities were grasped, and by whom, varied.
In this explanation, unlike in modernization theory, there is no inevitability
about these processes. The caution issued by Appadurai, with which we be-
gan—that whether the self-perceptions of those enumerated and classified
in these ways changed, and how much so, depended upon a range of circum-
stances—is very much to the point. For many it is no doubt true, as Ayesha
Jalal concludes in her study of Muslim conceptions of selfhood in South Asia,
that the meaning given to Muslim identity through colonial schemes of enu-
meration ‘‘remained more of an abstract legal category’’ than a living social
entity.64 Perhaps the greatest proof of this is that Muslim reformers like Sir
Sayyid spent much of their time berating their fellow Muslims for continu-
ing to be mired in petty minutiae and disputes—that is, for failing to discard,
and rise above, the local allegiances and conflicts that gave shape and texture
to their lives as Muslims.
But at the same time, this new way of being Muslim shaped others’ proj-
ects for their own and their community’s future. The idea of the backward
Muslim, which presumed and made possible a new way of thinking ‘‘Mus-
lim,’’ also made it possible to conceive of, and conceive the desire for, the
‘‘forward’’ or modern Muslim. This conception and desire was to animate
a number of diverse projects. Sayyid Ahmad Khan desired a ‘‘new genera-
tion of Muslims who would have the knowledge, skills and values necessary
to qualify them for public leadership,’’ 65 and hoped that the Muhammadan
Anglo-Oriental College would be the crucible in which this new generation
could be forged. Maulana Abul Kalam Azad, as Congress nationalist and then
Governmentality and Identity 127
as education minister of independent India, sought a Muslim identity which
would be securely anchored both in Islam and in Indianness, the two com-
bined in part by being ‘‘modern.’’ Muhammad Ali Jinnah, Qaid-e- Azam or
father of Pakistan, had his own visions of what the Muslim who was not
backward, but master of his own fortunes, needed to be like. Indeed, the
heterogeneity of these desires, and the variety of projects to which they gave
rise, ensured that the figure of the ‘‘backward Muslim,’’ whether he ‘‘in fact’’
existed or not, would have real and lasting historical consequences.
chapter five
The debates to which western education gave rise, and the intensity with
which these were debated, bore little relation to the actual numbers of Indi-
ans receiving such education. If this was so of education in general, it was
especially so of female education. In 1882 there were, in all of British India,
six girls in college, just over two thousand in secondary schools, and 124,000
in primary or ‘‘mixed’’ schools, the vast majority of these in the provinces of
Bombay, Madras, and Bengal, leaving a minuscule number of girls receiving
any formal education in the rest of British India.1 Well under 1 percent of girls
of school-going age (narrowly defined) were enrolled in any educational in-
stitution at any level,2 and for every thousand boys enrolled, there were only
forty-six girls.3 By early in the new century there were 160 females in arts col-
leges, but of these 124 were European, Eurasian, Indian Christian, or Parsi,
leaving thirty-six Hindu and Muslim girls attending college. Similarly, of the
thirty thousand girls enrolled in the higher echelons of secondary education
and receiving instruction in English, two-thirds were European or Eurasian.4
Where female education was discussed, the director general of education in
India observed in his quinquennial report for 1902–7, ‘‘In the main . . . it con-
notes primary education, that is to say, the teaching of little girls to read and
write in the vernacular, to do easy sums and a little needlework.’’ 5 Very often
it did not even mean that: many girls attended coeducational schools, which
usually meant boys’ schools with all-male staff that had been encouraged to
enroll girls but where, it was widely observed, girls received little education
and indeed little attention.6 A government statement in 1913 acknowledged,
‘‘The education of girls remains to be organised.’’ 7
Nonetheless, female education was the subject of constant discussion in
colonial India, in staggering disproportion to the number of girls affected.
Why was this so? The obvious answer might be that the depth and intensity
129
130 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
of the discourse bore witness to its controversial and contested character; that
those who urged female education were confronted with those who denied
the need for it, or argued against it. In fact, however, the discourse on female
education was very one-sided: by the latter nineteenth century most of the
many voices heard on the subject accepted its desirability, and urged its im-
portance. Far from being an answer to our question (Why was there so much
said and written about female education despite the small number of girls
receiving it?) this observation only yields a second question: Why so much
discourse, if there was agreement? In other words, why such belaboring of a
point on which a public consensus had seemingly been reached? And given
that the volume of discourse on this subject was not matched by dramatic
increases in the numbers of girls receiving education, yet another question:
What did this discourse on the desirability of educating women signify, if it
did not signal a newfound willingness to educate girls and women?
The discourse on women’s education was tied up with controversies over
‘‘the woman question’’ in colonial India, controversies which, it has often
been noted, had less to do with women than with what women were seen
to signify, or could be made to signify. That is, debates on the woman ques-
tion were connected to differing characterizations and assessments of Indian
(or Hindu) society and tradition, which often emerged and took shape in the
course of polemical exchanges between the colonial ruler and nationalists. To
investigate why female education was so extensively discussed (despite the
lack of opposition), and what the debates signified (if they were not trans-
lated into results), we need to begin with these exchanges and recreate the
discursive contexts in which they took place.
Who Signifies?
I began this chapter by observing that debates on the woman question in
colonial India were overdetermined by conflicts between nationalists and
India’s British rulers. The British claimed to be improving an India that was
economically but also socially ‘‘backward,’’ as the condition of her peasants,
untouchables, and women indicated. The spokesmen of Indian national-
ism, most of them western-educated, assumed that they were exempt from
this charge and argued that their uniquely privileged position—as mediators
between their rulers, whose modern world they participated in, and their
countrymen, whom they were in the best position to understand—required
that they be given a greater role and say in the governance of India. Later
they came to argue that the British were not an agent of modernity at all but
rather an impediment to achieving it, and that with Independence a mod-
ernizing élite, with the consent and participation of the backward, could lead
India into the modern world.
The character of these debates changed in response to political and other
changes. The isomorphism posited between woman, the untouchable, and
the peasant—all exemplars of backwardness—was challenged by national-
ism as it came to assert that while transforming the peasantry and reform-
ing or uprooting the caste system might have to await the gaining of state
power,72 the remaking of Indian women and of the Indian home was within
its power—and moreover, was its exclusive domain. There thus began the
project of ‘‘ideological-aesthetic meddlesomeness,’’ discussed in the preced-
ing pages, to remake the middle-class Indian woman. She and the home that
she was seen to preside over were to be rendered more modern, but at the
same time were to retain, and were charged with the function of signifying
and preserving, all that was distinctively ‘‘Indian’’ in a project that might
otherwise become nothing more than an attempt to make India resemble
England. Female education was an important part of the project to produce
this woman and this home, but the absence of any serious public opposition
to the project obscured the deep anxiety which was part of it, manifested in
repeated injunctions against letting the educated woman resemble the west-
ern woman.
As with other debates concerning the ‘‘woman question’’ in colonial India,
debates on female education were not about women but rather about what
they signified, or could be made to signify. But also at issue was who was to
make her signify; who could claim to be legitimately authorized to modern-
146 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
ize Indian women. The Indian élites sought to convince others, and perhaps
themselves, that they recognized the need to remake Indian women, and that
they were capable of formulating an agenda mapping out the character of
this transformation. They endlessly elaborated to others, and to each other,
what the iconic woman was to signify, and agonized over the lurking dan-
gers inherent in this project. Actually effecting this transformation mattered
less, since that was not what this elaborate discourse was about. Hence the
curious impression of two parallel discussions going on. One was about the
desirability of women’s education, and those taking part in and observing
this discussion were struck by the unanimity which had been reached on
the issue. The other discussion was among educational officials and others
directly involved in providing education, and those taking part in this discus-
sion were struck by the wretchedly slow progress being made: in the number
of students enrolled, in the level to which they progressed, and in the knowl-
edge and skills gained.Thus at the very time when, according to Purushottam
Das Tandon, the debate over whether to educate girls had been won even in
the Hindi-speaking regions, the director general for education was observ-
ing—as we saw at the beginning of this chapter—that there was very little of
the education in question actually happening, and what there was occurred
mostly at the lower levels of primary education. There is a curious air of un-
reality surrounding the discourse on female education—so many discursive
moves and declarations, so much argument produced to justify the necessity
and urge the importance of it, and yet so little happening ‘‘on the ground.’’ 73
This, I suggest, was because the discourse of female education was less
about effecting change than about staking out a claim: that only Indians
were authorized to act in this domain, and to map out what changes were
required. This claim was made on the grounds that the ability of the middle-
class Indian to speak for and represent his women and his home was not
contestable, in the way that his ability to speak for the peasant was.
However, the very circumstance that made nationalists choose woman as
a signifier and as a site of contestation—that male nationalists could, given
patriarchal assumptions shared by ruler and ruled, plausibly claim the right
to speak for and intervene in the lives of women—also constituted a poten-
tial weakness. To the very degree that ‘‘his’’ home was construed as his sov-
ereign domain and as constitutive of his identity, the middle-class, western-
educated Indian was marked by it, in a way that he was not marked by
the continued backwardness of the Indian peasant. The backwardness of the
peasant signified the backwardness of India; but the backwardness of the
Gender and the Nation 147
middle-class Indian woman could be seen to testify also to the backwardness
of the middle-class Indian. This much was to become especially clear during the
curious affair of Katherine Mayo’s Mother India; and the ensuing controversy
was also to prove a catalyst for a new urgency in nationalist ranks, which
sought to match discourse to results.
Mother India
In 1925–26 Mayo, an American journalist and author, made a three-month
trip to India with the intention of collecting information for a book. In 1927
Mother India was published in New York and then in London.The idea of India
as a mother had been a common and potent signifier in nationalist iconog-
raphy since the nineteenth century, and Mayo later explained that she had
chosen her title precisely to make ‘‘inescapable the contrast between, on the
one hand, florid talk of devotion and ‘sacrifice’ poured out before an abstract
figure, and, on the other hand, the consideration actually accorded to the
living woman, mother of the race.’’ 74
Her book was thus an ‘‘exposé’’ of the true condition of India, especially
of Indian women, and through this also a critique of nationalist demands
for greater self-rule. Mayo purported to show that Indian society and cus-
tom—for the most part Hindu society and custom—condemned women (and
also the untouchable castes and others) to lives of ignorance, slavery, and ex-
treme degradation; that it had always been thus; and that all talk of a ‘‘Golden
Age’’ of India, when a greater measure of equality and dignity prevailed, was
therefore myth. Whatever improvement there had been in the condition of
women was due to the efforts of India’s British rulers, who had not been as-
sisted and had very often been impeded by their Indian subjects, especially
nationalist politicians and speechmakers. Indians blamed England for woes
that were deeply rooted in their own culture, a fact they were unwilling to
even acknowledge, let alone address. The only prospects for improvement
lay in the hope that the educated classes in India might concede that the
chains that bound them were of their own making, and earnestly help the
British to improve India, rather than engage in nationalist mythmaking and
speechifying. Mayo’s book was presented as the effort of a well-wisher—it
was dedicated to ‘‘the peoples of India’’—undertaking the onerous and poten-
tially thankless task of holding up a mirror to Indian reality so that Indians
could more clearly see themselves, the necessary prelude to their improving
themselves.
148 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
The meat of the book lay in its graphic descriptions of child brides
psychologically and physically damaged by premature intercourse,often with
middle-aged husbands; of child mothers giving birth under the most un-
hygienic and primitive conditions, their reproductive organs irreparably
damaged if they survived at all; of the despair of these same mothers at giving
birth to daughters, who if not killed to relieve the family of future financial
burden were condemned to a future like that of their mothers; and of the
lives of women who lived in the utmost ignorance, imprisoned in purdah,
slaves to husbands whom they were taught from early childhood to regard as
their god. All these practices were rooted in Indian custom and Hindu tradi-
tion, which the mass of the people regarded as immutable, a view in which
their leaders concurred or which they lacked the courage and will to seek to
reform. Mother India documented other horrors as well, including the oppres-
sion of low castes by Brahmins, but it was the depictions of Indian women
in unbearable conditions, and the linking of these conditions to an alleged
Hindu obsession with sex (manifested in practices such as early marriage,
worship of the Siva lingam, and temple prostitution), which excited the most
comment.
And excite comment the book did—more accurately, it provoked a furor.
In England many hailed it as ‘‘independent’’ confirmation of what the British
authorities had been saying all along—the liberal New Statesman, which had
been relatively sympathetic to Indian nationalist claims, carried an unsigned
review by its editor which both captured and endorsed the tone of the book:
‘‘All who know anything of India are aware, of course, of the prime evils of
Hinduism, of the horrors of the child marriage system, of the universality of
sexual vice in its most extravagant forms, of the monstrously absurd brutali-
ties of the caste system, of the filthy personal habits of even the most edu-
cated classes—which, like the degradation of Hindu women, are unequalled
even amongst the most primitive African or Australian savages—of the uni-
versal cruelty to animals, and of the equally universal prevalence of laziness,
untruthfulness, cowardice and personal corruption.’’ Mayo, the review con-
cluded, ‘‘makes the claim for Swaraj seem nonsense and the will to grant it
almost a crime.’’ 75 Some British feminists joined in the condemnations of
India on behalf of their oppressed Indian ‘‘sisters.’’ In America Mother India
sold in huge numbers and shaped public perceptions of India for a long time
to come.76
The biggest reaction was in India, and it was almost unanimously hos-
tile. Within one year of its publication nine books appeared in reply, includ-
Gender and the Nation 149
ing one by the nationalist Lala Lajpat Rai and another by the indefatiguable
social reformer K. Natarajan; more appeared over the next few years.77 Some
Indian respondents saw Mayo’s condemnation of the alleged Indian obses-
sion with sex as evidence that she was herself ‘‘sex-mad.’’ 78 Most Indian re-
spondents read Mother India as a politically inspired attack upon nationalist
aspirations.79 And almost all condemned the book as an attack upon Indian
women. Thus in Calcutta Foreward characterized the book as a ‘‘Libel against
IndianWomanhood’’ and a headline in Amrita Bazaar Patrika read, ‘‘Gratuitous
Insult, Indian Women Blasphemed’’; and a large protest at the Calcutta Town
Hall was advertised as being held ‘‘to repudiate the scurrilous attacks and
malicious allegations made against the Indian womanhood by Miss Mayo.’’ 80
This was in addition to a host of responses in the press, including ones by
Indian women and by Gandhi and Tagore. Numerous public meetings were
held to denounce the book, and proposals to proscribe it were raised by Indian
members of the Central Legislative Assembly.
The content of Mother India, as noted by contemporaries, Mayo herself,
and many others since, was not new.81 As we have seen, the backward and
barbaric character of Indian or Hindu society, exemplified above all in its
treatment of women, had been a theme of some British writings since the
late eighteenth century, receiving formulaic expression with Mill in the early
nineteenth, and becoming an orthodoxy thereafter. Numerous Indian social
reformers had drawn attention to the social ills which beset India and had
sometimes described them in vivid terms, urging sweeping reforms of Indian
social practices. Yet the book became an event, the subject of a controversy
which, it has been observed, is perhaps only rivaled in recent times by that
surrounding Salman Rushdie’s The Satanic Verses.
Why was this so? If there was little new in the book, why such a fury of de-
nunciation? Mayo, who in 1931 published a sequel entitled simply Volume Two,
suggested that the response, most of which came from the politically minded
western-educated intelligentsia, was ‘‘simply and solely because the book was
being read in America’’;82 seeking independence from Britain, Indian nation-
alists were cultivating sympathy in America, and Mother India was a serious
setback in that effort. Malicious and self-serving, this explanation was none-
theless not without some truth. Indian nationalists had been publicizing
their cause in America and elsewhere, and after the publication of the book
Sarojini Naidu, with the blessing of the Indian National Congress, went on
a speaking tour of the United States to publicize the nationalist cause and
to undo the damage that Mayo’s book had done. However, this was hardly
150 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
an adequate explanation for the extent of the response in India, nor for the
indignation that the book aroused.
According to Mrinalini Sinha, whose introduction to a recent reprint of
Mayo’s book is the best study of the controversy, the key to the extraordinary
affair of Mother India lay in its timing rather than its content. The book ap-
peared just as a Conservative government in Britain was preparing to appoint
the Indian Statutory (Simon) Commission to examine the workings of the
Government of India Act of 1919. This act had conceded the principle of self-
governing institutions by creating elected assemblies in the provinces, with
control over some governmental functions. The concessions were limited—
the elected provincial governments had control over only local matters, the
British governors of the provinces continued to exercise supervisory control
and veto powers, and the franchise upon which provincial governments were
elected was a very narrow one—but the act had nevertheless been vehemently
opposed by many in Britain and by large sections of colonial officialdom in
India. It was hoped by die-hard imperialists (and feared by nationalists) that
the all-white Simon Commission was designed to check any further conces-
sions. Since the passage of the Government of India Act Indian nationalism
had also been transformed, for the first time becoming genuinely India-wide
during the Non-cooperation Movement of 1921–22, during which the gap
between middle-class nationalism and the peasantry had seemingly been
bridged. The years since the mass upsurge was called off had been a period
of relative quietude, but the transformation of the Indian National Congress
into a mass organization signaled the coming to maturity of the nationalist
cause, reflected in part in the declaration by Congress some months after the
appearance of Mother India that independence was its goal, a radicalization
which was affirmed at the 1929 Congress. A second wave of India-wide mass
protests followed during the Civil Disobedience campaign of 1930–34. Thus
it was ‘‘the changing imperatives of British imperialism and Indian nation-
alism in the 1920s that helped make a book, which was hardly original in
its subject or exceptional in its argument, the centre of an unprecedented
international controversy.’’ 83
Sinha’s explanation of the Mother India controversy thus hinges upon the
context in which the book appeared, and dismisses its content as ‘‘hardly
original or exceptional.’’ The most that could be said about the book’s content
is that it provided one of ‘‘the most systematic elaborations’’ of the ‘‘old im-
perialist theme’’ of India’s backwardness being manifested in the treatment
of Indian women.84 I find this explanation persuasive in part, but incomplete.
Gender and the Nation 151
What I offer below, through a close reading of Mother India, is a supplemen-
tary reading, one which draws attention to its content and the ‘‘artistry’’ with
which it was presented, and which focuses on a theme in the book which,
while not exactly original, gave it a polemical edge that helps explain why it
fueled so much debate, as well as what was at stake in that debate.
Vernacular Modernity
The Nationalist Imagination
The British claim that colonial rule was a pedagogic enterprise for the im-
provement of India, and that western education was one of the means toward
this end, was largely accepted by the new élites emerging under British rule.
The members and leaders of the nationalist organizations founded in the
latter part of the nineteenth century—most of them western-educated 1—
often singled out western education as one of the most important and valu-
able instruments through which the British were transforming India. The
annual sessions of the Indian National Congress were frequently the occa-
sion for such effusions: Sankaran Nair told the 1897 Congress session, ‘‘British
rule . . . furnished us with the one element, English education, which was
necessary to rouse us from the torpor of ages’’; at the 1902 Congress Surendra-
nath Banerjea declared, ‘‘The three great boons which we have received from
the British Government are High Education, the gift of a free Press and local
Self-Government . . . but High Education is the most prized, the most deeply
cherished of them all’’; and B. N. Dhar told the 1911 session of the Congress
that ‘‘the educational system which has immortalised the names of Bentinck
and Macaulay is perhaps [Britain’s] greatest gift to the people of India.’’ 2 If
nationalists and educated Indian public opinion more generally had a mis-
giving, it was that the colonial government did not provide enough of this
much-valued western education. By the latter nineteenth century the com-
plaint that the colonial authorities were not doing enough to promote educa-
tion had become ubiquitous; at the same time that notables in Congress were
lauding British rule for having provided India with western education, the
annual sessions of the Congress that they addressed were passing resolutions
urging the British Indian government to provide more of it.3
At the beginning of the new century educational reforms undertaken by
the viceroy, Lord Curzon, were interpreted by educated Indians as an effort to
159
160 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
diminish Indian access to western education and to assert dictatorial govern-
ment control over the educational sector, and were vigorously condemned.
Officialdom and Indian opinion were from this time polarized on the subject
of education,often bitterly so.The British characterized the Indian position as
a selfish one—so eager were the Indian middle classes to obtain the precious
certification regarded as a passport to employment that they cared nothing
about the poor quality of this education, and resisted all attempts to improve
it. ‘‘Multiply senators, multiply colleges, multiply university centres, courses
and faculties—and all will be well,’’ was how one critic of the Indian posi-
tion characterized it.4 Indians conversely saw in every government initiative
a hidden agenda directed at whittling back and controlling the education
sector. Sir Narayan Chandarvarkar, judge in the High Court of Bombay and
one-time vice-chancellor of Bombay University, explained that the educated
classes were not unconcerned about efficiency and quality, but expressed the
fear ‘‘that in the name of ‘efficiency’ of University education the interests of
its diffusion are likely to be sacrificed in India’’;5 and Curzon himself referred
with frustration to the ‘‘suspicion that [the government] encounters among
the educated classes that we really desire to restrict their opportunities and
in some way or other to keep them down.’’ 6
The demand for ‘‘more’’ education did not abate. However, from the last
decade of the nineteenth century demands for more education were joined by
a growing volume of criticism directed not simply at the insufficiency of edu-
cation but at the inadequacies of the existing system.7 By the early decades
of the twentieth century the criticism had become a torrent, commented on
by all observers of the educational scene. Government statements on educa-
tion policy regularly noted the many criticisms of the system of education,8
and at convocation ceremonies it was observed that university education was
being criticized from all quarters, for all manner of sins. In 1938 the Indian
vice-chancellor of Dacca University complained that ‘‘the blame for every evil
from which the country is suffering is laid at the door of the University. The
unemployment problem, the acute economic distress, the physical weakness
of girls and boys, backwardness in trade and industry, absence of a proper
national spirit, lack of reverence for one’s own society and country, the way-
ward conduct of youth, and the irreligious outlook of the present generation
are all supposed to be due to the defective system of University education.’’ 9
An inspector of schools attempted to sum up the indictment: ‘‘The Indian in-
telligentsia has attempted to diagnose the defects of the educational system
Vernacular Modernity 161
variously: it has made men mercenary and does not build character; its aims
have been secular and leave no room for godliness; it has neglected physical,
moral and religious training; it has made men unpractical and has neglected
vocational education . . . ; it imparts instruction through a foreign tongue
and has made sound education impossible; it has estranged the masses from
the educated classes . . . and lastly, it has utterly ignored India’s past culture,
traditions, philosophy, arts, learning and history and has bred in the youth
no love for their country.’’ 10
This plethora of criticisms fell into two broad categories.The first was that
western education was failing to produce the effects which it had been ex-
pected would follow from its provision. Education was meant to be producing
young men who could think for themselves and were prepared for a variety
of tasks and challenges, but for the most part was producing men who re-
gurgitated information they had crammed in examinations and were fit for
nothing but clerkdom in the government service; was meant to instill a mod-
ern outlook on the world but had instilled intellectual and moral confusion
instead; was meant to reshape lives, but was so far removed from the Indian’s
home life that life at school and life at home never connected.11 In short, edu-
cation was to be the instrument for modernity, and in this it was failing.This
was more than the complaint that there was not enough western education
for it to perform its modernizing role; it was rather the complaint that it was
failing in this role because the vehicle of transformation was itself counter-
feit. Indeed, there was a widespread perception that western education in
India was the name of the thing, rather than the thing itself.We encountered
evidence of this in previous chapters: a pamphleteer in Cuttack lamenting,
‘‘There are hardly any such things as students in the proper sense of the term
in our country’’;12 an eminent Indian convert to Christianity complaining of
the mechanical way in which students studied (‘‘A copying machine could do
the same’’);13 the editor of an important newspaper describing Indian univer-
sities as ‘‘bad imitations’’ of the (already imperfect) English originals,14 and
Indian colleges as ‘‘coaching agencies mis-named colleges.’’ 15 These and other
witnesses decried, time and again, that India had only the shadow of stu-
dents, not the substance; colleges which were really mere coaching agencies;
learning processes which could be performed by copying machines; schools
and universities which had neither real students nor provided real learning,
and which were themselves only the name-of-a-university. The debate on
western education in India, one could say, came to be haunted by the specter
162 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
of nominalism: the fear that the agency of modernity was not the real thing
but merely something bearing the name of the thing, not the genuine article
but a simulacrum.
The second category into which we can group criticisms of education were
laments about the effects that western education was having, rather than
what education was failing to do. Rooted in an alien culture, under the con-
trol of a foreign ruler, not having been adapted to the character of those
subject to it, western education was alienating its products from their own
traditions. Lajpat Rai described the existing system of western education
as ‘‘emasculating and enervating . . . denationalising and degrading.’’ 16 Har
Dayal referred to ‘‘the utter wreck of national self-respect which has followed
the establishment of the British schools and colleges in India.’’ 17 The art his-
torian A. K. Coomaraswamy described the educational system as one ‘‘that
has ignored or despised almost every ideal informing the national culture,’’
the products of which were ‘‘stranger[s] in their own land.’’ 18 The latter obser-
vation—that in becoming alienated from their culture the western-educated
had also become cut off and estranged from theircompatriots—was verycom-
monly made. When first introduced, western education had been widely ex-
pected to produce a class who would function as intermediaries between their
rulers and the masses of their countrymen. This had been one of the justifi-
cations for government patronage of education, and had become part of the
self-understanding of educated Indians. Now it was said, ‘‘Neither trusted by
their masters nor by the masses they form a class by themselves.’’ 19 Rabin-
dranath Tagore described the gulf between the western-educated and other
Indians as ‘‘the worst caste system that prevails at present in the country,’’ 20
and Bipan Chandra Pal similarly adjudged this chasm to be even greater than
that between high castes and untouchables.21
These two broad criticisms—that western education was failing as a ve-
hicle of modernity, and that it was ‘‘denationalizing’’ its products—were not,
on the face of it, logically related. The first criticism was voiced not only
by Indians and Indian nationalists but also often by the colonial authorities
themselves. Below I focus on the second criticism, which was more explicitly
nationalist, and on the various efforts to devise an education that would re-
inforce rather than undermine national identity. It will turn out, however,
that in the nationalist imagination the two criticisms were seen to be closely
connected, and this being so, the various schemes for a ‘‘national’’ education
sought a single solution to both problems.
Vernacular Modernity 163
National(ist) Education
The criticisms of the new, western education system led to various attempts
at providing alternatives, which would compensate for the perceived short-
comings of the official system. The Arya Samaj, a reformist Hindu move-
ment with its base in Punjab, founded the Dayanand Anglo-Vedic (dav) High
School in 1886 and the dav College, Lahore, in 1889. The dav ‘‘movement’’—
the high school and college were soon joined by many schools all over Pun-
jab—sought to provide an education which would combine ‘‘modern’’ and
therefore western knowledge with knowledge of Sanskrit and training in the
‘‘true,’’ Vedic origins of Hinduism, before these were corrupted by evil social
practices and idolatry. The management of the school, and its curriculum,
reflected these goals.22
On a smaller scale, but very much in the public eye, were the educational
experiments of India’s Nobel laureate Rabindranath Tagore. Tagore founded
his school at Santiniketan in 1901, the Viswa-Bharati university in 1919,23 and
Sriniketan, his school for ‘‘rural reconstruction,’’ in 1921. All were outside the
official system, which Tagore characterized as mechanical and productive of
imitation rather than originality. ‘‘We had to sit,’’ Tagore wrote, referring to
his own unhappyencounters with schooling as a young boy—‘‘inert, like dead
specimens of some museum, whilst lessons were pelted at us from on high,
like hailstones on flowers.’’ 24 The contrasts that Tagore continually drew in
his writings and speeches—between discipline and freedom, nature and the
natural versus the artificial and mechanical, passive versus active—provided
the background to his own pedagogic mission. At Santiniketan it was recog-
nized that the ‘‘restless wings given them [children] by nature’’ are absolutely
necessary for discovery and growth, and that seeking to discipline this rest-
less enquiry usually killed learning.25 ‘‘In proper schools boys . . . must never
be boisterous, they must not laugh too loud. But boys are born savages and
must pass through the stage of savagedom. I let them run and climb and
swing and when the rain fell, go out and get thoroughly drenched in the
open air.’’ 26 As in the ancient tapavana, or forest school, after which Tagore’s
school was modeled, teachers and pupils lived as a community, freedom con-
quered discipline, play was preferred to work, classes were conducted outside
in the open air, and the aim was to allow the child to develop rather than force
him into a mold. Tagore’s educational endeavors were an always implicit and
often explicit critique—as much on Rousseauan and Pestalozzian grounds as
nationalist ones—of the existing educational system.27
164 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
The Muhammadan Anglo-Oriental College (from 1920 the Aligarh Muslim
University) and the Benares Hindu University (1915) were both self-conscious
attempts to provide to religious communities an education that would equip
them with the modern knowledge necessary to face the (colonial) world, as
well as instruction in their cultural and religious tradition.28 Knowledge of
and pride in their ancestral (religious) traditions was to be a hallmark of the
education provided at amu and bhu. The Muhammadan Anglo-Indian Col-
lege played an important role in the development of a new Muslim identity,29
and bhu played an important role in the development of syllabi and text-
books in Hindi, produced a great many Hindi writers and critics, and trained
teachers who would go on to teach in Hindi.30
These various efforts were all nationalist inasmuch as part of what they
stressed and sought to offer to students was some quality of ‘‘Indianness’’
(or Hinduness or Muslimness) felt to be lacking in the official government
system, if not directly undermined by it.Tagore’s schools and university addi-
tionally sought to provide a more creative education than the officially man-
dated one. But one of the persistent problems to plague such alternatives
was that the instrumental advantages of education—recognized certifica-
tion, prestige (especially that associated with knowledge of English), and the
like—all belonged to the official system. Any alternative, ‘‘national’’ or other-
wise, usually sought to retain some of the attractions of the official system,
for fear of losing students;31 and in most cases (with the partial exception of
Tagore’s institutions) they sought to achieve recognition as bona fide institu-
tions from state authorities, and to add to or amend the authorized curricu-
lum rather than altogether replace it.The result, as the editor of the Dawn put
it in 1908, was that institutions established and controlled by Indians tended
to become ‘‘replicas of the Government model, without a separate mission or
nobler reason for existence.’’ 32 Thus it was in one sense a measure of the dav
High School’s achievement that its students sat for the matriculation exam
for entrance to university with great success, and that the school and college
came to be commended by the government; but in the eyes of some support-
ers this also came to be seen as a failing, with some Arya Samajis complaining
that the school ‘‘began to turn out not Gautamas and Kanads, but babus.’’ 33
Disagreements over the direction which education was taking was one of the
reasons behind a split in the Arya Samaj in the early years of the twentieth
century, with the departing members seeking to establish schools which pro-
vided an education fundamentally different from that provided within the
official educational system.34 Tagore’s school ignored the official curriculum,
Vernacular Modernity 165
and its students took the matriculation exam for entry to Calcutta Univer-
sity as ‘‘private students’’ rather than as pupils of Santiniketan, but late in
his life Tagore was to complain that even his college and school ‘‘are every
day becoming more and more like so many schools and colleges elsewhere in
this country: borrowed cages that treat the students’ minds as captive birds,
whose sole human value is judged according to the mechanical repetition of
lessons, prescribed by an educational dispensation foreign to the soil.’’ 35
There were also more overtly nationalist challenges to the dominant edu-
cation system.The slogan of ‘‘national education’’ was raised during the Swa-
deshi agitation in Bengal (1905–8), which followed upon the announcement
of the colonial government’s decision to partition the province of Bengal. As
part of the general protest the call was raised for students to withdraw from
government schools and colleges. Frantic efforts were then made to estab-
lish alternative educational institutions. The National Council of Education
(nce), established in 1906 to found a ‘‘national’’ education system, sought to
establish a network of schools under Indian control, unfettered by govern-
ment inspections and direction; the aim was to provide an education drawing
upon and emphasizing the richness of Indian traditions, delivered in Indian
languages, with English taught as a second language.36 For a period the nce
met with an enthusiastic response, and it succeeded in raising money and
establishing a network of schools, as well as its flagship, the Bengal National
College and School, in Calcutta. However, the usual problems soon began to
appear, including inadequate funds and the low esteem in which the certi-
fication offered by the alternative schools was held in the marketplace; and
as the Swadeshi agitation itself began to wane, so too did enthusiasm for the
nce system.The historian of the Swadeshi movement, Sumit Sarkar, sums up
the results thus: ‘‘One or two model institutions, at Santiniketan or Calcutta,
surviving as examples of non-political constructive swadeshi; a number of
national schools in East Bengal serving as seminaries and recruiting grounds
for revolutionary terrorism—such were the remnants of national education
in Bengal in the decade succeeding 1910.’’ 37
The call for a ‘‘national’’ education to replace the existing educational sys-
tem was, however, now on the agenda. In 1911 and again in 1916 the annual
session of the Congress passed a resolution declaring that ‘‘the time had ar-
rived for people all over the country to earnestly take up the question of
national education . . . and organize a system of education . . . suited to the re-
quirements of the country, on national lines and under national control’’ 38—
a significant departure from earlier years, when Congress resolutions had
166 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
simply called upon the colonial government to provide more education. The
call to boycott the officially sanctioned education system was raised again
during the Non-cooperation movement of 1920–22, this time nationwide.The
premise behind the mass campaign of ‘‘non-cooperation’’ was that British
rule survived principally because Indians were complicit in it, and conversely,
that it would be morally and politically undermined if they refused to co-
operate. Thus the call for non-cooperation or boycott included education,
and no one raised the clarion call as loudly, nor as emphatically, as Gandhi.
Again, efforts were made to establish an alternative system. Vidyapiths and
other national schools and colleges were established to offer an alternative
to ‘‘cooperating’’ with institutions that maintained the legitimacy of British
rule, institutions which, in Gandhi’s words, made of Indians what they ‘‘were
intended to become—clerks and interpreters.’’ 39
‘‘The aim of national education,’’ Gandhi wrote in Young India, ‘‘is just the
opposite. It is to turn out . . . men determined to end the alien rule.’’ 40 At
times it seemed that national schools were not principally about schooling
at all: ‘‘We did not start the Vidyapith and other institutions connected with
it merely for the sake of education,’’ Gandhi told the students of the Guja-
rat Vidyapith, with which he was closely associated: ‘‘We started the Vidya-
pith as a part of the campaign for non-cooperation . . . [. It is] an associa-
tion for Swaraj.’’ 41 Accordingly, what was important was not simply whether
these institutions remained independent of the government-mandated sys-
tem of grants and inspections, or which textbooks they used or how they
taught history.42 What was most important was whether they furthered the
aims of self-purification which were an essential and defining element of
swaraj, namely spinning, fighting the practice of untouchability, and pro-
moting amity among India’s religious communities. Gandhi told the stu-
dents of the Gujarat Mahavidyalaya that they were not there principally to
learn good English, or even good Sanskrit: ‘‘You are here to learn and acquire
things which you will not get elsewhere and which are far superior to those
enumerated above.These are: the Charkha, removal of untouchability . . . and
the unity of Hindus and Muslims and Parsis . . . It is of no account if you
pass in all other things except these.’’ 43 National schools were less schools
than (as Gandhi told the annual session of the Indian National Congress at
Belgaum in 1924) ‘‘factories where the first instruments of our freedom are
forged.’’ 44 At other times, however, Gandhi would emphasize pedagogic and
not simply political differences. Hewould declare: ‘‘[There is] a world of differ-
ence between our method of teaching and theirs.’’ 45 And indeed, in national
Vernacular Modernity 167
schools all teaching was done in the mother tongue of the region; history
and economics were taught from an Indian, patriotic point of view; even in
the teaching of math, the examples used sought to relate to Indian life; and
manual training, a favourite theme of Gandhi’s, received great emphasis.46
Gandhi, Tagore, the Arya Samaj, and various other proponents of national
education all adjudged the existing education system to be disastrously
flawed. It disseminated knowledge alien to the history and traditions of
India, through institutions and practices which were foreign imports. It was
thus necessary to substitute an education that was ‘‘national.’’ But what, pre-
cisely, was ‘‘national’’ about national education? The nationalist, education-
alist, and Arya Samaj leader Lajpat Rai put the question with his customary
directness: ‘‘What do we mean by national education? Is it the language which
is the medium of instruction, which makes it national, or the agency through
which it is imparted, or the agency which controls and regulates it, or the
books which are taught or the standards or ideals which underlie it?’’ 47
As we have seen, the answers varied, from the Arya Samaji stress on San-
skrit and reformist Hinduism, to Tagore’s mix of Pestalozzian pedagogy and
Bengali romanticism, to Gandhi’s ferocious championing of the self-reform
of Hindu society. The variety of answers is testimony to the richness of the
nationalist imagination. However, no one seriously proposed what might
seem the most obvious answer of all: that national education purvey the tra-
ditional or indigenous knowledges of India.
Vernacular Modernity
In India as elsewhere, anticolonial nationalism embodied the desire to be
‘‘modern but different’’—to acquire the characteristics that made the colonial
power strong, but to do so in the name of an irreducible difference that was
conceived in national terms, and for which nationalism purported to speak.
As Lajpat Rai put it, ‘‘We do not want to be English or German or Ameri-
can or Japanese . . . we want to be Indians, but modern, up-to-date, progres-
sive Indians.’’ 82 It was not enough to imitate the colonizer: if the project was
simply to become a mirror image of the original, there could be no ratio-
Vernacular Modernity 177
nale for the nationalist project. Chakrabarty writes that ‘‘the colonial experi-
ence of becoming modern is haunted by the fear of looking unoriginal . . .
Nationalist writings therefore subsume the question of difference within a
search for essences, origins, authenticities, which, however, have to be ame-
nable to global-European constructions of modernity so that the quintessen-
tially nationalist claim of being ‘different but modern’ can be validated.’’ 83
Partha Chatterjee, as we saw in chapter 5, argues that one of the means by
which nationalism sought to reconcile the search for national difference with
the pursuit of modernity was by dividing the world of social institutions
and practices into two domains, a ‘‘material’’ domain where ‘‘Western su-
periority had to be acknowledged and its accomplishments carefully studied
and replicated,’’ and a ‘‘spiritual’’ or ‘‘inner’’ domain, where national identity
was located, and which had to be safeguarded and preserved.84 In Chatter-
jee’s account, education was part of the ‘‘inner,’’ spiritual domain rather than
the ‘‘outside’’ of ‘‘economy and statecraft, science and technology.’’ Hence
‘‘nationalism sought to bring this area under its jurisdiction’’ by starting sec-
ondary schools and seeking to assert control over the universities.85
Here it seems to me that Chatterjee’s very fruitful distinction between
‘‘inside’’ and ‘‘outside’’ threatens to become coterminous with the more con-
ventional distinction between civil society and state, yielding the conclusion
that nationalism engaged in a Gramscian war of position, seeking to exert
control over civil society before the decisive struggle for state power. Such an
account would not be wrong, but it would be less insightful than the origi-
nal distinction between inside and outside, between that which is modern-
universal and must be imitated and acquired, and that where the ‘‘essential
marks’’ of identity are located, and which therefore must be protected and
secured. Education, I submit, was both important to and problematic for
nationalism, because it straddled this distinction. On the one hand, education
was where the knowledges, skills, and techniques of the modern, which the
nation-to-be had to acquire, were disseminated. That is why one could not
reject education, for to do so would be to give up on the aspiration to be mod-
ern. Herein lies the answer to the question I posed, namely the question of
why nationalism never sought to revive the study of indigenous knowledges,
such as a long and rich intellectual tradition in Sanskrit, as an alternative
to the dissemination of western knowledge. It did not do so because these
knowledges and traditions were not seen as conducive to modernity; however
plausible they were as assertions of difference, they were not ‘‘amenable to
global-European constructions of modernity.’’ But neither was colonial edu-
178 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
cation (unlike, say, the railway system) simply a site where the skills of the
modern could be acquired, because it was also a site where identities were
produced and secured. As a project to be modern, nationalism sought more
western education, which was seen as necessary to becoming modern; but as
a project to be ‘‘modern but different,’’ it also sought an education that would
preserve difference, even bring it to self-consciousness, rather than efface it.
In the words of Lajpat Rai, quoted earlier, it was necessary to become ‘‘mod-
ern, up-to-date [and] progressive,’’ but more specifically to become ‘‘modern,
up-to-date [and] progressive Indians’’ (emphasis added).
Hence the nationalist project to found a ‘‘national’’ education, an educa-
tion that would be modern without ceasing to be Indian. We saw that the
question of what was to count as ‘‘national’’ about national education was
one to which there were varied answers, rather than a single one. But—and it
is not the same thing as a common answer—across the spectrum of national-
ist opinion, and amid the diversity of types of ‘‘national’’ education on offer,
there was one element held in common: whatever else made this education
national, it had to be in the ‘‘vernaculars,’’ that is, in the languages of India.
Gandhi and Tagore, who despite great mutual regard disagreed on many
issues (including the desirability of boycotting government schools and col-
leges during the Non-cooperation Movement), spoke as one on this issue.
In an article in Young India titled ‘‘Evil Wrought by the English Medium,’’
Gandhi wrote, ‘‘No country can become a nation by producing a race of imi-
tators.’’ 86 As long as Indians gained knowledge through a language alien to
them, learned with great difficulty and only ever imperfectly acquired, they
would be condemned to being imitators, a nation ‘‘in itself ’’ (a mere coun-
try) but not yet a nation for itself. A metaphor invoked again and again by
Gandhi was that of blotting paper; because Indian education occurred in
English, ‘‘we have become blind imitators of European civilization—mere
blotting papers.’’ 87 The point was not whether Indians should acquire west-
ern knowledge. Gandhi would often (though not always) concede that knowl-
edge of western science and literature might be a good thing, but only as
long as it was acquired in the vernaculars. On this Gandhi was consistent
and emphatic, from his early pronouncements to his later ones. Gandhi’s
scheme for a Basic National Education, announced in 1937, proposed compul-
sory and free education for all children from seven to fourteen, with the edu-
cation in the vernacular tongue of the region where the school was located,
a strong focus on handicraft production, and the goal of using the handi-
crafts and productive work to eventually make these schools economically
Vernacular Modernity 179
self-supporting. This plan, intended for an independent India, was a very
radical departure from both the colonial education system and indigenous
traditions, not least because the centrality it accorded to manual, handicraft
labor had no precedent in either.88 After this plan had been adopted by Con-
gress (with the modification that schools were expected to become only partly
self-supporting, and that too over time),89 Gandhi declared, ‘‘the medium of
instruction should be altered at once and at any cost, the provincial languages
being given their rightful place. I would prefer temporary chaos in higher
education to the criminal waste that is daily accumulating.’’ 90
More than Gandhi,Tagore would emphasize the richness of European cul-
ture and acknowledge that India had much to learn from Europe. The idea
behind his ‘‘East West’’ university was precisely that the East and West could
meet, and enrich each other. But all instruction had to be in the vernacu-
lar. The importance of the mother tongue was the main subject of Tagore’s
address to the convocation of Calcutta University in 1937, the first time the
convocation had been addressed in Bengali.91 Where Gandhi employed the
metaphor of blotting paper,Tagore favored the image of a parasite: ‘‘our mod-
ern school and college education . . . has from its inception been parasitic on
a foreign tongue . . . Accustomed to live by borrowing, it has come to measure
attainment by largeness of debt’’ (115). There was nothing wrong with bor-
rowing per se—Tagore rejected the criticism of those who decried everything
western as foreign, for ‘‘What if the seeds came from foreign parts, did they
not fall and sprout on our own soil? That which can grow and flourish in the
country no longer remains foreign’’ (119). Thus there was no question of re-
jecting the West, or the English language, or modernity. The issue was rather
one of recognizing that under the official system students had been ‘‘brought
up to absorb the thoughts of others . . . and their own faculty of thought . . .
their creative inspiration, have all been enfeebled’’ (116). ‘‘Those who receive
such education,’’ Tagore told his audience, ‘‘cannot produce what they con-
sume’’ (115–16). For Indians to become producers and not simply consumers
of modernity, it was necessary for them to assimilate ‘‘the subject-matter of
education through one’s own language, just as, in order to incorporate food-
stuffs into the body, they have to be chewed with one’s own teeth, saturated
with one’s own digestive juices’’ (116).
But this answer also met the other major criticism of these years, namely
that the existing education system was simply inefficacious, that it was fail-
ing to make Indians modern. Tagore told the Calcutta convocation: ‘‘On be-
half of writers in Bengali, and for myself, I would claim that we have been
180 Modern Knowledge, Modern Nation
engaged in the work of implanting modern culture in the heart of our coun-
try’’; indeed, writers in Bengali had been doing so with greater success than
the university had done, because they implanted this modernity in the lan-
guage of the people, so that it could take root (122). Even Gandhi, sometime
critic of modern civilization, could write, ‘‘Under my scheme there will be
more and better libraries, more and better laboratories, more and better re-
search institutes. Under it we should have an army of chemists, engineers
and other experts,’’ with the important difference that ‘‘all these experts will
speak, not a foreign language, but the language of the people.’’ 92
To champion vernacular education was therefore not to choose Indian-
ness over modernity; it was a means of reconciling national difference with a
global modernity, making it possible to be both modern and Indian. Not only
could one be Indian and modern at the same time, but it seemed that the one
presupposed the other. The nationalist resolution of the ‘‘problem’’ of educa-
tion thus provided two seemingly unconnected problems with one solution:
vernacular education was a critical element in making education ‘‘national,’’
and also in making it an effective vehicle for modernity. For India, declared
her nationalists, the Indian modern had to come in the form of vernacular
modernity.
Being Modern
Characterizing some of our contemporaries as premodern, and in this sense
as belonging to the past even as they inhabit the present, should now be ethi-
cally unsustainable. There is an enormous condescension in such a ‘‘denial
of coevalness’’ 3 and the social engineering that often springs from it—the
attempts to gift peoples with modernity, by force if necessary—has been dis-
astrous. It is also intellectually unsustainable. The peasants in the Bolivian
tin mines who worshiped the god Tio were nonetheless part of a world capi-
talist market.4 The aboriginal peoples who have survived dispossession and
genocide are not a ‘‘survival’’ of an ancient past but are very much imbricated
in the modern-present.5 Indian peasants who do not display the ‘‘modern
outlook’’ participate in the world capitalist market, and since 1947, as citi-
zens, they have been participants in India’s parliamentary democracy. And
the motley figures encountered in this book—crammers and dowry seekers,
vice-chancellors who consulted astrologers, Brahmin clerks and industrial-
ists, ‘‘proud Muslims,’’ nationalists, modern housewives and mothers—all
engaged with and negotiated modern institutions, ideas, and practices. What
could it possibly mean to characterize them as premodern? Or depict them
as caught in a no-man’s land, stranded between the banks of a premodern
that they have left behind, borne along by various currents to the shores of
a modernity not yet reached? As one historian (also rejecting this all-too-
familiar narrative) plaintively asks, ‘‘Why should modernity still await us in
India, more than two hundred years after its career was launched in India
by European imperialism? How long does it take for an Indian to become
modern?’’ 6
A similar dissatisfaction with the narrative of an incomplete transition to
modernity has led some to suggest that we should cease to privilege the pro-
cess and the form in which modernity first arrived in Europe, such that all
other regions of the world appear to have only an imperfect or incomplete
Knowing Modernity, Being Modern 189
version of this original. It has been proposed that we allow for alternative
modernities, or multiple modernities, so that we can think of India, China,
and areas elsewhere as also part of the modern, even though their modernity
does not look like modernity in the West. But if this is to be more than just
a matter of tinkering with definitions, it requires a fundamental rethinking
of our understanding of modernity.
Recognizing this, Charles Taylor rejects the narrative which privileges the
European experience, and which treats it as what all societies must undergo
if they are to be classed as modern. He characterizes this narrative or theory
as one in which ‘‘modernity is conceived as a set of transformations which
any and every culture can go through . . . Modernity in this kind of theory
is understood as issuing from a rational or social operation which is culture-
neutral . . . a general operation that can take any specific culture as its in-
put.’’ 7 In this theory, the specificities that distinguish ‘‘premodern’’ cultures
do not matter, not because they are all seen to be alike but because the
culture-neutral processes of modernization run steamroller-like over all such
specificities. That is why modernity is always singular, why India and China,
when they become modern, will look like Europe, minor differences aside.
But modernity is more than just a set of economic and institutional arrange-
ments: it is also the practices, beliefs, and background assumptions that en-
able these economic and institutional arrangements to function. Why does
this account assume that the background assumptions and practices of the
modern will not even be inflected in any major way by the traditions they
encounter—and replace? Because what is implicit and often explicit in this
account is theview that the presumptions connected with modernity,or what
Taylor calls the ‘‘culture of modernity,’’ are not on a par with other cultures.
It is not simply one more way of construing and constructing human iden-
tity and its place in the world: ‘‘At the heart of this explanation is the view
that modernity involves our ‘coming to see’ certain kernel truths about the
human condition,’’ 8 such as instrumental rationality, and the assumption
that the individual is somehow more basic and more real than any collective.9
What Taylor is referring to is precisely the narrative discussed above, a nar-
rative in which the core presumptions of modern thought are unjustifiably
accorded privilege, because they are regarded not as just one possible way of
construing the world but as the right way, finally uncovered.
Taylor rightly rejects this account of modernity, and the accompanying
narrative telling us that the culture of modernity is the privileged bearer of
certain universal and trans-historical truths. He offers instead a way of con-
190 Knowing Modernity, Being Modern
ceiving modernity in which the cultures of regions that become modern leave
a lasting imprint on that modernity: ‘‘If the transition to modernity is like
the rise of a new culture [then] the starting point will leave its impress on the
end product . . . transitions to what we might recognize as modernity, taking
place in different civilizations, will produce different results that reflect their
divergent starting points . . . new differences will emerge from the old. Thus,
instead of speaking of modernity in the singular, we should better speak of
‘alternative modernities.’ ’’ 10 And just as our usual understanding rests upon
the presumption that the culture of modernity becomes universalized be-
cause it ‘‘unveils’’ the truth that has been there all along, so too the plural-
ization of modernities can only proceed by rejecting this idea, including with
reference to the West: ‘‘It is not that we [modern Westerners] sloughed off a
whole lot of unjustified beliefs, leaving an implicit self-understanding that
had always been there to operate at last untrammelled. Rather, one constel-
lation of implicit understandings of our relation to God, the cosmos, other
humans, and time was replaced by another in a multifaceted mutation.’’ 11
Disputing the account which claims that modern thought uncovers uni-
versal truths opens the way to recognizing that societies can be part of the
modern without having their peoples become individuals, live in a disen-
chanted world, or embrace instrumental rationality. This account confuses
products with processes—it wrongly assumes that bureaucratic rationality
presupposes rational bureaucrats, that the production of universal science
requires universalist scientists, and that capitalism requires maximizing in-
dividuals.12 The account might only be adequate to characterizing and under-
standing western modernity—if that. I say ‘‘if that’’ because Taylor’s argu-
ment has a double implication.The reason why we have thought of modernity
as singular is not that we arrogantly generalized from the experience of the
West. It is rather that in this understanding, premodern or ‘‘traditional’’ cul-
tures—including those of the West—are assumed to have had representations
and enchantments and metaphysics and cosmologies, whereas we moderns
have come to grasp (or been forced to see) the bedrock truths that under-
pinned these various constructions all along. If that is mistaken—if moder-
nity does not mean the replacement of ‘‘mere’’ representations and mis-
understandings by truth, but rather the replacement of what Taylor calls
one ‘‘social imaginary’’ by another, a fact obscured or even repressed by the
knowledge through which we grasp the modern—then there is an impor-
tant sense in which this explanation is simply mistaken, and not mistaken
only inasmuch as it is unjustifiably generalized to account for the nonwest-
Knowing Modernity, Being Modern 191
ern world. If modernity need not imply disenchantment, individualism, and
instrumental reasoning, and yet modern knowledge is often conceived as the
fruit of that disenchantment, then that modern knowledge cannot be moder-
nity grasped in thought.
Knowing Modernity
Taylor makes some bold intellectual moves, with radical implications. Reject-
ing the idea that the presumptions and the knowledge produced by moder-
nity are the unveiling of universal truths, he suggests instead that what
marks modernity is the shift from one constellation of background presump-
tions to another. But there is one move that he is reluctant to make, one ele-
ment that he explicitly exempts from his argument—science. Although, as
we have seen, Taylor rejects the idea that modernity involves our ‘‘coming to
see’’ certain truths, and writes that ‘‘facets of what we identify as modern,
such as the tendency to try to split fact from value or the decline of religious
practice, are far from reposing on incontestable truths which have finally
been discovered,’’ he also immediately adds that this is a claim that can be
made for modern physics.13 ‘‘There is some justification,’’ Taylor writes, ‘‘for
talking of our ‘‘coming to see’’ the truth when we consider the revolution of
natural science which began in the seventeenth century.’’ 14 Taylor is here not
just saying that science and technology are among the stuff of any modernity,
a claim that is unexceptionable if the term modernity is not to be emptied
of all meaning. The problem with the conventional account of modernity,
he is saying, is its tendency to lump together those truths that we do ‘‘come
to see’’ (science) with those presumptions (instrumental reason, individual-
ism, etc.) that are part of the social imaginary accompanying and produced
by western modernity, but that are not universal truths finally uncovered.
The reason for this exclusion is presumably that to extend the argument to
include science might be tantamount to declaring that just as individual-
ism and instrumental rationality are a social imaginary like any other, and
cannot lay any claim to being the truth revealed, so too modern science and
nonmodern cosmologies are just, and equally, parts of different social imagi-
naries. This is not a conclusion that Taylor is willing to embrace, and if these
are the choices,which is how matters are often presented—one thinks of older
debates on whether Azande witchcraft is as good as modern science—there
are few willing to embrace it.
But these are not the only choices, and Taylor’s exclusion of science from
192 Knowing Modernity, Being Modern
the general thrust of his argument derives from his having insufficiently
emancipated himself from the explanation that he criticizes. At the heart of
Taylor’s exclusion is the idea that while cultures produce the world they then
inhabit, there is also a nature, which is outside culture, though different cul-
tures regard and explain it in different ways. Once we accept an ontology that
declares the world to be divided thus, it follows naturally that knowledge of
the world should also be divided thus. All that remains to be determined is
where the line is to be drawn: over which territory the ‘‘human sciences’’ can
claim sovereignty, and how far the writ of ‘‘natural sciences’’ runs. The most
aggressive champions of Nature have sometimes come close to claiming that
even culture can be explained by neurons and evolution. The diviners of cul-
ture, by contrast, have for the most part accepted the duality, and with great
humility have sought only to point out that causes did not always explain
meanings, that the world man created was different from the one he found,
and so on—in short, that culture had its own domain. In more recent times,
in the wake of aggressively ‘‘constructivist’’ arguments, they have ventured
to claim more than that. And so we continually redraw the lines and thereby
seek to annex territory, through extravagant claims for nature and science on
the one hand and an increasingly solipsistic ‘‘culturalism’’ on the other;15 or
rather, the majority in each camp happily till their own fields, leaving their
generals, the theoreticians, to dispute the no-man’s land in between.
For a long time we have assumed that this division is real—indeed, we be-
gan to do so at the beginnings of the modern age, when Bacon, Descartes,
Hobbes, Hume, and many others rejected and sometimes mocked the idea
that ‘‘natural philosophy’’ could use concepts of ‘‘final causes’’ and ‘‘purpose’’
in explanation. The conventional way in which we understand this history
is to regard these moderns as having ‘‘come to see’’ that Nature did not em-
body meanings or ‘‘have’’ ends, and thus as reassigning purpose and meaning
to Culture. But the modern idea of nature is not the Greek physis with ‘‘pur-
pose’’ eliminated from it, and neither was it constituted by simply reshuffling
and reassigning the medieval and early modern categories of the supernatu-
ral, preternatural, artificial, and unnatural into already available categories
of culture or nature. ‘‘To reconstruct the meanings and resonances of early
modern nature,’’ Lorraine Daston writes, ‘‘requires setting aside the mod-
ern opposition of nature versus culture,’’ for ‘‘the very categories of nature
and culture, conceived in yin-yang complementarity, are of relatively recent
provenance.’’ 16 Historians of science like Daston, and Shapin and Schaffer,17
and philosophers like Latour, have in recent times offered the beginnings of
Knowing Modernity, Being Modern 193
an alternative account, one that has us see modernity as that which invents
the idea or artefact of nature, and does so at the same time as it invents society
and culture.
What characterizes modernity, Latour argues, is not its discovery that
‘‘Nature’’ was disenchanted, but its creation of Nature on the one hand and
society and culture on the other. Meanings and values belonged by defini-
tion to the societal and cultural pole, and thus the very idea of Nature had
disenchantment ‘‘built into it’’: in modern self-understandings ‘‘becoming’’
modern ‘‘consists in continually exiting from an obscure age that mingled the
needs of society with scientific truth, in order to enter into a new age that will
finally distinguish clearly what belongs to atemporal nature and what comes
from humans, what depends on things and what depends on signs.’’ 18 Latour
calls this—the separation of humans from nonhumans, of Nature from cul-
ture, of that which has no meaning but can be known from that which is
nothing but meanings and values—the ‘‘Great Divide.’’ He argues that it ex-
plains the other great divide, that between us moderns and the premoderns.
As Michael Adas shows, some of the initial ways in which Europeans con-
ceived of their superiority to non-Europeans (such as the notion that they
had true religion, while others had false gods) increasingly yielded to expla-
nations emphasizing the superiority of European science and technology, a
superiority seen as attesting that ‘‘European modes of thought and social
organization corresponded much more closely to the underlying realities of
the universe than did those of any other people or society, past or present.’’ 19
Or in Latour’s words, since the time that we created Nature and Culture as
opposites, and organized our knowledge around their opposition, we have
with great self-satisfaction regarded ourselves as ‘‘the only ones who differ-
entiate absolutely between Nature and Culture, between Science and Society,
whereas in our eyes all the others—whether they are Chinese or Amerindian,
Azande or Barouya—cannot really separate what is knowledge from what is
Society, what is sign from what is thing, what comes from Nature as it is from
what their cultures require.’’ 20
In arguments such as this science is not privileged, as it is forTaylor.That is
because the object to which it corresponds—the nonhuman, Nature in oppo-
sition to society and culture—is not regarded as the surplus or residue once
we have pushed to the limit the argument that knowledge is a way of orga-
nizing and being in the world, and not simply a way of knowing it. Weber
was wrong to see disenchanted nature as a ‘‘discovery,’’ as an unveiling of
a truth, but right to see it as a defining feature of how western moderns
194 Knowing Modernity, Being Modern
thought, and how they constituted their world. It is what, in the view of west-
ern moderns, most clearly distinguishes them from all the premoderns—but
that view needs to be reconsidered. The rethinking need not take the form of
concluding that moderns also project their cultural categories onto nature,
while pretending otherwise—it need not lead us to declare that nature too is
part of culture, and that nuclear physics is as constructed as water divining
(and no more true). It can more fruitfully lead to questioning and problema-
tizing the distinction between nature and culture. Daston does so through
a historical enquiry which demonstrates the contingency of our organizing
categories. Latour’s way of doing so is to argue that we moderns, and others,
are all ‘‘nature-cultures.’’ 21 According to Latour, as this becomes increasingly
apparent (for a variety of reasons), we can recognize that the way we thought
and constituted ourselves as modern is deeply misleading. Historically, draw-
ing a distinction between Nature and Culture was constitutive of modernity,
but for that very reason it is not thereby the best medium for comprehending
it. On the contrary; it is an impediment to understanding modernity. When
we come to recognize that the world is not ontologically divided into nature
on the one hand and culture on the other—the distinction that we thought
we alone had grasped, and that constituted the dividing line between us mod-
erns and the premoderns—then we also come to realize, as Latour signals in
the provocative title of his book, that We Have Never Been Modern.
While the separation between Nature and Culture is undoubtedly essen-
tial to our sense of ourselves as modern, it is not the sole or defining feature
of that sense. There are other sources and features of modernity, and the idea
of modernity cannot be conjured away by showing Nature to be an idea that
moderns need(ed), rather than a fact that they unearthed. Modernity is real,
even if it is not what we thought it was. What I find most stimulating in
Latour’s book is not, however, its details, but rather the attempt to show that
while modern thought has played an important role in constituting moder-
nity, it is not thereby a privileged medium for comprehending it. In Latour’s
argument, more sharply than in Taylor’s, modern thought is not the mod-
ern grasped reflexively; indeed, it is in important ways a bad guide to the
modern, even if it is the only one we have. The arguments of Latour, Tay-
lor, and others—including those critics of Reason who draw their inspiration
from Nietzsche and Heidegger, and who have provided the intellectual back-
ground to this project, even though I have referred to them sparingly in the
preceding pages—help me to clarify the implications of my own arguments
in this book.
Knowing Modernity, Being Modern 195
Our knowledge is not the privileged bearer of universal insights. Knowl-
edge is not necessarily a relation between a knowing subject and an object
known; we are not even all subjects; the world is not disenchanted. These are
not truths that are finally grasped by modern knowledge, but rather what
it has helped to bring into being. Yet from this it does not follow that mod-
ern knowledge is homologous with modernity, or even (a more modest claim)
with the western variant thereof. Thought can be out of alignment with the
world that it purports to describe, and that it has brought into being. This
is not something we can know by stepping outside modern knowledge and
gaining unmediated access to the real, since we would still have to explain
how we are able to gain such access, and would in any case still be trapped
within the representational epistemology that I have sought to render prob-
lematic. But it is something we can seek to explore by other means.
I have sought to do this by examining how knowledge traveled. West-
ern knowledge arrived in India through the coercive agency of colonialism.
We were told, most forthrightly by Macaulay, that this knowledge was true
and that our own knowledges, like our gods, were false. I have read the dis-
courses that western education generated as perturbations on the surface of
this knowledge, half-acknowledgments that the ‘‘foundational assumptions’’
underpinning and enabling modern knowledge could not in fact be assumed.
Nonetheless, that knowledge has now become global. There is no easy point
outside it, no escape from it other than by engaging with and through it; thus
I write as one of Macaulay’s misbegotten offspring, working with this knowl-
edge to contribute to the self-questioning that renews intellectual traditions
and keeps them alive. There are myriad ways of doing so, and I do not claim
any privilege for the tack I have taken. But if those who were once ‘‘subject to
pedagogy’’ can, long after they are gone, be studied in a fashion that subjects
modern western knowledge to critical scrutiny, there is a pleasing irony in
the thought that Macaulay’s bastard children will have contributed to the
critical appropriation of a knowledge that was once imposed upon them.
Notes
Introduction
1. Minute recorded by Macaulay, law member of the Governor-General’s Coun-
cil, 2 February 1835, reprinted in Zastoupil and Moir, eds., The Great Indian Education
Debate, 166.
2. Despatch from the Court of Directors of the East India Company to the Gov-
ernor General of India, 19 July 1854, section 7, reprinted in Richey, ed., Selections from
Educational Records, 366. The reasoning behind this, the Court of Directors went on
to explain, was that ‘‘the systems of science and philosophy which form the learning
of the East abound with grave errors, and eastern literature is at best very deficient
as regards all modern discovery and improvements’’ (section 8, 366).
3. The universities of Punjab and Allahabad were established in 1882 and 1887,
and by 1929 thirteen further universities had been established.
4. Lee-Warner, The Citizen of India, 1897.
5. Report of the [Young] Committee on Educational Hygiene, 6.
6. The Maitland Prize Essay at Cambridge in 1886 distinguished between ‘‘educa-
tion in its widest sense,’’ namely ‘‘all that tends to revolutionize thought in India, and
to make it conform to the developments of Western civilization,’’ and ‘‘the system
of education’’ instituted by the colonial government. Haines, Education and Missions
in India and Elsewhere, 32. Sir Richard Temple, recalling his career as a senior colonial
official in India, distinguished between that education imparted through ‘‘contem-
plation of the example set by the British Government in India in its wise legislation’’
and that imparted through ‘‘definite instruction.’’ Men and Events of My Time in India,
494. Sir Narayan G. Chandarvarkar, the distinguished vice chancellor of Bombay Uni-
versity, told a conference that ‘‘the very presence of the British with their traditions
of liberty . . . [was] an education to the people,’’ one fortunately supplemented by
the decision in 1835 to provide western education to Britain’s Indian subjects. Sir
Narayan G. Chandarvarkar, ‘‘Presidential Address,’’ Report on the First Bombay Educa-
tional Conference, ed. Jamnadas M. Mehta (Bombay, 1917), 12.
7. The system of education was top-heavy, with a disproportionate emphasis on
colleges and universities. But the numbers involved at this level of the educational
system, as a proportion of the total population, were of course minuscule. At the
primary level enrollment figures remained abysmal: fewer than one-fifth of boys
eligible to attend classes 1–4 of elementary school were enrolled in an educational
197
198 Notes
institution by the turn of the century. Lord Curzon in India, 331; by 1921–22 that pro-
portion had increased to 31.5 percent and by 1936–37 had just passed the halfway
mark. Sargent, Progress of Education in India, 1932–37, 125, table lvi. However, even
these figures are highly misleading.The percentages were calculated on the assump-
tion that 15 percent of the population was of elementary school–going age, the figure
widely used in Europe; but in India, as was often pointed out, the true figure was
certainly much higher than this. Officialdom in the princely state of Travancore
estimated that 25 percent was a more likely figure (Report of the Administration for
Travancore for 1915–16, quoted in ‘‘Percentage of Persons of School-Going Age,’’ Modern
Review, December 1917, 626–27). The Government of India continued to use 15 per-
cent, which made the numbers enrolled appear artificially high, but in-house official
correspondence acknowledged that the figure was misleading (Letter from Govern-
ment of India to Government of United Provinces, 4 January 1907, Home Education,
January 1907, 13(A), National Archives of India). Moreover, the figures on numbers
actually enrolled did not convey much information—they did not reveal how many
of those enrolled in educational institutions actually attended them regularly; and
‘‘wastage rates’’ were extremely high, meaning that a large number of those who en-
rolled in elementary school did not proceed as far as the fourth grade, conventionally
calculated as the minimum level of schooling necessary to achieve literacy.
8. Trevelyan, On the Education of the People of India, 13.
9. Pioneer, 10 January 1888.
10. Mahmood, A History of English Education in India, 1.
11. K.V.A., ‘‘Calcutta University Reform,’’ 10.
12. Among them Chakrabarty, Provincializing Europe; Mignolo, The Darker Side of
the Renaissance; Mitchell, Colonizing Egypt; and Nandy, The Intimate Enemy.
13. Foucault, ‘‘About the Beginnings of a Hermeneutics of the Self,’’ 223 n. 4.
14. ‘‘The fate of an epoch which has eaten of the tree of knowledge,’’ Weber wrote,
‘‘is that it must know that we cannot learn the meaning of the world from the re-
sults of its analysis, be it ever so perfect; it must rather be in a position to create this
meaning itself.’’ ‘‘Objectivity in Social Science and Social Policy,’’ 57.
15. Taylor, Hegel, 5.
16. He writes, ‘‘the transcendental presupposition of any cultural science lies in the
fact that we are cultural beings, endowed with the capacity and the will to take a delib-
erate attitude towards the world and to lend it significance.’’ Weber, ‘‘Objectivity in
Social Science and Social Policy,’’ 81. I will consider this passage and the claim made
in it in much greater detail in chapter 3.
17. ‘‘The world picture does not change from an earlier medieval one into a mod-
ern one, but rather the fact that theworld becomes picture at all is what distinguishes
the essence of the modern age.’’ Heidegger, ‘‘The Age of the World Picture,’’ 130.
18. Heidegger, Nietzsche, 17.
19. Heidegger was aware that drawing attention to what is different about the
modern situation can lend itself to historicist readings. His insistence that man be-
Notes 199
comes subject only with modernity ‘‘might give rise,’’ he writes, ‘‘to the notion that
the innermost history of metaphysics and of the change in its basic positions is
simply a history of the alteration in man’s self-conception.This opinion would corre-
spond completely to contemporary anthropological modes of thought. But it would
be an erroneous notion . . . in fact it would be the one error it is necessary to overcome.’’
Nietzsche, 138, emphasis added.
20. Poovey, ‘‘The Liberal Civil Subject and the Social,’’ 130.
21. The classic account and critique of this conception is Rorty, Philosophy and the
Mirror of Nature.
22. Chatterjee, The Nation and Its Fragments, chapter 6.
Unpublished Sources
Barry Papers, Cambridge South Asia Centre Library
Church of Scotland Foreign Mission Papers, ms 7530, National Library of Scotland
Government of India, Education Proceedings, 1911–1920, National Archives of India
Hartog Papers, mss Eur E 221, India and Oriental Research Collection, British
Library
Hicks Papers, Cambridge South Asia Centre Library
Government of India, Home Department (Education) Proceedings, 1869–1910,
National Archives of India
Orange Papers, Cambridge South Asia Centre Library
235
236 Bibliography
General Report on Public Instruction in the Lower Provinces of Bengal for 1857–58.
Calcutta, 1859.
General Report on Public Instruction in the Lower Provinces of the Bengal Presidency for
1844–45. Calcutta: Sanders and Cone, 1845.
General Report on Public Instruction in the Lower Provinces of the Bengal Presidency for
1859–60. Calcutta, 1861.
General Report on Public Instruction in the Lower Provinces of Bengal for 1860–61.
Calcutta, 1862.
Indian Educational Policy, Being a Resolution Issued by the Governor-General in Council on
the 21st February, 1913. Calcutta: Superintendent of Government Printing, 1913.
Indian Educational Policy: Resolution of the Government of India in the Home Department,
11th March, 1904. Calcutta: Superintendent of Government Printing, 1904.
Indian Universities [Raleigh] Commission Report. Simla, 1902.
Orange, H. W. Progress of Education in India, 1902–1907. Calcutta: Superintendent of
Government Printing, 1909.
Punjab University Enquiry [Anderson] Committee Report. Lahore: Superintendent of
Government Printing, 1933.
Report of the [Bombay] Board of Education for the Year 1845. Bombay: Government Press,
1847.
Report of the [Bombay] Board of Education for the Year 1846. Bombay: American Mission
Press, 1847.
Report of the [Bombay] Board of Education for the Year 1849. Bombay: Bombay
Education Society, 1851.
Report of the [Bombay] Board of Education from Jan 1, 1850, to April 30, 1851. Bombay:
Bombay Education Society, 1851.
Report of the [Bombay] Board of Education from May 1, 1851, to April 30, 1852. Bombay:
Bombay Education Society, 1852.
Report of the Committee Appointed by the Bengal Government to Consider Questions
Connected with Muhammadan Education. Calcutta, 1915.
Report of the [Young] Committee on Educational Hygiene. Naini Tal, 1913.
Report of the [Piggot] Committee on Primary Education. United Provinces, 1913.
Report of the [More] Committee on the Training of Primary Teachers. Bombay:
Government Central Press, 1938.
Report of the Director for Public Instruction, Bombay, for the Year 1863–64. Bombay:
Bombay Education Society, 1865.
Report of the Director of Public Instruction in the Bombay Presidency for the Year 1872–73.
Bombay, 1874.
Report of the General Committee of Public Instruction for the Presidency of Fort William in
Bengal for 1838–39. Calcutta: Military Orphan Press, 1840.
Report of the Indian Education [Hunter] Commission. Calcutta: Superintendent of
Government Printing, 1883.
Bibliography 237
Report of the National Committee on Women’s Education (May 1958 to January 1959).
Ministry of Education, 1959.
Report of the Travancore Education Reforms Committee. Trivandrum: Superintendent,
Government Press, 1934.
Report of the Unemployment [Sapru] Committee. Allahabad, 1936.
Report on Public Instruction in the Madras Presidency for 1881–82. Madras: Government
Press, 1883.
Sargent, John. Progress of Education in India, 1932–37. Delhi: Manager of Publications,
1940.
. Progress of Education in India, 1937–47: Decennial Review. Ministry of
Education, n.d. [1948].
Contemporary Sources
Adam, William. Reports on the State of Education in Bengal (1835 and 1838), ed.
Anathnath Basu. Calcutta: University of Calcutta, 1941.
Ahmad, M. M. Zuhurrudin. Present Day Problems of Indian Education (with Special
Reference to Muslim Education). Bombay, 1935.
Aiyangar, Rangaswami. Foreword. Messages to Indian Students (An Anthology of
Famous Convocation Addresses), ed. Purushottam Das Tandon. Allahabad:
Students’ Friends, 1936.
Aiyar, R. Rangaswami. ‘‘Is the Teaching Profession Calculated to Attract the Best
Type of Men?’’ Educational Review, June 1920.
An Address by S. C. Roy, Delivered on the Anniversary of the Students Weekly Service.
Cuttack: Star, 1911.
An Appeal to the British Nation for the Promotion of Education in India. Calcutta:
Calcutta Printing and Publishing, n.d. [1861].
‘‘A Native Philomath.’’ High Education in Bengal and the University of Calcutta.
Calcutta: Imperial Victoria, 1888.
Anuntharow, V. Female Education. N.p., 1916.
Archer, William. India and the Future. London: Hutchinson, 1917.
Banerjea, K. M. A Prize Essay on Native Female Education. Calcutta: Bishops College,
1841.
Banerjee, Gooroo Dass. Reminiscences, Speeches and Writings of Sir Gooroo Dass Banerjee,
comp. Upendra Chandra Banerjee. Calcutta: Narkeldanga, 1927.
Banerji, Nripendra Chandra. The Ideal of Swaraj in Education and Government.
Madras: Ganesh, 1921.
Banerji, Sasadhar. ‘‘Discipline.’’ Educational Review, January 1920.
Basu, Amrita Krishna. The Introduction of English and Its Effects on Bengalee Society:
A Paper Read in a Meeting of the Simla Literary Society on 10th July 1871. Calcutta:
Local, 1873.
238 Bibliography
Basu, B. D. The History of Education in India under the Rule of the East India Company.
Calcutta: Modern Review Office, n.d.
Besant, Annie. Wake Up, India. Madras: Theosophical Publishing, 1913.
Bhandarkar, Ramakrishna Gopal. The Bombay University Convocation Address of 1894,
Delivered by Ramakrishna Gopal Bhandarkar, Vice-Chancellor of Bombay University.
Bombay: Indian Printing, 1894.
Bhatt, Balkrishna. Bhatt Nibandhamala [Collected Essays]. Kashi [Benares]: Nagari
Pracharani Sabha, 1947.
. ‘‘Striyan’’ [Women] [1891]. Bhatt Nibandhamala [Collected Essays]. Kashi
[Benares]: Nagari Pracharani Sabha, 1947.
Bilgrami, Syed. Presidential Address at 26th Annual Session of the All India Muhammadan
Educational Conference, Lucknow, Dec 28, 1912. Delhi, 1913.
Bose, Pramatha Nath. National Education and Modern Progress. Calcutta: Kar,
Majumdar, n.d. [?1921].
Bryce, James. The Schoolmaster and the Missionary in India. Edinburgh, 1856.
Butler, Harcourt. Collection of Speeches. Rangoon: Government Press, n.d. [1927].
Chanda, Ramaprasad. ‘‘Future of Education in Bengal.’’ Modern Review, September
1917.
Chattopadhyaya, Goutam, ed. Awakening in Bengal in Early Nineteenth Century
(Selected Documents). Calcutta: Progressive, 1965.
Chaturvedi, S. N. The History of Rural Education in the United Provinces of Agra and
Oudh (1840–1926). Allahabad: Indian Press, 1930.
. An Educational Survey of a District, Being a Quantitative Study of Vernacular
Primary and Secondary Education in the District of Etawah in the United Provinces of
Agra and Oudh. Allahabad: Indian Press, 1935.
Coomaraswamy, A. K. ‘‘Education in India.’’ National Education, ed. H. V. Dugvekar.
Benares, 1917.
Cornelius, John J. A Study of Tagore’s Experiment in the Indianization of Education in the
Light of India’s History. Madras, 1930.
‘‘Correspondence on the Subject of the Education of the Muhammadan
Community in British India and Their Employment in the Public Service
Generally.’’ Selections from the Records of the Government of India: Home Department.
Calcutta, 1886.
‘‘Correspondence Relating to Education in the Lower Provinces of Bengal.’’
Selections from the Records of the Bengal Government, vol. 22. Calcutta, 1855.
Curzon, Lord. Lord Curzon in India, Being a Selection from His Speeches as Viceroy and
Governor-General of India, 1898–1905. London: Macmillan, 1906.
. Principles and Methods of University Reform, Being a Letter Addressed to the
University of Oxford. Oxford: Clarendon, 1909.
Dacca University Convocation Speeches, 1929–46. N.p., n.d.
Das, Santosh Kumar. The Educational System of the Ancient Hindus. Calcutta: Mitra,
1930.
Bibliography 239
Datta, T. K. What English Education Has Made of Us. Lahore: Doaba House, n.d. [1939].
Day, Lal Behari. Bengal Peasant Life, Folktales of Bengal, Recollections of My School-Days,
ed. Mahadevprasad Saha. Calcutta: Editions Indian, 1969.
. Primary Education in Bengal: A Lecture Delivered at the Bethune Society on
10 December 1868. Calcutta: Barham, Hill, 1869.
Dayal, Har. ‘‘The Social Conquest of the Hindu Race.’’ Modern Review, September
1909.
. ‘‘Some Phases of Contemporary Thought in India.’’ Modern Review,
November 1912.
. Thoughts on Education. New Delhi: Rajdhani Granthagar, n.d. [1908].
Dayal, Sibeswar. Female Education: How It Can Be Best Effected in Behar. Bankipore:
Behar Bandhu, 1908.
Dippie, H. ‘‘Principles of Education and Class Teaching.’’ Instruction in Indian
Primary Schools. Bombay: Oxford University Press, 1936.
Duff, Alexander. India and India Missions. Edinburgh: John Johnstone, 1839.
. Missionary Addresses. Edinburgh: Johnstone and Hunter, 1850.
. New Era of English Language and English Literature in India. Edinburgh, 1839.
Dugvekar, H. V., ed. National Education. Benares, 1917.
Dutt, G. S. A Woman of India, Being the Life of Saroj Nalini. London, 1929 [orig. pubd in
Bengali, 1926].
Elphinstone, Mountstuart. Selections from the Minutes and the Official Writings of the
Honourable Mountstuart Elphinstone, Governor of Bombay, ed. George W. Forrest.
London: Richard Bentley and Son, 1884.
Fuller, Bampfylde, The Empire of India. London: Isaac Pitman and Sons, 1913.
Gandhi, M. K. The Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi, vol. 48. Ahmedabad:
Navajivan Trust, 1958–2000.
. ‘‘Drain Inspector’s Report.’’ Young India, 1919–1931, vol. 9. Ahmedabad:
Navajivan, 1981.
. The Problem of Education. Ahmedabad: Navajivan, 1962.
. Young India: 1919–1931, vol. 9. Ahmedabad: Navajivan, 1981.
Gauba, Kanhaya Lal. Uncle Sham: The Strange Tale of a Civilization Run Amuck. New
York: Claude Kendall, 1929.
Ghosh, Aurobindo. National Education. Allahabad: Leader, 1918.
Ghosh, J. Higher Education in Bengal under British Rule. Calcutta: Book Company, 1926.
Gupta, K. C. Addresses on Educational Matters. Cuttack, 1901.
Haines, C. R. Education and Missions in India and Elsewhere. Cambridge: Deighton,
Bell and Sons, 1886 [Maitland Prize Essay, 1886].
The Hindu University: The Deputation in Calcutta. Calcutta, 1911.
Holmes, W. H. G. ‘‘University Education in Bengal.’’ Hindustan Review 23 (March–
April 1911).
Hunter, W. W. The Indian Musalmans. Lahore: Premier Book House, 1964 [1871].
. A Life of the Earl of Mayo, 2nd edn, vol. 2. London: Smith, Elder, 1876.
240 Bibliography
Huque, M. Azizul. History and Problems of Moslem Education in Bengal. Calcutta:
Thacker, Spink, 1917.
Indian Problems: Speeches by Lord Irwin. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1932.
Instruction in Indian Primary Schools. Bombay: Oxford University Press, 1936.
Iyer, C. S. Ranga. Father India. London: Selwyn and Blount, 1927.
Karim, Abdul. Muhammedan Education in Bengal. Calcutta, 1900.
Keane, William. A Letter to the Late Honourable J. E. D. Bethune, Esq., on the Present
State, and Results of Government Public Instruction in Bengal. Madras, 1851.
Keay, F. E. Indian Education in Ancient and Later Times. Oxford University Press, 1938.
Kerr, J. A Review of Public Instruction in the Bengal Presidency from 1835 to 1851, pt 1.
Calcutta, 1852.
K.V.A. ‘‘Calcutta University Reform.’’ Modern Review, July 1918.
Lee-Warner, William. The Citizen of India. London: Macmillan, 1897.
Lethbridge, Roper. High Education in India: A Plea for the State Colleges. London: W. H.
Allen, 1882.
‘‘Loyalty and Disloyalty.’’ Native Review, 8 June 1873.
Mahmood, Syed. A History of English Education in India. Delhi: Idarah-I Adabiyat-I
Delli, 1981 [1895].
Malaviya, Madan Mohan. The Hindu University of Benares: Why It Is Wanted and What
It Aims at. Allahabad, 1911.
Mayo, Katherine. Mother India. New York: Greenwood, 1969 [1927].
. Slaves of the Gods. London: Jonathan Cape, 1929.
. Volume Two. London: Jonathan Cape, 1931.
McDougall, Eleanor. Lamps in the Wind: South Indian College Women and Their
Problems. London: Edinburgh House, 1943 [1940].
. Women’s Christian College, Madras, 1919–1925. Madras: Madras Diocesan, n.d.
Mehta, Nagindas P. The Problem of Our Young Men after Leaving Schools and Colleges.
Bombay, 1915.
‘‘Memorial of the Central National Muhammadan Association,’’ presented to
Chelmsford and Montagu. Addresses Presented to Lord Chelmsford and Montagu,
unpublished collation, Nehru Memorial Museum and Library.
Mill, James. The History of British India. New Delhi: Atlantic, 1990 [1817].
The Miscellaneous Writings of the Late Hon’ble Mr. Justice M. G. Ranade. Bombay:
Manoranjan, 1915.
Mittra, Baboo Peary Chand. ‘‘A Few Desultory Remarks on . . . Reverend K. M.
Banerjea’s Prize Essay on Native Female Education’’ [January 1842]. Awakening
in Bengal in Early Nineteenth Century (Selected Documents), ed. Goutam Chatto-
padhyaya. Calcutta: Progressive, 1965.
Mohammad, Shan, ed. Writings and Speeches of Sir Syed Ahmad Khan. Bombay:
Nachiketa, 1972.
Muhammad, Shan, ed. The Aligarh Movement: Basic Documents, 1864–1898, vol. 3.
Meerut: Meenakshi Prakashan, 1978.
Bibliography 241
Mukerjee, Satischandra. An Examination into the Present System of University Education
in India and a Scheme of Reform. Calcutta, 1902.
Muller, Max. Anthropological Religion. London: Longmans, Green, 1892.
. Lectures on the Origin and Growth of Religion. Varanasi: Indological Book
House, 1964.
Murdoch, John. India’s Greatest Educational Need: The Adequate Recognition of Ethics in
Her Present Transition State. London, 1904.
Muslim Education, with Special Reference to the Madrasa-i-Azam. Madras, 1916.
Natarajan, K. Miss Mayo’s Mother India, 3rd edn. Madras: G. A. Nateson, 1928.
Nehru, Jawaharlal. Towards Freedom. New York: John Day, 1941.
O’Malley, L. S. S. Popular Hinduism: The Religion of the Masses. New York: Johnson
Reprint, 1970 [1935].
Pal, Bipan Chandra. Memories of My Life and Times. Calcutta: Bipanchandra Pal
Institute, 1973.
[Pannalala of Sujangarh.] Vanitabodhini, 2nd edn. Bombay: Karnatak, 1896.
Papers Connected with the Punjab University Question, Collected and Published by the
Executive Committee of the Indian Association. Lahore, 1881.
‘‘Papers Regarding the Educational Conference, Allahabad, February 1911.’’ Selections
from the Records of the Government of India, vol. 448. Calcutta, 1911.
‘‘Papers Relating to Discipline and Moral Training in Schools and Colleges of
India.’’ Selections from the Records of the Government of India (Home Department),
vol. 265. Calcutta: Superintendent of Government Printing, 1890.
‘‘Papers Relating to Public Instruction.’’ Selections from the Records of the Madras
Government, vol. 2. Madras, 1855.
Parulekar, R. V., ed. Survey of Indigenous Education in the Province of Bombay (1820–
1830). Bombay: Asia Publishing, 1945.
‘‘Percentage of Persons of School-Going Age.’’ Modern Review, December 1917.
Pioneer, 10 January 1888.
‘‘Politicus.’’ ‘‘A Peep into the History of Sanskrit Education in British India.’’ Modern
Review, August 1916.
Prabhu, R. K., and R. Kelekar, eds. Truth Called Them Differently (Tagore-Gandhi
Controversy). Ahmedabad: Navajivan, 1961.
Prasad, Ram. Teaching the Teacher. Allahabad, 1915.
Premchand. ‘‘Gorakhpur me Shiksha Sammelan’’ [Education Conference in
Gorakhpur, 1933]. Premchand ke Vicar [Thoughts of Premchand]. Allahabad:
Saraswati, 1988.
The Problem of Urdu Teaching in the Bombay Presidency. Government of Bombay, 1914.
Proceedings of the Punjab Educational Conference and Exhibition, Held in December 1926,
ed. J. E. Parkinson and R. H. Whitehouse. N.p., n.d.
‘‘The Public Services Commission and the Educational Service.’’ Modern Review,
August 1917.
Rai, Lajpat. The Arya Samaj. Lahore: Uttar Chand Kapur and Sons, 1932.
242 Bibliography
. Introduction. Thoughts on Education, by Har Dayal. New Delhi: Rajdhani
Granthagar, n.d. [1908].
. The Problem of National Education in India. London: Allen and Unwin, 1920.
Ranade, M. G. The Miscellaneous Writings of the Late Hon’ble Mr. Justice M. G. Ranade.
Bombay: Manoranjan, 1915.
Rao, K. Subba, ed. Convocation Addresses of the Universities of Bombay and Madras.
Madras: Lawrence Asylum, 1892.
Ratcliffe, S. K. ‘‘The Teaching of Morals and Religion.’’ Modern Review 4 (1908).
Ray, Prafulla Chandra. Essays and Discourses by Professor Prafulla Chandra Ray. Madras:
G. A. Nateson, 1918.
Reddy, C. Ramalinga. An Address to Students. Madras, 1910.
Reminiscences, Speeches and Writings of Sir Gooroo Dass Banerjee. Calcutta: Narkeldanga,
1927.
Report of the All-India Educational Conference, Calcutta, Dec 26–30, 1937, ed. R. M. Roy.
Calcutta, 1938.
Report of the Bengal Women’s Educational Conference. N.p., 1927.
Report of the First Bombay Educational Conference, ed. Jamnadas M. Mehta. Bombay,
1917.
Report of the Madras Educational Conference, Held on 21st and 22nd December, 1896.
Madras: Varodochari, 1897.
Report of the Proceedings of a Conference on Moral, Civic and Sanitary Instruction, Held on
6th and 7th April, 1910. Bombay: Bombay Guardian Mission, 1910.
Richey, J. A., ed. Selections from Educational Records. Calcutta: Superintendent
Government Printing, 1922.
Richter, Julius. A History of Missions in India, trans. Sydney Moore. Edinburgh:
Oliphant, Anderson and Ferrier, 1908.
Ronaldshay, Lord. India: A Bird’s-Eye View. London: Constable, 1924.
Roy Chowdhury, M. N. A Humble Appeal of a Humble Heart. N.p., n.d.
Roy, Krishna Chandra. High Education and the Present Position of Graduates in Arts and
Law of the Calcutta University. Calcutta, 1882.
Saiyidain, K. G. ‘‘Experiments in Education.’’ Indian Review, November 1915.
Sarkar, Benoy Kumar. The Pedagogy of the Hindu. Calcutta: Chuckerverty Chatterjee,
1912.
Sarkar, Jadunath. ‘‘Confessions of a History Teacher.’’ Modern Review, December
1915.
Sarkar, Jadunath. ‘‘The Vernacular Medium: Views of an Old Teacher.’’ Modern
Review, January 1918.
Sastri, Sivanath. A History of the Renaissance in Bengal: Ramtanu Lahiri, Brahman and
Reformer. Calcutta: Editions Indian, 1972 [1904].
Satthianadhan, S. History of Education in the Madras Presidency. Madras: Srinivasa,
Varadachari, 1894.
Selected Papers Read at Divisional Conferences Held in 1896. N.p., n.d.
Bibliography 243
The Selected Works of Maulana Abul Kalam Azad, ed. Ravindra Kumar, vol. 3. New
Delhi: Atlantic, 1991–92.
Sen, J. M. History of Elementary Education in India. Calcutta: Book Company, 1933.
Sen, Keshub Chunder. Letters on Educational Measures to Lord Northbrook, ed. G. C.
Banerjee. N.p., 1936.
Setalvad. Indian University Commission: Letters Addressed to ‘‘The Times of India’’ on the
Vice-Chancellor’s Vindication of Its Recommendations. Bombay, 1903.
Sharp, H. Rural Schools in the Central Provinces. Calcutta: Office of the Director-
General of Education in India, 1904.
Sherring, M. A. The History of Protestant Missions in India. London: Trübner, 1875.
Short Essays and Reviews on the Educational Policy of the Government of India, Reprinted
from the ‘‘Englishman.’’ Calcutta, 1866.
Shrivastava, S. N. L. ‘‘Some Aspects of Our Present Educational System.’’ Indian
Review, September 1940.
Sinha, Prabodh Chandra. Problem of Education in Bengal. Calcutta: Thacker, Spink,
1941.
Sinha, Sasadhar. ‘‘The Past, Present and Future of Indian Education.’’ Modern
Review, January 1936.
Smith, George. The Life of Alexander Duff. London: Hodder and Stoughton, 1879.
Speech of the Duke of Marlborough upon the Exclusion of the Bible from Government
Schools, House of Lords, 2nd July 1860. London: W. H. Dalton.
Subrahmanyam, S. ‘‘National Education: Literary or Technical?’’ Educational Review,
January 1921.
Sundaram, V. A., ed. Benares Hindu University, 1905 to 1935. Benares: Tata, 1936.
Tagore, Rabindranath. ‘‘Calcutta University Convocation Address, 1937.’’ University
of Calcutta Convocation Addresses, vol. 7 (1935–38).
. ‘‘The Diffusion of Education.’’ Modern Review, July 1939.
. ‘‘Indian Students and Western Teachers.’’ Modern Review, April 1916.
. ‘‘My School.’’ Modern Review, May 1925.
. ‘‘The Parrot’s Training.’’ Modern Review, March 1918 [repr. in Elmhirst,
Rabindranath Tagore; and Rabindranath Tagore: An Anthology, ed. Krishna Dutta
and Andrew Robinson (London: Picador, 1997)].
. ‘‘The Schoolmaster.’’ Modern Review, October 1924.
. ‘‘To the Child.’’ Modern Review, May 1925.
Tandon, Purushottam Das, ed. Messages to Indian Students (An Anthology of Famous
Convocation Addresses). Allahabad: Students’ Friends, 1936.
Temple, Richard. Men and Events of My Time in India. Delhi: BR, 1985 [1882].
Thapar, K. B., ed. Convocation Addresses of the Universities of Allahabad and Punjab.
Lahore, 1895.
. Convocation Addresses of the University of the Punjab. Lahore: Addison, 1903.
Thompson, Edward, and G. T. Garrat. Rise and Fulfilment of British Rule in India.
Allahabad: Central Book Depot, 1966 [repr.].
244 Bibliography
Trevelyan, C. E. On the Education of the People of India. London: Longman, Orme,
Brown Green and Longman, 1838.
University of Calcutta Convocation Addresses, University of Calcutta, 1914; 2nd edn.
1936.
Vankelal. Nari Sudasha Pravartak [Foundations of Women’s Welfare]. Allahabad,
1893–95.
Venkateswara, S. V. Indian Culture through the Ages. London: Longmans, Green, 1928.
Verma, Vishveshvar Nath. Shiksha-Samhar [Destruction of Education]. N.p., 1921.
Wanchoo, H. N. Studies in Indian Education. Allahabad: Allahabad Law Journal, 1934.
‘‘Watchman.’’ Higher Education and Popular Control. Calcutta, 1916.
Welinkar. Our Young Men: Two Lectures. Bombay: Bombay Guardian Mission, n.d.
[?1909].
Whitehead, Henry. The Village Gods of South India. Madras: Asian Educational Series,
1988 [1921].
Wood, Ernest. Selected Articles on National Education. Hyderabad, Sind: Sind, 1917.
World-Citizen. Sister India. Bombay: Sister India Office, n.d.
Zaidi, A. M., ed. Congress Presidential Addresses. New Delhi: Indian Institute of
Applied Political Research, 1985–.
Zaidi, A. M., and S. G. Zaidi, eds. The Encyclopaedia of the Indian National Congress.
New Delhi: S. Chand.
Other Works
Achyuthan, Mavelikara. Educational Practices in Manu, Panini and Kautilya.
Trivandrum: College Book House, 1974.
Adas, Michael. Machines as the Measure of Men. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989.
Ahmed, Rafiuddin. The Bengal Muslims, 1871–1906: A Quest for Identity. Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1981.
Allen, N. J., W. S. F. Pickering, and W. Watts Miller, eds. On Durkheim’s Elementary
Forms of Religious Life. London: Routledge, 1998.
Altekar, A. S. Education in Ancient India, 5th edn. Varanasi: Nand Kishore and Bros.,
1965.
Amin, Sonia Nishat. The World of Muslim Women in Colonial Bengal, 1876–1939.
Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1996.
Anderson, Benedict. Imagined Communities, 2nd edn. London: Verso, 1991.
. The Specter of Comparisons. New York: Verso, 1998.
Anderson, Perry. Passages from Antiquity to Feudalism. London: Verso, 1978.
Appadurai, Arjun. ‘‘Number in the Colonial Imagination.’’ Orientalism and the
Postcolonial Predicament, ed. Carol Breckenridge and Peter van der Veer.
Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1993.
Appleby, Joyce, Lynn Hunt, and Margaret Jacob. Telling the Truth about History. New
York: W. W. Norton, 1994.
Bibliography 245
Archer, William. India and the Future. London: Hutchinson, 1917.
Arnold, David, and David Hardiman, eds. Subaltern Studies VIII. Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1994.
Asad, Talal. ‘‘The Concept of Cultural Translation in British Social Anthropology.’’
Writing Culture, ed. James Clifford and G. E. Marcus. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1986.
. Genealogies of Religion. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993.
Austin, Granville. The Indian Constitution: Cornerstone of a Nation. Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1999.
Babb, Lawrence. The Divine Hierarchy: Popular Hinduism in Central India. New York:
Columbia University Press, 1975.
Bagal, Jogesh Chandra. Women’s Education in Eastern India: The First Phase. Calcutta:
World Press, 1956.
Bagchi, Jasodhara. ‘‘Representing Nationalism: Ideology of Motherhood in Colonial
Bengal.’’ Economic and Political Weekly, 20 October 1990, 27 October 1990.
Baker, Keith Michael. ‘‘Enlightenment and the Institution of Society: Notes for a
Conceptual History.’’ Civil Society: History and Possibilities, ed. S. Kaviraj and
S. Khilnani. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Balagangadhara, S. N. ‘‘The Heathen in His Blindness . . .’’: Asia, the West and the
Dynamic of Religion. Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1994.
Bambach, Charles. Heidegger, Dilthey, and the Crisis of Historicism. Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1995.
Banerjee, Sumanta. ‘‘Marginalization of Women’s Popular Culture in Nineteenth
Century Bengal.’’ Recasting Women, ed. Kumkum Sangari and Sudesh Vaid. New
Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1990.
Banerji, Himani. ‘‘Attired in Virtue: The Discourse on Shame (lajja) and Clothing of
the Bhadramahila in Colonial Bengal.’’ From the Seams of History: Essays on Indian
Women, ed. Bharati Ray. Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1995.
. ‘‘Fashioning a Self.’’ Economic and Political Weekly, 26 October 1991.
Barash, Jeffrey. Martin Heidegger and the Problem of Historical Meaning. Dordrecht:
Martinus Nijhoff, 1988.
Barrier, N. Gerald, ed. The Census in British India. New Delhi: Manohar, 1981.
Barry, Andrew, Thomas Osborne, and Nikolas Rose. Introduction. Foucault and
Political Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996.
, eds. Foucault and Political Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996.
Basu, Aparna. The Growth of Education and Political Development in India, 1898–1920.
Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1974.
. ‘‘National Education in Bengal: 1905–1912.’’ The Contested Terrain: Perspectives
on Education in India, ed. Sabyasachi Bhattacharya. New Delhi: Orient Longman,
1998.
Berkemer, G., et al., eds. Explorations in the History of South Asia: Essays in Honour of
Dieter Rothmund. New Delhi: Manohar, 2001.
246 Bibliography
Bhagavan, Manu. Sovereign Spheres: Princes, Education and Empire in Colonial India.
New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2003.
Bhate, Saroja. ‘‘Position of Sanskrit in Public Education and Scientific Research in
Modern India.’’ Ideology and Status of Sanskrit, ed. Jan E. M. Houben. Leiden: E. J.
Brill, 1996.
Bhattacharya, Sabyasachi, ed. The Contested Terrain: Perspectives on Education in India.
New Delhi: Orient Longman, 1998.
Bloch, Marc. The Historian’s Craft, trans. P. Putnam. Manchester: Manchester
University Press, 1979.
Borthwick, Meredith. The Changing Role of Women in Bengal, 1849–1905. Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1984.
Bourdieu, Pierre. ‘‘The Berber House.’’ Rules and Meaning, ed. Mary Douglas. New
York: Penguin, 1973.
Breckenridge, Carol, and Peter van der Veer, eds. Orientalism and the Postcolonial
Predicament. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1993.
Brown, Emily C. Har Dayal: Hindu Revolutionary and Rationalist. Tucson: University
of Arizona Press, 1975.
Brown, Wendy. States of Injury. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995.
Burchell, Graham, Colin Gordon, and Peter Miller, eds. The Foucault Effect. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1991.
Burckhardt, Jacob. The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy, trans. S. C. G.
Middlemore. New York: Mentor, 1960.
Burton, Antoinette. Burdens of History: British Feminists, Indian Women, and Imperial
Culture, 1865–1915. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1994.
, ed. Gender, Sexuality and Colonial Modernities. London: Routledge, 1999.
Byrne, Peter. Natural Religion and the Nature of Religion: The Legacy of Deism. London:
Routledge, 1989.
Canguilhem, Georges. The Normal and the Pathological, trans. Carolyn Fawcett. New
York: Zone, 1989.
Carr, David. Time, Narrative and History. Bloomington: Indiana University Press,
1986.
Carruthers, Mary J. The Book of Memory: A Study of Memory in Medieval Culture.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
Certeau, Michel de. The Writing of History, trans. Tom Conley. New York: Columbia
University Press, 1988.
Chakrabarti, Sambuddha. ‘‘Changing Notions of Conjugal Relations in Nineteenth
Century Bengal.’’ Mind, Body and Society: Life and Mentality in Colonial Bengal, ed.
Rajat Kanta Ray. Calcutta: Oxford University Press, 1995.
Chakrabarty, Dipesh. ‘‘The Difference-Deferral of a Colonial Modernity: Public
Debates on Domesticity in British Bengal.’’ Subaltern Studies VIII, ed. David
Arnold and David Hardiman. Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1994.
. Habitations of Modernity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002.
Bibliography 247
. Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference. Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 2000.
Chakraborty, Usha. Condition of Bengali Women around the 2nd Half of the 19th Century.
Calcutta: K. L. Mukhopadhyaya, 1963.
Chakravarti, Uma. ‘‘Whatever Happened to the Vedic Dasi? Orientalism,
Nationalism and a Script for the Past.’’ Recasting Women, ed. Kumkum Sangari
and Sudesh Vaid. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1990.
Chandra, Bipan. The Rise and Growth of Economic Nationalism in India. New Delhi:
People’s Publishing House, 1966.
Chandra, Sudhir. ‘‘The Cultural Component of Economic Nationalism: R. C. Dutt’s
Lake of Palms.’’ Indian Historical Review 12, nos. 1–2 (July 1985–January 1986).
Chatterjee, Partha. The Nation and Its Fragments. Delhi: Oxford University Press,
1995.
Chatterjee, Partha, and Gyan Pandey, eds. Subaltern Studies VII. Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1994.
Chaudhuri, Nupur, and Margaret Strobel, eds. Western Women and Imperialism:
Complicity and Resistance. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1992.
Chirol, Valentine. Indian Unrest. London: Macmillan, 1910.
Clifford, James. The Predicament of Culture. Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1988.
Clifford, James, and G. E. Marcus, eds. Writing Culture. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1986.
Clive, John. Macaulay: The Shaping of the Historian. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1987.
Clothey, F., ed. Images of Man: Religion and Historical Process in South Asia. Madras:
New Era, 1982.
Cohn, Bernard S. An Anthropologist among the Historians and Other Essays. New Delhi:
Oxford University Press, 1988.
. Colonialism and Its Forms of Knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1996.
Collins, Steven. Selfless Persons: Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982.
Conlon, Frank. ‘‘The Census of India as a Source for the Historical Study of
Religion and Caste.’’ The Census in British India, ed. N. Gerald Barrier. New Delhi:
Manohar, 1981.
Copjec, Joan, ed. Supposing the Subject. London: Verso, 1994.
Crook, Nigel, ed. The Transmission of Knowledge in South Asia. Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1996.
Dalmia, Vasudha. ‘‘Sanskrit Scholars and Pandits of the Old School: The Benares
Sanskrit College and the Constitution of Authority in the Late Nineteenth
Century.’’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 24 (1996).
Daniel, Sheryl B. ‘‘The Tool Box Approach of the Tamil to the Issues of Moral
248 Bibliography
Responsibility and Human Destiny.’’ Karma: An Anthropological Inquiry, ed.
Charles F. Keyes and E. Valentine Daniel. Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1983.
Daniel, Valentine. Fluid Signs: Being a Person the Tamil Way. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1984.
Daston, Lorraine. ‘‘Marvelous Facts and Miraculous Evidence in Early Modern
Europe.’’ Critical Inquiry 18, no. 1 (autumn 1991).
. ‘‘The Nature of Nature in Early Modern Europe.’’ Configurations 6, no. 2
(1998).
Datta, Nonica. ‘‘The ‘Subalternity’ of Education: Gurukuls in Rural Southeast
Punjab.’’ Knowledge, Power and Politics, ed. Mushirul Hasan. New Delhi: Roli, 1998.
Davis, Richard. Lives of Indian Images. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997.
Derrida, Jacques. Margins of Philosophy, trans. Alan Bass. Brighton, Sussex:
Harvester, 1982.
Deshpande, Madhav M. ‘‘Pandit and Professor: Transformations in the 19th
Century Maharashtra.’’ The Pandit: Traditional Scholarship in India, ed. Axel
Michaels. New Delhi: Manohar, 2001.
Dharampal. The Beautiful Tree: Indigenous Education in the Eighteenth Century. New
Delhi: Biblia Impex, 1983.
Dharmavira. Lala Har Dayal and Revolutionary Movements of His Times. New Delhi:
Indian Book, 1970.
Dilthey, W. W. Selected Writings, ed. and trans. H. P. Rickman. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1976.
Dirks, Nicholas. Castes of Mind. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001.
Douglas, Mary, ed. Rules and Meaning. Penguin, 1973.
Dutta, Krishna, and Andrew Robinson, eds. Rabindranath Tagore: An Anthology.
London: Picador, 1997.
Eck, Diana L. Darsan: Seeing the Divine Image in India, 3rd edn. New York: Columbia
University Press, 1998.
Eickelman, Dale F. Knowledge and Power in Morocco: The Education of a Twentieth-
Century Notable. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985.
Elmhirst, L. K. Rabindranath Tagore: Pioneer in Education. London: John Murray, 1961.
Emilsen, William. ‘‘Gandhi and Mayo’s Mother India.’’ South Asia 10, no. 1 (June
1987).
Fabian, Johannes. Time and the Other: How Anthropology Makes Its Object. New York:
Columbia University Press, 1983.
Fasolt, Constantine. The Limits of History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
2004.
Feuerbach, Ludwig. The Fiery Brook: Selected Writings of Ludwig Feuerbach, trans.
Zawar Hanfi. New York: Anchor, 1972.
Field, Harry. After Mother India. New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1929.
Fischer-Tine, H. ‘‘The Only Hope for Fallen India: The Gurukul Kangri as an
Bibliography 249
Experiment in National Education.’’ Explorations in the History of South Asia:
Essays in Honour of Dieter Rothmund, ed. G. Berkemer et al. New Delhi: Manohar,
2001.
Fisher, Fred B. India’s Silent Revolution. New York: Macmillan, 1919.
Forbes, Geraldine. ‘‘In Search of the ‘Pure Heathen’: Missionary Women in
Nineteenth Century India.’’ Economic and Political Weekly, 26 April 1986.
. Women in Modern India. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Foucault, Michel. ‘‘About the Beginnings of a Hermeneutics of the Self.’’ Political
Theory 21, no. 2 (May 1993).
. The Archaeology of Knowledge. New York: Harper Colophon, 1972.
. ‘‘Governmentality.’’ The Foucault Effect, ed. Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon,
and Peter Miller. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991.
. The History of Sexuality: An Introduction. New York: Pantheon, 1968–86.
Freedberg, Daniel. The Power of Images. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989.
Fuller, C. J. The Camphor Flame: Popular Hinduism and Society in India. Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1992.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg. ‘‘The Problem of Historical Consciousness.’’ Interpretive
Social Science: A Second Look, ed. Paul Rabinow and William Sullivan. Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1987.
. Truth and Method. London: Sheed and Ward, 1975.
Ganguli, Birendranath N. Dadabhai Naoroji and the Drain Theory. New Delhi, 1965.
Ghosh, Srabashi. ‘‘ ‘Birds in a Cage’: Bengali Social Life as Recorded in
Autobiographies by Women.’’ Economic and Political Weekly, 25 October 1986.
Ghurye, K. G. Preservation of Learned Tradition in India. Bombay: Popular Book Depot,
1950.
Godlove, Terry F. Religion, Interpretation, and Diversity of Belief. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1989.
Guha, Ranajit. ‘‘The Authority of Vernacular Pasts.’’ Meanjin, winter 1992.
. Dominance without Hegemony. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1997.
Guha, Sumit. ‘‘The Politics of Identity and Enumeration in India c. 1600–1990.’’
Comparative Studies in Society and History 45, no. 1 (2003).
Gupta, Charu. ‘‘Portrayal of Women in Premchand’s Stories: A Critique.’’ Social
Scientist 19, nos. 5–6 (May–June 1991).
Hacking, Ian. ‘‘Making Up People.’’ Reconstructing Individualism, ed. Thomas Heller,
Morton Sosna, and David Wellbery. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1986.
Hardy, Peter. The Muslims of British India. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1972.
Harrison, Peter. ‘‘Religion’’ and the Religions in the English Enlightenment. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1990.
Hasan, Mushirul, ed. Knowledge, Power and Politics. New Delhi: Roli, 1998.
Hegel, G. W. F. Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion [The Lectures of 1827], ed. Peter C.
Hodgson. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988.
250 Bibliography
Heidegger, Martin. ‘‘The Age of the World Picture.’’ The Question concerning
Technology and Other Essays, trans. William Lovitt. New York: Harper Torchbooks,
1977.
. Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. Oxford:
Blackwell, 2000.
. Nietzsche, vol 4, Nihilism, ed. David F. Krell, trans. Frank A. Capuzzi. San
Francisco: Harper and Row, 1982.
Heller, Thomas, Morton Sosna, and David Wellbery, eds. Reconstructing Individualism.
Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1986.
Hick, John. Foreword. The Meaning and End of Religion, by Wilfred Cantwell Smith.
Minneapolis: Fortress, 1991.
Hindess, Barry. ‘‘The Liberal Government of Unfreedom.’’ Alternatives 26, no. 2
(2001).
Houben, Jan E. M., ed. Ideology and Status of Sanskrit. Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1996.
Hoy, David Couzens. ‘‘History, Historicity, and Historiography in Being and Time.’’
Heidegger and Modern Philosophy: Critical Essays, ed. Michael Murray. New Haven:
Yale University Press, 1978.
Hunter, Ian. Culture and Government: The Emergence of Literary Education.
Houndsmill, Basingstoke, Hampshire: Macmillan, 1988.
. Rethinking the School, New York: St. Martins, 1994.
. ‘‘The State of History and the Empire of Metaphysics.’’ History and Theory 44
(May 2005).
Inden, Ronald. Imagining India. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990.
Izard, Michael, and P. Smith, eds. Between Belief and Transgression. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1982.
Jaffee, Martin S. Torah in the Mouth: Writing and Oral Tradition in Palestinian Judaism
200 bce–400 ce. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
Jalal, Ayesha. Self and Sovereignty: Individual and Community in South Asian Islam Since
1850. London: Routledge, 2000.
Jayawardena, Kumari. The White Woman’s Other Burden: Western Women and South Asia
during British Colonial Rule. New York: Routledge, 1995.
Jha, Manoranjan. Katherine Mayo and India. New Delhi: People’s Publishing, 1971.
Jones, Kenneth W. Arya Dharm: Hindu Consciousness in 19th Century Punjab. New
Delhi: Manohar, 1989.
Jones, Sue Stedman. ‘‘The Concept of Belief in The Elementary Forms.’’ On Durkheim’s
Elementary Forms of Religious Life, ed. N. J. Allen, W. S. F. Pickering, and W. Watts
Miller. London: Routledge, 1998.
Jordens, J. T. F. ‘‘Reconversion to Hinduism: The Shuddhi of the Arya Samaj.’’ Religion
in South Asia, 2nd edn, ed. Geoff A. Oddie. New Delhi: Manohar, 1991.
Joyce, Patrick, ed. The Social in Question. London: Routledge, 2002.
Kabir, Humayun. Education in New India. London: Allen and Unwin, 1956.
Bibliography 251
Kant, Immanuel. Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, trans. Victor Dowdell.
Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1978.
Kapferer, Bruce, ed. Transaction and Meaning. Philadelphia: Institute for the Study of
Human Issues, 1976.
Karlekar, Malavika. ‘‘Kadambani and the Bhadralok: Early Debates over Women’s
Education in Bengal.’’ Economic and Political Weekly, 26 April 1986.
. Voices from Within: Early Personal Narratives of Bengali Women. Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1991.
Kaviraj, Sudipta. ‘‘The Imaginary Institution of India.’’ Subaltern Studies VII, ed.
Partha Chatterjee and Gyan Pandey. Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1994.
. The Unhappy Consciousness. Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1998.
Kaviraj, Sudipta, and Sunil Khilnani, eds. Civil Society: History and Possibilities.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Kejariwal, O. P. The Asiatic Society of Bengal and the Discovery of India’s Past, 1784–1838.
Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1988.
Keyes, Charles F., and Daniel E. Valentine, eds. Karma: An Anthropological Inquiry.
Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983.
King, Richard. Orientalism and Religion: Postcolonial Theory, India and ‘‘The Mystic
East.’’ London: Routledge, 1999.
Kolb, David. The Critique of Pure Modernity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1986.
Koselleck, Reinhart. Futures Past, trans. Keith Tribe. Cambridge: mit Press, 1985.
Kumar, Krishna. Political Agenda of Education. New Delhi: Sage, 1991.
Kumar, Nita. Lessons from Schools: The History of Education in Banaras. New Delhi:
Sage, 2000.
. ‘‘Religion and Ritual in Indian Schools: Benaras from the 1880s to the
1940s.’’ The Transmission of Knowledge in South Asia, ed. Nigel Crook. Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1996.
, ed. Women as Subjects: South Asian Histories. Charlottesville: University Press
of Virginia, 1994.
Laird, M. A. Missionaries and Education in Bengal, 1793–1837. Oxford: Clarendon, 1972.
Latour, Bruno. We Have Never Been Modern, trans. Catherine Porter. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1993.
Latour, Bruno, and Steve Woolgar. Laboratory Life: The Construction of Scientific Facts,
2nd edn. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986.
Lelyveld, David. Aligarh’s First Generation: Muslim Solidarity in British India. Delhi:
Oxford University Press, 1996.
Lévi-Strauss, Claude. The Savage Mind. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1972.
Lévy-Bruhl, Lucien. How Natives Think, trans. Lilian Clare. London: George Allen
and Unwin, 1926 [1910].
Maclure, J. Stuart, ed. Educational Documents: England and Wales, 1816–1963. London:
Chapman and Hall, 1965.
252 Bibliography
Majumdar, R. C. ‘‘Nationalist Historians.’’ Historians of India, Pakistan and Ceylon, ed.
C. H. Philips. London: Oxford University Press, 1961.
. Renascent India: First Phase. Calcutta: G. Bharadwaj, 1976.
Malik, Hafeez. Sir Sayyid Ahmad Khan and Muslim Modernization in India and Pakistan.
New York: Columbia University Press, 1980.
Mallick, A. R. ‘‘Modern Historical Writing in Bengali.’’ Historians of India, Pakistan
and Ceylon, ed. C. H. Philips. London: Oxford University Press, 1961.
Marriot, McKim. ‘‘Hindu Transactions: Diversity without Dualism.’’ Transaction and
Meaning, ed. Bruce Kapferer. Philadelphia: Institute for the Study of Human
Issues, 1976.
, ed. India through Hindu Categories. New Delhi: Sage, 1990.
Marshall, P. J. Introduction. The British Discovery of Hinduism in the Eighteenth
Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970.
, ed. The British Discovery of Hinduism in the Eighteenth Century. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1970.
Marx, Karl. Capital, vol. 1. Moscow: Progress, 1978.
Marx, Karl, and Frederick Engels. Manifesto of the Communist Party. Peking: Foreign
Languages Press, 1968.
Massumi, Brian. ‘‘The Autonomy of Affect.’’ Deleuze: A Critical Reader, ed. Paul
Patton. Oxford: Blackwell, 1996.
McLane, John R. Indian Nationalism and the Early Congress. Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1977.
Michaels, Axel, ed. The Pandit: Traditional Scholarship in India. New Delhi: Manohar,
2001.
Mignolo, Walter. The Darker Side of the Renaissance, 2nd edn. Ann Arbor: University
of Michigan Press, 2003.
Millar, John. The Origin of the Distinction of Ranks. Bristol: Thoemmes Antiquarian,
1990 [1806].
Minault, Gail. ‘‘Other Voices, Other Rooms: The View from the Zenana.’’ Women as
Subjects: South Asian Histories, ed. Nita Kumar. Charlottesville: University Press of
Virginia, 1994.
. Secluded Scholars: Women’s Education and Muslim Social Reform in Colonial India.
Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1998.
Minault, Gail, and David Lelyveld. ‘‘The Campaign for a Muslim University, 1898–
1920.’’ Modern Asian Studies 8, no. 2 (1974).
Mitchell, Timothy. Colonizing Egypt. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988.
Mohanty, Jitendra Nath. Reason and Tradition in Indian Thought. Oxford: Clarendon,
1992.
Muecke, Stephen. Ancient and Modern: Time, Culture and Indigenous Philosophy. Sydney:
unsw, 2004.
Mukherjee, Haridas, and Uma Mukherjee. The Origins of the National Education
Bibliography 253
Movement (1905–1910), 2nd edn. Calcutta: National Council of Education,
Bengal, 2000.
Mukherjee, Himangshu B. Education for Fulness: A Study of the Educational Thought
and Experiment of Rabindranath Tagore. Bombay: Asia Publishing, 1962.
Murray, Michael, ed. Heidegger and Modern Philosophy: Critical Essays. New Haven:
Yale University Press, 1978.
Murshid, Ghulam. Reluctant Debutante: Response of Bengali Women to Modernization,
1849–1905. Rajshahi: Rajshahi University, 1983.
Murshid, Tazeen M. The Sacred and the Secular: Bengal Muslim Discourses, 1871–1971.
Calcutta: Oxford University Press, 1995.
Nandy, Ashis. The Intimate Enemy. Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1983.
. ‘‘A Report on the Present State of Health of the Gods and Goddesses in
South Asia.’’ Postcolonial Studies 4, no. 2 (July 2001).
Needham, Rodney. Belief, Language, and Experience. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1972.
Nigam, Sanjay. ‘‘Disciplining and Policing the ‘Criminals by Birth.’ ’’ Indian
Economic and Social History Review 27 nos. 2–3 (1990).
Oakeshott, Michael. On History and Other Essays. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1983.
Oddie, Geoff A. ‘‘Anti-missionary Feeling and Hindu Revivalism in Madras: The
Hindu Preaching and Tract Societies, C. 1886–91.’’ Images of Man: Religion and
Historical Process in South Asia, ed. F. Clothey. Madras: New Era, 1982.
, ed. Religion in South Asia, 2nd edn. New Delhi: Manohar, 1991.
O’Hanlon, Rosalind. Introduction. A Comparison between Women and Men, by Tarabai
Shinde. Madras: Oxford University Press, 1994.
Orsini, Francesca. The Hindi Public Sphere, 1920–1940. New Delhi: Oxford University
Press, 2002.
Pailin, David A. Attitudes to Other Religions: Comparative Religion in Seventeenth and
Eighteenth-Century Britain. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1984.
Palmer, Richard, ed. and trans. Gadamer in Conversation. New Haven: Yale University
Press, 2001.
Pandey, Geetanjali. ‘‘How Equal? Women in Premchand’s Writings.’’ Economic and
Political Weekly, 13 December 1986.
Pandey, Gyan. The Construction of Communalism in Colonial North India. New Delhi:
Oxford University Press, 1992.
Pant, Rashmi. ‘‘The Cognitive Status of Caste in Colonial Ethnography: A Review of
Some Literature on the North West Provinces and Oudh.’’ Indian Economic and
Social History Review 24, no. 2 (1987).
Patton, Paul, ed. Deleuze: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Blackwell, 1996.
Peabody, Norbert. ‘‘Cents, Sense, Census: Human Inventories in Late Precolonial
and Early Colonial India.’’ Comparative Studies in Society and History 43 (2001).
Perrill, Jeffrey. ‘‘Punjab Orientalism: the Anjuman-I-Punjab and Punjab University,
1865–1888.’’ PhD diss., University of Missouri, Columbia, 1976.
254 Bibliography
Philips, C. H., ed. Historians of India, Pakistan and Ceylon. London: Oxford University
Press, 1961.
Polanyi, Karl. The Great Transformation. Boston: Beacon, 1965.
Pollock, Sheldon. ‘‘The Death of Sanskrit.’’ Comparative Studies in Society and History
43, no. 2 (2001).
. ‘‘New Intellectuals in Seventeenth-Century India.’’ Indian Economic and
Social History Review 38, no. 1 (2001).
Poovey, Mary. ‘‘The Liberal Civil Subject and the Social.’’ Public Culture 14, no. 1
(winter 2002).
Prakash, Gyan. Another Reason: Science and the Imagination of Modern India. Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1999.
Puillon, Jean. ‘‘Remarks on the Verb ‘To Believe,’ ’’ trans. John Leavitt. Between Belief
and Transgression, ed. Michael Izard and P. Smith. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1982.
Rabinow, Paul, and William Sullivan, eds. Interpretive Social Science: A Second Look.
Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987.
Ramakrishna, V. ‘‘Women’s Journals in Andhra during the Nineteenth Century.’’
Social Scientist 19, nos. 5–6 (May–June 1991).
Raman, Sita Anantha. Getting Girls to School: Social Reform in the Tamil Nadu Districts,
1870–1930. Calcutta: Stree, 1996.
Ramanujan, A. K. ‘‘Is There an Indian Way of Thinking? An Informal Essay.’’ India
through Hindu Categories, ed. McKim Marriot. New Delhi: Sage, 1990.
Ramusack, Barbara N. ‘‘Cultural Missonaries, Maternal Imperialists, Feminist
Allies: British Women Activists in India, 1865–1945.’’ Western Women and
Imperialism: Complicity and Resistance, ed. Nupur Chaudhuri and Margaret
Strobel. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1992.
Ray, Bharati, ed. From the Seams of History: Essays on Indian Women. Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1995.
Ray, Rajat Kanta, ed. Mind, Body and Society: Life and Mentality in Colonial Bengal.
Calcutta: Oxford University Press, 1995.
Ricoeur, Paul. Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation, trans. David Savage.
New Haven: Yale University Press, 1970.
. ‘‘The Task of Hermeneutics.’’ Heidegger and Modern Philosophy: Critical Essays,
ed. Michael Murray. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1978.
. Time and Narrative, vol. 3, trans. K. Blamey and D. Pellauer. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1988.
Rorty, Richard. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1979.
Rosenthal, A. M. ‘‘Mother India Thirty Years Later.’’ Foreign Affairs 35, no. 4 (July
1957).
Russell, Ralph, and Khurshidul Islam. Ghalib: Life and Letters. Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1994.
Bibliography 255
Sangari, Kumkum, and Sudesh Vaid, eds. Recasting Women. New Brunswick: Rutgers
University Press, 1990.
Sarkar, Sumit. ‘‘ ‘Kaliyuga,’ ‘Chakri’ and ‘Bhakti’: Ramakrishna and His Times.’’
Economic and Political Weekly, 18 July 1992.
Sarkar, Sumit. The Swadeshi Movement in Bengal, 1903–1908. New Delhi: People’s
Publishing, 1973.
Sarkar, Tanika. Hindu Wife, Hindu Nation. Bloomington: Indiana University Press,
2001.
. Words to Win: The Making of Amar Jiban: A Modern Autobiography. New Delhi:
Kali for Women, 1999.
Schwab, Raymond. The Oriental Renaissance, trans. G. Patterson-Black
and V. Reinking. New York: Columbia University Press, 1984 [1950].
Seth, Sanjay. ‘‘Nationalism, National Identity and ‘History’: Nehru’s Search for
India.’’ Thesis Eleven 32 (1992).
. ‘‘Reason or Reasoning? Clio or Siva?’’ Social Text 78 (2004).
. ‘‘Rewriting Histories of Nationalism: The Politics of ‘Moderate
Nationalism’ in India, 1870–1905.’’ American Historical Review 104, no. 1 (February
1999).
. ‘‘Which Good Book? Missionary Education and Conversion in Colonial
India.’’ Semeia 88 (2001).
Shapin, Steven, and Simon Schaffer. Leviathan and the Air-Pump. Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1985.
Sharma, Narinder Kumar. Linguistic and Educational Aspirations under a Colonial
System. Delhi: Concept, 1976.
Sharma, Usha, and B. M. Sharma, eds. Women [sic] Education in British India. New
Delhi: Commonwealth, 1995.
Shils, Edward, and Henry Finch, eds. The Methodology of the Social Sciences: Max
Weber. New York: Free Press, 1949.
Shukla, Sonal. ‘‘Cultivating Minds: 19th Century Gujarati Women’s Journals.’’
Economic and Political Weekly, 26 October 1991.
Singer, Milton. When a Great Tradition Modernizes. New York: Praeger, 1972.
Sinha, Mrinalini. Editor’s Introduction. Selections from Mother India, by Katherine
Mayo, ed. Mrinalini Sinha. New Delhi: Kali for Women, 1998.
. ‘‘The Lineage of the ‘Indian’ Modern.’’ Gender, Sexuality and Colonial
Modernities, ed. Antoinette Burton. London: Routledge, 1999.
Sinha, Sasadhar. Social Thinking of Rabindranath Tagore. Bombay: Asia Publishing,
1961.
Smith, Jonathan Z. Imagining Religion: From Babylon to Jonestown. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1982.
Smith, Richard S. ‘‘Rule-by-Records and Rule-by-Reports: Complementary Aspects
of the British Imperial Rule of Law.’’ Contributions to Indian Sociology 19, no. 1,
new series (1985).
256 Bibliography
Smith, Wilfred Cantwell. Faith and Belief. Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1979.
. The Meaning and End of Religion. Minneapolis: Fortress, 1991.
Staal, J. F. Nambudiri Veda Recitation. The Hague: Mouton, 1961.
. Ritual and Mantras: Rules without Meaning. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1996.
Strathern, Marilyn. The Gender of the Gift. Berkeley: University of California Press,
1988.
Talwar, Vir Bharat. ‘‘Women’s Journals in Hindi, 1910–1920.’’ Recasting Women, ed.
Kumkum Sangari and Sudesh Vaid. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press,
1990.
Taussig, Michael. The Devil and Commodity Fetishism in South America. Chapel Hill:
University of North Carolina Press, 1980.
Taylor, Charles. Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975.
. ‘‘Two Theories of Modernity.’’ Public Culture 11, no. 1 (1999).
Tharu, Susie. ‘‘Tracing Savitri’s Pedigree.’’ Recasting Women, ed. Kumkum Sangari
and Sudesh Vaid. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1990.
Toulmin, Stephen. Cosmopolis: The Hidden Agenda of Modernity. New York: Free Press,
1990.
Trautmann, Thomas. Aryans and British India. Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1997.
Veyne, Paul. Writing History, trans. Mina Moore-Rinvolueri. Middletown, Conn.:
Wesleyan University Press, 1984.
Viswanathan, Gauri. Masks of Conquest: Literary Study and British Rule in India. New
York: Columbia University Press, 1989.
Waghorne, Joanne P., and Norman Cutler, eds. Gods of Flesh, Gods of Stone: The
Embodiment of Divinity in India. Chambersburg, Penn.: Anima 1985.
Walsh, Judith. ‘‘The Virtuous Wife and the Well-Ordered Home: The Re-
conceptualization of Bengali Women and Their Worlds.’’ Mind, Body and Society:
Life and Mentality in Colonial Bengal, ed. Rajat Kanta Ray. Calcutta: Oxford
University Press, 1995.
Warnke, Georgia. Gadamer: Hermeneutics, Tradition and Reason. Stanford: Stanford
University Press, 1987.
Weber, Max. ‘‘Objectivity in Social Science and Social Policy.’’ The Methodology of the
Social Sciences: Max Weber, ed. Edward Shils and Henry Finch. New York: Free
Press, 1949.
Winch, Peter. The Idea of a Social Science, 2nd edn. London: Routledge, 1998.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough, ed. Rush Rhees, trans. A. C.
Miles. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities, 1979.
Wood, Ananda K. Knowledge before Printing and After: The Indian Tradition in Changing
Kerala. Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1985.
Young, Richard Fox. Resistant Hinduism. Vienna: De Nobili Research Library, 1981.
Bibliography 257
Zammito, John H. Kant, Herder, and the Birth of Anthropology. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2002.
Zastoupil, Lynn, and Martin Moir, eds. The Great Indian Education Debate: Documents
Relating to the Orientalist-Anglicist Controversy, 1781–1843. Richmond: Curzon,
1999.
Žižek, Slavoj. ‘‘Is There a Cause of the Subject?’’ Supposing the Subject, ed. Joan
Copjec. London: Verso, 1994.
Index
259
260 Index
Colonialism (continued ) Fasolt, Constantine, 100–102
prise, 1–3, 5, 137, 159–60, 172; schools Female education, 137–42; anxiety about,
established during, 2; women’s status 142–44; better wife and mother dis-
under, 132–33 courses and, 139–42, 144; in Britain, 142;
Conring, Hermann, 100–102 colonial discourses on, 129–30, 145–47;
Coomaraswamy, A. K., 162 debate in newspapers and magazines
Cramming discourses, 22–28, 31–33, 42–45, on, 138–39; ‘‘denationalizing’’ fear and,
104; English and, 24–25; importance of 142–44; ‘‘desexing’’ fear and, 142–44;
exams and, 23; teachers and, 25 domesticity and, 139–41; Hinduism and,
Curzon, Lord, 22–26, 29–30, 52, 159–60 138–39, 141, 157; impediments to, 137–38;
middle-class support for, 138; missionar-
Daniel, E. Valentine, 69 ies and, 137–38; morality and, 141; Mother
Daston, Lorraine, 192, 194 India and, 154–55, 157; Muslims and, 141–
Dayal, Har, 162 42; numbers enrolled in, 129, 156–57;
Dayanand Anglo-Vedic High School (dav), prejudices against, 137–38; as return to
163–65 Hindu traditions, 139; Vanitabodhini and,
Debi, Kundamala, 139 138; ‘‘westernization’’ and, 143–45, 157;
de Certeau, Michel, 97–99 zenana education and, 138, 141, 154. See
Derozio, Henry, 50 also Women
Derrida, Jacques, 36 Feuerbach, Ludwig, 92
Dhar, B. N., 159 Foucault, Michel, 97, 120–21
Dilthey, Wilhelm, 82–86 Freud, Sigmund, 70; Wolf Man analyzed by,
Discovery of India, The (Nehru), 132 76–77
‘‘Disenchantment,’’ 4, 6, 94–95, 193, 195 Fuller, Bampfylde, 57
Dow, Alexander, 79 Fuller, C. J., 64–65
Dowries, 21–22 ‘‘Fuzzy communities,’’ 124–25
‘‘Drafts for a Critique of Historical Reason’’
(Dilthey), 83 Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 80, 83–90, 99
‘‘Drain Inspector’s Report’’ (Gandhi), 156 Gandhi, Mahatma, 156; on English language
Duff, Alexander, 49–51, 75 in education, 178–80, 182; response to
Duncan, Jonathon, 170 Mother India from, 156; at ‘‘Round Table’’
Durkheim, Émile, 60–61, 67, 69–70 conference, 167–68; western education
Dutt, G. S., 136 boycotted by, 166–67
Dutt, Toru, 134 General Committee for Public Instruction,
17
Eck, Diana, 65 Governmentality, 120–23
Education of the People of India, The (Tre- Government of India Act (1919), 150
velyan), 2 Government of India Resolution on Indian
Engels, Friedrich, 184 Educational Policy (1904), 52
English language, 1, 19, 24, 111, 113; cram- Government service, 18–20
ming for exams and, 24–25; Gandhi on Guha, Ranajit, 79
use in education of, 178–80, 182; Tagore
on use in education of, 178–80, 182; ver- Hacking, Ian, 109
nacular languages in education vs., 19, Hailey, William Malcolm, 21–22
24–25, 31, 165, 178–82 Hare, David, 180
‘‘Evil Wrought by the English Medium’’ Harrison, Peter, 62
(Gandhi), 178 Hartog, Philip, 168
Examination of Religions, An (Muir), 172 Hartog Commission, 71
Exams, 22–27. See also Cramming Hastings, Warren, 170
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 82–83
Index 261
Heidegger, Martin, 6–7, 96–97; on history, 116–17; on female education, 137–42; on
86–90 Sanskrit, 172
Hindess, Barry, 122 Indian Musalmans, The (Hunter), 111
Hindi language, 164 Indian National Congress, 149–50, 159; de-
Hindu College, 50–51 mands for western education and, 159;
Hindus, Hinduism, 62–68, 71–72, 172; national education and, 165–66
alternatives to western education and, Indian Unrest (Chirol), 52–53
163–64; call for revived pedagogy of, 169; Indigenous knowledge, indigenous educa-
concept of selfhood in, 68–69; female tion, 18, 32–33, 123, 167–76; arithmetic
education and, 138–39, 141, 157; mod- in, 38–39; as basis of national educa-
ern and Christian interpretations of, tion, 166–70; British funding of, 170–72;
62–63; in Mother India, 153–54; Mus- British reforms to, 172–73; calls for
lim participation in education vs., 113, revival of, 167–70; caste and, 37–38;
123–24; plans for Hindu University, 56; Chaturvedi’s experience of, 41–42; cram-
reinterpretation of, 63; western educa- ming and, 22–28, 31–33, 42–45; English
tion and, 48–51, 53–59, 75, 111; women vs. vernacular languages in, 31, 178–
and, 132–36 82; Gandhi’s plan for, 178–79; Gandhi’s
Historical Sketches of the South of India (Wilks), speech at ‘‘Round Table’’ conference
79 on, 167–68; Hinduism and, 169, 172;
History, 99; as ‘‘code,’’ 81, 90–94, 97, 101–2; memorization and, 32–36, 38; modern
Dilthey on, 82–86; ‘‘effective,’’ 87–88; western knowledge vs., 1, 34; Muslims
Gadamer on, 83–90, 99; Heidegger on, and, 119; Patshala and pyal schools of,
86–90; hermeneutics of, 79–84, 105; 38–40; Punjab University College and,
humanism-anthropologic presumption 169–70; reassertion of value of, 135, 167–
in, 6–7, 45, 81, 91–97, 103–4; knowledge of 89; resistance to western education
human sciences and, 82–83; Nietzsche by Indian students, 32–33; respect for
on, 95–97; objectivist presumption in, teachers and, 36–37, 39–40; rote learning
80–88, 90, 93, 186; primary sources and, and, 32–33, 42, 171; Sanskrit and, 172–76;
93, 99, 101–2; Roman Empire and, 100; as source of Indian backwardness, 171;
temporal mode of human being and, status and, 37, 39–40; Vedas and, 34–35;
86–91; textbooks of, 79; transcendental western curriculums and pedagogies vs.,
presupposition of Weber and, 94–97, 103– 34–42
4; writing, 5–8, 79–80, 102–6; writing Interdenominational Women’s Christian
Indian, 79–81, 102–3 College, 66
History of British India, The (Mill), 132
History of English Education in India, A (Mah- Jalal, Ayesha, 126
mood), 115
History of Hindostan, The (Dow), 79 Kali Ghat, 151–53
History of Rural Education in the United Prov- Kalikata kamalalya, 72–75
inces of Agra and Oudh, The (Chaturvedi), Kant, Immanuel, 28, 61, 83–84
41 Kaviraj, Sudipta, 124–25
Hunter, Ian, 121 Keay, F. E., 168
Hunter, W. W., 111–12, 117 Khan, Sayyid Ahmad, 112, 117, 126
Hunter Commission. See Indian Education Kielhorn, Franz, 173
Commission Knowledge. See Indigenous knowledge,
Huque, M. Azizul, 113 indigenous education; Medieval knowl-
edge; Modern, western knowledge;
India: A Bird’s-Eye View (Ronaldshay), 116 Premodern knowledge
India and Indian Missions (Duff ), 49 Kolb, David, 95
Indian Education Commission, 112, 114, Koselleck, Reinhardt, 91
262 Index
Lahiri, Ramtanu, 180 tion in history of, 80–88, 90, 93, 186;
Latour, Bruno, 192–94 premodern knowledge vs., 3–4, 188–91,
Lelyveld, David, 124–25 194; religion and, 60–62; sciences and,
Lévi-Strauss, Claude, 91, 97 82–83, 191–93; sense of ‘‘exoticism’’ of,
Lévy-Bruhl, Lucien, 66–68 2–3; unitariness of, 33
Limits of History, The (Fasolt), 100 Modern Review, 57–58
London University, 24 Moral crisis, moral character: Christian mis-
sionaries and, 47–51; denials by educated
Macaulay, Thomas Babington, 1, 5, 39, 49, 75, Indians of, 55; diagnosing, 57–62; female
176, 195 education and, 141; in Hindus, 58–59;
Madras: Bishop Corries Grammar School, humanism-anthropologic presumption
51–52; industrial leaders in, 71–72; and, 60–61; inconsistency in educated
university established in, 2, 26 Indians and, 57–60, 77; Indian teachers’
Madras Educational Conference (1898), 25, concern over, 56; lack in Madras indus-
39–40 trialists of, 71–72; mismatched modern
Madrassas, 119; in Calcutta, 170–71 categories’ role in, 60–62, 69–78, 186;
Mahmood, Syed, 3, 115 Report of the Indian Education Commission
Maine, Henry, 26 and, 52, 55; textbooks for instruction in,
Malaviya, Madan Mohan, 56 54; western education and, 47–62
Marriot, McKim, 68 Mother India (Mayo), 147–55; Calcutta in, 151–
Marx, Karl, 60, 184 53; child brides in, 154, 156; controversy
Matapariksa (Muir), 172 over, 148–51, 156–58; female education
Mayo, Katherine, 147–55 in, 154–55, 157; Gandhi’s response to,
Mayo, Lord, 112 156; Kali Ghat in, 151–53; nationalists’
Medieval knowledge, 36 reaction to, 149–50, 156–58; themes of
Memorization, 22–24, 28–30, 32, 35–36, 38 Indian backwardness in, 152–56; Volume
Mill, James, 132–33, 153 Two as sequel to, 149
Minault, Gail, 141 Muhammadan Anglo-Oriental College, 164
Missionaries: female education and, 137–38; Muhammadan Educational Conference,
godless education criticized by, 47–51 117–18, 124
Mitchell, Tim, 39, 67–68 Muir, John, 172
Mitra, Babu Pramadadas, 174–75 Muslim League, 124
Mitra, Peary Chand, 133–34 Muslims: educational ‘‘backwardness’’
Modern, western knowledge, 1; categories of, 110–17, 124; female education and,
of, 8; critique of dominant status of, 141–42; Hindus vs., 113; indigenous
3, 42–45, 60–61, 182, 186–95; diagnos- education of, 119; Muhammadan Anglo-
ing moral crisis and, 60–62, 69–78, 186; Oriental College and, 164; new ways
‘‘disenchantment’’ and, 4, 6, 94–95, 193, of being and, 123–27, 164; religious in-
195; education as disseminator of, 1, 80, struction and, 19, 114; statistical basis of
119, 122–23, 170, 185–86; foundational as- ‘‘backwardness’’ discourse and, 116–20
sumptions of, 8–9, 60–61; globalization
of, 3, 182–84, 195; history texts and, 79; Naidu, Sarojini, 139, 149
humanism-anthropologic presump- Nair, Sankaran, 159
tion in, 6–7, 45, 60–61, 81, 91–97, 103–4; Nandy, Ashis, 64
Indian nationalism and, 135–36, 176– National Council of Education (nce), 165
82; indigenous knowledges vs., 1, 34–42, Nationalism, nationalists, 123, 130–32; criti-
49; knowing subject and separate ob- cisms of western education and, 160–69,
ject created by, 3–4, 6–7, 60–61, 186, 195; 181–82; female education and, 142–46;
modernity and, 183–95; nature-culture material vs. spiritual domains and, 135–
divide in, 192–95; objectivist presump- 36, 157, 177; modern, western knowledge
Index 263
and, 135–36, 176–82; Mother India and, Sarkar, Sumit, 165
149–50, 156–58; ‘‘national education’’ Sarkar, Tanika, 135
and, 56, 164–67, 169–70, 178, 180–81; on Sati, 132, 134
revival of indigenous knowledge and Savitri, 134
education, 167–78, 181; on vernacu- Sen, Keshab Chunder, 71
lar education, 180–82; women’s iconic Shanti (Premchand), 143
status for, 130, 134–37, 142–46, 157–58 Sherring, M. A., 52
National Muhammadan Association, 113, 115 Singer, Milton, 71–75
Needham, Rodney, 67 Sinha, Mrinalini, 150, 157
Nehru, Jawaharlal, 132 Society for the Acquisition of General
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 95–97 Knowledge, 133
Non-cooperation movement, 131, 150, 166 Speech, writing vs., 36
Staal, Frits, 35
O’Malley, L. S. S., 63 Subcontinent knowledges. See Indigenous
Orsini, Francesca, 157 knowledge and education
Our Young Men (pamphlet), 24 Subjectivity, 18, 27, 42–45, 104
Swadeshi agitation (Bengal), 52, 165
Pal, Bipan Chandra, 29, 162
Patshala and pyal schools, 38–40 Tagore, Rabindranath, 162; on English in
Persian language, 111, 113 education, 178–80, 182; school estab-
Pioneer (newspaper), 2–3 lished by, 163–65, 167
Poona Sanskrit college, 172 Taylor, Charles, 4, 189–94
Population, 119–22, 124, 126 Teachers: cramming and, 25; moral crisis
Potter, W. A., 22 and, 56; respect and devotion for, 36–37,
Premchand, 143 39–40
Premodern knowledge, 3–4, 188–91, 194 Telang, Justice, 55
Provincializing Europe (Chakrabarty), 72 Textbooks, 25; history, 79; on moral charac-
Punjab, 169–70 ter, 54
Punjab University College, 169–70 Thibault, George, 174
Time and Narrative (Ricoeur), 89
Rai, Lajpat, 162, 167, 169, 176 Trevelyan, Charles, 2, 49
Ray, Prafulla Chandra, 17
Religion, 62, 97–98; western interpretations Universities, 2, 26
of, 60–62 University of Calcutta, 19–22, 24
Religion of the Masses, The (O’Malley), 63 University of Oxford, 24; cramming at, 26
Religious instruction, 19, 47–56; Hindi Urdu language, 113
textbooks for, 54; Muslims and, 19, 114,
164 Vanitabodhini, 138
Report of the Indian Education Commission Vedas, 34–35
(1883), 52, 55 Veyne, Paul, 91
Ricoeur, Paul, 86, 88–90 Viswa-Bharati University, 163
Ronaldshay, Lord, 116 Voltaire, 92
Volume Two (Mayo), 149. See also Mother India
Sanskrit language, 34–35, 103, 163, 172–76;
Benares Sanskrit College, 170–74; dav Warnke, Georgia, 85
high school and, 163–65; European en- Weber, Max, 4, 6–7; transcendental pre-
thusiasm for, 170–71; Indian Education supposition of, 94–97, 103–4
Commission on, 172; Poona Sanskrit Weltanschauung, 6, 96, 105
college, 172 Western education, 1–2, 122–23; alternatives
Santiniketan, 163–65 to, 56, 163–70; Anglicists and, 1, 17, 171,
264 Index
Western education (continued ) 80, 119, 122–23, 170, 185–86; moral decline
180; anxiety of cram and, 18, 22–28, 32– from, 47–62, 186; Muslims and, 19, 110–
33, 42–45, 104; ‘‘backward’’ Muslims 17, 124, 126, 164; ‘‘national education’’ as
and, 110–17, 124; in Bengal, 17–22; col- alternative to, 163–67, 169–70; nation-
lective identities and, 110, 126; colonial alism and, 56, 159–69, 176–78, 181–82;
governmentality and, 120–23; colonial religious instruction and, 19, 47–56, 114,
origins of, 1–3; criticisms of, 21, 160–69, 164; resistance by Indian students to,
181–82; Lord Curzon’s speech on, 29– 32–33; rote learning and, 22, 29–30, 186;
30; dav High School movement and, Sanskrit and, 163, 172–76; sense of ‘‘exoti-
163–65; demands for more of, 159–60; cism’’ of, 2–3; socialization and, 36–37;
denationalizing of subjects by, 160–62, status and, 180–81; Tagore’s alternatives
181; English vernacular languages in, 19, to, 163–65; urban middle classes and,
165, 178–82; exams in, 22–27; failure as 180–81; writing history of, 79–80. See also
vehicle of modernity of, 160–62, 181–82; Female education
failure to create knowing subjects of, 18, When A Great Tradition Modernizes (Singer),
26–33, 42–43, 106, 186; Gandhi on, 166–68, 71–72
178–79; government employment and, Wilks, Mark, 79
18–20; Hindu vs. Muslim participation Women: Child Marriage Restraint Bill and,
in, 111, 113; Hinduism and, 48–59, 75, 156; declining condition of, 132–35, 149;
111, 163–64; Indian National Congress iconic status in nationalist discourse of,
and, 159; Indian students’ distortion 130, 134–37, 142–46, 157–58; Mother India
of, 31–39; indigenous curriculums and and, 147–55; poem by Dutt on, 134. See
pedagogies vs., 34–42; instrumentalism also Female education
complaint and, 17–28, 31, 33, 42–45, 74, Writing, speech vs., 36
104, 186; marriage prospects and, 20–22;
memorization and, 28–29, 32; missionar- Young India (Gandhi), 166
ies’ critique of ‘‘godlessness’’ and, 47–51;
modern knowledge disseminated by, 1, Žižek, Slavoj, 76–77
Sanjay Seth is a reader in politics at La Trobe University, Melbourne. He is
also a professor of politics at Goldsmiths College, University of London.